Technology, Technological Determinism and the Transformational Model of Technical Activity. Clive Lawson Rough Draft, 16th July 2004 Abstract: Technology remains a relatively under-theorised category within the critical realist literature. This is surprising not only because of its central importance to a wide range of disciplines, but also because it seems to be a category about which critical realism has much to say. One aspect of technology that has proved to be especially problematic for commentators to accommodate is that technology’s constitution is as much a part of the social as well as the natural domains. This has caused problems to the extent that accounts of technology implicitly reduce one domain to another or only manage to distinguish one from the other in an unsustainable way (typically, those emphasising the social constitution of technology tend to treat the natural world as ‘constructed’ in much the same manner as the social world, and those stressing the importance of the material/natural component in technology tend to treat the social world overly mechanistically). This paper draws upon the critical naturalism of critical realism and the transformational model of social activity in particular to develop a conception of technology that avoids these problems. It then draws out some of the implications of this account. In particular, some attempt is made to re-cast claims made by some so-called technological determinists, such as Heidegger and Habermas, who on closer inspection seem to be posing important questions that simply cannot be addressed without the kind of systematic (ontological) elaboration of the social and natural domains that I am suggesting. 1. Introduction We all experience the role technology plays in social change on a daily basis. Whether cleaning our home, purchasing an air ticket over the internet, paying for shopping at a supermarket or borrowing a book from the library, we all experience a constant prodding to our normal and routine ways of doing things that can be attributed to the introduction of some new technology or other. But do such experiences provide evidence to support the thesis of technological determinism? One of the few sources of agreement in the recent technology literature, is that the answer to this question must be no, i.e., technological determinism must be wrong. However, I want to suggest that this ‘agreement’ actually obscures a problem with the treatment 2 of technology. Namely, I want to suggest that this rejection of technological determinism has meant that certain questions posed by so-called technological determinists remain untheorised or even unaddressed. Indeed I shall also argue that these questions are difficult to deal with in any sustainable way within the framework suggested by many of technological determinism’s critics, at least those most rooted in social constructivism. Implicitly, of course, I am suggesting that these questions asked by so-called technological determinists are important ones. And indeed I believe their importance explains why so many writers on technology are continually drawn to the thesis of technological determinism, accounting for the often noted fact that "as moths to the flame we [theorists of technology] find ourselves continually attracted to technological determinism’s alluring but dangerous glow" (Smith, 1996). I also want to argue that the issues at stake here are fundamentally ontological and that it is in this regard that critical realism has much to contribute to the study of technology at present. Although, surprisingly, little attention has been given by critical realists to technological issues, it would seem that the social ontology developed within critical realist accounts has much to offer a basic conception of technology and, consequently, the particular problems I address here. More specifically the (transformational) conception of social activity, which of course is particularly well suited to the avoidance of both determinism and voluntarism with regard to social phenomena can very fruitfully be applied to an account of technical activity. Furthermore, I shall argue that fundamental to an account of technology is a conception of its dual constitution in the social and natural domains. However, it is rare for technological commentators, especially recently, to attempt to elaborate an account of technology in terms of the differences between these domains. My intention here is to do just this by drawing upon the critical or qualified naturalism 3 developed within critical realist accounts. In so doing, not only do I explain the nature of the current impasse (with regards to technological determinism), but also provide a sketch of technology that incorporates what I see as the advantages of both (so called determinist and constructivist) positions, and provide some (rather speculative) attempts to re-cast the questions that technological determinists have posed. 2.1 Varieties of technological determinism? It is fair to say that technological determinism is most usually referred to in a crude, undifferentiated manner. To the extent that different strands of the technological determinist argument are distinguished, it is most common to find discussions of hard and soft technological determinism (see Smith & Marx, 1996). The hard-soft distinction is based upon a spectrum of technological determinisms – with movement along the spectrum involving the degree of agency, or the power to effect change, attributed to technology. At the hard end, technology has certain intrinsic attributes that allow little scope for human autonomy or choice. At the other end of the spectrum, soft determinism, simply emphasises the large scope for human interventions and choice. Indeed, for Smith and Marx at least "the soft determinists locate [technology] in a far more various and complex social, economic, political and cultural matrix" (1996, p. xii). The immediate problem with such accounts, however, is that it is not clear why they should be considered to be deterministic at