WHAT SORT OF FACT IS KANT’S FACT OF REASON? Tatiana Patrone tpatrone@ithaca.edu Introduction The Critique of Practical Reason, Kant says, aims to show “that there is pure practical reason” (5:3).1 Furthermore, if it succeeds in this, then “transcendental freedom is also established”.2 In order to accomplish both tasks, Kant’s Analytic shows, first, that all and only those wills that are subject to the categorical imperative of morality are transcendentally free. Second, it argues that human volition belongs to the set of wills that are subject to the moral law (and thus are free in this “absolute sense”). This second task involves an appeal to what Kant calls the fact of reason: through this “fact” Kant is able to ground his claim that humans have the faculty of pure practical reason and thus are also transcendentally free.3 Kant’s appeal to the fact of reason in the second Critique has not won over many supporters. The argument from the fact of reason has been called a “moralistic bluster” (by Allen Wood4) and one of the “most spectacular train wrecks” (by Paul Guyer5). One of the common concerns about Kant’s appeal to the “consciousness of the fundamental moral law” is that it begs the question of the second Critique, the task of which is to show (and not to assume) that our practical reason is in fact pure. Another concern (which is somewhat related to the question-begging issue) is that Kant intends the fact of reason to do too much heavy lifting in his 1 Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (in Kant: Practical Philosophy, translated and edited by Mary J. Gregor (Cambridge University Press, 1996). 2 Ibid. 3 I should say that this way of reading the second Critique has been developed by Onora O’Neil and Pavel Łuków (see especially his “The Fact of Reason: Kant’s Passage to Ordinary Moral Knowledge”, Kant-Studien 84 (1993), pp. 204-221.) And in this basic approach to the structure of the second Critique I agree with these readings that take the fact of reason to be a part of Kant’s argument to the conclusion that humans have pure practical reason, etc. 4 Allen Wood, Kantian Ethics (Cambridge University Press, 2008), 135. 5 Paul Guyer, “Naturalistic and Transcendental Moments in Kant’s Moral Philosophy”, (445) in Inquiry 50 (2007): 444-464. 1 system and that the whole critical corpus stands or falls with the success of this central argument in the Critique of Practical Reason. In what follows, I will look into one aspect of Kant’s argument from the fact of reason, namely into the question whether the fact of reason is empirical or a priori. Now, Kant claims that the fact of reason is a priori (after all, it is a fact of reason). But the Analytic does not give us a direct argument to this claim. It seems to me, however, that it is important for Kant to have an argument such as this at least available (if not explicitly presented). And here is why. The fact of reason is supposed to show unequivocally that humans are subject to the moral law; and it does this by appealing to our consciousness of being bound by the moral law. The status of the claim that we are conscious of the binding nature of morality would have important implications for the status of the claim that we are bound by the moral law. If our consciousness of the moral ought is an empirical fact about us, then – since a posteriori judgments do not deliver necessity – the claim that we are bound by the moral law would itself be a contingent claim. If, on the other hand, the fact of reason itself is a priori (and thus necessary), then the claim that we are bound by the moral law also becomes unconditional. And so I think it is worth discussing what arguments to the conclusion that the fact of reason is not an empirical fact about our psychological makeup are available to Kant. My plan for this paper is the following. After brief preliminary remarks on the complexity of the term Faktum and after explaining what I take Kant to mean by it, I will go over the examples of our common ethical judgments that Kant cites in support of his claim that we are aware of the binding nature of the moral law. Then, I explain what is at stake in arguing that the fact of reason is a priori (and not empirical). Before addressing the main question of the paper, I go over some prominent issues in Kant’s theoretical philosophy (the status of his ‘transcendental 2 psychology’) with the hope of learning some methodological lessons from the literature on this topic. Finally, I provide an argument (on behalf of Kant) to the conclusion that the fact of reason is a synthetic a priori proposition and for this argument I draw on what Kant actually says about the features of our volition. Preliminary remarks Before turning to the main question of this paper – whether Kant’s fact of reason is empirical or not – it is worth noting that there is a set of ambiguities associated with the term ‘fact of reason’. One ambiguity (which I will not address, but will only mention) is that ‘fact of reason’ is used by Kant to refer to at least two things. On the one hand, ‘fact of reason’ refers to our consciousness of the binding nature of the moral law, but on the other hand, Kant uses it to refer to the moral law itself. (Compare, for instance, 5:31 and 5:47, which say, respectively: “consciousness of this fundamental law [the moral law] may be called a fact of reason”, and “the moral law is given [to us], as it were, as a fact of reason”, etc.6) The second exegetical question concerning the phrase ‘fact of reason’ has to do with the term Faktum. The term is commonly translated into English as fact; indeed, even in contemporary German its synonym would be the word Tatsache (and in that English translations are no more misleading than the connotations of Kant’s text would have today even in his native language). But the second Critique does not contain a single reference to Tatsache (although Kant uses this term later, in the Critique of Judgment). Since the term Faktum is derivative from the Latin facere (to do, which has a connotation of activity) and since (in Kant’s time) it would I should note that Marcus Willaschek argues that in 5:47 “as a fact of reason” refers not to ‘the moral law’ but rather to its givenness to us. That is, according to Willaschek, the moral law is given to us as a fact, and the moral law itself is not a fact of reason. (See his Praktische Vernunft: Handlungstheorie und Moralbegründung bei Kant (Verlag J.B. Metzler, 1992), p. 181.) 