God and an Infinite Universe The Problem Big Bang Cosmology has led the majority in the scientific community to adopt a model of the universe that holds to a definite “end” to the material universe. If all the energy of which the universe of things is composed was at one original “moment” compressed into a single “point,” it follows, by definition, that beyond that “point” there was no material being. If all matter eventually appeared from this original energy, the universe of material things would only exist to the extent that this original energy has reached as a result of the initial “Big Bang.” Some who accept this model of the universe note, however, that because the energy and, hence, matter of which the things in the universe is composed did not exist beyond that “point,” this still does not mean that there was not “space” beyond it. In fact, it is argued, space itself is infinite while the material things in that “space” may be finite in extent. This question is of relevance to theology since the claim is often implicit that the object of theology, God, alone is infinite and the finite world cannot share in the infinite attributes of God. To say that space is infinite may suggest that time, too, is infinite and therefore God is not needed as a causal explanation of the world. This brief paper is intended as a reflection on the proposal of infinite space in order to respond to this challenge.1 God and Space Perhaps the most important issue in discussing this problem is determining an acceptable definition of “space.” Since space itself seems to be basic to all our concepts, providing a framework or context in which objects are placed, it does not seem possible for the human mind to conceptualize a non-spacial object. By “conceptualize” I mean form a visual image of a thing. This is why, for instance, it is so difficult for the human mind to deal with the various attributes of God (e.g., omnipresence). St. Augustine long ago struggled with material conceptions of God that seemed to lead to various contradictory affirmations.2 For instance, if God is non-spacial (and I cannot form an “image” of that which is without spacial extension) it follows that the term God has little conceptual meaning. On the other hand, if I think about God as stretched out through the universe like a transparent substance or “stuff,” I am led to various absurdities. For instance, if God is an evenly distributed substance, more of God is in the elephant than the human person. Recognition is owed to the students of my “Augustine and Aquinas” course (Fall, 2004), especially Gabriel Dickinson and Duncan Keen for raising this issue and offering valuable insights and challenges to my explanations. 2 Augustine, Confessions, 7.1: “Although I did not imagine you in the shape of a human body, I could not free myself from the thought that you were some kind of bodily substance extended in space, either permeating the world or diffused in infinity beyond it.” 1 1 St. Augustine was able to escape these difficulties by recognizing that God is not a material substance and therefore is not reducible to a visual concept. Instead, the better analogy for God is found in universal truths. The geometrical triangle, for instance, includes an endless range of possible sizes. None of these, as geometrical objects, is reducible to matter. Whenever a triangle is reduced to matter, it not only becomes definite or particular in size but it also ceases to be a geometrical triangle. (Its non-extended “lines” made of an infinite series of points become measurable chalk, for instance.) The properties of a triangle, however (e.g., the sum of its interior angles), are necessary and timeless. Further, they are not constricted or restricted by space since they are true wherever they are thought. The same kind of argument may be made with respect to any other “universal” category. Humanness, for instance, includes an endless series of possible sizes, shapes, colors, weights, ages, etc. Humanness cannot exist as a material object, however, since to be placed in matter would particularize it. Particular humans have a designated weight, shape color, etc., but they do not individually (or collectively) exhaust the full range of meaning for the universal category, humanness. It is nonetheless a truly meaningful idea since it enables us to group together classes of beings that genuinely share in common those categories embodied in the universal. Universals like these must have a spiritual or immaterial existence in an immaterial faculty (i.e., intellect) since a material faculty is ordered towards particular things. Like, for instance, the eye is ordered towards a particular object (viz., objects/shapes seeable by way of light). It is precisely the intellect, Augustine would argue, that most closely mirrors the divine essence. There is an objectivity in those universal ideas that the intellect considers that makes them discoveries of the mind rather than creations of it. In other words, the properties of a triangle are not generated by the mind but are discovered as they are deduced from its definition. For this reason, students are held accountable for incorrect deductions from geometrical figures. If such properties were minddependent, the truths about the objects would be subjectively determined and, consequently, none of them could be “false.” One of the consequences of this insight is that universal objects of intellectual contemplation have a certainty and stability about them that is not present in material objects. Material objects are part of the changing world and undergo generation and corruption with regularity. The greater stability and certainty of the objects of intellectual contemplation make them aspects of a superior kind of reality: mind. Since universals are not material, they also do not take up space. One could not peer into the head of a thinking person, for instance, and observe the universal notion