all. Neither hard nor soft are deterministic in any sense, given that some scope for the human choice is accepted by both, the disagreement being over how much. Indeed, this point seems to be the motivation for Bimber’s very useful if rarely cited, distinctions between nomological, unintended consequences and normative uses 4 of the term technological determinism (Bimber, 1996). The nomological is that which takes the 'determinism' in technological determinism most seriously: "technological determinism can be seen as the view that, in the light of …the state of technological development and laws of nature, there is only one possible future course for social change" (1996, p. 83). There is no scope for human desires or choices. Now, although this definition accords most closely with the philosopher’s (or common sense?) meaning of the term, Bimber argues that it is actually almost impossible to find any examples of technological determinism if such a definition is strictly adhered to. The most likely candidates (perhaps unsurprisingly?) emanate from the economics domain. The most familiar of these is Marx’s famous statement that "the hand-mill gives you society with the feudal lord; the steam-mill society with the industrial capitalist" (Marx, 1971, p. 109). However, it is very difficult to attribute anything like a hard or nomological form of technological determinism once a wider reading of Marx is undertaken (especially see Dickson, 1974; Rosenberg, 1976; Harvey, 1999, pp. 98-136). One sense in which Marx might be understood as encouraging such an interpretation is in his insistence that history or sequence matters, and indeed this can sound unduly mechanistic, and has been interpreted by later Marxists in an unduly mechanistic way (an obvious example is Heilbroner, 1967). But the crucial point that Marx, and indeed Heilbronner, are making is that some kinds of technology could not happen without others and some kinds of technology could not happen without others and that some kinds of social organisation could not happen without certain technological developments. This idea of the importance of sequence recurs throughout accounts that have been held up as examples of technological determinism. Perhaps the most sustained of these is that provided by Clarence Ayers, and which has had such a clear effect on the American 5 Institutionalists. On par with Marx’s handmill statement is Ayres contention that given “the shipbuilding and navigation skills in existence in 1492, America was bound to be discovered in a decade or two” (Ayres, 1952) – often read as betraying the worst kind of determinism. However, on closer reading, as with Marx, the point that emerges is that some technological development may be a necessary condition for some other technological development (or indeed social development). But nomological technological determinism requires that it is also a sufficient condition. And it is doubtful whether such a position can be found in any of the above contributors work.1 Bimber’s second use of the term, i.e. ‘unintended consequences’ technological determinism, is one that emphasises the process whereby human ideas, values, etc., become manifest in some particular technology so giving a fixity or concretisation to these ideas which is then hard to change. Perhaps the classic statement of such a position is that made by Langdon Winner (1977; 1980). And as his account explicitly brings out, although there is a concern with explaining the fact that technology appears to be out of our control, the point is not that everything is strictly determined or that choice is precluded. Rather, the point is that choices about the design and building of technology have implications that require some living with. The call, from Winner at least, is for greater democratic involvement at an earlier stage in the development of some technology, not that it is not possible. This general idea is also to be found in Marx with specific emphasis on the way that social relations become 1 Perhaps there is a case to made for that nomological technological determinism is alive and well in the writings of mainstream economists or in the more mathematical technological trajectories literature of neo-Schumpeterians of those such as Dosi <<refs not found - Not Found>>. However, in these accounts, the adoption of closed-system methods generally imposes a determinism throughout the social world (see - Lawson, T. 2004; T. Lawson, 1997). But there is nothing in these accounts that suggests that there is anything specific about technology that generates determinism of any sort, and thus does not really seem relevant here. 6 ‘concretised’ in particular technologies which then act to maintain or reproduce those social relations (MacKenzie, 1984) However, neither the nomological nor the unintended consequences uses of the term are, Bimber argues, the most familiar face of technological determinism within the technology literature. Rather, in what he dubs the normative version of technological determinism, technology appears to us as autonomous because the norms by which it is advanced are "removed from political and ethical discourse and … goals of efficiency or productivity become surrogates for value-based debate over methods, alternatives, means and ends" (Bimber, 1996, p. 82). Here technological development is an essentially human enterprise in which people who create and use technology are driven by certain goals that rely unduly on norms of efficiency and productivity. Thus other (ethical, moral) criteria are excluded, producing a process that operates independently of larger political processes and contexts. The end point is one in which society adopts the technologist's standards of judgement. Thus there is a technological domain, which includes elements of society generally, which acts as constraint and causal force on other aspects of society. The main examples this time appear to be from the philosophy of technology. Bimber singles out the contribution of Habermas (see especially; Habermas 1970}. And although