6 3 not have been synonymous with Tatsache (a later term7), it is reasonable to doubt whether Faktum is a term that describes a state of affairs rather than a certain act of reason. Within the growing literature on Kant’s notion of fact of reason, at this point I think that Marcus Willaschek’s analysis stands out.8 This is not the place to get into details of his work, and so I will only provide a couple of highlights and will also say what I take to be its essential lessons for the purposes of this paper. First, I think that Willaschek convincingly shows that Kant’s term Faktum is rich and that it cannot be reduced either to Tat (deed) or Tatsache (fact), and although it is closer to the former, the term really combines both meanings. Although Faktum is a noun (and although now its etymology is less telling that it would be in Kant’s time), the term has a strong connotation of activity, in particular – reason’s activity. Pure practical reason, Willaschek argues, reveals that we are bound by the moral law since it produces or delivers this moral law from itself and since it determines our will to moral action.9 In this, pure practical reason manifests itself through an act (Faktum) of delivering the moral law and of determining the will to action. In addition to arguing that Faktum is more appropriately rendered as act (or deed) (and thus is synonymous to Tat rather than Tatsache), Willaschek goes over the passages containing the term and shows that this rendition would clear up many confusions associated with the term, including the first ambiguity that I mentioned (i.e., that Kant uses Faktum to refer both to our consciousness of the moral law and to the moral law itself). Although the term Tatsache was coined in 1756 (to refer to “matters of fact” and specifically to an event, the occurrence of which was to be established though testimony), it was not widely used till later in 1790s. Kant does not use the term in the second Critique, although in his later Critique of Judgment, §91 (On What Kind of Assent Results from a Practical Faith) Kant uses it to refer to res facti – “objects of concepts whose objective reality can be proved are matters of fact [Tatsachen] (res facti), etc.” (On the history of the term ‘Tatsache’ and on its relevance to Kant’s (and then German Idealists’) term Faktum, see e.g., Paul Franks“Freedom, Tatsache and Tathandlung in the Development of Fichte’s Jena Wissenschaftslehre” in Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 79 (1997): 310-323, and also his “Transcendental Argument, Reason, and Skepticism: Contemporary Debates and the Origins of PostKantianism” in Transcendental Arguments: Problems and Perspectives, edited by R. Stern (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1999). 8 Marcus Willaschek, Praktische Vernunft: Handlungstheorie und Moralbegründung bei Kant (Verlag J.B. Metzler, 1992), chapter 10 (pp. 174-193). 9 E.g., Willaschek, 181. 7 4 What I take to be significant in this analysis is Willaschek’s emphasis on the distinction between factum brutum (as he puts it) and Faktum of reason. Pure reason, he points out, does not “discover” the moral law as we discover, e.g., the laws of nature. The moral law is not given to us as an independently existing fact (in which case Tatsache would be a more appropriate term for it). Rather, pure practical reason produces the moral law, and the moral law is not antecedently given to it but springs forth from its activity. But essentially whether Faktum is better rendered as act or as fact of reason is not what’s at issue here. Indeed, for the purposes of this paper this ambiguity is not all that important. I just mentioned that Willaschek’s analysis shows that the primary context of the term fact of reason is Kant’s claim that through the fact of reason (i.e., through its activity), reason attests to the fact that we are conscious of the fundamental law of morality. That is, reason’s activity delivers to us (the philosophers) evidence that humans are conscious of the moral law. The focus of this paper is this latter claim, i.e., the claim that humans are aware of the binding nature of morality, and the main question with respect to this claim is this: Is this an empirical (psychological) or an a priori (philosophical) claim about us? Before we turn to the passages that will be essential for answering this question, let me clarify what it is that I am proposing to inquire into. I take it that we can distinguish between at least three sorts of claims that could be relevant to a normative ethical theory, and that these claims would have different status in it. Consider the following propositions: (A) When having done something wrong, we usually feel guilty. (B) Humans tend to be deterred from wrongdoing by the threat of punishment. (C) Humans are aware of the binding nature of the moral law. 5 In what follows, I will specifically ask whether (C) is crucially different from (A) and (B). Let me explain. I take it that (A) and (B) are empirical claims about us, although the ways to verify (A) and (B) would differ. For Kant, as we will see, our awareness of the binding nature of morality (or (C)) is fundamentally different in that it is not an empirical claim. So, the task that I will pursue is to bring out the features of (C) that empirical claims such as (A) and (B) do not have. Another way that this question can be set up is by referring directly to Kant’s first lengthy passage that contains the term ‘fact of reason’. Although he briefly uses the term already in 5:6, the first substantive reference to it can be found only in 5:31. Here is the passage in full: Consciousness of this fundamental law may be called a fact of reason because one cannot reason it out from antecedent data of reason, for example, from consciousness of freedom (since it is not antecedently given to us) and because it instead forces itself upon us of itself as a synthetic a priori proposition that is not based on any intuition, either pure or empirical, although it would be analytic if the freedom of the will were presupposed; but for this, as a positive concept, an intellectual intuition would be