THE UNDERDETERMINATION OF THE MEANING OF LOGICAL WORDS BY RULES OF INFERENCE Elia Zardini LanCog Philosophy Centre University of Lisbon eliazardini@gmail.com Inferentialism about a class of expressions C is the view that the meaning of any expression member of C is constituted by the rules of inference associated with that expression. Global inferentialism is inferentialism about all the atomic expressions of the language. Even though with its own defenders (see Brandom [1994]), global inferentialism is wildly implausible: in the 16th century, the meaning of the English word ‘gold’ was arguably already different from the meaning the word would have had if used by a population whose inferential dispositions were exactly the same as those of the English population at that time, but whose environment were occupied by a gold-like substance whose atomic number is not 79. Hence, many inferentialists have retreated to the weaker claim (henceforth, ‘logical inferentialism’) that it is the meaning of the logical words that is constituted by the rules of inference associated with them (Tennant [1987], Read [2000]). While more plausible, logical inferentialism is still a very controversial view, which has crucially served as the meaning-theoretic foundation for a variety of recent attempts at accounting for our apparent a priori knowledge of logic (see e.g. Boghossian [1996]). The paper will present and discuss what I call ‘the underdetermination challenge’ to logical inferentialism. The challenge consists in arguing that some logical words are such that no set of formal, recursively enumerable rules of inference can completely fix their meaning. I will substantiate the challenge by looking at four broad classes of logical words. The first class concerns monadic intensional operators. For example, the modal operator ‘it is necessary that’ has actually been shown by philosophical reflection to be ambiguous among different readings (e.g. conceptual necessity, metaphysical necessity, nomological necessity), yet no plausible reading of it can be uniquely characterised by a set of rules of inference that may be associated with that operator, for, in all these cases, the associated rules of inference will yield a logic in the vicinity of S5. Also, every rule of inference that is sound with respect to (any reading of) it will also be sound with respect to the non-synonymous temporal operator ‘it will always be the case that’, and vice versa. A similar situation arises for epistemic operators like ‘it is certain that’ and ‘it is provable that’ and for determinacy operators like ‘it is definitely the case that’ and ‘it is settled that’, which pairwise share exactly the same rules of inference in spite of their being nonsynonymous. The second class concerns conditionals. I will briefly rehearse the reasons for thinking that indicative conditionals, just like subjunctive ones, are not captured by either material implication or by any standard “relevant” implication (since even the weakest standard “relevant” implications validate for instance transitivity). In the framework of conditional logics (see Chellas [1980]), I will then argue that no rule of inference actually seems to discriminate between indicative and subjunctive conditionals: if a rule of inference is clearly valid for the subjunctive conditional (like reflexivity), it also is clearly valid for the indicative conditional; if a rule of inference is clearly not valid for the subjunctive conditional (like monotonicity), it also is clearly not valid for the indicative conditional; if a rule of inference is neither clearly valid nor clearly not valid for the subjunctive conditional (like conjunction in the consequent), it also is neither clearly valid nor clearly not valid for the indicative conditional. The third class concerns quantifiers. I will argue that no inferentialistically acceptable rule of inference can distinguish objectual quantifiers from substitutional ones. Moreover, more complex, generalised quantifiers (for example, cardinality quantifiers such as ‘there are infinitely many’ and ‘most’), as well as higher-order quantifiers, demonstrably lack a set of sound and complete recursively enumerable rules of inference. I will show how these incompleteness phenomena can be used to generate another yet another version of the underdetermination challenge. The fourth class concerns the identity predicate. Drawing from examples from graph theory and symmetric universes, I will argue that, for many languages and domains, the usual rules of inference based (among others) on the indiscernibility of identicals fail uniquely to pick out identity (understood as the strongest universally reflexive relation— that is, as the relation that everything has to itself and nothing else) as opposed to weaker congruence relations. I will close by offering a tentative diagnosis of why logical inferentialism is subject to the underdetermination challenge. Just like non-logical words, logical words often have a quite specific content that is primarily grounded in and grasped by either paradigmatic applications to particular cases or by informal elucidations of the property they express. In both cases, the point of entry of meaning is situated on the world-word side rather than on the word-word side which is favoured by logical inferentialism and which is constituted by inferential transitions relying on formal, recursively enumerable rules. Contrary to what logical inferentialism requires, there is thus no reason to expect that a word that is primarily endowed with content by paradigmatic applications to particular cases or by informal elucidations of the property they express will exhibit any general inferential connection to other parts of language, let alone uniquely characterising ones. REFERENCES Paul Boghossian [1996], ‘Analyticity Reconsidered’, Nous 30, pp. 360–391. Robert Brandom [1994], Making It Explicit, Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA. Brian Chellas [1980], Modal Logic. An Introduction, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Stephen Read [2000], ‘Harmony and Autonomy in Classical Logic’, Journal of Philosophical Logic 29, pp. 123–154. Neil Tennant [1987], Anti-Realism and Logic, Clarendon Press, Oxford.