Habermas actually writes very little on technology, his position does clearly involve the more general features that Bimber has in mind, although at this level of generality it is perhaps as relevant to Mumford’s ‘megatechnics’ (1967) and Ellul’s ‘technique’ (1964). Habermas is attempting to ground what he sees as the negative or dystopian character of modernity in very general terms. Central to Habermas’s contribution, of course, is a Weberian differentiation of society into the spheres of work (which is success oriented, purposive action concerned with 7 controlling the world) and interaction (communication between subjects in pursuit of common understanding in the ‘lifeworld’). Modernity is characterised by the colonisation of the system of objectifying (delinguifying) behaviour of the former on the latter lifeworld. Thus the problem of modernity amounts to the inappropriate extension of one domain to another. Although Bimber fails to mention it, perhaps the most developed position of this sort is provided by the work of Heidegger. For Heidegger, we are engaged in a transformation of the entire world (and ourselves) into 'mere raw materials' or 'standing reserves' (1977) - objects to be controlled. But a place is given in Heidegger’s account of a process of instrumentalisation in which methodical planning comes to dominate, destroying the integrity of everything. An collection of functions replaces a world of ‘things’ treated with respect for their own sake. Heidegger's examples of the Greek jeweller making a chalice and a modern dam builder destroying the local environment show the difference Heidegger has in mind between (the older crafts-based activity of) bringing things together in harmony and the 'deworlding' of modern technology. The central point is that technology itself is not neutral. Everything is sucked up into the technological process and reduced to the status of a resource that has to be optimised in some way. Especially worrying is the idea that, in so doing, people grow to see themselves in the same way. Increasingly, sight is lost of what is being sacrificed in the mobilisation of human and other resources for goals that remain ultimately obscure. Although quite different in many respects, the concern of both Heidegger and Habermas is the same i.e. with the reduction of meaning and value of humans in the lifeworld. Human involvement is reduced to a minimum and the values of possession and control tend to dominate social life. Central is the idea that using technology 8 makes us become something else. The use of technology creates a new lifeworld, which separates, de-worlds, isolates and impoverishes both the natural world and our selves.2 2.2 The constructivist critique3 It is fair to say that, more recently at least, criticisms of technological determinism are most often made by, or with the help of arguments made by, social constructivists. There are though several dimensions to the constructivist rejection of technological determinism. There is an explicit rejection of the idea that technical change can be seen as a fixed, or on some monotonic 'trajectory'. Technological change is genuinely contingent and not reducible to some inner technological ‘logic’. The relation between science and technology (science is the independent, non political source of technological ideas) is questioned, as is the idea that technological change leads to (determines) social change and not vice versa. Instead, emphasis is placed, usually by drawing attention to a series of case studies, upon the contingent nature of technical change and on how technology is ‘shaped’, especially by different social groups in the process of settling a range of technological/ social controversies and disagreements (MacKenzie & Wajcman, 1985). However, as Winner famously argues, this emphasis on the social dimension of technology comes at a cost (Winner, 1991). In particular, what he terms ‘autonomous’ characteristics of technology are lost. To see why this might be, we 2 If not for limitations of space, I would also here address the more recent, and more social, reworkings of Heidegger’s work , such as that found in the work of Albert Borgmann (1984). 3 The main roots of social constructivist accounts of technology appear to lie in the sociology of scientific knowledge (for a good review see Bloor, 1976; Shapin, 1982). The term ‘social constructivism’ is most often used in a narrow sense to refer to the social construction of technology (SCOT) approach outlined by Pinch and Bijker (1987) or more recently by Bijker (1995) and related approaches (e.g. Woolgar 1991}. However, I shall also include here the ‘social shaping’ approaches (MacKenzie & Wajcman, 1985; Wajcman, 1991) and the actor-network approach of Latour (1987) and 9 need to consider the particular manner in which the social is brought in to the technological and in particular the role played by the ideas of symmetries. 4 Again the main idea is taken from the sociology of scientific knowledge literature (Bloor, 1976): that it is best to remain agnostic about the truth, falsity, rationality, etc., of competing claims in settling scientific controversies. Translated to the technological realm this means that the researcher should remain impartial with regards to the actual properties of the technology involved in determining which technologies become ‘settled upon’ (Pinch & Bijker, 1987). The researcher must, in other words, treat as possibly true or false all claims made about the nature of technology – such claims must be treated symmetrically (explaining them by reference to similar factors), since there is no independent way of evaluating the knowledge claims of scientists, technologists, etc. As in the sociology of scientific knowledge literature, two ideas underlie these arguments. First, the ‘real world’ plays no role in settling controversies (in settling the form that technology takes) and, second, that the researcher has no independent access to the world- so that there is no way of evaluating competing claims. Thus claims about the relative efficiency or successfulness of different technologies or technical progress (or how some technology comes to be accepted) are to be avoided (see also Staudenmaier, 1995; Pels, 1996). Secondly, given the emphasis upon the nature of technology itself in having much bearing upon its own acceptance or emergence, existing technology is understood to exist or is analysed in terms of the stabilisation of different controversies and disputes. Once stabilisation is achieved, controversy is removed and the properties of this stabilisation (how consensus is achieved) determines how Callon (1987).These approaches are roughly in agreement (to varying degrees) over the following points. 