required, which certainly cannot be assumed here. However, in order to avoid misinterpretation in regarding this law as given, it must be noted carefully that it is not an empirical fact but the sole fact of pure reason which, by it, announces itself as originally lawgiving (sic volo, sic jubeo).10 Let me put into focus what will interest us in this passage. Since Kant is talking about the fact of reason as a “synthetic a priori proposition” (Satz), and that the clear referent of the ‘fact of reason’ is consciousness of [the] fundamental [moral] law, we can take him to refer, roughly, to (C), i.e., to the proposition: Humans have consciousness of the fundamental moral law. He then 10 5:31 (emphasis added) 6 goes on to say that “it is not an empirical fact but the sole fact of pure reason”. This seems to go well with the claim that this fact is a “synthetic a priori proposition”: proposition (C), Kant adds, is not an empirical claim (it is not synthetic a posteriori). Rather, it is a fact of “pure reason”, namely, it has a priori origin (or else it would not be pure), and it is synthetic since it is not merely analytically deduced from the claim that humans are free (in the positive sense). Examples in support of the fact of reason Now, before we turn to the question itself – Why is the fact of reason not empirical, after all? – let me trace Kant’s claim that we are conscious of the moral law to the evidence that he provides for it. The claim itself, he points out, “cannot be reasoned out from antecedent data of reason” (5:31). By this Kant specifically means that the claim that we are conscious of the moral law cannot be analytically deduced from another claim – the claim that we are free in the positive sense of ‘freedom.’ Nonetheless, the claim that we are conscious of the moral law needs to be contextually situated. (In this, it reminds us of Descartes cogito – the inference that, although it is justificatorily foundational, nonetheless is thoroughly explained by Descartes.) We are, Kant says, “immediately conscious of the moral law” (by which, I think, he means that we are immediately conscious of its binding nature), but, he adds, we are conscious of it “as soon as we draw up maxims of the will for ourselves” (5:29). Thus, by “immediate” I think Kant specifically means that our consciousness of the moral law is not mediated (or based on) our consciousness of freedom. But notice that for the consciousness of the moral law to reveal itself, we nonetheless first need to “draw up maxims of the will for ourselves”. And so 5:31 that introduces the claim that Kant calls ‘the fact of reason’ is preceded by Kant’s famous gallows example in 5:30 (which does just that – “draws up maxims of the will”.) The example has two 7 parts (the first of which is the gallows question), and it is the second part that will interest us here. Kant writes: Ask [someone] whether, if his prince demanded, on pain of [an] immediate execution, that he give false testimony against an honorable man whom the prince would like to destroy under a plausible pretext, he would consider it possible to overcome his love of life, however great it may be. He would perhaps not venture to assert whether he would do it or not, but he must admit without hesitation that it would be possible for him. He judges, therefore, that he can do something because he is aware that he ought to do it and cognizes freedom within him, which, without the moral law, would have remained unknown to him.11 Kant’s immediate concern here is to show what he calls “the order of concepts” in us, i.e., to ground the claim that moral law is ratio cognoscendi of freedom and not the other way around. This point (concerning how freedom is related to morality) does not interest us here. What is relevant, however, is Kant’s claim that the case of bearing false witness (or rather our awareness that it would be wrong to do so) attests to the fact that we are conscious of the binding nature of the moral law. Notice, of course, that our ability or even our willingness to obey the moral law is not what’s at issue here; rather, it is our awareness that it would be wrong to bear false witness. This awareness of our duty not to bear false witness might seem to be too content specific, and so it is. But what Kant has in mind, I think, is the general fact that in cases where morality sharply contrasts with other, non-moral concerns (such as one’s wish to preserve one’s life), our conscience is a moral “compass” (Compasse) (as he says in the Groundwork12) that allows us to discern what acting out of duty requires. The case where an agent is conflicted between a moral 11 12 5:30 (emphasis added). See e.g., 4:404. 8 obligation (not to bear false witness) and a non-moral inclination (to save his life), because of this conflict, attests to the fact we are conscious of the “moral law within” us (as Kant puts it in 5:161). And this – Kant says – is not an empirical fact about our volition, but a “sole fact of pure reason” instead. What I think makes Kant’s claim even more interesting (and more puzzling) is that he also refers to like thought-experiments as experiments. Consider what he says in 5:92. Here, Kant comments on the importance of separating doctrine of happiness from doctrine of morals, and says that, unlike geometers, philosophers have to rest content with “cognition through mere concepts” since it is impossible to ground this cognition in “constructions” (the way geometers do). But he adds that here, philosophy can distinguish between different grounds of willing by “setting up an experiment”. He says: [A]lmost like a chemist, [a philosopher] can at any time set up an experiment with every human practical reason […] namely, by adding the moral law (as a determining ground) to the empirically affected will (e.g., that of someone who would gladly lie because he can gain something by it). […] If a man who is otherwise honest (or who just this once puts himself only in thought in the place of an honest man) is confronted with the moral law in which he cognizes the worthlessness of a liar, his practical reason (in its judgment of what he ought to do) at once abandons the advantage [and] unites with what maintains in him respect for his own person (truthfulness).13 Here we have another clear example of what one morally ought to do – telling a lie is contrasted with truthfulness, and even in a liar, practical reason “unites” itself with the latter. It is worth noting that Kant says this experiment to be possible with “every human practical reason” (mit jedes Menschen praktishen Vernunft). Again, the though here is not that everyone acts morally; 13 5:92-3. 