A NEURODYNAMIC THEORY OF SCHIZOPHRENIA AND RELATED DISORDERS Robert Miller Preface and Acknowledgements Preface and Acknowledgements Perhaps the most serious deficiency in research today - not only in psychiatry but in American science in general - is the absence of an overall theoretical framework. The accumulation of empirical observations, rather than the formulation of integrative theories is favored by the mechanisms involved both in the awarding of funds and in the editorial policy of most journals. Although scientific literature is now filled with important and well-documented findings, few if any investigators consider as one of their principal functions the integration of these findings into new theories of behavioral function. To understand the mechanism by which a psychosis of known etiology (e.g. amphetamine psychosis) is induced, for example, might require the integration of information about amphetamine’s pharmacology, and its effect on biogenic amine metabolism, neurophysiology, various enzyme systems and of course behavior. While an extensive literature of excellent work exists in each of these areas, and while the individual investigator may consider work in his own discipline in formulating these ideas, little effort has been directed towards a detailed examination of knowledge from many disciplines with a view to theory development. These words were written not recently, but a generation ago by A.J.Friedhoff (1971). They have been echoed many times more recently, and the situation Friedhoff described has not changed fundamentally since he wrote: That situation is now a characteristic of most countries which attempt to take science seriously, not only North America. The number of “important and well documented findings” has undoubtedly increased greatly, but the imbalance between the bounty of experimental findings and the dearth of unifying concepts has probably become even more glaring. It is with such criticism of much of modern biological psychiatry in mind that the present synthesis is attempted. Closely related to the lack of attention to theory in biological psychiatry, is another misconception. Over the last generation, psychiatry world-wide has paid particularly close attention to operationalized procedures for diagnosis, and replicability of diagnoses. This followed from careful studies under the auspices of the World Health Organization, in the late 1960s (Cooper et al, 1969; Kendell et al, 1971; Karno and Norquist, 1989), showing that diagnostic practices for psychotic illness in different parts of the world were very different: For instance, diagnostic labels on one side of the Atlantic were used in a different way from those on the other. As a result, the relative incidence of schizophrenia vs manic depressive illness was very different on the two sides, despite the fact that, with detailed instruments for assessing phenomenology, it was found that the range of patients’ 2 symptoms (and their frequency) were much the same. Since then great attention has been given to constructing schemes of diagnosis which ensure that different psychiatrists, faced with the same range of patients will come up with similar sets of diagnoses. This is undoubtedly of great value in improving communication between researchers. However, the prestigious schemes of psychiatric description and diagnosis produced in response to these pressures have not hitherto attempted to justify concepts of illness in terms of underpinning disease theories. The various disease entities formulated by schemes such as the DSM-III/DSM-IV system in North America, or the PSE-Catego system in the United Kingdom may thus have sacrificed conceptual validity in favor of replicability. In this writer’s view, this tendency represents a misunderstanding of the process of classification and concept formation, as it has occurred in the past in the most successful examples taken from the history of science generally. This point needs to be expanded: In any branch of science, the first, and most fundamental steps, upon which the establishment of that branch depends, involve the definition and validation of concepts, that is the process of classification. Until a classificatory scheme has been established, validated and has become generally accepted, there is uncertainty about the concepts with which one must reckon in any further attempts to understand or explain one’s subject matter. Unfortunately however there is no sure way of recognizing the most fruitful way of classifying a set of phenomena in advance of the actual revelation of how things should be understood or explained. That revelation is the most difficult step in any branch of science. Pending that revelation, a very unsatisfactory situation may exist, sometimes for a long period of time. A classificatory scheme may be established and hang in mid-air, so-tospeak, sometimes for many generations, with no more secure intellectual support than the authority of those who initially proposed the scheme and the faith of their followers. Only when the superior usefulness of one classificatory scheme for expounding some explanatory structure built upon it becomes clearly evident do the concepts of the scheme become validated in a manner which can command general agreement. Psychiatry is currently attempting to establish itself as a science with the power to explain, and it is therefore not a matter for surprise that classification of mental illnesses and abnormal mental states has recently been regarded as an issue of great importance. Spitzer and Williams (1980) writing in “Comprehensive Textbook of Psychiatry” give the purposes of classification as “communication, control and comprehension”. However, control is made more effective if one also comprehends; and communication is more important for what we understand than for what we do not. Hence, as in any other science, the third of these aims - the intellectual one of comprehension - must, in the long term, take precedence over the other two more Preface and Acknowledgements pragmatic aims. Nevertheless, psychiatric classification, including that of the major psychoses with which we are concerned here, at present serves the first two pragmatic aims to a greater extent than the third. Concepts are defined for immediate practical purposes of empirically-based treatment and prognosis, and for other related pragmatic purposes, rather than for any more fundamental understanding. These concepts therefore do not have the secure validation that applies to other established scientific concepts, or to many disease entities in other branches of medicine. There are virtually no true disease theories in psychiatry, except perhaps on the border with neurology. As far as schizophrenia is concerned, this weakness goes back as far as Kraepelin at the turn of the last century. His work on dementia praecox attempted to define a new disease concept. In the absence of defining etiopathological evidence, he used evidence about the long-term course of illness as a key element in his definition of disease entities. This aroused controversy in his own time, and has been the source of controversy ever since. Nowadays the tentative and provisional nature of present schemes of classification is obscured because of the enormous authority they are given by professional organizations. Researchers find themselves constrained to think only in terms of the disease concepts used in these authoritative but convention-based classificatory schemes. In addition, the implicit assumption is made in these schemes that mental illnesses should be defined as separate categories, rather than as extremes of dimensions, where the distribution of characteristics over a population may show a complete continuity between normality and extreme pathology. As a result, the use of these schemes may often actually be a barrier to creative thinking. They hinder attempts to work out categories or dimensions that really can be validated in a fundamental way, by reference to disease theories. For much of the last century this was inevitable. In modern times this weakness has been pointed out many times by (e.g. Kendell, 1987; Kringlen, 1994), but nevertheless persists. It is indeed regrettable that it persists at a time when there really are sufficient empirical data, in at least some areas of the study of mental illness, to establish theory-based categories or dimensions of illness. The reason why it persists (in this author’s view) is now a result of the structure of scientific and medical institutions rather than a necessity dependent on the current state of factual knowledge of mental illnesses, or on what is really required for advancement of understanding. What is a disease theory? It is a coordinated set of arguments which relate a defined fundamental cause to symptoms, to the course of the illness (and the symptoms at each stage), to laboratory findings about the illness conducted on living patients, whether biological or psychological or psychophysiological, to postmortem findings, and of course to effective treatments. The coordinated reasoning which links all these together is what validates a concept of illness. For psychiatric illnesses a variety of short-cuts has been proposed over the years: As just mentioned Kraepelin relied heavily on the course of illnesses, followed over many years, and its supposed correlation with psychological symptoms to define concepts of illness: Illnesses whose long-term course differed in severity were classed differently. However, according to such a criterion, cases of rheumatic fever which have no recurrences or long-term complication, and which do not become chronic would be put in a different class of illness from those cases which do, although, as we now know, they have the same underlying cause. The characteristic time course of symptoms in the short term (episodic vs continuous), could be held as a sure pointer, for instance to the difference between schizophrenia and manic-depressive illness. However, a little understanding of servo theory indicates that, for any system with a number of positive and negative feedback loops, and associated delays, minor change in the controlling parameters could bring about a radical shift from stability at one extreme situation to that at another, or to oscillation (“hunting”) between the two, at a wide range of oscillation frequencies. The system would be basically the same in all cases, but due to very minor changes would appear quite different. Some modern operationalized schemes of diagnosis rely entirely on the symptom pattern within a defined period of time. One difficulty with this is that even with this limited scope for definition of an illness, there may be a large number of different conventions for the groupings of symptoms needed to define a particular illness. This