4 Various accounts put this aspect as central stage (Collins, 1985; Lynch, 1992) some even present the field as a series of extensions of the symmetry principle (Woolgar, 1988) 10 that technology functions. The focus, as with the SSK literature, is upon how ‘closure’ is achieved. Crucial to the idea of closure, is the idea that technology is not interpreted or understood in any fixed way. These different interpretations of some technology are not only of its social characteristics or relative functionality, but of its technical content – of how it works. Thus ‘facts’ about technology are simply the (different) interpretations of different social groups (Bijker, 1995). It is thus a rhetorical process of settling dispute via negotiation and social action that is understood in the term ‘closure’. Technology is thus socially shaped and socially constructed. But, as such, and this is Winner’s point, the ability to distinguish technology from any other social phenomenon is lost. Thus is would seem to be possible to explain the one feature of technology, noted at the outset, that motivates most so called determinist accounts – how is it the case that technology continually prods or provokes all manner of social changes. Moreover, it also seems to generate certain tensions in the accounts of some constructivists themselves. For example, Latour seems unwilling to distinguish natural from social phenomena, even though he needs some such account to sustain the idea that technology explains the differences noted in spatial extensions of human and other societies (Latour & Strum 1987). Constructivists are clearly correct to argue, against nomological determinist accounts that contingency matters. However, little is said about the normative form noted by Bimber and others. Unseating the privileged position of science in technology’s development, whilst surely right, actually distracts from the very factors that Habermas, Heidegger and others are drawing attention to. The use of technology may bring with it values of possession and control that dominate social life and drain it of meaning, are questions about which the constructivist must remain silent. At root 11 here seems to be a failure to distinguish two quite different issues – the contingency and irreducibly social nature of technology.5 In arguing effectively that the latter calls for the former, perhaps the most plausible position (central to normative determinism) that contingency is consistent with a conception of technology in which it is not simply reduced to a social phenomenon, is missed. Taken together these problems have led to a tendency for various questions, which so called determinist accounts have raised, to be ignored or lost. For example, how do we account for the extent to which technology appears to be ‘out of control’? How do we make sense of the appearance of stages of development? How do we account for the constraining effect technology has on social organisation? What do we mean when we talk of technology concretising or fixing values or ideas? Why should the technological domain impinge, if it does, on other domains? And how are all these questions addressed whilst maintaining the irreducibly social character and essential contingency, insisted upon by constructivist accounts? I shall argue that these questions are best addressed by establishing a conception of technology that draws upon recent developments in social ontology. Specifically, I want to argue that technology is best conceptualised in terms of a transformational model similar to that developed within critical realist accounts of social ontology. 3 A Transformational model of technical activity The basic features of this model have been presented in different ways, notably as a corrective to existing voluntaristic or reificatory accounts of social structure or as a transcendental argument from the existence of generalised features of experience of 5 I am certainly not arguing that it is only social constructivists who make this mistake. Indeed, although I do not have space to pursue this here, I would argue that many explicit reactions to technological determinism have involved reduction of technology to a purely social phenomenon For an example of such a reaction within Institutionalist thought (see Brinkman, 1997) 12 the social world, such as routinised practices.6 Either way, the main point is that social structure only exists in and through the activity of human agents, even though it is not reducible to such activity. Put another way, against individualistic or voluntaristic accounts of social structure, structure pre-exists and is a necessary condition for all intentional agency, whilst, against reificatory accounts, structure only exists in virtue of the activity it governs. Thus if social structure always pre-exists actual behaviour this does not mean that individuals create structure in any sense but that it is actively reproduced or transformed. Similarly, if it is something that only exists in virtue of human activity, there is no sense in which it is outside of or external to human activity. However, neither are structure and agency simply moments in the same process – they are different kinds of thing. And it is this transformational nature of the connection between the two (interestingly, for my purposes, often conveyed by the Aristotelian metaphor of