9 rather, it is that everyone recognizes that there is such thing as acting morally. In this case specifically, ‘acting morally’ means being truthful, but Kant presumably wants to make a more general claim to the point that humans recognize the binding nature of morality. Again, this claim – although it is manifested in an experiment (akin to like experiments in chemistry) – is not empirical; rather, it is a synthetic a priori proposition. Armed now with Kant’s statement from 5:31 along with his two cases – (i) of bearing false witness, and (ii) of truthfulness – we are in the position to unravel Kant’s claim that his fact of reason is a synthetic a priori proposition. What’s at stake? Arguably, it must be rather important for Kant to show that the fact of reason is not empirical. After all, if the claim that we are aware of the binding nature of the moral law were empirical, then its status in Kant’s theory would have been quite different. As it stands, the fact of reason (Kant claims) attests to the fact that we are bound by the moral law. This, in turn, attests to the fact that we are free in the positive sense of ‘freedom.’ Before the introduction of the fact of reason in section 7 of the second Critique (in 5:31) Kant’s aim was to show the reciprocal entailment between transcendental freedom and being subject to the “formal practical principle”. Sections 5 and 6 respectively argue that: (A) If a will is to be “determinable” by purely formal practical principles, then it must be “transcendentally free” (Problem I, 5:29). (B) If a will is transcendentally free, then only a formal practical principle can “determine it necessarily” (Problem II, 5:29). After Kant establishes that “freedom and unconditional practical law reciprocally imply each other” (5:29), he turns to the next question concerning which one has primacy in our “cognition”. 10 We are, he claims, “immediately conscious of the moral law”, and thus only secondarily (through our consciousness of the moral law) we are conscious of freedom as well. Now, if this consciousness of the moral law were an empirical fact about us, then (in Kant’s jargon) it would provide us with quid facti, i.e., with knowledge of what is the case. But answering the question of quid facti is not sufficient for answering the question concerning whether the proposition is also objectively valid, or the question of quid juri. Essentially, if Kant’s fact of reason is empirical, a further argument would be needed to show that our consciousness of the moral law is ‘legitimate’ or, in other words, that this empirically confirmed consciousness cannot be explained away or dismissed as a contingent feature of ours. Kant’s argument, however, has no second leg – no inquiry into the question whether the fact of reason is warranted. This means, I think, that he considered it to be fairly clear that the fact of reason is not empirical, but rather a synthetic a priori proposition. Lessons from transcendental psychology Since the status of the fact of reason has not yet been discussed in the literature, what I will draw on is the discussion of a parallel issue in his theoretical philosophy. There, Kant’s “transcendental psychology” has been long regarded as a topic worth considering. His arguments in the first Critique appear to have a peculiar status since they fall in-between empirical studies of the phenomenal self (which Kant would want to distance himself from) and the noumenal realm (of which we cannot have knowledge). And since Kant never tires to insist on the distinction between quid facti and quid juri, it is essential (for him and for proponents of his theory) to show that the normative conclusions of the first Critique, i.e., conclusions concerning the objective validity of e.g., the categories of understanding, are not derived from 11 empirical premises concerning our psychological makeup. What I propose to learn from the discussion of Kant’s transcendental psychology and of issues related to it, are the criteria for delineating between empirical and non-empirical, transcendental accounts. Let me point out that there are vast disagreements within this literature, and that I will not be concerned with discrepancies between various interpretations of Kant. What will interest me here is a possible position that can be put together based on these discussions, a position that deals with a more general question about the difference between the features of empirical and of transcendental accounts of the cognizing self. In particular, I hope that the lessons that we learn here will allow us to focus on the status of Kant’s fact of reason. Consider, for instance, the analysis that Paul Guyer develops in his “Psychology and the Transcendental Deduction”. The question that Guyer sets to answer is “whether Kant’s transcendental deduction of the pure concepts of the understanding is a psychological argument” and, more precisely, “whether it is damagingly psychological”.14 Kant would obviously want to avoid psychologism in his transcendental deductions – his argument is supposed to be philosophical and not psychological, and the new method he devises for answering the quid juri question is the transcendental method. But the transcendental method – a inference from features of our cognition to the necessary conditions for them – needs to starts with an acceptable account of the explananda, i.e., of the features of our cognition. The question about the status of the explananda becomes crucial since they themselves need to be more than empirical facts about our cognitive makeup. Guyer then argues that there are three features (or criteria) that an empirical account of cognition would have to have. And, he goes on to claim, since none of the three features are Paul Guyer, “Psychology and the Transcendental Deduction”, p. 47 (in Kant’s Transcendental Deductions, edited by Eckart Förster (Stanford University Press, 1989)). 