is particularly true for an illness whose symptom patterns are as complex as those of schizophrenia. According to the doctrine that symptom patterns are sufficient to define an illness, the many different manifestations of syphilis should be classed as different diseases, as indeed they were, until it was discovered that they all had the same underlying cause. It might be thought that for an illness with a hereditary tendency, those of its features which tend to “breed true” must be keys to the real disease entity. However, the symptom pattern of any illness (and notably so for mental illness) results from the combination of the underlying causes of the illness, and a variety of other features, not themselves pathological, which may vary between persons. Thus, when a pattern of symptoms “breeds true” one does not know if it is the underlying cause which is inherited, or the ancillary contributions which may determine the way the illness expresses itself. One may try to define disease entities by the different classes of treatment which are effective in some illnesses, but not in others. This could sometimes be getting close to the fundamental nature of an illness, but again is influenced by many things other than the basic cause. Steroid hormones such as cortisone have been used to treat a wide variety of illnesses which we know from other information have quite diverse causes. For schizophrenia and related illness, any of these criteria (and many more) have been put forth as demonstrating the conceptual validity of one or another definition. But none of these criteria, taken singly, really establishes conceptual validity. Only the coordinated reasoning that pulls all these threads together is capable of that. If such coordinated reasoning is rigorous enough within itself, and withstands sufficient explicit tests and attempts at falsification to be convincing, is the conceptual 3 Preface and Acknowledgements validity of a disease concept established. Then we have a true disease theory; and we have a validated scheme of classification, which survives on its own merits, rather than on the authority of its proponents, and the faith of their adherents. If such an attempt at coordinated reasoning is successful, it may be expected to disregard some traditional concepts and distinctions. We may find that illnesses traditionally kept separate (though a relationship is acknowledged) come together; and we may also find that some groups of patients often included within a particular disease entity can no longer be so included. For the time being, to define the subject for study, we must have a provisional, relatively loose definition. For this purpose we use the encompassing phrase “Schizophrenia and related disorders”. This phrase includes the illnesses termed schizophrenia, manic depressive illness, schizoaffective psychosis, schizophreniform psychosis. Psychotic depression could also fall within the spectrum of disorders to be considered. We are also interested in psychological and other abnormalities of those at risk (e.g. genetically) for schizophrenia but not showing major illness (e.g. in what is called schizotypal personality disorder). Each of these conditions should themselves be allowed relatively flexible definitions, so that we do not, right at the beginning, lose the phenomenological richness by over-rigorous categorization. For the same reason, phenomenology of schizophrenia is sometimes documented in terms of autobiographical writings (collected in Appendix 3), so that the reader, perhaps sceptical of diagnostic systems, can stay in touch with the basic raw data. As we proceed, and the coordinated reasoning of the theory is developed, the definition and inter-relationship of the above diagnostic terms will be refined, other diagnoses will be compared, and some of these terms will be split. At the end of this work, after the theory has been presented, its implications for a more solidly-based typology will be summarized. Schizophrenia is, in a sense, like an onion: There are several layers of understanding. If we do not dissect the outer layers off neatly and accurately, we have no hope of seeing the deeper “core” of the onion in its correct shape. This book falls into several major parts, each with several chapters. Part I is a succinct summary of the whole argument, starting with a historical and philosophical introduction (Chapter 1), followed by synopses of the main steps in development of the theory (Chapter 2). In this presentation of the essence of the theory, there is no extensive reference to original papers dealing with empirical studies, but instead the chapter will refer forward to the sections and subsections in later parts, where the empirical evidence is discussed in detail. Part I of the book is intended to be read from beginning to end, along with the final summary in Chapter 13. The later chapters (forming Parts II to V) deal in detail with the empirical evidence from which the theory is derived. They can also be read from beginning to end. However, they may sometimes be rather indigestible, and so may be better regarded as sources of reference, rather than flowing text. Part II (Chapters 3 and 4) deals with background evidence about 4 genetic and environmental factors predisposing to schizophrenia. Part III (Chapter 5) deals with the “outer layer of the onion” – its most obvious features, as revealed in acute psychotic episodes. This leads to a fundamental question, about the origin of such active and acute psychosis in schizophrenia, which cannot be answered at this stage. To form a basis for answering this question, and for revealing the deeper nature of schizophrenia and related disorders we then turn to the enduring trait features of these disorders. Part IV (Chapters 6-10) deals with psychological evidence about trait abnormalities. Part V (Chapters 11 and 12) deals with biological evidence (electrophysiology and brain morphology), and Part VI (Chapter 13) provides a brief summing up of the concept of schizophrenia as it has by then emerged. In the course of these extensive sections, it will be clear that the distinction between the active state of psychosis and the enduring traits, present even when psychosis is well controlled by medication, is a very important one for the author. This distinction is introduced initially in Chapter 5. However, the distinction between state and trait aspects of schizophrenia is not a straightforward one, and the precise distinction will become clearer toward the end, as will the causal mechanisms which make psychotic breakdowns likely in persons who have the trait characteristics. The title of this book (“A neurodynamic theory of schizophrenia”) needs a word of explanation. It is not to be seen as a rival to other approaches to understanding schizophrenia, such as the “neurodevelopmental theory”, and indeed, in Part V and elsewhere, reference is made to developmental aspects of brain morphology in schizophrenia. However, the title is meant to indicate the levels of organization over which explanatory arguments are constructed. In principle, these levels could reach upwards from molecular genetics to developmental processes and growth factors, to structure of brain cells and tissues. Then it can reach to physiological processes in the brain, to cybernetics of nervous tissue, and related psychological processes, to influences of the psychological environment on the emergence of schizophrenia, and lastly to the manifest symptoms. However, to construct explanatory arguments reaching all the way from molecular genetic factors to symptoms may be too ambitious, and the lower levels of this hierarchy are beyond the author’s expertise. Therefore, the scope of the explanatory arguments developed here concentrate mainly on the span from cytology of nervous tissue and neuronal dynamics up to the level of the classic symptoms and other psychological abnormalities which define the disorder. For these reasons, the book is entitled “A neurodynamic theory of schizophrenia, and related disorders”. As author, I should explain the origin of this book, that is how a neuroscientist, working in an anatomy department should become so deeply involved with the subject of schizophrenia. It is in fact a very personal quest. As a young man, I was at one stage a medical student at Oxford University, becoming increasingly fascinated by the workings of the brain, though I tended to focus on scholarship, and assimilation of theories from many published sources, rather than experimental work. Preface and Acknowledgements However, in the early 1960s, I also suffered severe psychological problems, consisting, initially, of dramatic fluctuations of mood. This eventually led, in 1967, to a catastrophic psychotic breakdown, which finished any chance I had of completing the medical degree, and put me out of action (as far as developing a career for myself) for nearly three years, a long time at the age of twenty-four. Eventually, I retrained as a scientist, and after obtaining a doctorate at Glasgow University, I was able to return to Oxford as a post-doctoral researcher, and to my previous focus of interest in the brain. At that time I had another brief period in hospital - the result of curtailing the medication I was prescribed - when I learned that the diagnosis given for my illness was in fact schizophrenia. I see no reason to object to that, but it will be clear, even to those who have read only this far in the Preface, that I regard the concept of illness labeled in this way, whatever its clinical utility, as lacking a secure scientific validity. After that, I realized that I had an excellent grounding in the neuroscience of the time, a very accurate memory of my periods of illness, my wits were (mainly) intact, and I also was well aware that, at that time, there was only a very limited understanding of the disorder I had suffered. These factors determined the choice I made of the area on which my research would subsequently focus. In 1977 I emigrated to New Zealand, and was there able to start realizing the dream of what I now call “library-based theory” of brain function. As far as the study of psychotic illnesses goes, the 1980s and early 1990s were dominated by attempts to understand the theory of psychosis and its relation to dopamine. However, eventually it was forced on me that this is only part of the problem of schizophrenia. Research since then has attempted to develop a theory for the underlying constitution out of which psychotic episodes develop. The present work attempts to integrate these two bodies of theory into a coherent whole. There are many organizations and individuals I wish to acknowledge. First I must express my debt to the University of Otago. I am especially indebted to the Department of Anatomy and Structural Biology, and