the sculpting artist fashioning a product out of the material and with the tools available) that lies at the heart of the TMSA. The resulting emphasis, then, is upon transformation. Fig 1 The Transformational Model of Social Activity Social structures Socialisation, enablement Constraint . Reproduction/ Transformation Human agency Society, conceived of as the sum of the relations between agents is the ever present condition and continually reproduced outcome of social activity. Society acts as both an enabling and constraining influence on behaviour as well as, more 6 For the a statement of the former see Bhaskar 1989, and Archer, et al. 1998; and for a statement of the 13 constitutively, as a socialising force, thus impacting on how individuals react to the structural constraints and enablements they face. But as structure is only ever reproduced or transformed through human action, where such structure endures, its continuity as much as its change is a significant object of analysis. As such, social change is inherently non-deterministic. To capture this aspect of structure, following Giddens, the term duality of structure is often used. Similarly, it should be clear that although action, where it does, reproduces certain structural forms, this will typically not be the intention of this activity. Thus, my speaking English is not intended to reproduce the grammar of the language, although it does generally do so. Following Bhaskar, the duality of practice is used to capture this dual aspect of action. One more aspect of this account needs to be drawn out before we can return to a discussion of technology. Specifically, the TMSA can also be seen as an attempt to elaborate how the social and natural worlds differ, and specially as part of a qualified or critical naturalism (PON). In short, drawing un a conception of the natural world as governed by tranfactually operating generative mechanisms <<see - Not Found>> (Harré, 1970; Harré R. & Secord, 1972; Harré R. & Madden, 1975), the social can be viewed in the same way (thus providing the basis for a naturalism of some kind), the main differences depending on the differences in the kinds of mechanisms and powers that can be discovered (retroduced). For present purposes, the important differences lie in the relatively greater differentiability or isolatability of natural structures, and the possibility of closing off the operation of some mechanisms to observe the operation of others. Given the nature of the social world, as captured in the TMSA, such differentiability and ‘closedness’ will be rarely if ever the case. Such differences have been more formalised in terms of a series of limits naturalism. A latter see T. Lawson 1997 ). 14 major point of the TMSA is that social structures only exist in virtue of the activity they constrain or enable. Thus social structures depend, for their existence on the activities of agents and the conception agents have of such structures. As such social structures will not tend to endure across time and space in the same way that natural mechanisms do. Such differences (or ontological limits to naturalism) can be summarised as the relatively greater activity-concept-time-space dependence of social structures (see PON 1989 37-54, 174-179). The major epistemological limit is that whereas the differentiability of natural mechanisms means that the natural world may well be characterised very usefully in terms of closed systems, this is unlikely to be the case for much of the social world. This much should, for those familiar with critical realism at least, be familiar if not uncontentious. But how is any of this of relevance to a conception of technology? The central link, I want to suggest, comes when we focus upon that human activity that engages with technology in one way or another. The TMSA above is an attempt to draw out the main features of human agent’s relationship with social structure through the medium of social activity. The focus is on the plane of social relations. However, such activity can be viewed under another aspect – as technical activity. Human activity of course is essentially the same: people act, always intentionally, in conditions not of their own choosing but transforming the materials to hand. But here a distinction can be made between technical objects, that act as the condition and consequence of technical activity and the technical subjects, those human agents engaged in technical activity. These can be combined in a similar way to that above to provide what is effectively a transformational model of technical activity (TMTA). Here the technical subject and object are, similarly, not reducible to or derivable from each other, they are different kinds of things, even though both are, 15 in some sense, the condition and consequence of each other. However, important differences are apparent once the manner in which both act as condition and consequence in the TMSA and TMTA are focused upon. Consider Figure 2: Figure 2 - the Transformational Model of Technical Activity (devices/artefacts) Technical Object Socialisation, Reproduction/ enablement Transformation Constraint . (action/technique) Technical Subject Here the nature of the existing technological objects impose severe constraints on the kind of activity that can be pursued. Such objects both enable and constrain different kinds of activities. Thus distance is achieved between this and voluntaristic accounts that tend to see a special (abstract) place for both science and the lonely, inspired inventor, in the 'creation' of new technology. Instead, a condition for invention or developments in technology is the state of technology itself. This accords with the observations of those such as Heilbronner and Ayres, that there are stages in development (e.g. it is unlikely that the light bulb would be developed before electricity and that similar patents are often filed more or less simultaneously in different places). Furthermore, not only do the existing form of technical objects constrain or enable kinds of action but affect the very nature of the agent. Again consistent with the institutionalist literature, conditions not only constrain but socialise. Thus as, say, Veblen would argue, mass production brings with it different (socially acquired) capabilities and dispositions than craft work or agriculture. Similarly, the action of technical subjects conditions the development of technical objects. As with the TMSA, the emphasis is upon reproduction and transformation (this time of the technical object). In large part though, these come about through two relatively distinct kinds of action: developing or using technology. 