CONSTITUTION DAY: WHAT PRECISELY SHOULD WE COMMEMORATE? (James Madison Program Constitution Day Lecture, Princeton University, 9/17/09) Sotirios A. Barber My thanks to Professor George and Professor Wilson for asking me to open this afternoon’s conversation about the U.S. Constitution. Thanks also to Betsy Schneck for making the arrangements for my visit. And thanks to all of you for coming this afternoon. It’s good to be back before an audience of the Madison Program. As happy as I am to be here, however, I’m not sure what the occasion calls for. I’m supposed to say something that commemorates the founding of the Constitution. But how to do that isn’t clear to me. My problem is that founding a constitution is not the same thing as the constitution that’s founded. Founding a constitution is kind of action with its own set of virtues. A constitution in our sense is a document that establishes, empowers, and limits a government, or is supposed to. Which of these things should we emphasize today? Should we emphasize the founding and the virtues associated with that activity? Or should we focus on the immediate product of that activity, the constitutional document and its corresponding practices. We can’t emphasize the founding and the Constitution equally, and we can’t remember them in the same way. For not only are they different, they are in some ways opposed. To commemorate the founding we commemorate crafting something for ends external and superior to the thing crafted. To commemorate the Constitution we commemorate what’s supposed to be a supreme law, and to do so we assume a posture of fidelity to that law. Fidelity to authority is not a virtue of constitution makers as a type; their virtues are wisdom, magnanimity, and courage. The framers of our present constitution had their eye on the ends of government, not on what was then the law of the land. They had the courage to act with dubious legal authority to disestablish our first constitution. So commemorating the founding and the Constitution are not the same, and that’s why I’m not sure what’s expected of me today. I’ll do what I think best, therefore, trusting you to correct me later. I’ll contend that today, at Princeton, commemorating the founding is a better idea than commemorating the Constitution. To make my case, 1 (1) I’ll discuss the approach to things constitutional taken in recent years by Walter Murphy and some of his students and colleagues, and I’ll contrast their constructively critical approach with what I call “constitution worship.” (2) I’ll then argue that constitution worship is a bad idea, essentially because it misrepresents the human condition; (3) I’ll argue further that in commemorating the founding, we should focus less on the actors and the actions involved and more on the virtues that they represent; (4) I’ll argue that commemorating the founding rather than the Constitution is consistent with the principles of the Constitution itself; and (5) I’ll close with a thought about our prospects for reviving those virtue. 1. I emphasize at the outset that I’m not saying that commemorating the founding over the Constitution is better everywhere and on all occasions. My thesis today is specific to this place and to places like it. Let me explain. Princeton is surely the best place to talk about the Constitution. Princeton’s leadership in constitutional studies has been unchallenged for many years, thanks to decisions that Professor Walter Murphy made in the mid 1970s and to the subsequent work of Professors George, Macedo, Whittington, Schepele, and Eisgruber. No group of scholars anywhere, certainly none living today, has achieved the breadth and depth of thought about the Constitution in the combined works of these Princetonians. The examplar of the Princeton approach to constitutional studies is Murphy’s prize winning book on creating and maintaining constitutional democracy, published by Johns Hopkins in 2007. Murphy agrees with James Madison that no form of government has any value beyond the well-being of its people and that any constitution can fail in pursuit of this object. Murphy asks how constitutional democracies are doing. How, for example, does constitutional democracy in America compare with the coercive capitalism of Singapore and Korea regarding political freedoms, per capita income, public safety, and public 2 education? Because Murphy asks and answers these questions honestly, his findings provoke our concern as well as pride. The political freedoms of Singapore don’t compare with ours, of course, but we Americans spend more on prisons than on higher education, and that fact should make us worry about the nation’s future. Murphy’s book inspired a conference here at Princeton in 2007 on the limits of constitutional democracy. Next year Princeton University Press will publish a collection of essays from this conference. Most of the writers for this volume, like its editors, Stephen Macedo and Jeffrey Tulis, are Murphy’s former students or colleagues. These writers discuss problems like the nature of constitutional failure and success, how or whether constitutional governments have coped and can cope with emergencies of different kinds, and how constitutional governments can and should adjust to the increasingly global nature of economic, environmental, and security demands. In the volume’s concluding