the three persons who have headed that Department since I arrived in 1977, the late Bill Trotter (1922-2001), Gareth Jones, who was chairman between 1984 and 2003, and, in recent years, Helen Nicholson. It was they who provided the essential intellectual environment in which it was possible to bring this work to completion. I consider myself very fortunate to have found such a supportive niche in which to do my research. In 1999 I resigned my paid position at Otago, but retained most valuable links with the university and the department, as Honorary Fellow. Since then I have had two years of paid employment in the Northern hemisphere: In 2003-2004 I was able to work at the Zentral Institut für Seelische Gesundheit at Mannheim, Germany, making use of the excellent library there. This visit was supported by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft, to whom I give my sincere thanks. A year later, I was able to spend eleven months in Montreal, in association with the Department of Psychiatry at McGill University, again making use of the superb libraries at that university. During this period I was supported by the Jewish Community Endowment Fund to whom I am also enormously grateful. One other organization deserves my full-hearted thanks - the Schizophrenia Fellowship of New Zealand. I have had a close association with this organization, since its foundation in 1977, the year I arrived in New Zealand. I believed then that many of the ideas on which psychiatric practice in relation to schizophrenia was founded where fatally flawed, notwithstanding the excellent clinical skills of some psychiatrists. Therefore, I wanted to avoid what was said in the textbooks, and get as close to the raw evidence on this subject as possible. With no basic medical (let alone psychiatric) qualification, it was through my contacts in the Schizophrenia Fellowship that this became possible. The many heartbreaking stories I have heard in my contacts with the families in the Schizophrenia Fellowship, as well as the sharp insights I have gained about symptoms, from talking with people who have experienced them, have greatly deepened both my concern for and my understanding of this disorder. Amongst the many individuals who have supported and encouraged me, and fostered my development as a scientist, and as a student of psychotic disorders, I would like to mention the following: First, I acknowledge the important part played by the late George Gordon (1920-2002). He was my supervisor of studies throughout my undergraduate years, and it was in his laboratory, as a post-doctoral student, that I did single-unit recording work, which provided the empirical basis for much of my later theoretical work, including the “central hypothesis” for schizophrenia, whose implications are explored in the present work. I also thank the late Charles Phillips (1916-1994), who gave me much vital support during a difficult period in 1973, and later was of great help in publication of my first book, in 1980. I thank Peter Usherwood, my doctoral supervisor for seeing me through the thesis, and, since then for all his steadfast support and friendship. I thank a number of scientists working in Otago whose experiments have complemented some of my theoretical work, especially in relation to the actions of the transmitter dopamine - Jeff Wickens, Brian Hyland, Dorothy Oorschot, Jason Kerr, John Reynolds and the late Mark Tunstall. I thank my friends in Tübingen especially Valentino Braitenberg, Almut Schüz, and Neils Birbaumer - who have supported me in many ways in the years during which this work was being assembled. (In fact Valentino, independently, has used assumptions about “axonal delay lines”, closely related to the “central hypothesis” in the present work, to explain aspects of cerebellar function.). In Kingston Ontario, I thank my longtime collaborator, Rick Beninger for the insights we have jointly developed about the relation between the functions of dopamine and psychotic symptoms. There are three experienced psychiatrists who I would also like to thank. Guy Chouinard has been a friend and collaborator since 1989, and has supported and guided me in many aspects of the present work. Eric Chen has been a sounding-board in discussion of some of the most difficult parts of the theory presented here. Pat McGorry, pioneer of early intervention for psychotic disorders, gives me faith that mental health services for psychotic disorders can be better than they 5 Preface and Acknowledgements were. In the actual production of this work, the help of several ever-willing people in Otago should also be thanked: Robbie McPhee for all artwork, Ross MarshallSeeley for supervising my computing and word-processing requirements, the always-efficient and courteous staff of Otago University Medical Library, and Peter Herbison for his expertise in the statistical meta-analyses presented in Chapter 12. Lastly I thank Kate Ball for her participation in many discussions of the theory presented here. At the time of finalizing this work, she understands more than anyone, apart from the author, the details of the reasoning on which this theory is based. The scientific literature on which this work is based has been surveyed up to June 2007. Data for the meta-analyses 6 in Chapter 12 (tabulated in Appendix 6) were finalized around November 2005. The decision to publish it on-line was taken reluctantly, after unsuccessful approaches to about eight international publishing houses. This may be an indication that, for serious scientific monographs, especially if they are large and complex, the future lies with the internet. Hard copy, and electronic copies will be archived within the library system of Otago University. Robert Miller Dunedin, August 2007 Chapter 1. History and philosophy of the disease concept, and their application to models and theories of mental illness 1.1. Historical development of disease concept. In antiquity, the Hippocratic school, which flourished between 450 and 350 B.C., regarded medicine as the practical art of curing. Each case was considered on its merits, though similarities between cases were used to guide treatment (Bernal, 1964; p.187). Diseases were due to natural rather than divine causes, and philosophy was not recommended as a basis for medical practice. The doctrine of the four humors, first advocated by Empedocles at the start of this period, led to the idea that diseases come from “within”, reflecting an imbalance between normal factors within the body. This may be regarded as the origin of “physiologic” concepts of disease. The four humors bore no real relation to physiology, but much later the same doctrine of imbalance between real physiological factors within the body as the cause of disease, continued this tradition. In such a concept of disease, it is likely that the imbalances are regarded as quantitative departures from normal, rather than qualitative abnormalities. Such physiologic concepts of disease would thus tend to be expressed dimensionally rather than categorically. In addition, in such a concept of disease, it is difficult to make a sharp separation between the disease and the patient: The disease is an imbalance within the patient. From this period until well after the Renaissance, medicine was guided by the humoral theory, until empirical investigations supplanted it. The other philosophical tradition has its roots in Aristotle, who suggested that individual things and classes of things could have their “essences”, those features which an individual thing (or a universal) could not lose without losing their special identity. Much later, in the seventeenth century, in the writings of Thomas Sydenham (1624-1689), this was the origin of “ontological” or “essentialist” concepts of disease. Sydenham challenged the humoral/physiologic view of antiquity. He emphasized careful clinical description of each patient, and as a result, was able to assert that illnesses, like plants, fell into natural types (Bynum, 1993). The disease essence is then conceived to be separate from the person who is afflicted: Unlike the humoral or physiologic concept of disease, such diseases may be imposed on the person from outside, though this is not a necessary aspect of the ontological view of disease. Emergence of the idea that diseases could have their essences separate from the patient was encouraged by the work of Linnaeus (1707-1778), whose approach was avowedly Aristotelian. As a botanist, his work on classification of plants is well known. He suggested that there were essences, the same for all members of a plant species. His contemporary, Buffon (1707-1788), advocated, in contrast, that “nature knows only the individual”, and suggested that classifications such as Linnaeus’ were imposed on Nature as a matter of convenience, but did not correspond to the underlying realities. Linnaeus was also medically trained, and produced another essentialist classification, that of diseases (Bynum, 1993). Accordingly, diseases were conceived categorically rather than dimensionally. Early clinical description of some illnesses (e.g. those associated with fever) clearly supported this ontological viewpoint, that there were specific disease entities. For botanical classification we now have sound theoretical reasons why Linnaeus was correct and Buffon incorrect: The essence of a plant species is defined by its characteristic genetic make-up, which, amongst many other things, permits faithful sexual reproduction of that essence only with members of the same species, so that the essence is transmitted quite categorically except in a few exceptional cases. For classification of diseases, theoretical reasons for adopting ontological rather than physiologic conceptualizations are more complex and less clear cut. In the nineteenth century, the focus was on identifying symptoms and syndromes with particular anatomicallydetected lesions in specific internal organs. During this phase there was no clear commitment on the underlying philosophical issue of physiologic vs ontological concepts of illness. However, with the success of bacteriology under Pasteur (1822-1895), the essences of many important illnesses could be redefined in terms of the effects of specific micro-organisms invading the body from outside. In a somewhat less categorical manner, Virchow (1821-1902) had advocated an essentialist view of other sorts of disease, based on the category of cellular change occurring in the body, by which diseases could be defined and diagnosed (Maulitz, 1993). Definition of abnormal variants of specific genes, or of autoantibodies to specific body proteins are other modern versions of essentialist definitions of diseases. In the latter cases they reflect internal abnormalities rather than ones imposed from outside. In all these types of illness we now know that there are sound bases, similar to that which applies to botanical classification, for classifying on 7 History and Philosophy the basis of clearly separate categories, each with their own essence. However, for other types of disease, which became more significant in the twentieth century, for instance degenerative and other chronic diseases, the ontological view did not fit so well. For these, knowledge of the underlying mechanisms suggested that there was a quantitative imbalance of endogenous processes, a reversion to the concept of an imbalance of natural humoral factors, as believed before the Renaissance. For instance the idea of hypertension implies an increase in blood pressure along a continuous variable, rather than a categorical departure from normality. 