16 The former is the most obvious sense of technical activity. Existing artefacts or devices are transformed into different objects. This is typically what we mean by invention or innovation. However, a crucial difference with the TMSA needs to be registered here. Technical activity does not change the laws of physics or, more generally, the material content of technical objects. It is solely the form of such objects that is, where it is, transformed. Thus it is the form that is irreducibly social. Clearly, new materials are brought into use in the development of some object. But, as with the sculpting artist, it is form that the human agent brings to the materials. However, unlike society which would cease to exist without its reproduction and transformation through human activities, the objects of technical action would not disappear without such action. However, the question to ask, then, is would these objects still be technology in any sense if humans disappeared? A knife has a measurable sharpness, but this quality is only sharp or a hazard or of any importance at all in relation to human beings. Thus a stone or a tree trunk can be used by people, and in and through use, become technical objects. Thus technology as such requires both a relation to people and a transformed 'form'. The main point to make about technical objects, then, is that they have material content but social form.7 The content of such objects is as unchangeable to us as is gravity. The sphere of natural relations, which constitute the object's content, is something we harness or position ourselves with respect to. But there are two distinct senses in which technical objects have social form. First, this harnessing or positioning involves re-forming the object, thus different materials are combined in different ways, various characteristics of the natural world (or existing technology) are isolated and recombined in different contexts. This re-forming reflects (and of 7 I am grateful to T. Lawson for this formulation (see T. Lawson 1997 ,p 327n ) 17 course embodies) human desires, purposes and values as well as, especially, given the nature of technical action, of know-how. The resulting technological objects are then, a kind of concretisation, objectification or repository of these ideas and knowledge.. about ways of doing things However, there is a second sense in which technical objects have a social form which is more 'ongoing', which is of most relevance in considering the reproduction rather than the transformation involved in technical action. Specifically, I mean here the moment in which the social-relational character of an object is reproduced through its use by people, typically as a means to some other end. Thus when I use a machine in my place of work or a mobile phone on at train, I am reproducing (although usually without intending it) some or other set of social relations as I do so. As noted above, existing technological forms as well as the relations in which they stand to human beings are reproduced as technology is used. The latter though not the former is only reproduced to this extent. It should be remembered, of course that the technical activity does not take place in a vacuum. Thus there is also the need, in practice, effectively, to combine the TMSA with the TMTA. Thus the material conditions of some action involve both technical and social relations. The main point to make is that both the current state of technical objects and social structures, both act simultaneously as condition and consequence of human action and thus mutually condition each other. Alternatively put, both the TMSA and the TMTA are continually in play. Thus just as the forms of social relations that emerge are always embedded with existing networks of technical objects, so the reproduction and transformation of different technical objects always takes place, and must be embodied within a network of existing social relations. This point is returned to below. For now, it is enough to point out that not only are existing ideas or know-how reflected or concretised in the form of technical objects but so to 18 are the nature of existing social relations. Moreover, it becomes impossible to understand the nature of society without some understanding of the (nondeterministic) role played by the current state of technology 4. Implications of the TMTA I believe the implications of conceptualising technology and technological activity in the above terms to be both far reaching and particularly useful. However, given space, I shall address myself here to only a few of the issues raised in the discussion of technological determinism provided above. These fall briefly into two categories the implications of a transformational conception and the implications of the dual nature of technical objects. The emphasis on a transformational conception of technical action, focuses attention upon conditions and consequences of action rather than creation out of nothing. This much is in line with those such as Ayres who emphasise that invention does not result from the whims of detached ‘genius’ inventors, but typically involves a re-combination, in situ, of existing technical objects. Thus is sensitises the enquirer to the importance of historical, or path dependent, context. But a conception of stages or sequence is accommodated in a way that does not exclude the essentially social nature of such a process. Indeed it would seem to amply accommodate positions such as that of Winner in which the (social) consequences of action become the technical conditions for future action. Most importantly, this accommodation of the main insights of all these theorists is done with out at all encouraging the label of technological determinism. Thus, just as the TMSA has clarified a relation between structure and agency that steers a course between determinism and voluntarism, the TMTA does performs the same task in the technological realm. 