essay, Christopher Eisgruber looks back and notes that none of the essays is “triumphal” in tone. None boasts that “’We Americans did it!’” – that “’[w]e created a constitution that has endured for more than two centuries,’” and that we have shown mankind what we said we would, “’the possibility of government by reflection and choice.’” The essays are more thoughtful and truer to the facts, says Eisgruber: “They teach us that there are limits inherent in the very commitment to reflection and choice. Reason is fallible, choices can be catastrophic, and governments founded upon a commitment to reason and choice therefore confront specific, durable risks of failure.” Commitment to a politics of reason makes constitutional failure an ever-present and continuing possibility of the American system, says Eisgruber, a challenge “that animates the constitutional enterprise and [that] should be simultaneously daunting and thrilling to citizens who desire to govern themselves.” So, then, a key element of the Princeton approach is a willingness to confront the real and continuing possibility of constitutional failure. Contrast this attitude with that of the man who conceived Constitution Day. I refer to Senator Robert Byrd of West Virginia. It was Sen. Byrd who authored an amendment to the Appropriation’s Act of 2005 mandating that schools receiving federal funds do something on or about Sept. 17 every year “to commemorate the forming and the signing of the Constitution.” In words reminiscent more of Confederate Virginia than loyalist West Virginian, Sen. Byrd calls 3 the constitutional document “the foundation of our freedoms.” He also claims that “these few pages written on parchment” “established for all time the direction and structure of these United States.” Because he “care[s] so deeply about this precious document,” he summons “all Americans to take the time on September 17th to read, analyze, and reflect on the Constitution” and the legacy of its heroic framers, namely, “the great treasure that is our nation and our form of government.” By doing this, he concludes, “[e]ach of us” can help discharge “an obligation to hand that treasure on to future generations intact and strong and secure.” Sen. Byrd thus expects Americans to commemorate the Constitution in a triumphal spirit. If the senator’s expectations governed here, one day each year you would have to agree or pretend to agree that the Constitution is precious, that it is the foundation of our basic liberties, that it will last forever, and that each generation is obligated to pass it to the next. Yet, clearly, such a celebration of the Constitution would be unsuitable here, for Sen Byrd’s way seems opposed to the constructively critical spirit of the Princeton approach. This approach, as Professor Eisgruber indicates, tries to cope with the continuing and real possibility of constitutional failure, a possibility Senator Byrd wants to deny. But no one can successfully deny this possibility. The framers certainly did not. The very fact that there were framers and a founding belies Senator Byrd’s view of the Constitution. From the perspective of framers, (1) a constitution is an instrument of ends like justice and the blessings of liberty; (2) these ends are real goods, and because they are real goods, (3) we can fail to achieve or approximate them. James Madison presupposes real goods in a famous passage of the 45th Federalist: “No form of Government whatever,” he says, “has any other value than as it may be fitted for the attainment of” the people’s happiness. He’s prepared to reject the Constitution and abolish the Union itself should either prove “inconsistent with the public happiness.” (45:309; Cooke). Madison thus reduces all man-made schemes of government – all constitutions on the American model – to the status of means to things whose meaning and value are fixed by nature, not subject to our will. We can’t just take a vote and decide what life, liberty, and happiness are. Their nature is beyond our capacity to change and 4 our definitions are mere attempts to capture their nature. That’s why our efforts to pursue these goods can fail. On the other hand, Madison had more to say that is relevant to the problem of what we should commemorate. He wasn’t always sensitive to the possibility of constitutional failure. Had he been so he might have been more receptive to Thomas Jefferson’s proposal for periodic constitutional conventions. In Federalist 49, Madison rejects Jefferson’s proposal because, he says, frequent appeals to the people would imply “defect[s] in the government” and deprive it “of that veneration which time bestows on everything, and without which perhaps the wisest and freest governments would not possess the requisite stability.” To this he adds that except perhaps for “a nation of philosophers” or Plato’s philosopher kings, “the most rational government” needs “the prejudices of the community on its side” (49:340). In light of this thought maybe we should commemorate the Constitution Sen. Byrd’s way. Maybe we should tell ourselves that the Constitution will endure indefinitely as the source of our freedoms and the foundation of our national identity. We are hardly a nation of philosophers, and political instability might well result from a general awareness of the Constitution’s defects and the possibility of its failure. Let’s