Thomas Aquinas, Treatise on Law Date: February 23, 2009 Presenter: Nick Coccoma Summary of Work: Aquinas's political and legal theory is important for three reasons. First, it reasserts the value of politics by drawing on Aristotle to argue that politics and political life are morally positive activities that are in accordance with the intention of God for man. Second, it combines traditional hierarchical and feudal views of the structure of society and politics with emerging community-oriented and incipiently egalitarian views of the proper ordering of society. Third, it develops an integrated and logically coherent theory of natural law that continues to be an important source of legal, political, and moral norms. Main Point of Section: In the Treatise on Law, Aquinas concerns himself with the origins of law. He wants to know the source of the obligation that law imposes. The questions are these: “By what warrant does the human legislator bind the consciences of people? Doesn’t this power belong to God alone? If people possess it, what are the limits within which they may exercise it?” Key Ideas: 1. Source of the law is God. The root of obligation is in the divine conception of the order proper to the universe. Human Law, to be just and morally obligating, must therefore be rooted in Divine Law. People cannot originate the law themselves. Aquinas rejects Divine Right theory because it contributes a divine quality to political authority. No authority, not even the sovereign, can impose an obligation on the citizen where it is not already latent in the nature of things. 2. Essence of Law: An ordinance of reason for the common good made by one who has care for the community and is promulgated. (90.4) 3. Kinds of Law: A hierarchical typology of laws. * But the eternal, natural, and human laws are all one rule progressively specified. a) Eternal: The rational governance of everything on the part of God as ruler of the universe (91.1). Divine Providence. b) Natural: The participation in the eternal law by rational creatures (91.2). The objective link between our minds and God’s mind. c) Human (Positive): Particular applications of the law derived by reason. d) Divine (Positive): That part of the eternal law that God positively revealed, imperfectly to the Jews in the Law and perfectly through Christ. Helps us attain our supernatural end. Outline: Question 90 : Essence of Law “An ordinance of reason for the common good made by one who has care for the community and is promulgated.” a) Ordered: Law is an ordered rule and measure of acts. It ‘induces’ or obligates us to act/not act. (Obligation is the binding of the free will to perform that act which is necessary for the attainment of happiness; it is different than necessitating. Free will allows us to act/not act accordingly). b) Reason: Reason reveals the above order. The first principle of human acts is reason, because we act primarily by recognizing and knowing the good end that the will presents to the intellect. This is more than saying law is rational in character—Aquinas has in mind teleological reasoning. c) Common Good: Reason orders us toward common happiness through law, not mere individual happiness. (This is not to say that Aquinas doesn’t care about the individual.) d) One who has care: Law is based in the community, and making the law belongs either to all the people or some public person who has responsibility for all the people. Thus even without organized representative institution, the ruler is to keep the common good as her/his aim in legislating. Corrupt governments are those that aim at the private good of the rulers rather than the common good. In practice, Aquinas preferred a government where leaders (aristocracy) elected by the people (democracy) assist a ruler (monarch). e) Promulgated: In order to bind people, laws must be applied to them. This application occurs when they are notified of the laws through promulgation. Promulgation is thus necessary for the law to obtain force. 1st Art. Does law pertain to reason? Ans.: Law is a rule and measure of acts, whereby people are made to act or restrained from acting. Reason is the rule of these acts, since it directs acts to an end. 2nd Art. The Common Good as Law’s End. The first principle in practical matters (which are the object of the practical reason) is the ‘last end’, and the last end of human life is happiness. That happiness includes all society, so law—under the guidance of reason—serves the common good. 3rd Art. Can human reason make laws? That is, can any one person make laws for himself? Ans.: No. To order anything to the common good belongs to the whole people or to a guardian of the whole people. 4th Art. Law must be promulgated. On that note, the natural law is promulgated by the very fact that God instilled it in our minds as to be known by us naturally. Question 91: Kinds of Law 1st Art. Eternal law. A law is nothing else but a dictate of practical reason emanating from the ruler of a community. The world is ruled by Divine Providence, meaning that it is governed by Divine Reason. It’s ideas of the government are thus a law, and since Divine Reason is not subject to time, this law is eternal. Aquinas believes God’s wisdom includes a sense of the proper ordering of the whole community of the universe. God’s Divine Reason must have a most perfect ‘idea’ of how to order things. This wisdom is the eternal law. 2nd Art. Natural law. Rational creatures, insofar as they partake of a share of providence, have a share of the Divine Reason, whereby they have a natural inclination to their proper acts and ends. This participation in the eternal law is natural law. Natural law allows us to discern between good and evil, and is an imprint of Divine Light. Natural law is the group of universal obligations of right reason concerning the good of nature that we should pursue and the evil we should avoid. 