Is there identity of person between a living human being and a separated soul? Christopher Martin 249 Studia Theologica VI, 4/2008, 249 - 253 1. Theological preamble “Personal identity” is a question which in secular philosophy, analytical philosophy in particular, is treated as unproblematical, although of course there are differing answers given. An attempt to develop the question, however, in the context of faith, leads to problems. I don’t know whether my problem – is there identity of person between the living human being and the separated soul? – is properly a philosophical question or a theological question. Thomas Aquinas, whose ideas I shall be exploring, clearly treats it as a philosophical question in the Summa, but we have the authority of the later Cajetan to support us if we decide that it is a theological question. Moreover, in the Commentary on I Corinthians 15,, if that text is authentic, we find Thomas himself apparently doubting whether the immortality of the soul can be proved independently of faith in the resurrection1. I shall treat “person” and “self” as synonymous, and treat them both as clearly instantiated in our use of personal pronouns. I want to suggest that for St Thomas there is not and cannot be a concept of “personal identity”, especially when looking at the personal identity of a human person across death. Trying to develop one seems to lead to a string of heterodox views. In a nutshell, St Thomas maintains that the separated soul is not the self – “anima mea non est ego”. He uses this phrase twice in his commentary on the first epistle to the Corinthians, Chapter 152. He also maintains, in the Summa, the soul of St Peter is not St Peter: that when we say “Sancte Petre, ora pro nobis”, we are speaking loosely. We call St Peter’s soul by the name that he had when he merited to pray for us, during his lifetime, and in order to proclaim our faith in the future resurrection, when St Peter will be St Peter again 3. that it is not strictly correct to say that St Peter is in Heaven. This teaching seems fully in accord with that of the Council of Vienne, which stated that the rational soul is the form of the body. In I Cor. C. 15 l. 2: “[Q]uia si negetur resurrectio corporis, non de facili, imo difficile est sustinere immortalitatem animae.” Also, In I Cor. C. 15 l. 4: “Nec obstat, si dicatur quod anima separata praemiatur, quia, ut probatum est supra, non posset probari quod anima esset immortalis.” 2 In I Cor. C. 15 l. 2: “Alio modo quia constat quod homo naturaliter desiderat salutem sui ipsius, anima autem cum sit pars corporis hominis, non est totus homo, et anima mea non est ego; unde licet anima consequatur salutem in alia vita, non tamen ego vel quilibet homo.” 3 S. Th. IIª-IIae q. 83 a. 11 obj. 5 Praeterea, anima Petri non est Petrus. Si ergo animae sanctorum pro nobis orarent quandiu sunt a corpore separatae, non deberemus interpellare sanctum Petrum ad orandum pro nobis, sed animam eius. Cuius contrarium Ecclesia facit. Non ergo sancti, ad minus ante resurrectionem, pro nobis orant. Ad 5 Ad quintum dicendum quod quia sancti viventes meruerunt ut pro nobis orarent, ideo eos invocamus nominibus quibus hic vocabantur, quibus etiam nobis magis innotescunt. Et iterum propter fidem resurrectionis insinuandam, sicut legitur Exod. III, ego sum Deus Abraham, et cetera. Here St Thomas clearly seems to accept the premiss of the objection, that “Anima Petri non est Petrus”. 1 Is there identity of person between a living human being and a separated soul? Christopher Martin 250 However, I have against me here (and apparently against St Thomas, and even, perhaps, against the Council of Vienne) a letter of the Sacred Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, dated 17th May 1979. The crucial section of this seems to say that “the Church affirms the survival and subsistence after death of a spiritual element which is endowed with consciousness and will, so that the human “self” subsists. The Church uses the word “soul, consecrated by Scripture and Tradition, to designate this element”4. I have to say that I find this passage difficult to understand, or to believe. It seems to affirm the existence of a “self” – a word put into quotation marks, and thus presumably being used as a technical term – after death, and then glosses this usage with the word “soul”, drawn, as the letter says, from Scripture and Tradition. Surely in a statement of the Church’s teaching the word used in Scripture and Tradition should come first? And what is the technical “self” which the letter affirms to exist? Perhaps I am being distracted by the fact that the editio princeps of this letter is in French, when I say I suspect that a Cartesian sense is being given to the word. Surely the Cartesian self has no place in an affirmation of the Church’s belief? Where is there room here for the doctrine of the Council of Vienne, which says nothing of the “moi” or “ego”? Perhaps I am being too suspicious. Perhaps all the use of the word “self” means is that I shall live after death, when my separated soul survives my death. But this is already enough to seem to contradict St Thomas. In any case, I submit my discussion here to the judgement of the Church. I only intend to discuss the implications of what St Thomas says, on the supposition that what St Thomas says is in fact consonant with the faith of the Church. It is perhaps worth noticing that the Catechism of the Catholic Church (1992 and 1997) does not pick up on the content of this letter of the Sacred Congregation for the doctrine of the Faith. Also we should note that for St Thomas the identity of a human person is simply the identity of a human being, and in that case it is clear that a separated soul is not the same human person (because it is not a human being) as the living human being whose soul it was and will again be at the resurrection. 