admit, however, if only to ourselves, that celebrating as Sen. Byrd proposes would be a pretense for us -- perhaps a noble pretense, as Plato might say, but still a pretense. We know, and Sen Byrd surely knows, that our system has its problems and that his view of what grounds our freedoms and national identity are at best debatable and have been debated for centuries. Despite Madison’s statement about the prejudices of the community, Madison also knew the Constitution was imperfect. In letters to Jefferson of September and October of 1787 Madison doubted that the Constitution would either achieve “its national objects” or prevent injustices by the states, injustices, Madison said. “which every where excite disgust against the state governments.” The chief cause of Madison’s pessimism was the refusal of the Constitutional Convention’s to give Congress a general veto over state laws. Madison also saw equal representation of small and large states in the Senate as “a lesser evil” forced on the Convention by political realities. These concessions of the Convention in behalf of state sovereignty ran counter 5 to the large republic argument that Madison offered in Federalist 10 as the heart of his constitutional theory. Such was Madison’s mind in the late 1780s. He recommended reverence for a constitution he believed seriously defective. Two obvious problems would attend Madison’s advice. The first would be identifying its addressees. Who exactly would Madison be talking to? Who should cultivate veneration for an admittedly defective constitution? Would the nation be divided into two kinds of people, the few enlightened and the many benighted, with the few deceiving the many for the good of all? Might an elite judicial corps or a joint congressional committee affect needed constitutional change under cover of constitutional interpretation, for example? Since Madison was no populist, we can’t dismiss some such possibility as consistent with his principles if not his expectations. If we granted it for argument’s sake, however, other problems would rush in. Constitutional interpretation has its limits. It can change our understanding of ideas like due process, equal protection, and the scope of the commerce power; but it can’t reach the electoral college, the composition of the Senate, or a politics that, thanks partly to the framers themselves, substitutes group interests for public purposes. Once the limits of interpretation were reached, the enlightened few would find themselves cultivating reverence for an admittedly defective constitution. Their question would be what ours is today: How can veneration for a defective constitution correct its defects? How can reverence for a defective constitution improve the nation’s ability to defend itself from foreign enemies or facilitate the well-being and foster the decency of its people? The Federalist Papers defend a scheme of government that is supposed to lead the public to a better understanding of its true interest. How could a defective constitution do this? To the extent that our government did educate the public to its true interests, the Constitution wouldn’t be defective; and if it were defective, the government couldn’t educate the public to its true interests. We’re left to wonder, therefore, why anyone would follow the advice that emerges from Madison’s exchange with Jefferson. Why would anyone foster reverence for an admittedly defective constitution? A defective constitution wouldn’t need reverence; it would need reform and the constructive criticism that precedes reform. It would also need an institution of some sort that concerned itself with the problem of 6 constitutional reform on a continuing basis, a stable institution to address a standing problem, the “ever-present and continuing possibility” of constitutional failure. I don’t deny that we have to accept and work with a defective constitution, for there is no such thing as a perfect constitution. I deny that there can’t be a perfect constitution even in theory. But accepting and working with a constitution is one thing, venerating it is another. I question why anyone should encourage across-the-board reverence for any man-made institution. Venerating something tends to blind us to its defects, the opportunities to correct them, and the need to foster the skills and attitudes for correcting them. Taken seriously and to its logical limits, reverence for an imperfect constitution carries frightening moral risks. I’ll elaborate this last contention. 2. Let me first repeat a point. Acknowledging the Constitution’s defects as Madison did to Jefferson, presupposes that the constitution and the government it establishes are answerable to standards of good policy and right conduct that are not of its making – goods and standards it can fail to approximate. Acknowledging the potential for failure thus goes hand in hand with belief in the existence of real goods and real standards – real goods as opposed to merely subjective or conventional goods. Reverence for a constitution implies a different view of the world. When we think of reverence we think of its highest form, the posture we’re supposed to have toward God, or maybe Nature or Nature’s God. We revere, say, God the Maker – the source of our identity, and therewith what’s good for us, and the source of the standards by which we ought to treat each