14 12 applicable to Kant’s account of our cognitive makeup, Kant’s theory must not be empirical in the damaging sense of ‘empiricism’. The three criteria that Guyer identifies are the following: (1) “The premises of a psychological argument … must postulate the actual occurrence, indeed at moments that are at least in principle determinable, of specific forms of experience or inputs to the mind as well as of specific acts of mental processing of or reaction to these inputs” and “the character of the output of the psychological mechanism will be correlated to such features as the actual number of inputs or frequency of operation”.15 (2) “The assertions about the nature of the mental acts of input and processing that constitute the premises of psychological arguments are contingent rather than necessary truths”.16 Put slightly differently, “psychological premises are ones to which there are conceivable alternatives. They cannot be truths entailed directly by the concept of human nature, nor even by any more general concept, such as that of a “cognitive system”, but must, like the more particular propositions they support or explain, be “matters of fact””.17 (3) “Psychological premises are ordinarily assumed to be discoverable only by some empirical method, even if that method be as easy as introspection of ourselves and observation of the manners of others”.18 Using this set as a starting point, we can say that an empirical account is methodologically different from a philosophical one. I take it, (1) and (3) can be reduced to the same idea: an empirical account is based on inductive generalization from a set of occurrences a, b, c, etc., 15 Guyer, 54. Guyer, 54 (emphasis added). 17 Guyer, 55. 18 Guyer, 55 (emphasis added). 16 13 where a, b, c, etc., are particular events (I think that this is what Guyer means by “actual occurrence”, etc. in (1)). The last point is important since experience in general is essential for any account of cognition – psychological and philosophical alike. An a priori account of cognition would not be independent from all experience; after all, as Kant puts it in B1: “all our cognition commences with experience, yet it does not on that account arise from experience”.19 Empirical account (borrowing this distinction) would not only “commence with experience” but also would “arise from experience”. A philosophical account – although it would start with experience as its explanandum – would not “arise from it”. Returning to the question concerning the method of an empirical account, then, we can say that it is essentially inductive, since it starts with particular cases a, b, c, etc., which are the data of either introspection or observation (or both), and it would ground a conclusion based on what is learnt from this sample. And, as Guyer points out, “the character of the output of the psychological mechanism will be correlated to such features as the actual number of inputs or frequency of operation”. In other words, an inductive inference would be all the stronger, the more cases we would consider and the more representative our sample would be. This method, as Guyer says in (2), is a method of acquiring knowledge of “matters of fact” rather than of e.g., deducting our knowledge from the concept of a human being. That is to say (as he puts it), “the premises of psychological arguments are contingent rather than necessary truths”.20 (This latter In B2, Kant goes on to say: “by a priori cognitions [we will understand] not those that occur independently of this or that experience, but rather those that occur absolutely independently of all experience” (and he then goes on to add that there is a difference between a priori and pure, e.g., ‘Every alteration has a cause’ is a priori but not pure, since ‘alteration’ itself is an empirical concept and a pure cognition has nothing empirical with it). I think that B2 is consistent with what I have to say, though, since my point is only that the question concerning a priori vs. empirical cognitions arises insofar as we have cognitions at all, i.e., we start from the fact of experience in general and ask what the necessary conditions for the possibility of experience are. 20 I have reservations with the way that Guyer puts this last point; or at least, I would make a weaker claim that this. While for Kant and for his predecessors necessity is a “mark by means of which we can securely distinguish a pure cognition from an empirical one”, I am not sure that the inverse holds. That is, from the fact that a cognition C is not necessary we cannot conclude that it is empirical. And since an empirical method (induction) would fail to produce a cognition with a mark of necessity, it would not follow that the truth is contingent in the sense that it 19 14 way to put it, though, seems to me to be parasitic on the statement concerning the methodology of an empirical inquiry. In other words, the test of conceivability, I think, is actually a poor guide to settling the issue. A more reliable way to get to the idea of necessity as opposed to contingency of our results would be to look at the methods of inquiry and not to the question whether a feature of ours could be other than what it is.) But if not through observation, introspection, and generalization from given occurrences, in what way are we to gather ‘data’ concerning the features of our cognitive makeup? Although experience is still the starting point of a philosophical inquiry, we are keeping in mind that (i) it is experience in general we are talking about when we do philosophy rather than psychology and that (ii) we are reflecting on the features of this experience. In his “Empirical, Rational, and Transcendental Psychology: Psychology as Science and as Philosophy”, Gary Hatfield echoes the point made by Guyer.21 Hatfield aims to spell out the features of transcendental psychology and, more specifically, to show that it is not empirical (and so his discussion is related to Guyer’s analysis that we just looked into). Hatfield’s considered view on the status of Kant’s project is the following: Even in arguing for his transcendental philosophy Kant surely must appeal to experience to ground some basic claims, for example, that we experience in space and time, that we are finite intelligences, that we have some sensations and feelings. But this sort of “empirical” data was accepted even by Crusius, the most avowedly aprioristic metaphysician of Kant’s time. And reasonably so. If it were otherwise, any could be otherwise (or, as Guyer puts it, that C has “conceivable alternatives”). At best, from the fact that C results from an empirical investigation, we can conclude that further proof is required (and might be possible) to show that C is a priori. (This is, again, the quid facti vs. quid juri distinction at work.) 21 Gary Hatfield, “Empirical, Rational, and Transcendental Psychology: Psychology as Science and as Philosophy” in Cambridge Companion to Kant, edited by Paul Guyer (Cambridge University Press, 1992). 