1.2. History of the disease concept, as applied to mental illness. In the field of mental disorders, certain concepts of disease such as “mania” and “melancholia” go back to antiquity, were referred to by Hippocrates, and were subsequently attributed to imbalance in the humoral system. Thus in general they were conceived as “physiologic imbalances”. In the early post-Renaissance world, writers on mental illness slightly amended the humoral view, by allowing, in addition, a mixture of external causes, both biological and socio-environmental (Brown, 1993; p 440). Sydenham, who tried to identify the essences of disease, as did Linnaeus for plant species, did not follow this through to mental disorders: For him, “hysteria” (in those days having characteristics similar to epilepsy, and considered by Sydenham to be a mental disorder), was really defined by exclusion, an illness which did not add up to any then-known disease (Hunter and MacAlpine, 1963; pp 221) A century after Sydenham, the Scot, William Cullen (1710-1790) (originator of the word “neurosis”, still much in use today) wrote of mental illness as occurring when there was “some inequality in the excitement of the brain”, for when this happened “recollection cannot properly take place, while at the same time other parts of the brain, more excited and excitable, may give false perceptions, associations and judgments” (cited by Brown, 1993; p. 441). As a result Cullen was able to conceive of insanity as originating as a dynamic disturbance of the brain, which may have no discernible gross anatomical traces therein. For Cullen, such diseases were not ontological, had no discrete “essence” (Bynum, 1993). This concept of dynamic imbalance in the brain, which did not stretch the old humoral concept very far, is quite similar to that advocated here by the present author. After the French revolution Philippe Pinel (1745-1826) was an important figure, and though influenced by Cullen, himself emphasized psychological factors in mental illness, together with careful listening to patients telling their story, and a rejection of somatic treatment (Brown, 1993). As a result of careful clinical studies, the school of psychiatry founded by Pinel and his pupil Esquirol (1772-1840) defined a variety of syndromes: “Démence précoce” was defined by Morel, “Folie circulaire”, the precursor of the modern concept of manic-depressive psychosis or bipolar disorder by Falret, and “Délire de Persecution”, precursor of paranoia, by Lasègue. Falret was also the first to suggest that the course of an illness was useful in delineating psychiatric entities: 8 “for... the idea of a natural course of illness that can be foreseen presupposes the existence of a natural kind of disease” (see Beumont, 1992). This appears to be one of the first definite suggestions that mental illness could be conceived in an ontological manner, as a series of essences of disease afflicting a patient, rather than as an imbalance of endogenous factors. The tradition was developed by Kahlbaum and Kraepelin in Germany, and survives implicitly today in many operationalized schemes of psychiatric classification1. The concept of psychosis appears at about this time, but its history is complex and curious, and was not based on the French school of syndromology. While the term “neurosis” goes back to Cullen, “psychosis” arose later, implying disorder of general function of nervous system, but without fever (Berrios, 1987). In the early nineteenth century “neurosis” implied “organic”, while “psychosis” referred to a psychological or experiential state. At this time “neurosis” was a much larger concept than it is now, and psychosis was smaller. In the mid-nineteenth century Von Feuchtersleben (1847: see Berrios, 1987) could assert that every psychosis was also a neurosis (i.e. involved disorder of the brain as well as experiential disorder), though the converse need not be so. By the early twentieth century, psychoses were considered to be divisible into organic and functional types (see Bonhoeffer, 1909). The former had identifiable biological causal agents (e.g. cerebral damage, infection or poisoning), while the latter were without discernible anatomical findings or other evidence of a definite cause. Nowadays there are some national differences in the use of the word “psychosis”. In the English-speaking world, the term generally implies “a break with reality”, in other words, a state dominated by delusions, hallucinations and other related symptoms. In some European traditions however, the use of the term corresponds more closely to its original use, an experiential disorder with or without identified physical basis, and not necessarily including hallucinations and delusions. In Germany, at the start of the nineteenth century, the teachings of Kant were influential. He taught that both psychology and psychiatry should be branches of philosophy, not of medicine (a tradition that was of relevance even in the twentieth century when figures like Jaspers and Heidegger were professional philosophers, but also deeply interested in psychiatry and psychology). Thus, in the early nineteenth century German psychiatry was mentalist. It was only a reaction to this mentalism which brought somatic 1 The subsequent history of psychiatry in France is described by Pichot (1967; 1992). Compared to German psychiatry, French psychiatry has tended to be more clinical and descriptive, with less concern for systematization of mental disorders. However, since the early twentieth century, the criterion of “chronic deteriorating course” has been used rather systematically in defining schizophrenia (Pichot, 1982). As a result, schizophrenia has a somewhat narrower definition than in Britain or USA; and other delusional states, not fulfilling this criterion, have assumed greater importance. Moves to develop a nation-wide consensus on psychiatric diagnosis in France occurred later than in UK and USA (see Pull et al, 1987a,b). History and Philosophy psychiatry to prominence in Germany (Beumont, 1992). By the middle of the nineteenth century there was vigorous debate between “Somatikers” and “Psychikers” (Brown, 1993, pp.438). By 1880, the “somatikers” were in the ascendancy, and Germany was becoming pre-eminent in psychiatry, with more professors of psychiatry than in either France or England. Amongst these was Griesinger, who was clear in his belief that the mental diseases were brain diseases, and also believed that “psychosis” was a unitary concept. A more enduring influence was Kahlbaum, who adopted the French concern with sorting mental illnesses into syndromes, and, following Falret, took the long-term course of an illness to be one of its more important characteristics. Kahlbaum’s continuation of the French attention to defining syndromes, led to the first description of catatonia, while his pupil Hecker first described hebephrenia. Their aim was to work towards genuine disease categories. By the end of the century, the question was not so much whether mental disorders could be classified as disease states, but rather how that should be done. The definitive achievement of this was left to Kalhbaum’s successor, Emil Kraepelin. Although, by the end of the nineteenth century, the “somatikers” were clearly dominant in Germany, Kraepelin was critical of the mythological nature of many of their conjectures about the brain (Beumont, 1992). He concentrated on clinical detail rather than pathological or laboratory findings. Kahlbaum’s project of defining disease entities within psychiatry seemed more feasible when the many manifestations of syphilis became unified within a single bacteriological theory. Before that, the classification of the chronic psychoses was impossible because they could not easily be separated from the many cases of general paralysis. Once these were identified and separated, more serious study became possible of the remaining cases. Kraepelin followed the idea of Falret and Kahlbaum that longitudinal progression of an illness was an important characteristic (Berrios and Hauser, 1988). Primed with this idea, he had been struck early in his career by the fact that some asylum patients showed progressive development of dementia, and came to resemble one another. Having reached this conclusion, he set to work cataloguing the symptoms in all patients, to work out ways of predicting which patients would show such progressive deterioration. As a result he unified Morel’s “démence précoce”, Heckers' “hebephrenia” and Kahlbaum’s “catatonia” to give a disease concept to which he gave the Latinized name “dementia praecox”. In this, Kraepelin, considered that he was making a conceptual synthesis similar to that which had recently been achieved in the case of syphilis (Shorter, 2005; p. 270). The criterion for defining dementia praecox, and the key for classification of symptoms was the long term course of the illness (i.e. progressive deterioration, not characteristic of the other entities he defined, paraphrenia and manic depressive illness). Within this general concept of a deteriorating disease, subtypes were recognized - catatonic, hebephrenic, paranoid - corresponding in general to the syndromes recognized by earlier researchers. The model of disease represented by these entities, suggested initially by Falret and Kahlbaum and brought to clear form by Kraepelin was clearly ontological: With “dementia praecox” Kraepelin thought he was defining a disease essence. However, the long term course of an illness does not bear as close a relation to its underlying cause as does an identifiable microorganism. Thus, it is easy to point out the circularity in Kraepelin’s method 2. Moreover, although the distinction between deteriorating and nondeteriorating diseases was the defining criterion for Kraepelin’s disease categories, Kraepelin recognized that a minority of those with the symptom picture usually associated with deterioration, did in fact recover (13% according to Lehmann, 1980). In addition, towards the end of his career