1 While evolutionary approaches to the human mind and behavior come in a variety of forms (Heyes, 2003), evolutionary psychology represents a more restricted research program that is focused on mental adaptations (Day & Wilson, 1999; Tooby & Cosmides, 1992). Adaptations are characterized by complex, functional organization that is generally assumed to require many generations of persistent selection in order such complex structures to emerge (Dawkins, 1986). As a result, this focus on adaptations places a heavy historical constraint on evolutionary psychology. Evolutionary psychology is restricted to the study of psychological mechanisms that would have been advantageous in ancestral environments (Tooby & Cosmides, 1990). To the extent that a trait is evolutionarily novel, evolutionary psychology would seem to have nothing substantive to say about it. This limitation is further compounded by evolutionary psychology’s emphasis on modular psychological mechanisms (Tooby & Cosmides, 1992), further restricting the scope of the hypothesized psychological adaptations. Evolutionarily novel traits, per se, are not necessarily problematic for evolutionary psychology. The approach naturally applies to only a restricted class of phenomena and nonevolved traits clearly fall outside of its scope. However, when such traits are complex and functionally organized, evolutionary psychology is seriously challenged (Bloom, 1999). Evolutionary psychologists place considerable stock in the claim that natural selection is the only scientifically plausible source of complex, functional organization, yet abundant evidence speaks against this claim such as William Paley’s famous example, the watch. Of course, Darwinists would want to make a distinction between natural functional organization and artificial functional organization, with the human eye being an example of the former and the watch being an example of the latter. However, the heart of many debates around evolutionary psychology is whether the human mind is better viewed as an artificial cultural construction. Although theoretically beyond their purview, evolutionary psychologists had better have something to say about evolutionarily novel functional organization. Gould (1991, 2002) has argued that evolutionary psychology would benefit by adopting the concept of exaptation in explaining aspects of human behavior and mental life that are evolutionarily novel. However, the concept of an exaptation is, I will argue, ill-suited for explaining evolutionarily novel functionality. Evolutionarily novel functionality suggests a different sort of explanation in terms of co-opted adaptations that has been widely employed by many evolutionary psychologists and associated researchers to account for a wide range of evolutionarily novel traits. In this paper I attempt to systematize this disparate literature to clarify the logic and scientific value of what I have called the modules and metaphors program. The Concept of Exaptation In their classic paper on exaptations, Gould and Vrba (1982) begin their discussion by noting that there are two conceptions of adaptation that were in use amongst biologists. On the one hand there are biologists like Williams (1966) and Darwin, himself, who restrict the term adaptation to traits that were “built by natural selection for the function[s they] now serve,” on the other hand there are those biologists such as Bock (1979) who more generally apply the term to any trait “that enhances current fitness, regardless of its historical origin” (Gould & Vrba, both quotes p. 5). 2 Gould and Vrba (1982) argue that this is a serious conflation of two largely unrelated ideas: historical origin via natural selection and current utility. In an effort to correct this confusion, Gould and Vrba coined the term, exaptation, to describe traits that currently enhance fitness, but did not evolve for that reason. We suggest that such characters, evolved for other usages (or for no function at all), and later “coopted” for their current role, be called exaptations … They are fit for their current role, and hence aptus, but they were not designed for it, and are therefore not ad aptus, or pushed towards fitness. They owe their fitness to features present for other reasons, and are therefore fit (aptus) by reason of (ex) their form, or ex aptus [emphasis original] (p. 6). Many evolutionary psychologists that I have discussed the concept of exaptation with harbor the mistaken belief that exaptations are defined by their relation to some structure. Typically it is assumed that the concept exaptation refers to coopted adaptations or spandrels (the nonfunctional byproducts of adaptations, Gould & Lewontin, 1979). Consider, for example, Buss, Haselton, Shackelford, Bleske and Wakefield (1998) who suggest that there are two types of exaptations: co-opted adaptations and co-opted spandrels, or Andrews, Gangestad, and Matthews (2002) who define exaptations as “a pre-existing trait (i.e., one that has already evolved) that acquires a new beneficial effect without being modified by selection for this effect” (p. 491, emphasis mine). However, exaptations are not defined by their relation to any particular structure, they are defined in the negative by the lack of a history of selection. Moreover, even if one were to argue that exaptations necessarily bear a relation to some prior structure, there is nothing in Gould and Vrba’s definition of the term that restricts their relationship to prior evolved structures as these evolutionary psychologists do, i.e. there is nothing ruling out exaptations as currently useful noise in the system (see, for example, Gould, 2002, p. 1282-1284). The Adaptivist and Adaptationist Programs It is curious that such confusion should abound over the concept of exaptation, because the critique that Gould and Vrba advance is one that evolutionary psychologists strongly embrace. Prior to the late 1980’s the term evolutionary psychology was not in general usage. In academia and the wider public at large, sociobiology was the term generally applied to evolutionary analyses of the human mind and behavior. The term evolutionary psychology was introduced to draw a distinction between two different schools of evolutionary thought: the adaptivist program and the adaptationist program, with evolutionary psychology the chosen label for the latter program as applied to the study of the human mind. Given that much of what was previously called sociobiology was research conducted within the adaptivist program, the new term, evolutionary psychology, wasn’t simply a rebranding of sociobiology but the sign of a theoretical fission within the human sociobiological community. It is difficult to understand evolutionary psychology’s commitment to historical analysis and mental modularity without an appreciation of the differences between these two research programs. 3 In an influential string of papers, Symons (1987, 1989, 1990, 1992) drew a distinction the adaptationist program as practiced by Darwinian psychologists (i.e., evolutionary psychologists) and the adaptivist program as practiced by Darwinian anthropologists, owing primarily to the fact that many of the former are psychologists (though not all, as Symons himself exemplifies) while many of the latter are anthropologists. The adaptationist program is focused on identifying and explaining the traits of organisms in terms of adaptation – components of an organism’s phenotype that were specially designed by natural selection to solve an adaptive problem. An adaptive problem is any long-standing problem that would have imposed significant selection pressures in the evolutionary history of the species. It is the emphasis on special-design as the mark of adaptation that has led to evolutionary psychology’s interest in mental modularity. However, this does not imply any commitment to a Fodorian (1983) definition of modularity, e.g., with an emphasis on informational encapsulation, but a commitment first and foremost to psychological special-design. Adaptivists also see their program as being focused on evolved traits, but the adaptivist program is quite different from the adaptationist program. Rather than focusing on the design of phenotypic traits, adaptivists focus on the reproductive consequences of phenotypic traits, often in the context of the whole organism (Smith, Borgerhoff Mulder, & Hill, 2000, 2001). The focus of research in this program is on traits that increase reproductive success (or fitness proxies such as foraged calories), i.e. traits that are adaptive. Adaptivists are generally less concerned about whether the trait in question bears evidence of special design or has the right evolutionary pedigree. It is in the context of this fission between adaptivist and adaptationist approaches to human evolution that the term evolutionary psychology rose in prominence. The critique, moreover, is not one-sided. Many Darwinian anthropologists have serious misgivings with the research program advocated by evolutionary psychologists and prefer instead to call themselves human behavioral ecologists (Smith et al. 2000, 2001). I highlight this debate, not to weigh the relative merits of the two programs, but to draw attention to the fact that evolutionary psychology is a very specific program of evolutionary research (contrary to some inflationary claims, e.g. Heyes, 2003) which leads to my more immediate concern, that adaptivists and adaptationists face different theoretical challenges. Specifically, while the potential existence of exaptations poses a serious risk to the adaptivist program, they should be of little or no concern to adaptationists, i.e. evolutionary psychologists. “We believe that the failure of evolutionists to codify such a concept [of exaptation] must record an inarticulated belief in its relative insignificance” (Gould & Vrba, 1982, p. 13). I intend to do precisely this, articulate the relative insignificance of exaptation to adaptationists. Exaptations as an Adaptivist’s Problem As a program focused on the reproductive consequences of contemporaneous traits, the potential existence of exaptations poses an important challenge to the adaptivist program (Barrett, Dunbar, & Lycett, 2002). The reason is straightforward, adaptivists need be concerned that the traits that they are studying have the right sort of history to be properly considered to have evolved. If Gould and Vrba’s (1982) analysis is correct, then exaptations represent a class of traits that are not adaptations, but by virtue of their 4 current utility are liable to be confused for such by adaptivists. Indeed, it is difficult not to come to the conclusion that Gould and Vrba (see also Gould, 1991) primarily had adaptivists in mind when promoting the concept of exaptation. Note, for example, their discussion of Bock (1979) who explicitly defined adaptations in adaptivist terms: “An adaptation is, thus, a feature of the organism, which interacts operationally with some factor of its environment so that the individual survives and reproduces” (p. 39, quoted from Gould & Vrba, 1982, p. 5). How adaptivists might deal with this problem will not concern us here since we are primarily interested in the problems besetting evolutionary psychologists. Evolutionary psychologists qua adaptationists need not worry about the potential existence of exaptations because the focus of their program is special design, not current utility, and exaptations are not characterized by special design. Adaptationists face difficulties of their own; they need to be vigilant against traits that are complex and functionally organized, but are not plausibly adaptations, by virtue of the wrong historical pedigree. It is these traits and not exaptations that could potentially be confused for adaptations by evolutionary psychologists. Do such traits exist? Yes, I would contend, as I have already alluded to above, that various cultural phenomena and many instances of expertise arguably appear complex and functionally organized, yet lack the proper history. Before considering such traits in detail, it will help to consider what role, if any, the concept of exaptation might play in our understanding of them. Unlike Symons’ unrelenting critiques of adaptivists, Gould and Vrba (1982) were more pluralistic in their prescriptions. For while Symons has argued that adaptivism represents a