2. Personal identity “as such” A possible way of approach to the question of the identity of the human person would be to try and establish what is personal identity as such, and then apply the notion to the human person. Indeed, it might be thought that the best way of approach would be to first examine identity as such, then apply it to the identity of the person, and then apply it to the human person. I do not think that either of these methods has any value. There is a discussion within analytic philosophy about identity as such: most authors (for example Wiggins) regard it as an absolute notion, while Geach (practically on his own) regards it as a relative notion – for a to be identical with b, a must be the same F as b, for some reading of F. I don’t know whether Geach has theological notions definitely in mind, but there would seem to be a clear Trinitarian reason for the position he maintains. SCDF Lettre, 17-V-1979 “L’Eglise affirme la survivance et la subsistance après la mort d’un élément spirituel qui est doué de conscience et de volonté en sorte que le « moi » humain subsiste. Pour désigner cet élément, l’Eglise emploie le mot « âme », consacré par l’usage de l’Ecriture et de la Tradition”. The editio princeps is in French. 4 Is there identity of person between a living human being and a separated soul? Christopher Martin 251 One of the key notions tied up in that of identity is Leibniz’s Law: if a and b are identical, then everything which is true of a must also be true of b. But while a Christian wants to maintain that the Son is identical with the Father, a Christian also has to affirm that while the Father begets, the son does not beget. Further, a Christian must say that while the Son suffers, the Father does not suffer. If we hold a relative notion of identity, there is no difficulty here: we can say that the Father is the same God as the Son, but not the same person. As one of the Fathers of the church put it, the three persons of the blessed Trinity are allos kai allos kai allos, but not allo kai allo kai allo – someone and someone and someone, but not something and something and something. Even apart from theological considerations, I think that Thomas would agree with Geach here (or that Geach is agreeing with Thomas). For Thomas, we know that ens et idem convertuntur; and we also know that quodlibet esse est secundum formam aliquam. From this it would follow that omne idem est secundum formam aliquam: thus, identity is relative. So much for the notion of identity “as such”: what about the identity of a person “as such”? This notion is, I think, almost equally problematic. Consider the identity of a game “as such”: is there any such thing? Is there, to put it another way, any relevant “such”? I would say not: different games are identified or made to be the game that they are by different criteria. For example, the identity of some games require identity of players, while this does not seem to be the case for other games. Some games are limited in time; others are not. And so on. Hence there is no such thing as the identity of a game “as such”: only the identities of different games of different kinds. (We might make a parenthesis here on the distinction between diachronic identity, identity through time, and synchronic identity, identity at a given time. These two may easily come apart: in a living thing, diachronic identity depends on form, while synchronic identity depends on matter. It is perhaps worth noting that for the divine persons there is no diachronic identity, as they do not exist in time. Perhaps the same is true of angelic persons, who are also not in time, thought there are or have been subject to some change.) To a Thomist these remarks might suggest that identity is an analogous notion, which may very well be true, but it may not help us very much. It is fairly clear that the prime analogates in the order of being are the divine persons, but I would also maintain that they are the prime analogates in the order of knowledge as well. The notion of “person”, which is not to be found in Greek philosophy, was forged in Trinitarian, theological disputes. But if the divine persons are the prime analogates in both the order of being and in that of knowledge, and they are also unknowable by us in this life, the use of the idea of “analogy” here seems to be of little helpfulness. I want to suggest, then, that any time we try to discuss the notion of personal identity we should always explicitly relativise the notion: we should discuss the identity of a divine person, of an angelic person, or of a human person. This is not an ad hoc proposal: there are many notions which do not determine criteria of identity, and whose identity we Is there identity of person between a living human being and a separated soul? Christopher Martin 252 cannot therefore discuss. We cannot discuss the identity of a thing or of an event, though there may be many things or events – rivers, mountains, lumps of gold, statues, words, kisses, blows – whose identity we can discuss. I wish now to discuss St Thomas’s view that the identity of a human person is the identity of a human animal, that is, of a form in matter. From this it follows immediately that the separated human soul, which is not a human animal, is not a human person or self. Granted, as St Thomas insists, that the human being, and therefore the human person, will live again after the resurrection: what happens, if we may put it that way, in between? What, to put it another way, are the criteria of identity across death? St Thomas’s eschatology maintains that all that remains