15 sort of reflection on human experience whatsoever would count as “empirical”, effectively rendering all philosophy empirical by stipulation. For the purpose of reading and interpreting Kant, and for many other purposes, we are well advised to distinguish between treating reflection on ordinary experience as a minimal starting point for philosophy and adopting an empirical approach when formulating and confirming explanatory theses in philosophy.22 Here, what I take to be significant is the emphasis on “reflection on ordinary human experience”. A philosophical argument of the variety that interests us here starts with a fairly noncontroversial set of cases, judgments, or propositions about the world that we make all the time. How often or how reliably we come up with these is not really what’s at issue (as it would be with an empirical investigation). Rater, our cases or samples will be representative enough in that any set of cases, etc. of a certain type would do. Thus, in Kant’s speculative realm, any cognition would do since all cognition has the same fundamental features. Similarly, common moral judgments that we make would allow us to conclude that humans are aware of the binding nature of morality. (Or so Kant believes it to be the case.) Why the fact of reason is synthetic a priori If we now look at the passages surrounding Kant’s discussion of the fact of reason, we can notice just that: Kant claims that the fact of reason (i.e., that we are aware of the binding nature of the moral law) is evident from reflection on our common judgments when it comes to ethical issues. Let me give a couple of examples where Kant adopts this approach. Consider what he says e.g., in 5:32, 5:36, and 5:91-2 (although in general, I would claim, consulting our common judgments 22 Hatfield, 216 (emphasis added). 16 is one of the leitmotifs of the second Critique). Right after Kant first introduces the fact of reason (in 5:31), he comments on it in the following way: The fact [of reason] mentioned above is undeniable. One need only analyze the judgment that people pass on the lawfulness of their actions in order to find that, whatever inclination may say to the contrary, their reason, incorruptible and selfconstrained, always holds the maxim of the will in an action up to the pure will, that is, to itself inasmuch as it regards itself as a priori practical.23 We see that Kant is here introducing the method of “analyzing judgments that people pass” – the tool that will prove both useful and (as we will soon see) indispensible for the argument in the Analytic. Here (in 5:32), the fact of reason is said to be grounded on an analysis such as this. In particular, I think, what becomes evident from this analysis is that people without fault distinguish between morality and self-love. And so in 5:36 (again, appealing to the data of common moral cognition), Kant will highlight this aspect of our moral judgments. After introducing the categorical imperative of morality into the second Critique (in 5:31), and after claiming that we can also see that humans regard themselves to be bound by it (in 5:31-2), Kant goes on to emphasize that there is a sharp boundary between morality and self-love. He goes over several features that show that moral principles are quite heterogeneous from counsels of prudence, and he reiterates that the difference between morality and self-love is apparent “even to the most common human beings” [für den gemeinsten Menschen vernehmlich]. And so, for instance, in 5:36 Kant says: “So distinctly and sharply drawn are the boundaries of morality and self-love that even the most common eye [das gemeinste Auge] cannot fail to distinguish whether something belongs to the one or the other”. (The details of Kant’s series of claims in this section 23 5:32 (emphasis added). 17 do not interest us here; what is important is the appeal to our common ethical judgments as the stratum that if not grounds, then surely anchors our moral theory.) Finally, in 5:91-2, Kant explicitly points out that a project such as his second Critique can be “justified” by appeal to our common ethical judgments. The principles are the first “data” of a pure theory: an empirical ethical theory that starts with the sensibly determined notion of the good has a less sophisticated structure, but a pure doctrine of morals that cannot help itself to a sensibly determined starting point has no other way to get off the ground but through considering reason’s principles. When it then comes to answering the question whether these principles are applicable to our actual volition, the justificational strategy, Kant says, is to consider our common understanding of morality. Thus, in 5:91-2 he writes: “the justification of moral principles as principles of a pure reason could also be carried out very well and with sufficient certainty by a mere appeal to the judgments of common human understanding”. Furthermore, the feeling of respect for the law that serves as a clear indication of moral principle rather than a principle of self-love, “is made known so saliently and so prominently that no one, not even the most common human understanding [der gemeinste Menschenverstand], can fail to see at once in an example presented to him, that he can indeed be advised by empirical grounds of volition to follow their charms but that he can never be expected to obey anything but the pure practical law of reason alone” (5:92). (Notice the appeal to the “most common understanding” here.) Again, setting aside the details of the arguments in 5:32, 5:36 and 5:92, let me point out Kant’s characteristic appeal to what we can now call common moral judgments