deep conceptual error of dubious scientific value (a “misuse of Darwinism” to quote from one of Symons’, 1992, titles), Gould and Vrba largely accepted the adaptivist program and simply recommended that it be recognized as the study of aptation (environmental fit) rather than the study of adaptation: “we are not trying to dismantle Bock’s [adaptivist] concept. We merely argue that it should be called aptation (with adaptation and exaptation as its modes). As aptation, it retains all the favorable properties for testing enumerated above” (p. 7). Indeed, Gould (1991) would later urge evolutionary psychologists to consider exaptations as worthy of scientific study – “a crucial tool for evolutionary psychology” to quote from the title of the paper. This is a rather peculiar position for Gould to adopt given his earlier claim that “As evolutionists, we are charged, almost by definition, to regard historical pathways as the essence of our subject” (Gould & Vrba, 1982, p. 7) – a sentiment clearly shared by Symons and other evolutionary psychologists. Clearly some theoretical exegesis is required here. What is missing, both from Gould and Vrba’s (1982) discussion of exaptation and Gould’s (1991, 2002) understanding of evolutionary psychology, is the theoretical centrality of special design. It is precisely because adaptations are characterized by complex, functional organization that adaptationists stress the importance of taking a historical perspective – complex structures take a very long time to assemble via the process of natural selection. Were adaptations simple in their organization – and undoubtedly all evolved traits were initially simple in their structure – there would be no need to posit a great depth of history. Special design is central to Williams’ (1966) conceptualization of adaptation and it is central to Symons’ critiques of the adaptivist program, but it is nowhere to be found in Gould’s (1991, 2002; Gould & Vrba, 1982) discussion of exaptation or evolutionary psychology. 5 According to the adaptationist program, evidence of special design and not reproductive success plays a central role in the elucidation of evolved function. If some phenotypic trait were shaped by natural selection for one function, but increased reproductive success in contemporaneous environments by taking on a new role, it is the past history of selection and not current reproductive success that would best account for the detailed structure of the trait (Tooby & Cosmides, 1990). Indeed, unlike Gould and Vrba (1982) who hold that one of the defining characteristics of adaptations is that they currently useful: “a feature is an adaptation only if it was built by natural selection for the function it now performs” (p. 5, emphasis mine), adaptationists do not take current utility to be one of the defining characteristics of adaptations – the selective environment may have changed rendering the trait useless, though possessing evidence of special design for some past function all the same. Consider again, Paley’s watch. It makes little difference whether the watch still functions or has ceased to do so, the complex design of the watch demands an explanation – adaptations are no different. By focusing on design as opposed to current utility, adaptationists are less likely to attribute the wrong selective history to an exaptation than adaptivists. This focus on special design is just the corrective that evolutionists need to avoid being misled by exaptations. That Gould and Vrba (1982) do not mention this, let alone develop this theme, is astonishing given that they explicitly acknowledge their debts to Williams (1966), in which this idea is thoroughly developed, as an important precursor to their proposal. Bait and Switch: Spandrels, Not Exaptations Why should Gould and Vrba (1982) adopt the seemingly contradictory positions of critiquing adaptivism on the one hand and embracing it as the study of aptation on the other? Why should Gould and Vrba avoid all mention of special design? The answer to both questions is clearly laid out in Gould (2002, see the section titled “The complete version, replete with spandrels: Exaptation and the terminology of nonadaptive origin” p. 1246 ff.): the concept of exaptation was introduced to bolster the import of another of Gould’s theoretical developments, the concept of a spandrel (Gould & Lewontin, 1979). “The key to this expansion of evolutionary theory [to include traits that never were adaptations] therefore lies in the category of currently useful traits with nonadaptive origins” (Gould, 2002, p. 1248). Without a science of aptation, there would be no need for the systematic study of traits with nonadaptive origins and an appreciation of the significance of special design would compromise the whole project. Reading Gould (1991, 2002) more carefully, it is clear that his main recommendation to evolutionary psychologists is not that they should employ the concept of exaptation more often, but that they should consider the possibility that important constituents of the mind have their origins as spandrels, not as adaptations. A failure to appreciate the central role of spandrels, and the general importance of nonadaptation in the origin of evolutionary novelties, has often operated as the principal impediment in efforts to construct a proper evolutionary theory for the biological basis of universal traits in Homo sapiens – or what our vernacular calls “human nature.” (Gould, 2002, p. 1264). 6 Why spandrels? Natural selection built the brain; yet, by virtue of structural complexities so engendered, the same brain can perform a plethora of tasks that may later become central to culture, but that are spandrels rather than targets of the original natural selection (Gould, 1991, p. 57). Simply put, by virtue of the human mind’s complexity, the number of spandrels must vastly exceed the number of adaptations, hence by sheer numerical superiority, spandrels will play a far greater role as co-optable structures than adaptations. There are problems with this argument, but before considering them, it is necessary to clarify that spandrels are neither identical to exaptations nor did Gould prioritize the study of exaptations over the study of spandrels. Exaptations, as we have seen above, can either trace their origins either to prior adaptations or to nonadaptive structures such as spandrels and noise in the system. Hence, the set of spandrels is not coextensive with the set of exaptations. Moreover, it is clear from the emphasis that Gould (1991, 2002) places on co-opted spandrels as opposed to co-opted adaptations – of which he gives no human examples nor devotes much discussion – that he is less concerned with the possibility of exaptation, per se, than he is with the possibility that a major portion of the human mind may be nonadpative in origin. This is reinforced by the fact that Gould devotes no discussion to one of the key features of exaptations; namely, that they are currently useful. Although Gould (1991) mentions several possible exaptations, in no instance does he provide any evidence that they are currently useful in either the biologist’s sense of enhancing reproductive success or according to any other metric, though perhaps he felt that the utility of traits such as “singing Wagner” is self-evident. The failure to specify the manner in which cultural traits such as “reading, writing, or any form of mental expression not in the initial repertoire of large-brained populations; add most of the fine and practical arts, the norms of commerce, the practices of war” (Gould, 1991, p. 59) are currently useful is no small oversight. There is a long tradition of anthropological functionalism that claims precisely this (Malinowski, 1922; Radcliffe-Brown, 1952). Gould (1991, 2002) makes no reference to this extensive literature because, as a biologist, he is presumably advocating a specific conception of utility in terms of reproductive success as suggested by Gould and Vrba (1982). Anthropological functionalism wasn’t without its critics and biological functionalism of the sort that Gould would appear to be advocating would face even fiercer resistance. All of this leads to the conclusion that Gould was not advocating wider use of the concept exaptation, but wider consideration to the possibility that contemporary human traits may have nonadaptive origins. This brings us back to the argument that spandrels, by their sheer numerical superiority as co-optable structures, will be far more important to the study of the human mind than are adaptations. There are two problems with this argument. First, it assumes that evolutionarily novel traits will be more important, not just to the study of human mind and behavior in general, but even to human nature (see quote above). Second, it assumes that existence is the sole criterion for co-optability, ignoring other relevant 7 properties such as a trait’s potential to do useful work. Gould (1991, p. 59) is cognizant of the former problem and addresses it forthrightly: Go down the list of what you regard as human universals and cultural predictabilities. How many would you putatively assign to adaptation, and therefore view as amenable to sociobiological explanation? Incest avoidance? Such universal gestures as eyebrow flashing? Fine – but how long is your list and how much of our human essence, how much of what really makes culture, will you find? Unfortunately, the matter is more complicated. Consider, for example, language. Reading and writing, two of Gould’s putative exaptations, are undoubtedly evolutionarily novel, but not entirely. They are built on a cognitive adaptation for spoken language (Pinker, 1994; though Gould, 1991, p. 61-62, argues that spoken language is likewise an exaptation). Consider another of Gould’s (1991) examples, arithmetic. Undeniably, formal arithmetic is an evolutionarily novel cultural construction, but there is very good evidence suggesting that formal arithmetic is an elaboration of two evolved number systems (Dehaene, 1997): one for exact, small number calculations (Wynn, 1995) and another for approximate large number calculations (Dehaene & Cohen, 1991). Religion, another of Gould’s (1991) putative co-opted spandrels has also been analyzed in terms of co-opted adaptations (Boyer, 2003). Moreover, Gould’s (1991) own list of co-opted spandrels: reading and writing, the norms of commerce, and the practices of war, casts doubt upon his argument because these are not human universals. Numerous cultures exist or have existed within the past millennia that lacked a written language (Pinker, 1994). The norms of commerce are not universal, but vary within a restricted repertoire (Fiske, 1991). Likewise, it would be difficult to maintain that the practices of war are universal cross-culturally. What is universal are universal grammar, trade and warfare, more generally (Brown, 1991), but at this level of generality, adaptationist claims are quite plausible (Pinker, 1994; Cosmides & Tooby, 1992; Wrangham & Peterson, 1997, respectively). Looking beyond this possibly ill-chosen list of examples, it surely is the case that spandrels vastly outnumber adaptations. Moreover, as I will argue later, it is not human universals that challenge evolutionary psychology, but some cross-cultural differences and there are stronger grounds for believing that cross-cultural differences map onto evolutionarily novel traits than do cross-culturally universal traits. So the question remains, do spandrels provide a better source of co-opted traits than do adaptations, raising the important question of the relative co-optability of spandrels and adaptations. Gould (1991) initially had little to say about the co-optability of spandrels, but in The Structure of Evolutionary Theory (Gould, 2002, p. 1277 ff.), the issue of the relative co-optability of traits is addressed more substantially, where he draws a distinction between inherent potentials and available things for co-optation. Inherent potentials are potential, but nonmanifested uses of a trait. The inherent potentials of any object (for uses other than their intended purpose of manufacture) establish a large and important category of attributes in the exaptive pool of any individual (Gould, 2002, p. 1278). 