3rd Art. Human law. Human laws are the dictates of practical reason. They particularize the general principles we know from the natural law. It’s the law of states, of our societies. We cannot ‘act’ natural law since it encompasses universal obligations. We do not fully participate in Divine Reason and thus cannot know each and every single truth. We thus look to the general principles we have in the natural law (such as the precept ‘do good, avoid evil’) and use our reason to draw particular conclusions (‘Help the elderly lady carry her bags’). 4th Art. Divine Law. We need this because our end is eternal happiness with God, which is disproportionate to our natural faculties. Furthermore, divine law establishes one rule of what one should or should not do, eliminating multiple standards. Third, divine law helps govern our interior selves, which human law cannot. Fourth, human law does not criminalize all evils since to do so would do away with many good things, and would hinder the advance of the common good. Divine law thus covers and forbids all evils that human law cannot address. 5th Art. Divine law is God’s self-revelation. It comes in two forms: The revelation to the Jews, and Christ: The Old and the New Law. 6th Art. Sin is not another law, because it deviates from the law of reason. It is rather an inclination of sensuality stemming from the body, and has the ‘nature’ of a law. Question 92: Effects of the Law 1st Art. To make people good. The proper effect of law is to lead people to their proper virtue, and since virtue is that which makes its subject good, it follows that the proper effect of law is to make those to whom it is given good. 2nd Art. To command (good acts), prohibit (bad acts), permit (indifferent acts), and use fear of punishment to ensure obedience. Question 94: Natural Law 1st Art. What is it? A habit? Ans.: Not essentially or properly, but insofar as we “hold something by habit.” 2nd Art. Does it have several precepts or only one? Ans.: There is one general precept: Good is to be done, evil avoided. This precept stems from the first principle of practical reason. Under that, however, we have many manifestations of it flowing from the instinct for self-preservation, from things nature has taught us (e.g., we should educate the young), and from natural inclinations of our reason (e.g., our natural inclination to know the truth about God, to live in society, etc.). All of these lesser precepts flow from the first. Reason has the capacity to perceive what is good for human beings by following the "order of our national inclinations." These Aquinas lists as self-preservation (an end that human beings share with all substances), family life and bringing up offspring (which is shared with all animals), and the goals of knowing God and living in society (which are shared with all rational creatures). These goals in turn are seen as obligatory because practical reason perceives as a basic principle that "good is to be done and evil is to be avoided," which is a self-evident principle like the principle of non-contradiction. 3rd Art. Are all acts of virtue prescribed by the law? Ans.: Yes, but only insofar as each person’s reason naturally dictates to him to act virtuously. But if we consider the virtuous acts themselves, i.e., in their proper species, then not all virtuous acts are prescribed by natural law, because many things are done virtuously to which nature does not incline at first but which, through the inquiry of reason, have been found by men to be conducive to living well. 4th Art. Is the natural law the same in everyone? Ans.: In terms of general principles, yes. But in terms of the conclusions drawn from those principles, the truth is not the same for all in all cases. Certain obstacles can prevent the concretization of the law in the best way, and our reason can get perverted by passions or evil so that we don’t have full knowledge of the law. 5th Art. Can natural law be changed? Ans.: “First” principles cannot. But “secondary” precepts of natural law, which “follow as immediate conclusions from first principles,” can be changed “in a few cases because some special reasons make its precepts impossible to observe,” although, except for the mention of polygamy in the Old Testament, there is no further discussion of the difference between the two types of principles. It is also possible for there to be additions to the natural law of “provisions that are useful to human life.” Also, we must use prudence and equity in our legislating. The latter is what lets a ruler depart from the letter of the law when its strict application would violate its spirit. 6th Art. The natural law cannot be blotted out, because it is written on our hearts. Not even sin can remove it. Question 95: Human Law 1st Art. Are human laws useful? Ans.: Yes, because they restrain—through fear of punishment— those prone to vice, people who must be led to virtue through compulsion. 2nd Art. Do all human laws come from the natural law? Ans.: Yes, insofar as they are just. A law is just if it is in accord with reason. The first rule of reason is the law of nature. Also, human laws are conclusions based on principles, which come from the natural law. 3rd Art. Divine law fosters religion; natural law fosters discipline; and human law fosters the common good. Law of Nations: is related to natural law as "conclusions from principles," conclusions that enable people to relate to one another in all societies.31 Aquinas therefore classifies the law of nations as a type of human law, that is, the particular applications of natural law derived by reason, while he calls the more specific and variable applications of human law "civil law" (from civitas = 'city'). Both varieties of human law are derived from natural law, and if human law disagrees with natural law, "it is no longer a law, but a corruption of law.”