in general, i.e., to the general features of how we engage the world practically. This appeal, I think, is akin to the appeal to experience in general made by transcendental philosophy in the theoretical realm. And much like Hatfield stresses, the tone of this appeal is not empirical in any meaningful sense 18 of “empiricism”. And although the starting point (in some sense) is experience, the way that we deal with experience is methodologically not empirical. Reflection on our common moral judgments has to do with discerning the structure of our faculties in virtue of which our experience is what it is. Now, in the second Critique Kant does not complete the argument in this way. That is, he does not trace the features of our experience explicitly to the structure of our faculties. Perhaps, he holds the features of our common judgments to be self-evident and requiring no further explanation.24 Here, in particular, I am talking about our capacity to see the distinction between moral principles and non-moral counsels of prudence (or self-love, as Kant puts it). The examples that he provides have to do with our capacity to draw the contrast between the moral ought and the concerns for one’s happiness. But after introducing the fact of reason in 5:31, in 5:32 we find a discussion that, I think, comes very close to an explanation of why it is that humans see so clearly the distinction between morality and self-love. 5:32 contains a Remark to a Corollary (to §7): §7 introduces the “fundamental law of pure practical reason” (in a formulation that closely resembles FUL), and its Corollary says that “pure reason is practical of itself alone and gives (to the human being) a universal law which we call the moral law” (5:31). And so the transition from §7 to its Corollary has to do with moving from the law of pure practical reason in general to its specifically human manifestation as an imperative. The 24 In some sense, I think that this is exactly the reason for the lack of explicit justification of the fact of reason. I think that Kant was certain that humans are aware of the binding nature of morality, and that (more specifically) by ‘morality’ he understood the necessary, universal, etc. principles that command us to φ! (unconditionally). Karl Ameriks in his “The Practical Foundation of Philosophy in Kant, Fichte, and After” puts the more general claim concerning Kant’s presuppositions this way: “Kant would often appeal to common claims that he (naively, we would now say) assumed no sane person of his time would put in real doubt. Such claims included the fundamentals of mathematics and logic, the general fact that there is “experience”, that is, a warranted determination of empirical objects, and also the fact that we acknowledge categorical demands of morality. Kant understood transcendental philosophy to be an a priori account of these assumptions, an account that would appreciate the metaphysical complexities of alternative views, and that would offer its own framework as the best way “to save the phenomena” and to keep people from abandoning common sense in the face of modern philosophical perplexities”. (See Ameriks’s “The Practical Foundation of Philosophy in Kant, Fichte, and After” in The Reception of Kant's Critical Philosophy: Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, ed. by Sally Sedgwick (Cambridge University Press, 2000).) 19 Remark to the Corollary is dedicated to the distinction between our (at best pure) will and what Kant calls the “holy will”, i.e., “such a will as would not be capable of any maxim conflicting with the moral law” (5:32). Kant explains that only for the human will (as an imperfect will) the moral law is an imperative (not merely a law) of reason. He says of human beings: The moral law is for them an imperative that commands categorically because the law is unconditional; the relation of such a will to this law is dependence under the name of obligation, which signifies a necessitation, though only by reason and its objective law, to an action which is called duty because a choice that is pathologically affected (though not thereby determined, hence still free) brings with it a wish arising from subjective causes, because of which it can often be opposed to the pure objective determining ground and thus needs a resistance of practical reason. […] In the supremely self-sufficient intelligence, choice is rightly represented as incapable of any maxim that could not at the same time be objectively a law.25 The contrast that Kant is drawing now is between human volition and holy volition. For our purposes, we need to focus on the clause that describes our capacity to choose as “pathologically affected” but at the same time not necessarily “determined” in this way. Our will therefore is pulled into two directions: on the one hand, there are “subjective causes” (inclinations) at work here, and on the other hand, our will recognizes the binding nature of the objective moral law.26 25 5:32 (emphasis added). We find similar analysis of our pathologically affected and yet free choice in The Metaphysics of Morals. Here, Kant says: “The very concept of duty is already the concept of a necessitation (constraint) of free choice through the law. […] Such constraint does not apply to rational beings as such (there could also be holy ones) but rather to human beings, rational natural beings, who are unholy enough that pleasure can induce them to break the moral law, even though they recognize its authority; and even when they do obey the law, they do it reluctantly (in the face of opposition from their inclinations), and it is in this that such constraint properly consists”. He then adds (in a footnote): “Yet if a human being looks at himself objectively […] he finds that as a moral being he is also holy enough to break the inner [moral] law reluctantly; for there is no human being so depraved as not to feel an opposition to breaking it and an abhorrence of himself in the face of which he has to constrain himself [to break the law]” (6:379-80; emphasis added). I am using Mary J. Gregor’s translation here (in Kant: Practical Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, 1996). 