8 Available things are simply that, traits that are potentially available to be co-opted. The attributes in the second major category of the exaptive pool are, by important contrast, actual entities, pieces of stuff, material things that have become parts of biological individuals for a variety of reasons…, but that have no current use (Gould, 2002, p. 1279). Gould further treats these as not only as mutually exclusive “attributes,” but also seemingly as mutually exhaustive attributes. Presumably, one would imagine that the probability that a class of traits: adaptations, spandrels, or noise, would be co-opted would be a simple function of their frequency as available things weighted by the strength of their inherent potential – i.e., that these are different aspects of a trait. Yet, Gould only treats traits with no current use as being available things, thereby excluding adaptations that are presently useful and exaptations, which are by definition currently useful. What then are adaptations and exaptations, which Gould and Vrba (1982) collectively refer to as aptations or traits that fit their environment? Presumably they are inherent potentials: Inherent potentials “capture the important concept so poorly expressed in the old term ‘preadaptation’ – that is, suitability for anther function not presently exploited because the feature has been adapted by natural selection for a different utility” (Gould, 2002, p. 1278, emphasis mine). Moreover, one is forced to assume that inherent potentials are things, just like available things, in order to avoid attributing a series of categorical errors to Gould (2002, p. 1285) when he proposes the combination inherent potentials with various subcategories of available things. Hence, rather than contrasting traits with adaptive origins with traits with nonadaptive origins (Gould, 1991), Gould (2002) contrasts currently adaptive traits with currently nonadaptive traits. Unfortunately, Gould (2002) again digresses into an argument for the greater frequency of spandrels as available things, this time at the species level, as opposed to the organismal level as spandrels were originally conceived (Gould & Lewontin, 1979). Yet, his choice of terminology and expressed intention are quite informative. The restriction of the term inherent potentials to traits that that are presently useful would appear to concede that use begets use. Second, Gould (2002, p. 1286, Gould regularly uses the arcane terms Franklins and Miltons interchangeably with inherent potentials and available things, respectively. I substitute the latter for the former here) clearly abandons the effort to present a convincing argument that nonadaptive traits are more co-optable than adaptive traits: “I chose this [basis of primary ordering] because [available things] (and not [inherent potentials] pose a genuine challenge to the exclusivity of adaptationist mechanisms.” Indeed, in the discussion that follows, Gould draws out the radical nature of his proposal without ever justifying an emphasis on nonadpative traits in terms of their contribution to the phenotype of an organism. In the end, no convincing argument is ever offered for expecting traits with nonadaptive origins will make the largest contribution to the functional organization of an organism other than the fact that spandrels possess a numerical advantage. Novel Design as an Adaptationist’s Problem. 9 The foregoing discussion should not leave one with the impression that evolutionarily novel traits pose no problems for adaptationists, because they can indeed, be quite problematic (Bloom, 1999). However, the challenge to the adaptationist program is not posed by exaptations or spandrels, but by instances of evolutionarily novel functional1 organization. The reason is straightforward. Complex functional organization, i.e., special design, is assumed by adaptationists to be diagnostic of adaptations, so if evolutionarily novel functionality exists, it drives a wedge between special design and historical origin – i.e., one can no longer assume that traits bearing evidence of special design have evolutionary origins in the process of natural selection. Exaptations pose no special challenge in this respect because they are not characterized by the evidence of special design in the way that adaptations are. Exaptated adaptations, can be quite problematic in this respect, though this is not by virtue of their continuing to enhance reproductive fitness, but by virtue of their co-opting a prior design for a novel function. Hence, co-opted, but nonexaptated, adaptations are equally problematic. Ultimately, coopted adaptations or exadaptations, as I will call them, do not pose an insurmountable problem to evolutionary psychologists. Indeed, the possibility that adaptations can be coopted for novel purposes potentially extends the scope of evolutionary psychology to include some evolutionarily novel traits. It is the study of precisely these traits that is the focus of what I will call the modules and metaphors program, but before considering this program in detail it will be necessary to consider the more problematic cases of evolutionarily novel functionality with nonadaptive origins. Evolutionarily Novel Functionality with Nonadaptive Origins Gould (1991, 2002), of course, has argued that former spandrels represent an important class of exapted traits. Do co-opted spandrels display evolutionarily novel functionality? Regardless of whether they are exapted or simply co-opted, it seems rather unlikely that spandrels could be confused for adaptations since, almost by definition, spandrels are parts and not functional wholes. Hence, spandrels, as Gould’s (2002) classification as available things and not inherent potentials suggests, are less likely to have potential functionality. Any particular spandrels may, of course, play a functional role in some novel structure or function, but in isolation, a spandrel is not likely to be confused for an adaptation proper as opposed to an adaptive design feature – an important component part – of a candidate adaptation. Over evolutionary time, a former spandrel may come to occupy a larger and larger functional role, but at this point we would no longer be considering an evolutionarily novel trait. Similar arguments and more convincingly apply to instances of co-opted system noise. Far more problematic than co-opted spandrels and noise are instances of expertise. Although discussions of evolutionarily novel functionality often revolve around cultural traits, cultural traits tend to be a manifestation of a more general problem, expertise – i.e., acquired competence. Expertise is problematic because mental mechanisms underlying it bear evidence of some of the same qualities invoked as evidence of “special-design” in psychological adaptations. Not only is expertise domainspecific, but experts “have their knowledge organized in particular ways, ways that make that knowledge more accessible, functional, and efficient” (Bédard & Chi, 1992), some of 10 the very same attributes that have been attributed to psychological adaptations (Tooby & Cosmides, 1992). Typically, however, expertise is viewed as an individual trait. Most of us are novices at specific skills, arts and sciences, with a much more restricted range of individuals displaying markedly better ability being deemed experts. Indeed, the word would seem to loose its meaning if everyone were an expert at a particular task. The individual nature of expertise is in marked contrast to the species-universal expression of adaptations suggested by evolutionary psychologists (Tooby & Cosmides, 1992). Hence, it would seem unlikely that expert abilities would ever be confused with adaptations. Moreover, Bloom (1999) has questioned the significance of acquired expertise by arguing that no one person acquires expertise on his own, but relies on a history of cultural evolution to accumulate the knowledge that individual experts then acquire. This, however, would seem to miss the point. To the extent that experts exhibit complexly organized functionality in their domain of expertise (and arguably they do), then natural selection would not appear to be a privileged source of functional design. Moreover, there is no reason why expertise should only be considered an individual trait. Wagner (1999) has argued that reading could be considered a form of expertise displayed by most Western adults – one could, for example, compare early learners with adults who have achieved full reading competence. Indeed, it could be argued that we all are experts to some extent when it comes to the practices of our culture(s). Those who participate fully in a religion are experts at that religion. Hence, there is not such a clear separation between cultural practices and individual expertise. Cultural and individual expertise, however, are just symptoms of a far more vexing problem. While cultural and individual expertise suggest alternate sources of functional design, their manifestations are not readily confused for natural design due to fairly clear signs of recent origin and their heterogeneous distribution through human populations. However, a potential alternate source of functional design opens the door to the possibility that even universal traits are examples of expertise and not adaptation. Consider two hotly debated examples, face processing and cheater detection. A number of researchers have argued that face processing constitutes an innate, domain-specific competence (see Kanwisher, 2000) that some evolutionary psychologists have argued is an evolved adaptation (Duchaine, Cosmides, & Tooby, 2001). Opposing this view are those who argue that face processing is a form of acquired expertise (e.g., Diamond & Carey, 1986; Gauthier & Tarr, 1997). Or consider the debate over social reasoning on the Wason selection task. Cosmides and Tooby (1992; Cosmides, 1985, 1989) have argued that “cheater detection” on social contract versions of the selection task is the product of evolved, cognitive adaptations for social exchange. One of the most favored alternative explanations is pragmatic reasoning schemas theory (Cheng & Holyoak, 1985), which argues that humans typically acquire domain-specific knowledge structures relating to social regulations by virtue of extensive, goal-directed exposure to such rules – in effect, that humans typically acquire an expertise for reasoning about social regulations such as social contracts. Acquired expertise represents a serious challenge to the adaptationist program for it not only represents an alternative account of functional design, but also, as these purported examples illustrate, expertise need not be limited to culturally and individually variable competences, but may extend to universally expressed competences. 