of triangle. The notion itself takes up no space but is nonetheless “omnipresent” if by that we understand that it is universally true and accessible to minds. Its universality is not as extended matter. Augustine is only one step from the existence and nature of God. Since the universals are not dependent on human minds but are discovered by them and, further, since the universals are properly objects of a mind, it follows that their proper “home” is a mind that has commensurate eternality and immutability. The mind of God is, then, the eternal abode of all unchangingly true ideas and propositions and they derive their ultimate certainty and ground from God. The human intellect knows things by 2 the “light” of the divine intellect by participating in its truths by discovery. God’s mind is the cause of these truths but the human mind “sees” them in its contemplation of things. When the human person sees beauty, then, in another face, a sunset and a well-played symphony, it does so by the light of unchanging beauty that functions as the ground of all true perception of beauty in things. The symphony is perceived as an instance of beauty, the meaning of which is stable and enduring, although the symphony itself, in time, will cease to exist.3 God, then, is non-spacial in the sense that He does not have the quality of being a material object existing in a designated “location” subject to causal interaction with other objects in His environment. God is everywhere inasmuch as all truth is present within the divine mind (including all those things that participate in the universal, unchanging “archetypes”). God is nowhere in space, however, inasmuch as He is not a particular expression or participation in absolute truth but is, rather, the home of all truth. The universe, it would seem, is the stage upon which the particular instances or participations in divine truth are set. Since they participate in that which is higher, it is altogether necessary to say that God’s mode of being is non-spacial. The Problem of Space There is no one definition of space.4 Many of the Presocratic philosophers, especially the Atomists, thought of space as the area within a container. Others described space in ways that suggested it was a physical substance distributed throughout the universe and filling the area between other objects. Others, like Aristotle, sought to define space as simply the position of things in relation to others. The history of reflection on this topic is long and complicated. Essential to the problem is our seeming inability to think about space directly. We always focus on objects that exist in space. Immanuel Kant identified space as one of the necessary categories of the mind into which all “phenomena” or sense-data is “poured.” The mind, then, cannot think of any object without placing it in a spacial framework. Conversely, it is difficult to think of space itself without also thinking of those objects that exist in space. Whenever the claim is made that the universe, including space, has a limit, the immediate response is often that this does not make sense. What is on the other side of the expanding universe? Assuming Big Bang Cosmology, the universe is expanding indefinitely. Doesn’t space already exist so that the material universe has somewhere to expand? If there is truly nothing outside the confines of the present universe, would this not restrict the ongoing expansion of the universe? It should not surprise us that we have difficulty thinking about nothingness beyond the current perimeters of the universe. Nothingness has no positive contents. Further, if the mind is ordered towards grasping real things in space, it follows that the 3 See Plotinus, Beauty. It is arguable that this particular neo-Platonic work exercised significant influence on Augustine in escaping the grips of Manichaeism. 4 For a helpful survey of major views, see J. Smart, “Space,” in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (NY: Macmillan, Inc., 1967). 3 mind will have great discomfort when faced with absolute nothingness as an object of thought. We tend to reify nothingness and usually this will turn into empty space. On the other hand, we must be concerned about the fact that the universe seems to have the potential of indefinite expansion. If we imagine the various stages of the development of the universe, at least as modern cosmology describes it to us, the universe has progressively spread outward in all directions. The possible range of its expansion seems indefinite. In other words, is there anything illogical with thinking of a universe one inch wider than the present one? If not, at what stage does it become illogical? I can’t think of one. There is nothing illogical in thinking of a universe a hundred billion more light years across. The possible range of the universe seems practically without limit. If the cosmologists are correct, however, there is a real limit to the actual extent of the physical universe but there is no actual limit to its potential extent. This observation leads to a helpful insight that may lead to a working definition of space. If we grant that the present extent of the physical universe is finite but that there is no particular limit to its potential extent, we can say that the “space” outside the physical universe is presently the potential setting for the universe as we know it. As potential, it has no actual positive content but only potential content. When we grant that there is an indefinite possible expansion and development of the universe, we are admitting that there are no constraints on its possibilities (at least in respect to expansion). Since space otherwise has no function or content, we conclude that it is equal to possibility. The difference between space within the present universe and that beyond it would be that the former is the setting for the actual universe of things. It is not the only possible setting for