other, and therewith our rights. Sen. Byrd apparently wants us to feel the same about the Constitution: It made us a nation, according to Sen Byrd, even though the Preamble indicates otherwise. The Constitution is the source of our rights, says Sen Byrd, even though the Ninth Amendment all but explicitly says otherwise. But never mind the Preamble and the Ninth Amendment. Let’s grant Sen. Byrd’s view for argument’s sake and see where it leads. Assume that the Constitution made us and is the source of our rights. But then notice that the Constitution speaks for We the People. If the Constitution made us as a people, and if the Constitution speaks for us as a people, then it follows that we made 7 ourselves a people and that we are the source of our rights. We the People decide the biggest questions for ourselves: who and what we are, what’s good for us, what rights we have, how we should treat each other. Since the Constitution declares our voice the “supreme Law,” we as a people answer ultimately only to ourselves. Never mind any higher authority or the rest of the “candid World” to which we once gave reasons for declaring our independence. Revering the Constitution thus turns out to be a form of selfworship, and the big problem with self-worship is that it makes little sense in a world not of our making and beyond our control. I’m aware that some politicians and some intellectuals will say things to the effect that we do make our own reality. I doubt anyone really believes this, however. We can cope with reality, of course, changing things to our liking temporarily and at the retail level. But coping is not making, and retail is not wholesale. If we really could make our own reality our success would follow upon the mere declaration of it, and failure would be impossible. The Constitution would be a good constitution and we’d be happy solely by proclamation, just as the God of Genesis created the world by saying let it be. Suffice it to say that if we have made our own reality, the reality that we’ve apparently made includes a reality beyond our making, and beyond our control. The proposition that we can make or have made our own reality is thus the reductio ad absurdum of constitution worship. Then there’s the problem of who the word “we” includes. Who is the ‘we’ in the proposition that “We the people decide what’s good and right for ourselves.” The armed force of the Union took a step toward settling this problem in the 1860s when it forced the Southern states to accept the Fourteenth Amendment. This amendment and other constitutional provisions combine to make all native-born and naturalized persons members of the constituent we, regardless of race, parentage, religion, or wealth. This, at any rate, is the normative part (or part of the normative part) of the answer to who we might be, and the normative part not only has a force of its own, it will register in any social-scientific answer. The social-scientific finding that segments of the population felt politically disfranchised would be visible solely in light of the presumed legal-moral fact that it should be otherwise. But of course for much of the nation’s history – as much as three-quarters to date – it was otherwise. For much of the nation’s history, law-abiding and socially productive parts of the adult population were excluded from the constituent 8 we, despite the creed that none should be governed without their consent. The nation’s history thus shows that who we are is itself a political problem, perhaps the biggest political problem. It makes no sense, therefore, to say that we decide the biggest questions; for with no antecedent agreement on the biggest questions, there is no we. The American constitutional text is rich with assumptions about who we are. The text thus supposes a pre-existing community whose members aspire above all else to public goods like the common defense and the general welfare. The text treats these goods as real goods, goods that naturally attract competing conceptions. The text also indicates that we value these goods more than we value their competing conceptions. Articles I, V and VII indicate that the best versions of these goods and the means thereto will be pursued through a continuing process of public deliberation. By banning titles of nobility and religious tests for national office, Articles I and VI indicate that the evidence supporting policy choices will be accessible in principle to people generally, not solely to any special generation, blood line, or divinely favored calling or group. Agreement in these matters – what and who we are, what we want most, how to seek the best conceptions of what we want most, the best means thereto, and what makes one’s experience evidence for all – agreement in these things wouldn’t be everything, but it would be a lot – enough to keep us talking and working together. Disagreement in these things was enough to cause one civil war and may yet cause another. Adequate levels of agreement in these things depends on the general attractiveness of real goods, goods not of our making. By implicitly denying the existence of such goods, constitution worshippers leave nothing for competing conceptions of an idea to get closer to. Competing conceptions of justice, the general welfare, and the like are no longer versions of general ideas in whose light some conceptions are better than others; they’re just competing conceptions, period. With nothing to get closer to, deliberation degenerates from a truth-seeking process to a bargaining process. As a type, bargainers aim for the bottom line; they support bargaining only to the extent that its payoff is more attractive than that of other processes. Where processes like fraud and violence pay enough to justify the risks, bargainers see no reason for bargaining. Constitution worship thus leaves force as the ultimate source of what’s good and right – the source, rather, of what’s called good and right. This downward spiral from Constitution worship to force makes 9 constitution worship a bad idea. Better, I submit, to commemorate the founding than the Constitution. 