11 Of course, the challenge raised by expertise and other forms of evolutionarily novel functionality is that they arise de novo – that the structure of the underlying mechanisms is, to some interesting extent, not co-opted from prior adaptations. It is far from obvious that this is indeed the case. In casting doubt on this claim I do not simply mean the trivial objection that learning requires a learning mechanism that in turn may be an adaptation. No, I mean that it is far from clear that the structure of the compiled mechanism itself is novel as opposed to borrowed from a pre-existing adaptation. Expertise may also depend on the co-optation of adaptations to some interesting extent. The Modules and Metaphors Program A wide variety of researchers including cognitive anthropologists, cognitive neuroscientists, and evolutionary psychologists have conducted research on evolutionarily novel competences according to a common set of assumptions or goals: 1) natural selection has shaped the human mind to provide it with a range of cognitive adaptations for solving problems that would have confronted ancestral humans, 2) evidence for these adaptations comes in the form of universal, domain-specific psychological faculties or knowledge, i.e. modules, 3) these mental adaptations have been co-opted or culturally elaborated giving rise to evolutionarily novel phenomena such as law, literature, mathematics, science and religion, and 4) research in this program strives to understand the structure of cultural phenomena in terms of mental structure inherited from prior psychological adaptations and not the current utility of cultural phenomena. Hence, the focus of this research program is on exadaptations, not exaptations. Perhaps the most articulate exponent for this emerging research program is Dan Sperber (1994; Sperber & Hirschfeld, 2004) who has initiated some of the themes that I will elaborate upon here. Modules The term module means different things to different people. Perhaps the best known characterization of modules is Fodor’s (1983) analysis of input systems – i.e., perceptual systems and language. Fodor proposed that modules possess a collection of properties such as domain-specificity, informational encapsulation, limited central access, and a fixed neural architecture. Evolutionary psychologists, on the other hand, have viewed cognitive adaptations more generally as modules, be they input systems or central processes (Cosmides & Tooby, 1994). According to this analysis, modules qua cognitive adaptations bear evidence of special design for solving specific adaptive problems (Tooby & Cosmides, 1992). Cognitive adaptations will, of course, tend to possess many of the properties identified by Fodor such as domain-specificity, speed, a fixed neural architecture and a robust and reliable development, but there is no reason to assume that they will necessarily possess these or any other of Fodor’s proposed properties. To begin with, Fodor restricted his analysis to input systems and it would be rather arbitrary to restrict mental adaptation in this way. Properties such as limited central access, shallow outputs (at least so far as this means nonconceptual representations), and mandatory operation (at least with respect to externally presented input stimuli) that primarily apply to peripheral mechanisms are, therefore, overly restrictive. More importantly though, 12 there is no reason to assume that modules constitute a classical category with necessary and sufficient features. Like many other biological kinds, modules will presumably display a family resemblance relation to one another with no one set of features shared between all members, but each module bearing some subset of features characterizing the kind more generally. Special design also evades strict definition in terms of necessary and sufficient properties (Williams, 1966). Instead, one will have to proceed on a case by case basis using a task analysis of the problem to be solved to see if there is sufficient justification for concluding that a specific mechanism is an adaptation. Because different adaptive problems pose different challenges, it is unlikely that there will be any universal standard of special design. As with the concept of fitness, the “specialness” of any one design can only be judged with respect to alternative designs. Likewise, the domainspecificity, informational encapsulation, speed, and so forth of any one mechanism can only be judged with respect to alternative mechanisms. One can think of adaptations as having an organized structure that embodies a particular mode of operation, a modus operandi, that was designed for a specific set of problems encountered in ancestral environments. Keil (1994) has referred to a cognitive mechanism’s mode of construal, however, this frames things not only in cognitive terms but in a relatively narrow way suggesting that the task of a cognitive mechanism is conceptualization. Not only does this choice of terminology fail to capture different types of information processing such as inference, but it would also be awkward to apply to noncognitive adaptations such as the heart. Hence, I will refer more generally to an adaptation’s modus operandi. The modus operandi is not the same as an adaptation’s function, where function is the adaptive effect that the adaptation brings about. The difference is that between means and ends. The modus operandi of an adaptation is the means by which it brings about its adaptive ends or functions. Given the multiple realizability of functions (Fodor, 1975, 1981; Putnam, 1975), the modus operandi of an adaptation more closely reflects its particular structure than does the adaptation’s function. While Fodor’s and Putnam’s analyses of function were focused on cognitive functions, not biological functions, the same arguments would readily apply to biological functions as suggested by biological analogues like the wings of birds, bats and insects. Perhaps less problematically one can borrow the term, domain, from the cognitive sciences to refer to an adaptation’s range of application – that which the adaptation acts upon. A domain is not necessarily a body of knowledge or information, but can be viewed more broadly as the object, substance, or entity upon which the adaptation acts, which may or may not contain an informational component. Again, consider the heart. One can think of blood as the heart’s domain of application – the substance upon which it acts – without thereby committing oneself to a conception of a domain in terms of informational content. Typically the domain of an adaptation is in some sense external to it and, in many cases, even external to the organism. The blood that the heart pumps is not intrinsically part of the heart, but external to it – part of its environment. Therefore, one can make a distinction between the complex, functional structure of an adaptation, most clearly reflected by its modus operandi, and its domain of application, that aspect of the environment that it operates on, to bring about an adaptive end, the adaptation’s function. An important distinction for the modules and metaphors program is that between an adaptation’s proper and actual functions (Millikan, 1984; Sperber & Hirschfeld, 13 2004). The proper function of an adaptation is the set of its effects that are causally responsible for the adaptation’s existence and design – i.e., what biologists typically refer to as an adaptation’s function. The actual function of an adaptation is the set of effects that it currently brings about, regardless of whether these contributed to the existence and design of the adaptation. Millikan (1984, p.2) illustrates the distinction with the following example. The human hand undoubtedly evolved for “grasping, manipulating, pushing or pulling.” These are proper functions of the hand. Yet, hands can also be used “as matter upon which to draw, as subjects for physiological experimentation, as objects of aesthetic contemplation, etc.” These uses, in addition to grasping, manipulation, pushing and pulling, are actual functions of the hand. Sperber (1994) later extended this idea in drawing a distinction between an adaptation’s proper and actual domains, where the proper domain of an adaptation is that which it was selected to operate on whereas the actual domain is that which it does operate on regardless of whether it was selected to do so. These distinctions between proper and actual functions / domains are adaptationist distinctions. It is the past history of selection that determines which effects are and are not part of an adaptation’s proper function. An adaptivist, on the other hand, might follow Gould (2002) and distinguish between effects that do and do not currently enhance fitness (inherent potentials and available things, respectively), but given that these are defined in terms of present as opposed to past utilities, these would not be coextensive with the proper and actual functions of an adaptation. Likewise, exaptations, or more properly their effects, do not coincide with the actual functions of an adaptation for not only may the actual function of an adaptation include its proper functions, the actual function of a mechanism is not limited to those effects that enhance fitness. More importantly though, it is the adaptationist’s focus on organized structure and the recognition that such structures can persist, lag behind environmental changes, that recommends an adaptationist, but not an adaptivist, account of metaphor. Metaphors Metaphorical and analogical reasoning processes in humans have been widely documented by cognitive linguists (e.g., Lakoff, 1987) and cognitive psychologists (e.g., Gentner, Holyoak, & Kokinov, 2001). Metaphorical thought processes entail mapping the structure of a source domain onto a target domain. There are, however, constraints on this mapping. First, as Lakoff (1987, p. 276) notes, “To function as a source domain for a metaphor, a domain must be understood independent of the metaphor.” Hence, in order to serve as a source domain, one must already have an intuitive understanding of the domain, which is exactly what cognitive adaptations provide for their proper domain of application. Moreover, cognitive adaptations provide a structured understanding of their proper domains and it is this structure or modus operandi that can potentially be applied to the target domain. A second constraint on metaphorical thought processes rarely if ever discussed by students of metaphor is the need to contain informational corruption (Cosmides & Tooby, 2000). Consider one of Lakoff’s (1987) metaphors, anger (target domain) as a heated fluid in a container (source domain), as in “He was bursting with anger” (p. 385, emphasis original). Whatever practical use this metaphor has could easily be outweighed by the potential damage done to one’s stored knowledge were one to erroneously store 14 the belief that anger is in fact a heated fluid in a container. Were this to happen one might entertain the erroneous beliefs that one could cook with anger, heat a home with it or drive a piston with it. Alternatively, one might attempt to reduce someone’s anger by pouring cold water on them. What prevents this from happening when concepts from these two domains are brought together and connected in thought? Cognitive linguists have implicitly recognized the significance of this problem by embracing Fauconnier’s (1994, 1997) theory of mental spaces, which effectively deals with it. Mental spaces are cognitive workspaces within which the contents of discourse or thought can be represented. Without delving too deeply into Fauconnier’s theory, several aspects of mental spaces are worth noting. First, multiple mental spaces can be entertained simultaneously, but new spaces are always introduced within a parent space, the original parent space being the speaker’s or thinker’s understanding of reality. In the embedded spaces, truth relations can be suspended or made conditional on the space. For example, suppose someone was considering a picture that Alan took of Mary. The person might construct a picture that Alan took space in which Mary might be wearing a red dress, whereas in reality as the thinker knows it (the parent space) Mary is wearing pants and a white blouse. Second, although connections may be made between spaces – the Mary in the picture that Alan took space is connected to the Mary in the parent reality space – the contents of an embedded space cannot migrate to the parent space, i.e., Mary’s wearing a red dress is contained within the picture that Alan took space. Moreover, logical relations only hold within a space – i.e., within the picture that Alan took space, Mary cannot simultaneously be wearing a red dress and not wearing a red dress, whereas between spaces logical contradictions such as this may hold. Therefore, the contents of an embedded space cannot alter the contents of the parent space though their logical entailments, i.e., the fact that Mary is wearing a red dress in the picture space does not cause one to revise one’s belief that Mary is wearing pants and a blouse in the parent reality space. Thirdly, many cognitive linguists, including Fauconnier (1997), have analyzed metaphor as a mapping from a parent source-domain space to an embedded target-domain space. Hence, given the bounded and contained nature of mental spaces, metaphorical thoughts entertained within the embedded target-domain space cannot migrate to the parent space (the thinker’s reality space), thereby corrupting his or her knowledge of the world. Although Fauconnier and others have put mental space theory to considerable use in explaining many aspects of language and discourse, no cognitive linguists that I am aware of has offered an account of why humans possess the ability to form mental spaces. Cosmides and Tooby (2000), on the other hand, have provided an evolutionary explanation of why such mechanisms are needed to avoid informational corruption. Rather than adopting Fauconnier’s mental space