19 It would also seem that the TMTA as set out above, provides a useful framework for comparing different conceptions of exactly what technology is. For some, technology comes close to being a way of doing things (e.g. Ellul’s ‘technique’) or are things which embody knowledge of ways of doing things. <<e.g. Bunge insistence that social organisations are technology as much as machines or high yield grain (Bunge 1999) Those within technology studies seem unwilling to rule out such approaches (for not being about technology ‘proper’) as they do seem to have something to say about distinctly technological processes. The TMTA has the advantage of providing a framework within which these contributions can be at least situated. However, in the above, I have tended to restrict the definition of technology to technical objects (which of course are still social in the senses noted above). Technical objects, like social structures, are then artefacts. And the tendency to reduce technology to simply another social phenomenon can be seen in part to result from an acknowledgement that technical objects and social structure are the outcomes of action (are artefacts) in the absence of an account of the kinds of artefacts involved (the constructivist mistake). This last point brings us on to the second set of implications: how do social structures and technical objects, as artefacts, differ? On this conception, the difference lies in the fact that for technical objects although the form is social, the content is not. More specifically, a series of differences follow that relate to technology’s being rooted in a different way in the natural domain via the relative concept-activity-spacetime independence of the natural world and the relatively greater differentiability of natural mechanisms. Again, any attempt at an exhaustive account of these implications is beyond the scope of the present paper. But the following should at least be suggestive. 20 First, this account provides a much more complex grounding of the positions such as Marx, Winner etc, for whom technology concretises the social in some way. Ideas of endurability, fixity etc. seem plausible but are notoriously difficult to pin down and are always open to counterexample. However, locating the concreteness of technical objects in the relatively greater concept-activity-time-space independence of the natural world seems would seem to avoid such problems in a sustainable way. However, a more contentious set of implications follow from a focus on the kinds of technical activity noted above. Returning to the TMSA, the main types of activity distinguished were those which transform or reproduce social structure. Loosely translated to the technical domain, we focus rather on activities of invention or use. However, it is clear, on reflection, that these activities are actually quite different. It is perhaps best to conceive technical action as involving two distinct moments. The moment of invention will typically deal with the detection of natural mechanisms, which given their relative differentiability, will typically involve the pursuit of isolation or de-contextualisations of the natural world. This is essentially Heidegger’s main insight. Once isolation has occurred, recombination of different mechanisms and existing technical objects often seems to provide a spur for much technological innovation (Lawson, 2000). However, a second moment to technical activity, mostly concerned with the ongoing use of objects, will be involved in recontextualising or re-embedding these objects within particular contexts. This second moment will tend to involve very different skills, attitudes, activities, etc to the isolating moment. A feel for ‘fit’, place, contingency etc. is required in the process of re-embedding which is of a different nature to that most useful at the isolating stage. Put another way, the isolating stage involves an ability to deal with or negotiate 21 predominantly closed systems, whereas the secondary moment involves the ability to deal with open systems. Now of course, I am talking of abilities to deal with open and closed systems as personal character traits or competences. And there is no a priori reason to think that those who are comfortable or capable with one should be so with the other. Indeed, recent accounts of autism, in which particular inabilities to deal with open systems would seem to underlie some very stereotypically autistic behaviour (such as being unable to deal with contingency, social (as opposed to fixed or binary) rules, inability to maintain empathic social relations, etc.) suggests that differences in abilities are great. Thus given technology’s dual constitution, I am suggesting that the technological domain is a point of overlap or even ‘battleground’ for the competing mindsets, values, etc attached to open and closed system ways of thinking about the world. Such a scenario would seem to provide a solid foundation for Bimber’s normative technological determinists. The invasion of the lifeworld by the technological can better be understood in terms of the mistaken application of ideas, values, methods, concerns of most directly relevance to closed systems to situations that are predominantly open. However, without a conception of these different moments of technical activity, and without some kind of sustained ontological elaboration of the social and natural domains, it is not clear that these concerns can even be posed in a sustainable way. 4. Conclusions A series of important problems posed by so-called