3. But this conclusion needs refinement. We should commemorate the founding and the framers, to be sure, but commemorating them should have a larger point. If we focused solely on a particular act and particular group of actors, the reason would lie in the excellence of their particular product, the Constitution in this case, which would at best be a contingent and potentially failed instrument of its ends. If there’s lasting, noncontingent value in commemorating our framers and our founding it lies in what they aspired to demonstrate: mankind’s capacity for “establishing good government from reflection and choice.” Commemorating people and events close to us is of lasting value if we take them as indicative of prospects for ourselves. They made and remade constitutions, we’re sprung from them, maybe we can emulate them, when the time comes, if it hasn’t already. 4. I know that this position opens me to the charge of lawlessness, ingratitude, and even impiety -- sin against a document and a system that we are sworn to preserve and pass to the future. Permit me a brief defense against this charge. First a quick review: I’ve argued that we should commemorate the founding, not the Constitution, and I’ve argued for commemorating the founding for the virtues it represents, not for the constitution it produced. My argument so far has been an argument from the possibility of constitutional failure, a possibility I claim no one can deny. I’ve argued elsewhere to the same conclusion from the nature of the people’s welfare, which Madison says in Federalist 45 is the supreme object of any good government, regardless of form. I can’t summarize my argument from welfare here and I wouldn’t if I could, for it wouldn’t answer the present charge. Arguments from the possibility of failure and from the nature of human welfare appeal to goods higher than the law, like security and happiness. Because American systems of law are expressly established to pursue these goods, laws disconnected from reasonable versions of these goods aren’t really laws, or so I contend. No doubt some of 10 you will see this instrumentalist attitude toward law as a formula for chaos, and I confess it may well be. Better, you might say, some authority, however flawed, than none at all. I respect the point. So let me try a different tack. I may not succeed, but I’d like to try. Let me try to defend commemorating constitution makers and their virtues by appealing not to higher values but to the law itself, to the Constitution itself. Assume we all take an oath to preserve and defend the Constitution. I’ve taken the oath in good faith, as have many of you. Walter Murphy’s Purple Heart and Distinguished Service Cross attest his good faith. Our question now is whether the oath favors the Constitution and its founding more than the virtues that the American founding sought to represent. Once again, we can’t commemorate both at the same time, for a constitution that worked well would eliminate the need for further acts of constitution making and reform, and celebrating the virtues of reformers as such would be both pointless and subversive of a good government. Why remind people of virtues that aren’t needed anymore and whose revival might be harmful? So, again, our question: Does the oath to preserve and defend the Constitution elevate this constitution and its founding over mankind’s capacity to establish good government from reflection and choice? I don’t think it does. Let me briefly indicate why. Swearing to preserve and defend the Constitution is not promising to leave it as is, for the Constitution itself provides for change in Article V. By providing for amendments, Article V implies that the Constitution may need amending. Article V thus bestows on the Constitution a specific property, the property of amendability. The amendability of this constitution and therewith the opportunity and the right to redo the framers’ work is thus made part of what we take an oath to preserve and defend. As an old teacher of mine once put it, our constitution is officially “open to thought” – that is, opened to reasoned change. Let’s think about this a bit further. In view of Article V, we’re under an obligation to preserve and defend almost no part of our existing constitution because almost every part is amendable. We can’t amend Article VII, the ratification article, because ratification occurred in historical time that we can’t revisit (as far as I know). But Article V is different. We can reconsider Article V, and we may have to, for Article V has problems. Article V puts equal suffrage of the states in the Senate