framework, they suggest that a system of metarepresentations in which truth relations are suspended are required to handle the problems of informational corruption posed by communication and various forms of thought. Fauconnier’s mental spaces are simply a specific instance of such a representational system and so I will refer more generally to the ability to form metarepresentations. Both Fauconnier (1994, 1997) and Cosmides and Tooby (2000) consider these metarepresentational abilities to be a separate faculty of mind. This raises the possibility that metaphorical thought may be dissociable from other thought processes. Evidence 15 from autism suggests precisely this. It has been suggested that autism is characterized by an impaired ability to form metarepresentations (Suddendorf, 1999). It is interesting to note, therefore, that persons with autism appear to have a reduced appreciation of metaphor. They also have difficulty imagining the unreal (Scott & Baron-Cohen, 1996). Mention Gilbert experiment and Hermer and Spelke experiments here from an adaptationist perspective, such intuitive understanding is structured – embodies a particular modus operandi. An adaptationist account of metaphor However, Boyer (1994) has objected to the nonrigorous use of “metaphor” as a mechanism for understanding religious thought, but trope of metaphor is a familiar one that gives a good sense of the phenomenon I am proposing and, nonetheless, is harmless provided one spells out the mechanism by which metaphorical inferences are achieved. One of the ways in which the concept of “metaphor” is made more rigorous within this program is by supplying a scientifically sound theory of base domains. One of the problems besetting the study of metaphor in cognitive linguistics (e.g., Lakoff, 1987), for example, is the lack of a coherent theory of base domains. Thought, according to Lakoff (1987) is both embodied and imaginative. Metaphor, an important aspect of imaginative thought, employs concepts derived from our embodied cognition. But what is embodied cognition? Thought is embodied, that is, the structures used to put together our conceptual systems grow out of bodily experience and make sense in terms of it; moreover, the core of our conceptual systems is directly grounded in perception, bodily movement, and experience of physical and social character (p. xiv, emphasis original). However, a definition of embodied cognition such as this either includes too much or too little. Assuming that we are materialists and not dualists, what is excluded from this definition? If nothing is excluded, then how can we make sense of Lakoff’s characterization of imaginative thought? Thought is imaginative, in that those concepts which are not directly grounded in experience employ metaphor, metonomy, and mental imagery – all of which go beyond the literal mirroring, or representation, of external reality. It is this imaginative capacity that allows for “abstract” thought and takes the mind beyond what we can see and feel. The imaginative capacity is also embodied – indirectly – since the metaphors, metonymies, and images are based on experience, often bodily experience (p. xiv, emphasis original). Clearly, Lakoff has a restricted sense of embodiment in mind, otherwise there would be no room left for imaginative thought. But if the base domains are restricted to concrete, physical existence, then how can we begin to make sense of the mind-body problem, not 16 its solution, but the very fact that it is or ever was viewed as a problem? For if mind, a nonphysical concept, is based on physical metaphors, how could it ever appear that the former is incompatible with the latter? The modules and metaphors program handles problems such as these with ease. Our evolved human nature supplies our base domain concepts and inferences. Evolutionary theory provides clear guidelines as to what these base domains might be, they are constituted by the adaptive problems that would have confronted our ancestors. Evolutionarily novel problems constitute the range of target domains to which our repertoire of evolved concepts and inferential machinery can be imaginatively applied. Problems of translation, from mind to body, and the like, result from the modularity of the cognitive adaptations. Concepts designed for one adaptive problem may be unavailable to or incommensurate with other adaptive problems. Moreover, the metaphorical extensions of base concepts could potentially inherit these same properties, with concepts derived from one adaptive problem being incommensurate with those derived from different adaptive problem. This line of analysis could, in turn, also be extended to account for incommensurate, cultural worldviews. It should be noted that an evolutionary account of cognition need not preclude the possibility that cognition is embodied. On the contrary, the sort of framework typically adopted by evolutionary psychologists (e.g., Tooby & Cosmides, 1992) represents a specific theory of how cognition is embodied. Consider, for example, the following descriptions of embodiment offered by Lakoff (1987): Conceptual embodiment: The idea that the properties of certain categories are a consequence of the nature of human biological capacities and of the experience of functioning in a physical and social environment. It is contrasted with the idea that concepts exist independent of the bodily nature of any thinking beings and independent of their experience. Functional embodiment: The idea that certain concepts are not merely understood intellectually; rather, they are used automatically, unconsciously, and without noticeable effort as part of normal functioning (pp. 12-13). This view of cognition as pragmatic and shaped by the life-history of the organism is quite similar to that espoused by evolutionary psychologists. Moreover, the automatic, unconscious, and effortless quality of embodied cognition fits squarely with the view that cognitive adaptations are modular instincts (cf. Fodor, 1983). Where the evolutionary view diverges from Lakoff’s account of embodiment is in the mechanism by which embodiment is achieved. Lakoff’s mechanism of embodiment is question-begging given that it relies upon unmediated experience as the source of cognitive structure, but experience, in the psychological sense, requires a prior set of cognitive mechanisms that do the experiencing. Experience in a direct physical sense leaves unexplained how the mind is shaped by the physical environment. By contrast, the theory of evolution by natural selection provides a workable mechanism by which the mind can be shaped to fit the physical environment. How does the program work? 17 Is it compatible with evolutionary psychology? Is it compatible with evolutionary psychology? In The Prehistory of the Mind, Mithen (1996) launched into an attack on evolutionary psychology citing precisely the sort of phenomena that I have suggested the modules and metaphors program can handle – cultural innovations of anatomically modern humans in which evolved, purportedly modular abilities are applied outside of their proper domains. According to Mithen this dissolution of domains constitutes prima facie evidence that the mind of modern humans is not modular. This argument has been further taken up by Chiappe (2000) who argues that cross-domain integration is particularly evident in the phenomenon of metaphor, a key element of my proposed program for dealing with evolutionarily novel, cultural phenomena and expertise. Hence, the question inevitably arises is what I am proposing complementary to or opposed to evolutionary psychology? Yes, I would argue, the modules and metaphors program is compatible with evolutionary psychology. It requires evolutionary psychology as a means of investigating source conceptual and inferential domains. What these critiques turn on is an overly narrow view of modules, one that evolutionary psychologists need not and do not subscribe to. Ultimately, the appeal of modularity to evolutionary psychologists is that it appears to capture the adaptationist’s concept of “special design.” Special design typically viewed in engineering terms of economy, efficiency, accuracy, and so forth, with the claim being made that domain-specific mechanisms are more likely to exhibit these qualities than domain-general mechanisms (Tooby & Cosmides, 1992). To the extent that a domain-general mechanism is more economical, efficient, and accurate than a domain-specific mechanism, then natural selection should clearly favor the domaingeneral mechanism. That a mechanism is informationally encapsulated, cognitively impenetrable, mandatory, fast or possess any other quality characteristic of modules according to Fodor (1983) is irrelevant – though the argument could easily be made, for example, that to the extent that cognitive adaptations are economical and efficient they will be informationally encapsulated and fast. These qualities of special design, economy, efficiency, accuracy, and so forth are not simply abstract concepts, they refer to biological structures. The qualities of special design act as a guide in determining the function of the structure under investigation as a means of explaining the organization of that structure. Again, special design and its associated qualities are relative to a particular set of environments – the ancestral environments in which the mechanism evolved. There is no incoherence in claiming that adaptive design lags behind environmental changes – evolution thorough natural selection is an extremely slow process. Consequently, it is not problematic for evolutionary psychologists when an evolved structure persists and even operates in novel environments that it was not designed for. Once we distinguish between the structure of a mechanism (embodying a particular modus operandi) and its domain of application, we have all we need to answer the critics. The complex, functional structure of an evolved mechanism can persist and continue to operate despite radical changes in the environment in which it operates. While its proper domain of application remains fixed, its actual domain of application can 18 change with changing environmental circumstances. What is problematic for an evolutionary view of mind, regardless of whether the mechanisms in question are domain-specific or domain-general – is not sudden changes in the domain of application but sudden changes in the organizational structure of the mechanism. What the critics need to argue, but have not, is that complex functional design of a cognitive adaptation is changed in the near term (and not simply towards dysfunction) by changes in the environment. Yet this is not what Chiappe (2000), for example, claims. Indeed, the very phenomenon that Chiappe invokes against the modularity of mind, namely metaphorical reasoning, assumes a persistence of structure. Were the structure of an organizing concept from a base domain to change in the process of being applied to the target domain, the end result would fail to be a metaphor. Exadaptations How does that work? Do they exist? There are, perhaps other types of byproducts, such as vestigial organs, but the type of byproduct that I have in mind when coining the term exadaptations are adaptations that have largely been co-opted for evolutionarily novel uses (Buss, Haselton, Shackelford, Bleske, & Wakefield, 1998, refer to these as co-opted adaptations). When speaking of psychological adaptations, it will help to make a distinction between an adaptation’s modus operandi and its domain of application. When the environment changes from ancestral conditions, there can be a lag in which the adaptation continues to operate, but is applied in different circumstances. With morphological adaptations, the persistence of the adaptation in the face of changing environmental circumstances is easy to detect – the physical structure either remains or it does not. Take a fish out of water and its fins remain. They look pretty much as they did in water and probably move much the same way as well. With psychological adaptations the picture is less clear, it is much more difficult to point to a physical structure. Instead, psychological adaptations are potentially recognized by their modus operandi, their characteristic way of operating – even with quite radical changes in the domain of application, operation of