26 20 Perhaps it merits a mention that on the other side of the spectrum, Kant puts what he calls the “animal choice” (arbitrium brutum) – the capacity to choose that “can be determined only by inclination (sensible impulse, stimulus)”.27 And so there are three types of volition (or choosing) possible: (1) In a holy being, the choice is determined only by the moral law. (2) In a human being, the choice is determined either by the moral law or by inclination. (3) In non-rational being, the choice is determined only by inclination. With this distinction in place, we can see that humans are the only beings who are capable of feeling the pull of both morality and sensible causes. And the examples that Kant provides in order to show that we are conscious of the binding nature of morality are the cases where we are at a crossroads and where the distinction between morality and self-love is manifested especially clearly. Thus, faced with the choice of “giving false testimony” and “immediate execution”, one acutely feels the duality of practical principles: one understands that it is wrong to give false testimony, but one also feels a strong inclination to preserve one’s life. And so any case where the agent perceives this duality will reveal to us (the philosophers) that the agent considers herself to be subject to the moral law. If this is the way ultimately to reconstruct Kant’s argument, then it can be shown that the phenomenology of our experience, i.e., the fact that we are aware of the binding nature of the moral law, is grounded on the structure of our faculties.28 In particular, it is based on the fact 27 The Metaphysics of Morals, 6:213. In “The Fact of Reason: Kant’s Passage to Ordinary Moral Knowledge”, Pavel Łuków makes a similar point. He says that humans have “dual citizenship” – one in the empirical and one in the noumenal worlds, and that the fact of reason is a “phenomenological consequence of having to take both standpoints [the empirical and the moral]” (214). (See Pavel Łuków, “The Fact of Reason: Kant’s Passage to Ordinary Moral Knowledge”, Kant-Studien 84 (1993), pp. 204-221.) In my paper, I am reluctant to put the point in this way, since I do not want to claim (yet) that the moral law has its seat in the noumenal realm (although, of course, it does). All Kant needs to show at this leg of the argument is that we are conscious of the binding nature of a moral law; the rest of the second Critique argues what the nature of this moral law must be, etc. 28 21 that we are both “unholy enough” and “holy enough” (as Kant puts it in his “Doctrine of Virtue”) since we are subject to both the commands of morality and the demands of our sensible nature. Recall, that I said earlier that this rout of justification – the rout that traces the features of our experience (in this case, our moral judgments) to the structure of our faculties – would avoid the problem of empiricism. If this rout is what Kant has in mind, then his claim that humans are aware of the binding nature of morality would acquire a status of an a priori claim. That is, Kant is not appealing to our introspection and then generalizing the results of what such introspection would reveal to a common understanding. Rather, his false testimony example is a case-study in the structure of our common moral cognition; and this case-study can be part of the transcendental argument concerning the necessary conditions for the possibility of the fact of reason. Again, this possibility has to do with the structure of our faculties (in this case our will). Arguably, at this point Kant’s overall argument to the conclusion that morality rests on the categorical imperative of reason travels a full circle. What I have in mind (but what I cannot adequately cover at present) is that Kant’s Groundwork supplies the argument to the conclusion that our common rational moral cognition attests to the fact that the moral law is none other than the categorical imperative. The second Critique does not provide the analysis of our common moral judgments, although it does point to them in support of the claim that we are aware of the binding nature of morality. Section I of the Groundwork, on the other hand, does just that: it provides a detailed analysis of our common rational moral cognition that culminates (at the end of the section) in the pronouncement that the ‘supreme principle of morality’ is the following: “I ought never to conduct myself except so that I could also will that my maxim become a universal law” (4:402). 22 Conclusion We started with Kant’s claim that the fact of reason is a synthetic a priori proposition and his warning not to take this Faktum to be empirical; the fact of reason, he says, is “the sole fact of pure reason” (5:31). I argued that, given the structure of the second Critique, Kant is quite right in issues this warning, and that it is unfortunate that he does not spell out an argument that would sufficiently ground his claim. I said that there exists a similar exegetical worry with respect to his transcendental psychology – part of his corpus that must belong to philosophy and yet that is dangerously close to psychology. My hope was to learn from what I consider to be successful defenses of Kant on that front – from the accounts that spell out the differences in methodology between psychology and transcendental philosophy. The key difference (I think) is the contrast between psychology’s inductive method and philosophy’s method of reflection on experience. I then argued that Kant seems to be ‘reflecting’ on the features of our common moral cognition throughout the second Critique in that he frequently appeals to the ethical judgments that we make (‘we’ here is ‘most common human understanding’, not philosophers, of course). And the key salient feature of these judgments is the sharp distinction between morality and self-love. Finally, I made an attempt to explain (on behalf of Kant) in virtue of what we acutely perceive this distinction: I argued that, in comparison to holy and animal volition, human capacity to choose is uniquely pulled into two directions (toward living up to the moral ought and toward satisfying the demands of our sensible nature). This duality, then, as a condition sine qua non, grounds our consciousness of the moral law, and since this duality is a necessary feature of our volition, the phenomenological consequence of it must be an a priori fact as well. 23