of the human person between death and the resurrection is the intellectual soul, which he insists more than once may be called by the name of the person, though improperly5. This means that all that continues to exist, of the previously living human being, are certain thoughts. But how can they be our thoughts if we do not at that time exist? Or, if one objects to the phrase “at that time”, one might say, how can these thoughts, which are thought between my death and my resurrection, be my thoughts if between my death and my resurrection I, this human being, do not exist? To sharpen the problem, we might point out that we say that between my death and the resurrection I will have undergone the particular judgement. But how can it be that I will have been judged – future perfect tense – when there appears to be no future in which I will exist? – simple future. What, we might ask, is the subject of my soul’s incorporeal thought? To say “my soul” is just to repeat the problem. Is it a person? A person is the subject of certain (rational) actions – it is because we know that the table is incapable of such actions that we know that it is not a person. But what are the criteria of identity for such a subject of such actions? It begins to look as if, since there will be actions of the relevant kind, there must be a subject, and the subject must be a person, and that subject will not be I. Who, what then will it be? 5 Super Rom., cap. 7 l. 3. Prosequamur ergo declarando qualiter haec verba et sequentia diversimode possunt utroque modo exponi, quamvis secunda expositio melior sit. Quod ergo dicitur primo ego autem etc. sic intelligendum est, ut ly ego pro ratione hominis intelligatur, quae est principale in homine; unde videtur unusquisque homo esse sua ratio vel suus intellectus, sicut civitas videtur esse rector civitatis, ita ut quod ille facit, civitas facere videatur. Also Super Sent., lib. 2 d. 18 q. 2 a. 1 ad 1. Ad primum ergo dicendum, quod locutio illa est synecdochica; ponitur enim pars principalis, scilicet anima, pro toto homine; et hic modus loquendi consuetus est in sacra Scriptura, et apud philosophos; unde philosophus dicit 9 Ethic. quod totus homo dicitur intellectus, per modum quo etiam tota civitas dicitur rector civitatis; Super Sent., lib. 3 d. 22 q. 1 a. 1 ad 7. Ad septimum dicendum, quod philosophus loquitur figurative, et non proprie: unde ipse dicit, quod ita homo dicitur intellectus sicut civitas rex, quia totum quod est in civitate, dependet ex voluntate regis, and Quaestio disputata de anima, a. 12 ad 13. Ad decimumtertium dicendum quod homo dicitur intellectus esse, quia intellectus dicitur id quod est potius in homine, sicut civitas dicitur esse rector civitatis; non tamen hoc dictum est eo quod essentia animae sit ipsa potentia intellectus. Is there identity of person between a living human being and a separated soul? Christopher Martin 253 Rational actions – thoughts, acts of will – are identified in one way by their content. But this seems to be useless here, since it would seem that in this sense two people can have the same thought. Actions are specified by their end; rational actions are specified by an end rationally grasped. But for the angels and the blessed this specification would be one and the same. The only other way we can identify thoughts and differentiate them from others is by their subject – but this seems to bring us round in a very tight vicious circle. We cannot say that we identify persons by their thoughts and then say that we identify thoughts by the persons who think them. Let us imagine this problem solved for a moment, and suggest that separated souls will have sufficiently different mental, intellectual, propositional contents to distinguish them. Even St Michael and St Gabriel, we may imagine, may have subtly different mental histories, so to speak. And if this is true of the angels, as it may be, a fortiori it could be true of human separated souls, who will have had different mental histories, and thus mental contents. We are still left with the question, who or what has this mental history or content? Obviously, according to St Thomas, it will not be a human being, and thus not a human person. Will it then be another person? Or even a person of a different kind, and thus a fortiori another person? This sounds fantastic and clearly contrary to the mind of the Church. If what survives my death is a different person from myself, then it will be a different person from myself who is judged and perhaps damned for what I have done. Perhaps the absurdity of this position is what inspired the letter of the Sacred Congregation for the doctrine of the Faith. A possible compromise would be to say that there is as much identity between myself and my separated soul as it is possible for there to be between a human person and a separated soul. Or we might take a hard logical line and say that it is senseless to speak of there being identity between a living human being and a separated soul. This has the following advantage: that if it is senseless to speak of identity, then it is senseless to speak of difference. This not mean a retreat into agnosticism. It rests on the facts (if they are facts) that the identity of a human being is the identity of an animal, while the identity of a separated soul is the identity of its mental contents. We may also say, I think, that a human being and a separated soul can have identical or significantly overlapping mental contents. The fantasy of my separated soul being a different person from myself derives from the fantasy that it is the same person of myself: and both, I want to suggest, are illusions. Christopher Martin Center for Thomistic Studies University of St Thomas Houston, Texas