a psychological adaptation can potentially be detected if its modus operandi is sufficiently distinctive. There are a variety of ways in which the domain of application of a cognitive adaptation can be altered. The environment can change such that the adaptation’s proprietary inputs no longer exist, in which case the adaptation can either cease to operate or its modus operandi may be applied to a novel set of inputs. However, the adaptation’s evolved domain of application need not disappear, it may simply contract or even expand. In the case of domain expansion, the adaptation can continue to perform its evolved function, yet simultaneously operate on novel inputs. Here it will help to make use of additional distinctions. Millikan (1984) has made a distinction between an adaptation’s proper function – the effects that it was designed by natural selection to bring about – and an adaptation’s actual function – the effects that it does in fact bring about. Sperber (1994) further elaborated Millikan’s proposal by distinguishing between 19 an adaptation’s proper domain – the range of situations (contents) the adaptation evolved to apply to – and the adaptation’s actual domain – the range of situations (contents) that the adaptation applies to. The proper function / domain of an adaptation is a matter of historical fact, it does not change as the environment changes, unless, of course, one is talking about long periods of change over which time natural selection has had time to alter the constitution of the adaptation accordingly. It is the actual function / domain of an adaptation that is potentially much more fluid and liable to change with environmental changes. So to rephrase, as the environment changes, the actual function / domain of the mechanism can contract, perhaps even to nothing; it can expand beyond the proper function / domain; or it can shift to entirely new functions / domains. When I speak of an adaptation as having largely been co-opted, I mean that the adaptation’s modus operandi is still largely in evidence – i.e., the adaptation is not dysfunctional. (To avoid conflating dysfunctions with adaptations with intact modus operandi, but altered domains of application, I will limit my discussion to changes in an adaptation’s actual domain, ignoring its actual function). Since the modus operandi of the adaptation more or less intact, the resulting behavior will display complexly organized functionality. However, in the case of broadened or displaced actual domains, the ‘adaptation’ is in fact, doing something novel, something that it was not selected for, hence it would perhaps be best to speak of the resulting trait as being a byproduct and not an adaptation. With broadened domains, one could continue to speak of the adaptation in its proper domain while referring to the extended, novel uses of the adaptation as being a byproduct of the adaptation. This class of byproducts, ‘adaptations’ with extended or displaced actual domains of application arguably constitute the primary source of exadaptations. They are problematic for adaptationists because, owing to their relatively intact modus operandi, they appear very much like adaptations – they perform complexly, functionally integrated operations – but because the domain of application is novel, i.e. they lack the right evolutionary pedigree, they are not adaptations. This is not to say that any time there is an environmental change, exadaptations will result. In many cases, the end result will be dysfunction. Because functionality is to some extent preserved with exadaptations, species with some control over their environment may choose to augment these novel functions or even bring about entirely new functions without the aid of prior environmental change. Humans are very adept at altering their environment to suit their ends. But humans also appear rather unique in having some grasp of the contents of their own minds as well (Karmiloff-Smith, 1992). Hence, humans are perhaps uniquely positioned to enhance and shift the application of their adaptations, including mental adaptations, to new ends, giving rise to what Sperber (1994) has termed the cultural domain of an adaptation. Consider one evolutionarily novel cultural innovation, written language. Written language clearly is built on a foundation provided by a prior adaptation, spoken language (Pinker, 1994). Spoken language typically remains intact in those who can read and write, but the actual domain of this adaptation has been extended by environmental props, written text, that have been devised, refined and culturally transmitted by humans. Several cognitive anthropologists have suggested that that written language is not unique in this respect, that many cultural phenomena and individual expertise originate in this way, as novel applications of psychological adaptations (Atran, 1990; Boyer, 1994, 2003; Sperber, 1994, 2001; Sperber & Hirschfeld, 2004). Indeed, 20 several evolutionary psychologists have also argued that social and cultural phenomena such as erotica (Salmon & Symons, 2003), law (Fiddick, 2004), religion (Kirkpatrick, 1999), and the concept of race (Cosmides, Tooby, Kurzban, 2003; Gil-White, 2001; Kurzban, Tooby, & Cosmides, 2001) are extended or displaced applications of adaptations. Add Dehaene (1997) to this list for arithmetic Exaptation as a theoretical diversion Exaptation, Gould (1991) contended, is precisely the concept that evolutionary psychologists need to make sense of evolutionarily novel cultural phenomena. Yet, across numerous scientific investigations of cultural phenomena as diverse as literature (Salmon & Symons, 2003), religion (Boyer, 1994, 2003; Kirkpatrick, 1999) and science (Atran, 1990), the phenomena under investigation are traced back to adaptations by means of a common mode of mental operation – a characteristic modus operandi – with minimal reference if any made to the current utility of the trait (and far less still to utility in terms of enhanced reproductive success). Nor is it surprising that this should be the case, for the concept of exaptation suffers from precisely the same defects as the adaptivist program. Namely, investigations of current utility provide little insight into the structure of the trait under investigation (Symons, 1990). It is the ability to explain the structure and organization of a cultural phenomenon that many social scientists are interested in, not demonstrations of enhanced reproductive success, which is primarily of parochial interest. Like their colleagues operating from different theoretical frameworks, what these cognitive anthropologists and evolutionary psychologists seek to understand is the structure and organization of the phenomena under investigation. Where they differ from their colleagues is in proposing that these phenomena bear a noncoincidental resemblance to traits that are arguably adaptations. What they need is not the concept of exaptation, but the concept of exadaptation. The criticisms that I have raised about exaptations are not new. Buss et al. (1998) have put forward similar and more detailed criticisms of the concept of exaptations. However, arguing against the theoretical coherence and practical utility of the concept does little to address the problem of evolutionarily novel functional design and critiques of exaptation (e.g., Andrews, Gangestad, & Matthews, 2002; Buss et al., 1998) have typically offered little in the way of guidance for dealing with the problem. Instead the tendency has been an attempt to defang exaptation by casting it as a more onerous concept than adaptation by, for example, arguing that the postulation of an exaptive hypothesis requires one to first consider and then rule out adaptationist hypotheses. While this is may be true in theory, scientific progress routinely advances in much smaller measures, for truth be told, adaptationists rarely establish that a particular trait exhibits special design, for example. They may strive for such evidence, but whether or not they ever convincingly reach it is another matter. Moreover, some pieces of the empirical puzzle may be far more important in keeping a project alive than others, so while it be the case that exaptations pose a greater evidentiary burden, an immediate grasp that a particular trait lacks the right sort of history may be all that is required to sustain an exaptive hypothesis. Unless, of course, there is some rival account of evolutionarily novel 21 traits. Again, what is required is not just the concept of exadaptations or co-opted adaptations, but a research program for dealing with them. What do evolutionary psychologists have to gain from the modules and metaphors program? What do evolutionary psychologists have to gain from the modules and metaphors program? Notes on Gauthier Anyway, I recall you mentioning that when autistics are competent at recognizing / remembering faces, they process them in different ways than normals. Is this correct and if so, could you possibly supply me some references. Here's why I'm curious. I'm writing up the presentation that I gave last fall in Ottawa. One of the things that I argued then was that rather than arguing against the domain specificity of face processing with her greeble studies, Isabel Gauthier has in fact co-opted the face processing mechanism. Indeed, the more she shows that greeble recognition is like face recognition, the more she paints herself into a corner. Why? Well, this is where the autistism findings, if I recall what you said correctly, come into play. The autism results show that the specific mode of cognitive processing associated with faces in normals is not driven by the stimuli. Autistics process exactly the same faces as normals do, but they process them in different ways. Hence, to be a competent face processor does not mean that you will display inversion effects and the like. Inversion effects are not a property of the stimulus, but of the mind that processes the stimuli. So too the extent that greeble experts display the peculiarities of normal face processing they appear to be invoking the same cognitive mechanisms, when conceivably they could have invoked different cognitive mechanisms -- i.e. those used by autistics. Hence, it would seem to me that all Gauthier has shown is that greeble experts use their face mechanisms to recognize greeble. Now this might seem to have a residual downside to this in that face mechanisms do not process faces and faces alone. However, I can't see this as being a particularly damning critique of the modularity (specialization of face processing). Still, it is not as bad as it first seems, since not everyone uses their face mechanisms to process greebles, only greeble experts -- i.e., you really have to work at it to trick the face mechanisms to process greebles, a little tweaking is required to get it going. Again, this is exactly the sort of developmental trajectory one would expect if you trying to get a mechanism to do something it wasn't designed to do. I have argued that the modules and metaphors program is not simply compatible with the practice of evolutionary psychology, but that it is actually dependent upon evolutionary psychology to provide a source of scientific insight into the base domains of concepts and inferences that are available for co-opting. However, this need not mean 22 that the benefits are reciprocal. What are evolutionary psychologists to gain from the modules and metaphors program? The benefits, I will argue, are several. Explaining expertise Expertise, as I have suggested, represents a viable alternative account of adaptive design and hence one of the most important theoretical challenges to evolutionary psychology. Fortunately, the modules and metaphors program provides an alternative account of expertise. Consider in a bit more detail this time, the debate over face processing. One of the most prominent arguments against the existence of specialpurpose facial recognition mechanisms is that many of the same phenomena have been taken as evidence for the distinctiveness of facial recognition, such as configural processing, also are purportedly displayed by people trained to recognize individual “greebles” – imaginary 3-D creatures that are distinguished on the basis of the relations of their features as opposed to distinctive parts, i.e. their configural properties (Gauthier & Tarr, 