Kraepelin was forced to the conclusion that the dichotomy between dementia praecox and manic-depressive psychosis in terms of symptom picture was not as sharp as he initially proposed (Berrios, 1987). Thus, despite the authority which has been given Kraepelin’s concepts of disease since his death, he was himself aware, by the end of his life, of major inadequacies in his categorization. Eugen Bleuler (1857-1939), the Swiss psychiatrist, gave us the name “schizophrenia” (or rather “the group of schizophrenias”) in place of “dementia praecox”. He did not to have a single defining criterion (such as deterioration, for Kraepelin), and did not assume schizophrenia to have the inevitable deterioration assumed in Kraepelin’s main works (Lehmann, 1980). Thus Bleuler’s concept could cope with the proportion of atypical cases, recognized by Kraepelin, who did not deteriorate. He accepted the three main subtypes defined by Kraepelin, adding a fourth – “simple schizophrenia”. He described mental symptoms in a manner similar to Kraepelin, but, having been influenced by the totally different ideas of Sigmund Freud, he saw in them the play of psychological and social factors in the environment as well as a brain disorder. He also reconceptualized many of these symptoms, so that most of them became secondary to the primary processes which, for him, were disturbances of affect, association and volition. He assumed he was describing a disease, but it is difficult to specify what his criteria were for defining that disease category. One presumes these were put together subjectively, which is doubly unsatisfactory when a concept is defined in which there are rather different subdivisions, and no etiological or pathological basis to unify them. 2 For instance, David Hill (1983, p.77) writes: "The tautology is obvious. First one excludes from the construct those who do not meet the outcome criterion. Second, one gives the construct a title - x. Third, one cites as evidence for the construct the fact that all who have disease x also have a common outcome - y. That disease x results in outcome y is a hypothesis which cannot be disproved if x is defined in terms of the presence or absence of outcome y." Hill then quotes from Kraepelin to show that this was actually part of Kraepelin's thinking. However, in defence of Kraepelin, it should be pointed out that pioneer efforts in classification are very likely to be circular in this sense. This is because they are constructions attempting to make sense of a chaos of information. They are conjectures for future generations to evaluate, rather than tested and verified hypotheses. Hill's criticism could just as well be applied to Linnaeus's botanical classification, at the time it was first advanced, for instance in the authoritative claim that the reproductive parts of plants were most important as a basis for classification. 9 History and Philosophy In the years after Kraepelin and Bleuler, there were various attempts at modification of, or addition to, Kraepelin’s scheme. Some of these represent personal choice in style of classification, between the “lumpers”, seeking a simple system, and the “splitters” who prefer a more complex system, which preserves more of the richness of the raw data. In 1933, Kasanin (Lehmann, 1980) proposed an additional category - schizoaffective disorder - whose symptoms had aspects of both schizophrenia and manicdepressive psychosis. This development was intended to cope with the proportion of cases, recognized by Kraepelin, where the symptom picture was intermediate between that of dementia praecox and manic-depressive psychosis. In 1939, Langfeldt also introduced the term “schizophreniform psychosis” to accommodate the fact that some patients had episodes of illness, which were symptomatically characteristic of schizophrenia, but short-lived (Lehmann, 1980). From this distinction Langfeldt also derived a division between “reactive” and “process” schizophrenia, the latter having the poor prognosis of Kraepelin’s concept. This distinction guided much research in the 1950s and 1960s, and is mainly used nowadays in Scandinavia. The term “schizophreniform psychosis” is still used widely, and in DSM-III, refers to a schizophrenia-like illness with duration less than six months. Kraepelin was not the only researcher in the late nineteenth century to offer a system of classification of major mental disorders. Wernicke also had a scheme of classification, based on cerebral localization within multiregion systems of the brain. This scheme was superceded by Kraepelin’s mainly because of Wernicke’s untimely death. However, there are recent signs of renewed interest in Wernicke’s system (Wright et al, 1999). In the middle years of the twentieth century, the Wernicke tradition developed independent of Kraepelin’s ideas, particularly in the work of Kleist and Leonhard (see Ban, 1982). These researchers regarded the features of the end-states of illness, rather than those of the acute phase, as the key to classification. From data on the end-state, both researchers made a major subdivision within the schizophrenias, and each subdivision had its own subtypes. According to Kleist (following Wernicke), each major type results from impairment in one or more neurological systems. Those which affected just a single system were referred to as “systematic” schizophrenias, those which affected several, as “unsystematic”. Leonhard (1959; see English translation, 1979), working mainly after World War II, adopted the same terminology, but based it on possible genetic differences between types, as is the case for subgroups in certain neurological diseases. He thus hoped to subdivide a heterogeneous population of patients into a series of smaller but more homogeneous subgroups. As a result, a scheme of classification was constructed with many more entities than in previous schemes, to cope with the many different courses and symptomatic end-states a schizophrenic illness might have. His scheme is better known on the continent of Europe, especially in Würzburg, than in the English speaking world. The best known of Leonhard’s concepts in the Englishspeaking world is the division of affective illness into 10 unipolar disorder (i.e. depressive illness) and bipolar illness (manic-depressive illness). With regard to schizophrenia, some of Leonhard’s entities will be mentioned later in this book, and so it is appropriate to give an introduction to his scheme. The “cycloid psychoses” were distinguished by their benign prognosis, as indicated by an acute illness always followed by complete remission. The schizophrenias themselves were divided into two main groups - the unsystematic and the systematic schizophrenias. The “unsystematic” schizophrenias were envisaged to have clearer genetic determinants than the “systematic” ones. The unsystematic forms (affective paraphrenia, periodic catatonia and cataphasia) varied considerably from each other in symptom picture in the acute productive stage. Periodic catatonia (reviewed by L.R.Gjessing, 1974) was an entity originating with Kraepelin (1909) who described cases of periodically recurring catatonic excitement, separated by regular intervals. The whole group of schizophrenias included 2-3% of cases of periodic catatonia (according to both Kraepelin and R Gjessing). However, Stober et al (2002) gives a lifetime prevalence in the general population of 0.1%, equivalent to about 10% of all cases of DSM-III schizophrenia. Similar discrepancies between studies in prevalence of this subtype are documented by Ban et al (1984). It is thus likely that this condition is not yet adequately defined, in part because the periodic symptoms can appear right at the beginning of the illness, or later after a more typical schizophrenic illness, and so are often indistinguishable from more typical cases, in the short term. Leonhard’s systematic schizophrenias included the classical Kraepelinian subtypes (catatonic, hebephrenic and paraphrenia). Despite modern drug therapy, these subtypes, according to Leonhard, commonly showed an end-state of irreversible impairment. Since (according to Leonhard) they have a much weaker tendency to be inherited than the unsystematic types, Leonhard takes them to arise from influences in the psychosocial domain or the physical aspects of the environment. Leonhard’s claims about the different role of inheritance in his different subtypes are discussed in section 3.4.1. A key point in interpreting that issue is how Leonhard’s subtypes correspond to schizophrenia defined in modern operational schemes like DSM-III. This question has not been well studied, but in a twin study of Franzek and Beckmann (1998) it is reported that 100% of cases of “systematic schizophrenia” also fit DSM-III-R criteria for schizophrenia, while only about two-thirds of cases of “unsystematic schizophrenia” do so. Another relatively recent trend is to greatly simplify the subtyping of schizophrenia. Crow (1990a,b) has developed the concept of a “continuum of psychosis”, with no sharp cut-offs, but a continuous dimensional change, between schizophrenia in its various forms, schizoaffective disorder, bipolar affective disorder, or indeed unipolar depression. Another simplifying principle used by both Crow (1980, 1982, 1985) and Andreasen and Olson (1982) is to employ the conceptual distinction between positive and negative symptoms, which originated in the nineteenth century. In this way of thinking, positive symptoms are abnormal because something is added onto normal function, while negative symptoms are abnormal because some function, normally History and Philosophy present, is missing. This distinction, originally made about individual symptoms, has then been applied to define syndromes of schizophrenia itself (Type I and Type II, in the writings of Crow; “positive schizophrenia” and “negative schizophrenia” according to Andreasen and Olson). During the first half of the twentieth century, it is apparent that grouping of symptoms to give definitions of schizophrenia and related disorders was accomplished in a rather subjective fashion, varying according to the writer. Moreover, in most of the above schemes, the criteria for allotting a patient to one or other diagnosis, or subtype was not stated in explicit operationalized manner, so that replicability of diagnosis between psychiatrists was not good. In response to these perceived inadequacies, Kurt Schneider produced the first operationalized scheme of diagnosis for schizophrenia, published in English in 1959. In contrast to early dichotomies between the psychikers and the somatikers, Schneider was ready to accept that any psychosis was both psychic and somatic. He writes (1949/59): “ ‘Organic psychosis’ will not do as a . . .title because we regard schizophrenia and cyclothymia as ‘symptomatic’, attributable to primary organic causes (as yet unknown) in the same way as all illnesses are organic”. Schneider put particular emphasis on symptoms, observed at one point in time, for characterizing an illness. However, he also recognized that the relation between these symptoms and the eventual diagnosis was more indirect than for other types of disease. In contrast to Kraepelin, he did not regard longitudinal data about course and outcome as pertinent in reaching a diagnosis. He emphasized certain psychotic symptoms which represent the most severe departure from normal psychology as being of special importance in distinguishing cyclothymia (i.e. the manic phase of manicdepressive illness) from schizophrenia. These included the following: audible thoughts; voices heard arguing, or commenting on the patient’s actions; the experience of influences playing on the patient’s body (somatic passivity experiences); thought withdrawal; volitional acts that are experienced by patients as the work or influence of others. These symptoms were designated by Schneider as symptoms of “first rank”, of such significance in diagnosis that they should overrule any other symptoms present at the same time. This ranking was the forerunner of the hierarchical nature of parts of the British Present State Examination. It was also the start of the operationalizing of psychiatric diagnosis, which is so much a part of today’s psychiatric culture, with its emphasis on inter-rater reliability. After World War II, British psychiatry was much influenced by developments on the continent of Europe. The explicitness of Schneider’s criteria was influential in the development of the British instrument for description and classification of psychiatric symptoms - the Present State Examination (PSE)(Wing et al, 1974). This includes 140 symptoms, whose definition and scoring is carefully specified. As with Schneider’s criteria, data on course and outcome were of no significance in definition of disease categories. The CATEGO program combines these 140 symptoms to give 38 syndromes, which are then further combined to give diagnostic classes. These do not have quite the same implication as a formal diagnosis, and there is no suggestion that they correspond to disease entities. The diagnostic category “S”, incorporates information about a variety of symptoms of schizophrenia, with Schneider’s symptoms of first rank playing an important part in its definition. In the first chapter of Wing et al (1974) it is suggested, quoting Hempel (1959), that “the ideal classification should be mutually exclusive, and jointly exhaustive; that is each object should be allocated to one class and to one class only, and a class should be allowable for each object, thus ensuring a minimum of uncertainty and ambiguity”. Thus, the P.S.E. is explicitly categorical in approach, although it does not intend to identify disease types. The categorical nature of the P.S.E. is adopted for pragmatic reasons associated with clinical practice, rather than for theoretical reasons associated with the nature of the underlying disease entities. Another feature of the P.S.E., which appears in the transformation of syndromes into diagnostic classes, is that it is hierarchical. In other words, if a class low in the hierarchy is identified in a patient, together with one higher in the hierarchy, the higher class is taken to subsume the lower one, and becomes the designated class. (For instance, psychotic symptoms override depressive ones, and schizophrenic symptoms override other psychotic symptoms, while Schneider’s symptoms “trump” them all.) This hierarchical principle has its counterpart within modern biological taxonomy, where it is referred to as the “cladistic” approach to classification (e.g. Parshall and Priest, 1993). American psychiatry in the middle years of the twentieth century did not consider that formal diagnosis was very important (Lorr, 1966). Diagnostic schemes under DSM II3 were thus not explicit, though for schizophrenia they were based generally on Bleuler. They produced a far higher incidence of schizophrenia than European or British criteria. However, by 1980, this was no longer the case (Kendell, 1987). At that time the most widely used schemes in North America were those of Feighner, the Research Diagnostic Criteria (RDC) and the newly-published DSM-III. All of these took the presence of manic or depressive symptoms as exclusion criteria for the diagnosis of schizophrenia. Unlike European and British systems, they insisted on a minimum duration of symptoms (2 weeks for Feighner, 6 months for RDC and DSM-III), though they made no assumptions about long-term course in their categorization. Since the DSMIII/IV systems are now the most widely used worldwide, some detail should be given on the underlying style of these systems and their assumptions. DSM-III, DSM-III-R and DSM-IV were produced for several purposes: clinical, research, educational but, in the introduction to DSM-IV it is stated that “Our highest priority has been to provide a helpful guide to clinical practice” (American Psychiatric Association, 1994). In contrast to DSM-II, DSM-III “introduced a number of important methodological innovations, including explicit diagnostic criteria, a multiaxial system and a descriptive approach that attempted to be neutral with respect to theories of etiology”. However, two features of DSM-III/IV show a clear, though implicit commitment on the important theoretical issue “DSM”: Diagnostic and Statistical Manual, of the American Psychiatric Association, in its various editions 3 11 History and Philosophy referred to above: This issue is whether mental illnesses have an “essence” (for instance one which might be imposed from outside as in certain other classes of illness) as opposed to a physiologic imbalance of factors which must come from within, and which would be difficult to separate from the patient or the “person”. These features of the DSM-III/IV systems belie their alleged neutrality on theoretical issues. First, DSM-III and DSM-IV are explicitly categorical rather than dimensional classifications4. As in the P.S.E., this choice is for pragmatic reasons, associated with clinical decision making, rather than as a commitment to a particular concept of mental illness. Thus, in the introduction to DSMIV, it is emphasized that, despite the categorical nature of the DSM-IV system, there are likely to be many patients whose condition is intermediate between the categories defined therein. Some advantages of a dimensional approach are admitted, but these are outweighed by the practical disadvantages. (For instance it is suggested that dimensional classifications are less familiar and less vivid, and there is no agreed basis for the appropriate dimensions.) Nevertheless the categorical presentation of the classification makes it more difficult to formulate disease theories based on dimensional concepts, or physiologic imbalances, even though theoretical arguments (discussed below) suggest that this is more appropriate. The second indication that an implicit theoretical choice has been made about the nature of mental illness comes in the very definition of mental illness. In the introduction to DSM-IV, the comment is made that “a common misconception is that classification of mental disorders classifies people, when actually what are being classified are disorders that people have”. This statement is used to justify the humane preference for usages such as “a person with schizophrenia” rather than “a schizophrenic” 5. However, it also seems to be saying that mental illness is imposed on the person, rather than being an imbalance of the internal factors which go to make up a person6. This implicit choice of the 4 Analysis of the structure of symptom groupings in DSM-III-R, by Gara et al (1992) suggests that it is in fact a hybrid of categorical constructs of disease with some other principle (perhaps dimensional). 5 With regard to the choice between word usages like “a person with schizophrenia” as opposed to “a schizophrenic”, the present author, like the authors of DSMIII/IV, prefers the former usage. However, the present author's reason for this preference is different from that in DSM III/IV: It is not based on a presumption about whether the illness is imposed upon the person, rather than being part of the person. Instead this preference is adopted because the former of these two usages is of greater therapeutic benefit to patients: The best way to encourage the integration of a person, whether sick or healthy, is to treat them as an integrity, and help them to develop such integrity as they are capable of. The former usage thus encourages patients suffering from schizophrenia to reintegrate their personality as far as they can, whereas the latter tends to dismiss the patient as permanently “invalid” as a person. 6 Schneider has a more complex view on this matter. He writes (1949/1959, p. 95): “Psychosis, and in particular schizophrenia, always involves an over-all change, and therefore individual phenomena have only a limited claim for 12 ontological concept of mental illness is particularly striking when it comes to personality disorders, which, in DSM-IV are assessed in a different section (different “axis”) from the other mental disorders. For instance, the personality variant “schizotypal personality disorder” (SPD) is widely regarded as having a relation to the vulnerability to schizophrenia and other endogenous psychotic illnesses, but comes in a quite different section of the manual from schizophrenia. The situation becomes yet more complex when it is realized that patients who will receive the DSM-III diagnosis of schizophrenia also have, in the premorbid phase, an increased likelihood of satisfying criteria for DSM-III personality disorders, and not only the schizotypal personality (Hogg et al, 1990). If the DSM-IV definition of mental disorder is applied to personality disorders, it makes the paradoxical implication that a personality disorder is an “illness a person has” (the person presumably nevertheless remaining in some sense as a stable entity throughout), rather than something abnormal actually within the person. The contrasting viewpoint seems more plausible: Viewed from a “physiologic” or dimensional viewpoint, personality variants may arise from imbalance in the very factors which go to make up a person, and, as such, are trends along the same dimension which, in more extreme form, leads to the major mental disorders. Two general observations can be made as comments on this brief survey of the history of the disease concept in psychiatry since the Renaissance. First, considering the wide range of definitions which have been offered for concepts of mental illness over the centuries, and their regular change over