virtually beyond amendment by permitting change only on the consent of each affected 11 state. In addition, three-quarters of the states are most unlikely ever to make the constitution easier to amend than it presently is. These virtually unamendable provisions of Article V are virtually closed to thought, closed to reasoned reconsideration. And because they are closed to rethinking, they offend the very principle of amendability that Article V would represent. Article V is thus at war with itself; it represents a principle that it violates. This isn’t a problem unique to Article V, it holds for any attempt to institutionalize thought – any attempt to bring thought down to earth, so-to-speak, by operationalizing it, by manifesting it in a rule that governs our actual conduct. Under the right circumstances any rule can defeat the purposes it was designed to serve. Under the right circumstances (or the wrong ones) a rule can be at war with the principle that justifies it. To the extent that a constitution’s amending rule becomes unworkable or unworkable in a timely way, the rule ceases to be what the Constitution says it is: part of larger scheme for pursuing real goods. It ceases to be the amending rule because it fails to do the work of an amending rule. The framers of our present Constitution encountered such a situation in Article XIII of the Articles of Confederation. Here was a rule that gave a bare majority of the smallest state (1/60th of the nation’s total population) a veto over everyone else, and past experience had proved Article XIII unworkable. Madison was clear in Federalist 45 about the only rational course in this circumstance: ignore the old rule, submit a new rule to the people, and let them accept or reject the new rule as they choose to act on it or not. (45:263) Quoting from the Declaration of Independence and citing the nation’s revolutionary experience with unauthorized committees, congresses, and constitutional conventions, Madison said that “in all great changes of established governments, forms ought to give way to substance” lest the “transcendent and precious right of the people to ‘abolish or alter their governments” be rendered “nominal and nugatory.” (40:265) Since the people can’t “move in concert towards their object” in a spontaneous fashion, Madison added, “it is . . . essential that such changes be instituted by some informal and unauthorized propositions, made by some patriotic and respectable citizen or number of citizens.” (40:265). So, the founding generation simply acted through Article VII and installed a new constitution. And it did this in the only way it could have peacefully done 12 so: by following the lead of “some patriotic and respectable . . . number of citizens” and approving propositions that were “informal and unauthorized.” My defense against the charge of lawlessness, therefore, is the constitutional text that embodies the principle of amendability and the historic words and actions that honored that principle. Commemorating the founding over both the Constitution would be no lawless act; nor would it violate the constitutional oath. The constitution itself, as written, together with the actions that produced it and the tradition that justifies it -- all these things display a principle of amendability. This principle of amendability points ultimately not to a set of rules but, as Madison indicated, to a competent and patriotic leadership community that both trusts the public and enjoys the public’s trust. Our openness to thought – the possibility of government by reflection and choice -- depends on this ensemble of virtues and actors. So, I think, does the Constitution’s survival. 5. In conclusion let me say that the nation today seems very far from the virtues and attitudes on display at the founding. Why this is so is beyond my pretensions, but I will mention possibilities that seem worth discussing. I personally would start with the rise of the religious right, the political power of the business community, and the grip of positivism on the social sciences, for each of these forces in its own way elevates man over nature and sees moral truth as an artifact of will flowing from arbitrary preference. Some of my friends will blame secular public reasonableness of the very kind I hold to be the Constitution’s central aspiration. And they may be right, for reason can turn on itself, collapse into nihilism, and free people from the civilizing attractions and restraints of religion. All sides should revisit the framer’s decision to rely less on public spiritedness in both the electorate and the government than on private incentives checking and balancing each other. Yet all can doubt whether anyone could have done better than the framers, for human nature may preclude a lasting relationship of trust between ordinary people and a competent and genuinely public-spirited elite, not to mention the problems of creating and maintaining the latter. This afternoon is the wrong time to explore these questions. But this is the right place. Thanks to the Madison Program, the Center for Human Values, the Law and 13 Public Policy Program, and the University’s central administration, Princeton is on track to remain the leading place for an honest debate on constitutional fundamentals. Continuing this debate is the best way to commemorate the American founding. 14