1997). For example, facial features (e.g. the eyes or nose) studied in the context of a whole face are recalled best when they are later recalled in the context of the same face as opposed to the parts in isolation or a configurally transformed face (e.g., the mouth placed lower on the face) suggesting that facial features are not represented independently, but holistically as part of a whole face. By contrast. no advantage is observed for the recognition of house features or inverted face features in configurally intact targets (Tanaka & Farah, 1993). Gauthier and Tarr (1997) reported the same upright, intact configuration advantage for the recognition of greeble features in greeble experts as opposed to greeble novices (see also Gauthier & Nelson, 2001, for a review of the expertise findings). The process of acquiring expertise, however, is entirely understood. One way that people could become experts, according to the modules and metaphors program, is by recruiting a pre-existing module that was designed by natural selection for some other function. Indeed, such a process would be expected to result in precisely the “qualitative shift in processing” that Gauthier and Tarr (1997) take as indicative of expertise. Moreover, the more the domain of acquired expertise resembles the domain of a preexisting module, the more likely that that module will get recruited. Again, greebles were designed precisely to draw upon the same configural processing that face recognition requires (Gauthier & Tarr, 1997). Moreover, if in the process of becoming a greeble expert, people simply recruit face processing modules, then precisely the same neural structures should underlie face recognition and greeble recognition, which, it turns out, is the case (Gauthier, Tarr, Anderson, Skudlarski, & Gore, 1999). Of course, the explanation for these findings that Gauthier and her colleagues would like to give is that face recognition is really a form of acquired expertise, but the results could also be interpreted in precisely the opposite direction from the perspective of the modules and metaphors program, namely that in the process of becoming a greeble expert, Gauthier’s subjects have simply co-opted their face processing mechanisms (cf. McKone & Kanwisher, in press). How can we tease these two proposals apart? Empirically, it is could be fairly difficult to distinguish between the proposals. For example, while one might speculate that a face processing mechanism should presumably show a face advantage in terms of accuracy or robustness of configural effects, there is a 23 considerable confound in that most people will have considerably more experience processing faces than greebles. Ultimately, the most persuasive arguments are likely to be theoretical. Unless advocates of acquired expertise want to argue that all expertise, regardless of the domain involves the same mental processes and recruits the same neurological structures, then they are going to have to admit that they are implicitly arguing for a different collection of innate faculties. If not a face-specific faculty, then a configural processing faculty and the burden then falls upon the advocates of the expertise position to explain why natural selection would have favored the evolution of such a faculty of mind. What plausible selection pressures could have favored the evolution of configural processing, per se, when it primarily seems to be invoked by individual bird, car, face and greeble recognition (see Gauthier & Nelson, 2001, for a defense of the position that expert bird, car, face and greeble recognition all recruit the same mental / neurological structures)? Cast in this evolutionarily light, it seems far more parsimonious to claim that configural processing is simply a design feature of an evolved face recognition mechanism. Drawing defensible boundaries around adaptationist proposals The modules and metaphors program can potentially help evolutionary psychologists from falling into the trap of trying to explain too much in terms of adaptive design. Without a distinction between the proper domain of an evolved mechanism and its actual metaphorical extension, evolutionary psychologists could be tempted to explain more than is warranted by a consideration of the evolutionary history of an adaptation. Consider, for example, the debate over Cosmides’ (1989) attempt to account for reasoning about social exchanges and social laws with the same adaptationist explanation. According to social contract theory, people possess an evolved “look for cheaters” algorithm that is activated in situations involving social exchange, cooperation for mutual benefit. In providing an evolutionary rationale for this proposal, Cosmides (1989; Cosmides & Tooby, 1989, 1992) referred to evolutionary theories of reciprocal altruism that suggested that reciprocal altruism could not evolve without the ability to detect and punish cheaters (e.g., Axelrod & Hamilton, 1981; Trivers, 1971). These evolutionary models invariably featured two agents potentially engaged in a reciprocal exchange of benefits, yet Cosmides applied her account of cheater detection beyond the confines of reciprocal exchange. Cosmides (1989) tested her proposal using the well known Wason selection task in which subjects are asked to reason about a conditional rule. As Cosmides rightly noted, an offer to engage in social exchange can be phrased as a conditional rule of the form: If you take the benefit, then you must pay the cost, and when social exchanges (which Cosmides referred to a personal exchanges) are so phrased and embedded in the selection task, performance on the task improved substantially. However, social contracts rules such as this can also be used to describe situations in which no reciprocity or exchange of benefits takes place. For example, Cosmides argued that the drinking age rule: If you drink alcohol, then you must be at least 21 years old, is social contract and likewise activates the proposed “look for cheaters” algorithm. Indeed, social law versions of social contract rules – social contracts that do not involve social exchange – also reliably elicit correct performance on the selection task. 24 Rather than arguing that these social laws are metaphorical extensions of social exchanges, brought about straightforwardly by similar rules, Cosmides provided a generalized account of reasoning about social contracts that blurred the distinction between personal exchanges (proper social exchanges) and social laws, like the drinking age rule. Cheng and Holyoak (1989) correctly noted this apparent inconsistency in Cosmides’ formulation of the theory. However, rather than dealing with the problem honestly by either formulating an alternative evolutionary theory of cooperation that extended beyond social exchanges or proposing a distinction between the proper and actual domain of application of the hypothesized mechanisms, Fiddick, Cosmides, and Tooby (2000, Appendix A) simply asserted that there is no evolutionary justification for distinguishing between social exchanges and social laws. There are, in fact, good grounds for skepticism. To begin with, the very theories that Cosmides’ (1985, 1989; Cosmides & Tooby, 1989) cited make no reference to anything like social laws. They deal primarily with social exchanges involving two parties, both of which receive a benefit. Fiddick et al. (2000) also objected that Cheng and Holyoak (1989) narrowly interpreted exchanges to mean the exchange of objects. This is a mischaracterization of Cheng and Holyoak’s argument. Their argument with respect to rules such as the drinking age rule is not that age is not an object, but that it is not a benefit to the other party. Regardless of whether initially casting the theory in terms of reciprocal exchange was too narrow a focus (cf. Cummins, 1999; Hiraishi & Hasegawa, 2001), the attempt to explain all performance displaying the same modus operandi as being part of the proper function of the proposed mechanism was clearly an error and resulted avoidable confusion and skepticism regarding the claims of evolutionary psychology. A better approach would have been to limit the scope of one’s adaptationist arguments and invoked the something like the modules and metaphors framework beyond defendable adaptationist boundaries. Gaining insight from culture and expertise The modules and metaphors program suggests the means by which the students of culture and expertise can potentially apply evolutionary psychological findings to their own phenomena of interest even when what they are studying is not even conceivably an adaptation. This is likely to prove most profitable when the phenomenon that they are studying bears some evidence of complex functionality and, hence, may reflect co-opted functional design. The benefits, however, do not only flow one way, from evolutionary psychology to cultural and expertise studies. If one accepts that cultural phenomena and expertise can be reflections of functional design, then it becomes possible to study functional design via its metaphorical extension. Not only is there a long cultural tradition in art, literature, and religion – not to mention the formal studies of these phenomena – attempting to make the ineffable manifest, but sometimes cultural products provide unique insights into the minds that make them that would not otherwise be available. Given the inevitable constraints that the conflicting interests of the sexes imposed on observed mating behavior, the idealized worlds of romance and pornutopia provide valuable insights into the mating psychology of human females and males that might not otherwise be observable (Salmon & Symons, 2003). However, in using romance novels, erotica and pornography to understand the minds that produced it, one is working within 25 the modules and metaphors program, only working backwards from metaphorical extensions to the evolved modules presumably give shape to the cultural products. Critiques of exaptation (Andrews et al., 2002; Buss et al., 1998) would leave one with the impression that this could be a particularly perilous enterprise, for not only would one first have to establish reasonable grounds for assuming the existence of a mental adaptation, but one would also have to argue that the cultural phenomenon or instance of expertise under investigation is a metaphorical extension of that adaptation, with the implication being that it would be easier simply to pursue the adaptationist program. However, no science worthy of the name is transparent, even mental phenomena are not readily transparent to the researchers studying them and all the more so when the mental structures in question are modular with little cognitive access. Hence, the speculative hypothesis that some cultural phenomenon is the metaphorical extension of a mental adaptation based upon the recognition of a common modus operandi could provide a valuable source of insights into the structure and operation of the mental adaptation. By a process of reflective equilibrium working from cultural trait to psychological trait and vice versa, one can potentially refine one’s understanding of both the psychological trait and the cultural phenomena that are likely extensions of it. Conclusions By providing an adaptationist alternative to exaptation, the modules and metaphors program can hopefully put to rest a bad explanation for a real phenomenon. That phenomenon is evolutionarily novel complex functionality, which is potentially problematic for adaptationists since it challenges the priority of natural selection as the source of natural design. However, through framework of the modules and metaphors program, evolutionarily novel functional design can potentially be explained as the metaphorical extension of prior adaptive designs. 26 References Andrews PW, Gangestad SW, Matthews D Adaptationism - how to carry out an exaptationist program BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES 25 (4): 489-504. AUG 2002 Atran, S. (1990) Cognitive foundations of natural history: Towards an anthropology of science. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. Atran, S. (2002). Modest adaptationism: Muddling through cognition and language. BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES 25 (4): 504-506. AUG 2002 Axelrod, R., & Hamilton, W. (1981). The evolution of cooperation. Science, 211, 13901396. Barrett, L., Dunbar, R., & Lycett, J. (2002). Human evolutionary psychology. New York, NY: Palgrave. Bédard, J. & Chi, M. (1992). Expertise. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 1, 135-139. Bloom, P. (1999). The evolution of certain novel human capacities. In M. Corballis & S. Lea (Eds.). The descent of mind. (pp. 295-310). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Boyer, P. (1994). The naturalness of religious ideas: A cognitive theory of religion. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Boyer, P. (2003). Religious thought and behavior as by-products of brain function. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 119-124, Adaptations, exaptations, and spandrels Author(s): Buss DM, Haselton MG, Shackelford TK, Bleske AL, Wakefield JC Source: AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGIST 53 (5): 533-548 MAY 1998 Cheng, P., & Holyoak, K. (1989). On the natural selection of reasoning theories. Cognition, 33, 285-313. Chiappe, D. (2000). Metaphor, modularity, and the evolution of conceptual integration. Metaphor and Symbol, 15, 137-158. Cosmides, L. (1985). Deduction or Darwinian algorithms?: An explanation of the “elusive” content effect on the Wason selection task. Doctoral dissertation, Harvard University. University Microfilms 86-02206. 27 Cosmides, L. (1989). The logic of social exchange: Has natural selection shaped how humans reason? Studies with the Wason selection task. Cognition, 31, 187-276. Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1992). Cognitive adaptations for social exchange. In J. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The adapted mind. (pp. 163-228). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Cummins, D. D. (1999). Cheater detection is modified by social rank: The impact of dominance on the evolution of cognitive functions. Evolution & Human Behavior, 20, 229-248. Daly, M. & Wilson, M. (1988). Homicide. Hawthorne, NY: Aldine de Gruyter. Dehaene, S. (1997). The number sense. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Dehaene, S., & Cohen, L. (1991). Two mental calculation systems: A case-study of severe acalculia with preserved approximation. Neuropsychologia, 25, 1045-1054. Dennett, D. (1995). Darwin’s dangerous idea. New York, NY: Simon & Schuster. Diamond, R., & Carey, S. (1986). Why faces are not special: An effect of expertise. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 115, 107-117. Evolutionary psychology and the brain AU: Duchaine, Bradley; Cosmides, Leda; Tooby, John SO: Current Opinion in Neurobiology. Special Issue: Cognitive neuroscience. Vol 11(2), Apr 2001, pp. 225-230 Fessler, D., & Navarrete, C. (2003). Meat is good to taboo: Dietary proscriptions as a product of the interaction of psychological mechanisms and social processes. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 3, 1-40. Fiddick, L. (2004). Natural law and natural selection. In C. Crawford and C. Salmon (Eds.). Evolutionary psychology, public policy, and private decisions. (pp. 169-194). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Fiddick, L., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (2000). No interpretation without representation: The role of domain-specific representations and inferences in the Wason selection task. Cognition, 77, 1-79. Fodor, J. (1983). Modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press / Bradford Book. 28 The development of face expertise AU: Gauthier, Isabel; Nelson, Charles A SO: Current Opinion in Neurobiology. Special Issue: Cognitive neuroscience. Vol 11(2), Apr 2001, pp. 219-224 Gauthier, I. & Tarr, M.J. (1997). Becoming a “greeble” expert: Exploring mechanisms for face recognition. Vision Research, 37, 1673-1682. Gauthier, I., Tarr, M. J., Anderson, A. W., Skudlarski, P., & Gore, J. C. (1999). Activation of the middle fusiform ‘face area’ increases with expertise in recognizing novel objects. Nature Neuroscience, 2, 568-573. Gentner, D., Holyoak, K., & Kokinov, B. (2001). The analogical mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Ghiselin, Michael T. (1973). Darwin and Evolutionary Psychology. Science 179: 964968. Gould, S.J. (1991). Exaptation: A crucial tool for an evolutionary psychology. Journal of Social Issues, 47, 43-65. Gould, S.J. & Lewtonin, R. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society London, Series B, 205, 581-598. Gould, S.J. & Vrba, E. (1982). Exaptation: A missing term in the science of form. Paleobiology, 8, 4-15. Hiraishi, K., & Hasegawa, T. (2001). Sharing-rule and detection of free-riders in cooperative groups: Evolutionarily important deontic reasoning in the Wason selection task. Thinking and Reasoning, 7, 255-294 Kanwisher, N. (2000). Domain-specificity in face perception. Nat. Neurosci. 3, 759-763. Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1992). Beyond modularity: A developmental perspective on cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, fire, and dangerous things. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Does the human brain process objects-of-expertise like faces: an update Elinor McKone * School of Psychology, Australian National University ACT 0200 Australia and Nancy Kanwisher 29 Functional magnetic resonance imaging of mental strategy in a simulated aviation performance task AU: Peres, Michel; Van De Moortele, Pierre Francois; Pierard, Christophe; Lehericy, Stephane; Le Bihan, Denis; Guezennec, Charles-Yannick SO: Aviation, Space, & Environmental Medicine. Vol 71(12), Dec 2000, pp. 1218-1231 Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Ruth Garrett Millikan, White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice (Cambridge, Mass.: Bradford Books/MIT Press, 1993) Mithen, S. (1996). The prehistory of the mind. London: Thames and Hudson. Murphy, D., & Stich, S. (2000). Darwin in the madhouse: Evolutionary psychology and the classification of mental disorders. In P. Carruthers & A. Chamberlain (Eds.). Evolution and the human mind: Modularity, language, and meta-cognition. (pp. 62-92). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Newell A., & Simon, H.A. (1972). Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Pinker, S. (1994). The language instinct. New York, NY: Morrow. Salmon, C. & Symons, D. (2003). Warrior lovers: Erotic fiction, evolution, and female sexuality. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Scott, F. J., & Baron-Cohen, S. (1996). Imagining real and unreal things: Evidence of a dissociation in autism. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 8, 371-382. EROTIC FICTION, EVOLUTION AND FEMALE SEXUALITY Smith EA, Mulder MB, Hill K Controversies in the evolutionary social sciences: a guide for the perplexed TRENDS IN ECOLOGY & EVOLUTION 16 (3): 128-135 MAR 2001 Dan Sperber (1994). “The modularity of thought and the epidemiology of representations” in L. Hirschfeld & S. Gelman (Eds.) Mapping the Mind (pp. 39-67). New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN: 0521419662 0521429935 (pbk.) 30 Dan Sperber (2001) “Mental modularity and cultural diversity” in H. Whitehouse (Ed.). The debated mind. New York: Berg. ISBN: 1859734278 (cloth) 1859734324 (pbk.) Dan Sperber & Lawrence Hirschfeld (2004) “The cognitive foundations of cultural stability and diversity” Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 40-46. Steen, F., & Owens, S. (2001). Evolution's pedagogy: An adaptationist model of pretense and entertainment. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 1, 289-321. Symons, D. (1990). Adaptiveness and adaptation. Ethology and Sociobiology, 11, 427-444. Symons, D. (1992). On the use and misuse of Darwinism. In J. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The adapted mind (pp. 137-159). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Tanaka, J.W. & Farah, M.J. (1993). Parts and wholes in face recognition. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 46A, 225-245. Superior digit memory of abacus experts: An event-related functional MRI study AU: Tanaka, Satoshi; Michimata, Chikashi; Kaminaga, Tatsuro; Honda, Manabu; Sadato, Norihiro SO: Neuroreport: For Rapid Communication of Neuroscience Research. Vol 13(17), Dec 2002, pp. 2187-2191 Thornhill, R. & Palmer, C. (2000). A natural history of rape. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. (1990). On the universality of human nature and the uniqueness of the individual: The role of genetics and adaptation. Journal of Personality, 58, 17-68. Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. (1992). Psychological foundations of culture. In J. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The adapted mind (pp. 19-136). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Trivers, R. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology, 46, 35-57. 31 Wagner, R. (1999). Searching for determinants of performance in complex domains. In P. Ackerman, P. Kyllonen, & R. Roberts (Eds.). Learning and individual differences: Process, trait, and content determinants. (pp. 371-385). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Disorder as Harmful Dysfunction: A Conceptual Critique of DSM–III–R's Definition of Mental Disorder AU: Wakefield, Jerome C. 1, 2 SO: Psychological Review. Vol 99 (2), April 1992, pp. 232-247 Williams, G. (1966). Adaptation and natural selection. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Wrangham, R., & Peterson, D. (1997). Demonic males: Apes and the origins of human violence. London: Bloomsbury. Wynn, K. (1995). Infants possess a system of numerical knowledge. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 4, 172-177. 32 Footnotes 1 Here, as in the rest of the paper, I mean function in the nontechnical sense as a system of parts working as a whole, typically to bring about some useful end with no implication that use translates to reproductive success. When referring to functions in the evolutionary biologist’s sense of the term I will refer to proper functions (Millikan, 1984) as I will explain in more detail later. 33 Scraps Many will undoubtedly associate the term with Fodor’s (1983) analysis of input systems – i.e., perceptual systems and language. According to this analysis, modules are characterized by a list of features with domain-specificity, informational encapsulation, limited central access and a fixed neural architecture among the most important features. By why privilege one analysis of modularity, especially when there exists a variety of opinion on the matter (e.g, Barrett, in press; Chomsky, 1980; Jackendoff, 1987; Marr, 1982; Sperber, 1994). Perhaps it might seem inconsistent on my part sticking to a strict definition of evolutionary psychology while asking for some leeway on the definition of modularity, however there are important differences between the two situations and it will be instructive to consider them. To begin with, the concept module or modularity was in fairly wide circulation before Fodor published his analysis, so much so that Chomsky (1980) could repeatedly use the term in a monograph intended for a general audience without either defining or referencing the term. Cosmides and Tooby (1987, p. 283), on the other hand, explicitly referenced and defined the term evolutionary psychology in what would be a foundational paper in the emerging field. More importantly though, Fodor’s (1983) use of the term modularity was roughly comparable to Chomsky’s (1983) use of the term, Marr’s (1982) use of the term, and so on. Goal of Fodor’s analysis was, presumably to get at the essence of the mental kind “module,” whereas the essence of Cosmides and Tooby’s (1987) analysis was to draw a distinction between different styles of evolutionary theorizing. Hence, when evolutionary psychology is later characterized in much broader terms (Heyes, 2003), such that it includes not only research programs that were explicitly contrasted with evolutionary psychology and whose practitioners publicly reject the label (Smith, Borgerhoff Mulder, & Hill, 2000, 2001), but also behaviorism, an inclusion that both sides of this schism would reject, then one is simply misapplying the term. However, when later analyses of modularity are proposed and adopted, one is not necessarily misapplying the term. As Sperber (1994, p. 42) remarks: “If modularity is a genuine natural property, then what it consists of is a matter of discovery, not stipulation.”