technological determinists simply cannot be addressed by critics wedded to a social constructivism which ultimately reduces technology to the social, thus making it impossible to consider the possible 22 nature of any ‘autonomous’ qualities it may have. This paper, by drawing on the social ontology of critical realism, has attempted to provide a framework in which the insights both of so-called technological determinists and their constructivist critics can be accommodated without so reducing technology to just another social phenomenon or committing the error of ‘nomological’ determinism. Some of the more obvious characteristics of technology (its endurability, concreteness, quick diffusion etc.), seem to be unproblematically grounded by conceiving of technology in terms of its social form and material content, given the critical realist account of the differences between the social and natural domains. Lastly, the normative concerns of various philosophers of technology have been re-cast in terms of the different moments of technical activity suggested by the TMTA i.e. of isolation and re-embedding. Bibliography Archer, M, et al. Critical Realism: Essential Readings. London: Routledge, 1998. Ayres, C. The Industrial Economy. Cambridge: Houghton Mifflin, 1952. Bhaskar, R. The Possibility of Naturalism. Brighton: Harvester, 1989. Bijker, W.E. "Of Bicycles, Bakelites, and Bulbs: Toward a Theory of Sociotechnical Change," 380, 1995. Bimber, B. "Three Faces of Technological Determinism." In Does Technology Drive History? the Dilemma of Technological Determinism, edited by M Smith and L Marx, 79-100. Mass: MIT Press, 1996. Bloor, D. Knowledge and Social Imagery. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1976. Borgman, A. Technology and the Character of Contemporary Life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press., 1984. Brinkman, R. "Toward a Culture-Conception of Technology." Journal of Economic Issues 31, no. 1027-1038 Dec ,1997. Bunge, M. "Ethics and Praxiology as Technologies." Techne 4, no. 4, 1989. Callon, M. "Society in the Making: The Study of Technology as a Tool for Sociological Analysis." In The Social Construction of Technological Systems: 23 New Directions in the Sociology and History of Technology, edited by W Bijker, T Pinch, and T Hughes. Mass: MIT, 1987. Collins, H. M. Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice. Beverly Hills, Calif: Sage, 1985. Dickson, D. Alternative Technology and the Politics of Technical Change. Fontana, 1974. Ellul, J. The Technological Society, (J. Wilkinson, Trans.). New York: Vintage, 1964. Harré R., and E. Madden. Causal Powers. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1975. Harré R., and P. Secord. Blackwell, 1972. The Explanation of Social Behaviour. Oxford: Basil Harré, R. Principles of Scientific Thinking. London: Macmillan, 1970. Harvey, D. Limits to Capital. London: Verso, 1999. Heidegger, M. The Question Concerning Technology, W. Lovitt, Trans. New York: Harper and Row, 1977. Heilbroner, R.L. "Do Machines Make History?" Technology and Culture 8 (1967): 335-45. Latour, B. "Science in Action - How to Follow Scientists and Engineers Through Society," 274 p. (ill), 1987. Latour, B, and S Strum. "The Meanings of the Social: From Baboons to Humans." Information sur les Sciences Sociales 26 (1987): 783-802. Lawson, T. Reorienting Economics. London: Routledge, 2004. Lawson, C. "Collective Learning and Epistemically Significant Moments." In High Technology, Networking and Collective Learning in Europe, edited by D Keeble and F Wilkinson. Ashgate, 2000. Lawson, T. Economics and Reality. London: Routledge, 1997. Lynch, M. "Going Full Circle in the Sociology of Knowledge: Comment on Lynch and Fuhrman." Science, Technology and Human Values 17 (1992): 228-33. MacKenzie, D. "Marx and the Machine." Technology and Culture 25 (1984). MacKenzie, D, and J Wajcman. "Introduction: The Social Shaping of Technology." In The Social Shaping of Technology, edited by D. MacKenzie and J Wajcman. Milton Keynes: Open University Press., 1985. Marx, K. The Poverty of Philosophy. International, 1971. Mumford, L. The Myth of the Machine: Technics and Human Development. New York: Harcourt, 1967. 24 Pels, D. "The Politics of Symmetry." Social Studies of Science 26 (1996): 277-304. Pinch, T, and W Bijker. "The Social Construction of Facts and Artifacts: Or How the Sociology of Science and the Sociology of Technology Might Benefit Each Other." In The Social Construction of Technological Systems: New Directions in the Sociology and History of Technology, edited by W Bijker, T Pinch, and T Hughes. Mass: MIT Press, 1987. Rosenberg, N. "Marx as a Student of Technology." Monthly Review 1976, 56-77. Shapin, S. "History of Science and Its Sociological Reconstructions." History of Science 20 (1982): 157-211. Smith, M. "Technological Determinism in American Culture." In Does Technology Drive History? the Dilemma of Technological Determinism, edited by M Smith and L Marx, 1-36. Mass: MIT Press, 1996. Smith, M, and L.(eds) Marx. Does Technology Drive History? the Dilemma of Technological Determinism. Edited by M Smith and L Marx. Mass: MIT Press, 1996. Staudenmaier, J. "Problematic Stimulation: Historians and Sociologists Constructing Technology Studies." In Research in Philosophy and Technology, Vol. 15: Social and Philosophical Constructions of Technology, edited by C. Mitchem. Greenwich, Conn: JAI Press, 1995. Wajcman, J. Feminism Confronts Technology. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press., 1991. Winner, L. Autonomous Technology. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 1977. ———. "Do Artifacts Have Politics?" Daedalus 105 (1980): 121-36. ———. "Upon Opening the Black Box and Finding It Empty: Social Constructivism and the Philosophy of Technology." In The Technology of Discovery and the Discovery of Technology., edited by J. Pitt and E. Lugo. Blacksburg, Va: Society for Philosophy and Technology, 1991. Woolgar, S. Science: The Very Idea. Chichester: Ellis Horwood/London & New York: Tavistock, 1988.