the centuries, a degree of scepticism is entirely appropriate. At different times, and in the hands of different investigators, the complex phenomenology of mental illness has been subdivided in all sorts of ways. Schemes vary idiosyncratically according to whether the subdivision is into few or many categories, the explicitness vs implicitness of the process of categorization, and the criteria on which the categorization is based. Such history would give anyone pause before accepting many of the modern categories of psychiatric illness as anything more than currently fashionable conventions. Such scepticism is especially appropriate for that central concept in psychiatry, schizophrenia, and its distinction from manic-depressive illness. Even the authoritative scheme of Kraepelin, still a major influence a hundred years after its first formulation, has survived merely because there has been no better alternative. It has always been subject to unanswered criticism, even from its originator, and cannot in any sense be claimed to have withstood critical test. The widespread adoption of operationalized criteria for diagnosis has improved consensus between psychiatrists using the same criteria. However, this does not constitute support for the conceptual validity of such diagnostic review in themselves. . . A psychotic phenomenon is not like a defective stone in an otherwise perfect mosaic. Psychotic individuals . . .are no less closed microcosms than normal persons, or the bodily organism itself, and as such they have their own particular principle of unity.” However Schneider also admits next that “a psychotic patient can sometimes stand apart from his psychosis as a person.” History and Philosophy schemes. Diagnoses of disorders in the schizophrenia spectrum may change between successive episodes of illness. Stable diagnoses are found in no more than 60-80% (varying with the diagnosis), as summarized in Appendix 1A. There is a tendency for the proportion of cases with the schizophrenia diagnosis to increase over time, and for that of other related diagnoses to decrease (Appendix 1B). The stability of DSMIII diagnosis over time is less than its reliability between raters at any one time (Y.R.Chen et al, 1996). Moreover the reliability of DSM-III across races is a point of concern (see section 4.9.). This was examined by Loring and Powell (1988), by asking a range of 488 psychiatrists to give a DSM-III diagnosis for two case histories. While the same information was provided to all psychiatrists upon which to base the diagnosis, the race and gender of the supposed “patient” was varied between psychiatrists. The difference made by this variable was very large. Admittedly this was no indication of the reliability of DSM-III when used under research conditions: In this study psychiatrists were the experimental subjects, rather than the researchers, and the results probably reflect the reliability of DSM-III in the circumstance of a routine clinical examination rather than in research studies. Nevertheless, the pointed question must be asked: Does the current parceling of psychiatric disorders, in schemes such as DSM-III or DSM-IV, define real disease entities; or does it merely codify distinctions which are unclear both conceptually, and in practice? The parceling of psychiatric disorders may be as much a human construction as is the conventional distinction, on the basis of size alone, between a horse and a pony. The latter is a quite replicable criterion, but sacrifices conceptual validity, since, as we all know, ponies are really a subclass of horse. The same comment might apply to current operationalized diagnostic schemes. The other general comment which can be made is that, at least since the time of Pinel, systems for classification and description of mental illness have generally been avowedly atheoretical. This harks back to the original Hippocratic tradition, that philosophy had no place in the healing art of medicine. The lesson from the dark ages, when humoral theory held up progress for many centuries perhaps reinforces the tendency for medicine, even today, to be strictly empirical, rather than theory-based. Modern attempts to create “theories” of mental disorder, such as those of Freud, are now largely dismissed as pseudo-science, and have entrenched the tendency in psychiatry to scorn more genuine attempts to build underlying theory. It may be true that “there is nothing so practical as a good theory” 7; but, for something as complex as medicine, the corollary has seemed more appropriate that “there is nothing so impractical as a bad theory”. We see the scepticism of theory in Pinel, whose tradition was that of careful clinical description, directed at defining nosological categories and avoiding speculation about etiology or pathology. His pupil, Esquirol wrote “I have observed the symptoms of madness and have studied the ways, the habits and needs of lunatics . . keeping my attention on the facts, I have brought together those of a 7 An aphorism adopted by many, but probably originating with James Clerk Maxwell similar nature. I described them as I saw them. I have rarely sought to explain them” (Beumont, 1992). Kraepelin, Schneider, the British PSE and the American DSMIII/IV systems are all also atheoretical descriptive or classificatory schemes, attempting to be neutral with regard theories of causation. Schneider (1949/59), while asserting the special value of certain symptoms for distinguishing schizophrenia from cyclothymia, also writes (p.133) that “the value of these symptoms is. . only related to diagnosis; they have no particular contribution to make to the theory of schizophrenia.” The quotation with which the Preface to this work begins suggests that the scorn of theory in psychiatric research is one its biggest weaknesses. General medicine nowadays considers itself to have a fully scientific basis (although its day to day application is always an art). Psychiatry likewise aspires to be scientific. Acquaintance with history of scientific progress as a whole shows that it has always involved interaction between experiment and theory, between observation and idea. To study a major natural phenomenon, such as mental illness within the framework of science, but without being concerned with underlying theory is deeply paradoxical. The lessons coming from the humoral theory or from Freudian psychoanalytic theory should not be that one should scorn all engagement with theory. It should be that researchers should look with critical imagination for good theories, rather than judge the merits of theory by reference only to its worst examples. The discussion above about DSM-III/IV indicates that the attempt to eschew theoretical implications cannot be successful. Theoretical implications, are bound to creep into any classificatory system, whatever the intention behind the system. This being so, theoretical biases should, in this author’s opinion, be openly declared. Despite the atheoretical nature of psychiatry, some useful theoretical and philosophical reasoning is now possible. Some of this is of a general nature, which constrains the sort of classification or typology which can be offered in the field of mental illness. These general issues are discussed in the next section. However, they in turn have influence on the possibilities for further expansion of specific theoretical reasoning, which might permit the construction of true disease theories. Later sections of this chapter discuss the direction in which one should look for a true disease theory of schizophrenia. The detailed expansion of specific theoretical arguments referring to schizophrenia then dominate the rest of this book. 1.3. Models of illness: the medical model and alternatives. In science the word “model” is used in several different ways. Here it is used to refer to a general framework of ideas, or philosophy, within which more detailed and explicit theories may be developed. In the area of major mental illness, many such frameworks for thinking are possible. One cannot envisage formulation of true theories until one has specified the model to be used, that is, the general approach or philosophy to be adopted. In the medical (or biomedical) model of illness, theories 13 History and Philosophy of disease are based on abnormal processes defined at the biological level. For general medicine, the biomedical model has allowed the classification of diseases into a number of types. These include disorders classed as infectious, hereditary, degenerative, autoimmune, neoplastic, psychosomatic, developmental, traumatic and so on. Generally these classes of illness (except possibly psychosomatic disorders) occur as much in animals as in humans. Each of these classes has its own specific disease theories. In terms of earlier debates about mental illness they are primarily somatic rather than psychic theories. The biomedical model certainly applies to disorders of the nervous system, since there are many highly respectable disease theories and disease entities in neurology. However, as the preceding discussion of the history of concepts of mental illness shows, there has been and still is dispute about where major mental disorders, such as schizophrenia fit into the classification. There are some indications that one or other of the above types may apply to schizophrenia: Schizophrenia has a genetic component to it, although the pattern of inheritance is not simple, nor as strong as is sometimes claimed (Chapter 4). It is also common nowadays to regard schizophrenia as a “neurodevelopmental disorder”, a proposal discussed in Chapter 12. Some researchers have suggested that schizophrenia may be a disorder related to an infective agent (e.g. Torrey et al, 1988), an autoimmune disorder (Knight et al, 1987), or a degenerative disorder (Harrison, 1995). However, major mental disorders are confined mainly to humans, and this is specifically true for schizophrenia. This argues against fitting schizophrenia into the above classification of illnesses, which applies generally across species. The applicability of the biomedical model to schizophrenia has often been explicitly challenged. This is part of a wider questioning, in some circles, of the biological approach to psychiatry. Historically these challenges have come from a variety of directions, discussed by Siegler and Osmond (1966, 1974; see also Siegler et al, 1969). In the nineteenth century, the moral view of mental illness was influential, where correctional or educational methods were employed to encourage patients to “take responsibility” for their behavior (Siegler and Osmond, 1966). Early in the twentieth century, the psychoanalytic view was pioneered by Freud. It was suggested that psychiatric symptoms arise from repressed childhood emotional trauma, which