actuality, however, and therefore when the potential expansion becomes actual, so does the space. Space is simply the term we give to the place and framework in which existence occurs. On the other hand, think of the following: What if the universe were impossible? In other words, what if there were nothing at all (not even God)? In such a scenario, there would be no space. If space is the possibility for actuality (in this case, material actuality), if nothing could have existed, there would also be no context in which potentialities could be actualized. If my refrigerator can only hold 100 gallons of water, it follows that it cannot hold 200 gallons of water. There is no room for the actualizing of a potentiality that is not allowed by the nature of the case. If there is no potential for the emergence of the universe, there is also no framework in which such a universe could exist. This is because the framework itself only has meaning in the face of potentiality. If the universe is not possible, then neither is space. God and Possibility Since the universe does exist and since we have granted that there is nothing contradictory or repulsive in the idea that its extent seems without boundary, are we justified in claiming that the universe is infinite? If so, how does this relate to the restriction of infinity to God, as was indicated at the beginning of this article? 4 First, a distinction must be made between a potential infinite and an actual infinite. When we say that space is infinite, we mean that there is no measurable limit to the possibilities of a universe existing in space. It is always possible to think of a universe with something more than what it currently has. This is like saying that numbers are infinite. It is always possible to add another unit to a previous collection of units. Numbers never become actually infinite, precisely because it is always possible to add one more. One never reaches a stage in counting when one has arrived at an infinite collection of units. If one has an infinite collection of books, for instance, how many would remain if one is borrowed? The fact is that no such collection could possibly exist. The fact that the parts comprising the collection are finite and measurable, so must the sum total. If we can always conceive of adding an additional book, we speak of the possibility as infinite since there is no necessary boundary. We never reach a point in our collecting when we conclude that adding another book is beyond conception. There is no real infinite of finite things. What follows from this is that nothing finite can ever be actually infinite. Infinity is a theoretical notion applicable to abstract notions (e.g., geometrical lines) or a description of a series that has no necessary boundaries or inherent restrictions. If nothing physical or spacial can ever achieve actual infinity, we conclude that we have properly reserved true infinity for God alone. In respect to God, we grant actual infinity on the basis of the observation that the cause of the actuality of possible things (including space and matter) must be selfexplained and therefore truly boundless in duration and power. If God were limited in the sense of duration, for instance, we would have no true explanation of the actuality of anything at all. It is God that provides a “ground” and basis for the actual existence of things that are potential when considered in themselves. Since the universe does not have the attribute of infinity and self-sufficiency (as evidenced in its progressive development towards actuality) these must belong to another. Of course, this would not follow if the universe did not exist. If there were nothing, there would be no reason to believe in potentiality. No worry, though. In such a case, there would be no one to worry about such things! Since there is a universe, we are forced to affirm the real existence of infinite self-existent being and also say that these attributes must belong to a reality fundamentally distinct from this universe. If, however, God is the ground of potential realities, God also turns out to be the justification for a potential infinity of space. It is because God is unlimited in His causal power that we also conclude that there is no limit to what God can create. There is nothing impossible about God creating a new “universe” each moment for all eternity. Space, in this context, is unlimited inasmuch as God’s potential creative activity is unlimited. This provocative line of thought might actually lead us to suggest that space and the mind of God converge. Space, as possibility for the expansion of the universe, is unlimited precisely because of the unlimited power of God. Since space has no real conceptual meaning apart from the notion of possibility but possibility only has meaning in relationship to actuality (i.e., God),5 we may be 5 Possibility only has meaning in relationship to existing actuality. It would make no sense to speak about a possible meeting with my grandmother this weekend if, in fact, she died ten 5 justified in concluding that the space that envelops this universe of actual things is the unlimited possibility that is only meaningful in the context of the infinitely actual God. In my garage there is a large work table. Right now it is covered with various objects. I have no “space” to work in and therefore am restricted in what I can do there. If space were potentially finite, we would be saying that God would have limitations or a boundary point in what He could create. Since there is yet more that God could create than what has been created, we must affirm that there is “space” for divine creative activity beyond this universe and that the space for God’s creation is without limit. Mark McNeil, Theology Dept. Strake Jesuit College Preparatory September 16, 2004 years ago. Possibility for the universe only makes sense if there is some causal power that could produce it as an effect. 6