needs to be brought to consciousness before the underlying problem could be resolved. Although Freud himself did not apply his method to schizophrenia his followers did so, with the result that, in one chapter of recent psychiatric history, insightoriented psychotherapy was a common treatment for schizophrenia. Bad parenting was held to be a dominant cause of schizophrenia (Bateson et al, 1956; Bateson, 1973). Another view of schizophrenia which challenges the biomedical model suggests that the mentally ill are victims of labeling, by a society which cannot tolerate deviance (Lemert, 1951; Becker,1973). Some have gone so far as to suggest that mental illness does not actually exist (Szasz, 1972). It has been suggested that mental illness in individuals is a reflection of intolerable tensions generated within a family (Laing and Esterson, 1964), or of “sickness” (in some 14 sense) within society as a whole (Siegler et al, 1969). These alternative models lack support from systematicallycollected evidence and comparison with control groups. They took no notice of the evidence, available at the time of publication, on genetics or effective pharmacotherapy, and they have not needed to take notice of brain mechanisms in understanding schizophrenia. Although the psychological and social ideas they are based on have some credibility and may be relevant to our larger-scale appreciation of mental illness, none of them give precise clues to the exact nature of symptoms and other features of schizophrenia, nor have they proved themselves in terms of the effectiveness of treatment offered on their basis. Empirical studies in an anthropological framework give no support to the “labeling” theory of major mental illness (Murphy, 1976). The World Health Organization transnational study of schizophrenia (World Health Organization, 1973), using an instrument for eliciting symptoms which was replicable across very different cultures, found that similar phenomenology occurred across very different cultures, and was thus unlikely to be simply a product of social factors within a particular culture. Nevertheless, there are some well established facts that are not easily compatible with the biomedical model applied to schizophrenia. The WHO transnational study of schizophrenia, revealed that people who met diagnostic criteria for schizophrenia in developing countries had better long-term outcomes than those in the developed “Western”style countries (Leff et al, 1992; Jablensky, 2000). Although this fact was established more than twenty years ago, little subsequent research has looked for the reason for this remarkable difference8. In addition, more recent work, especially that conducted in Britain and Holland, on the incidence of schizophrenia in some immigrant groups, suggests that there may be major contributory causes in the psychosocial realm (see Chapter 5). Using the “biomedical model”, psychiatric researchers have so-far failed to come up with detailed disease theories, comparable in rigor to those for other established disease theories (including neurological disorders). In the atheoretical vacuum favored in psychiatry, bitter controversy can still flourish, about these fundamental issues. The advent of neuroleptic drugs in the 1950s showed that drug treatment, as used in other well-defined classes of disease, can often be remarkably effective. This has been one of the strongest lines of support for a biomedical model of schizophrenia. Here again there is controversy however. The classical neuroleptic drugs have never been popular with patients, because of their frequently unpleasant side effects. As a result, in some quarters, the beneficial effects of these drugs were discounted, and these drugs have been branded as no more than “chemical straitjackets”. Advocates of such viewpoints have generally also jettisoned the biomedical model of mental illness. The appearance of a new generation of antipsychotic drugs, with fewer and less serious side effects is beginning to weaken this line of argument, and thus 8 A recent study (Patel et al, 2006) has raised questions about the WHO findings, and suggested that a systematic reexamination of the issue is needed. History and Philosophy to strengthen the biomedical model of schizophrenia. Genetic studies by Kety and co-workers (see Chapter 4) gave further support for a biomedical model. Using subjects who were adoptees and therefore brought up outside their biological family, they separated the genetic factors from psychosocial influence from a family where a parent had schizophrenia. Despite these lines of support for the biomedical model, its applicability to schizophrenia is not yet completely established. It cannot be so until a comprehensive disease theory for the schizophrenias has been constructed and becomes accepted. 1.4. Specific versions of the medical model applied to schizophrenia. At present, two specific versions of the biomedical model applied to schizophrenia have wide currency. The stress-vulnerability (or “stress-diathesis”) model accounts for the fact that psychosocial as well as biological factors are relevant to the manifestations of schizophrenia. An underlying constitutional weakness is supposed to exist in the brain, but its expression as illness (or as relapse when there is a previous history of illness) is influenced in a major way by psychosocial stresses from the patient’s environment. In general terms, this seems an accurate way to conceive schizophrenia, and distinguishes major mental illness from most neurological disorders of the brain, where social factors do not have such a decisive impact. However, the stressvulnerability model has not yet been developed in a way which gives a specific account of all features of schizophrenia, nor has it led to precise definition of the nature of either the underlying vulnerability in the brain, nor the characteristics of the stress which make the latent vulnerability manifest as illness. Thus, while in general it is likely to be correct as a “model”, it has not served as a basis for construction of a proper disease “theory”. Another version of the biomedical model applied to schizophrenia views this illness as a “neurodevelopmental” disorder. This is based mainly on two features of the illness: It has a tendency to be inherited at least in a substantial proportion of cases (Chapter 3); and, as revealed by CT or MRI scans, brain morphology deviates from normality, most of this deviation predating onset of illness, rather than being caused by it (Chapter 12). Much of what is known of this morphological deviance is about the relative size of different components of the forebrain in schizophrenia, compared to control groups. Any disorder with a hereditary tendency and associated with morphological deviance which predates the manifest illness can be regarded as a developmental disorder, although this is a far cry from a well-reasoned disease theory. Developmental biology of mammals has not yet unraveled the detailed relation between genetic factors and morphological variation in the adult. We have scarcely begun to understand the relation between the genetic factors predisposing to schizophrenia and deviations in brain morphology (see Jones and Murray, 1991). The abnormalities we know about - mainly in the size of brain components - are only indirectly related to aspects of brain cytology likely to be under direct genetic control. Moreover there is little understanding of how morphological factors relate to neurocybernetic functions whose disturbance leads to the symptoms of schizophrenia. Thus, we would appear to be a long way from constructing logical arguments relating symptoms of schizophrenia to the underlying neurodevelopmental abnormalities, let alone the basic genetic abnormality. As Jones and Murray (1991) have written: “genes code for proteins, not for auditory hallucinations in the third person”. Thus, the neurodevelopmental hypothesis, while no doubt true in general terms, holds little promise of delivering in the near future a closely reasoned argument relating causal factors (partly genetic) to symptoms and other key features of the illness. Given this rather unpromising scenario, is there any approach to this complex illness which might deliver arguments of sufficient precision to be called a theory? 1.5. Information sources for a theory of schizophrenia. In the Preface to this work, the question was posed: What is a disease theory? The answer given was (paraphrasing) “a series of arguments which give a comprehensive explanation of why the disease is how it is, rather than of some other nature”. To create a theory of disease, we need coordinated reasoning, providing an explanation of all of its important features, within an overall framework of causation. In this process, observed correlation between variables will undoubtedly be important. However, correlation may be very indirect, and is not the same as explanation or causation. For that one needs to show the logical links between phenomena as examples of more fundamental causal principles. The skill in using correlative data in construction of explanatory arguments and theories comes in selecting correlations where one suspects the variables to be relatively directly linked in causal terms. There is a degree of art or subjectivity in this process, whose success can only be judged when the explanatory argument is successfully assembled. The previous subsection suggests that we are currently some way from assembling an explanatory argument of schizophrenia based on developmental neurobiology or its genetic basis. However, three other areas of research have produced abundant and detailed evidence, likely to have closer logical and causal relations to functional disturbance in schizophrenia than developmental biology and its genetic basis. (i) The symptoms of schizophrenia (especially the psychotic ones), may seem strange, yet are striking and distinctive. Their singular nature suggests that they are specific pointers to the nature of an underlying disease process, if only we knew how to interpret them. They can admit few rigorous explanatory arguments. Although strange, we need not assume them to be totally alien. It would be better to assume that these symptoms arise by modifications and distortions of normal human psychological processes. If we could clarify the links between normal psychology and its disturbance in schizophrenia, we would open an important door on the nature of the illness. (ii) Laboratory studies of schizophrenia, have also revealed a great deal about abnormal psychology, behavior 15 History and Philosophy and psychophysiology, both in the psychotic phases of schizophrenia, and in intervening periods when less dramatic disablement is present. This evidence is based on a century of development and progressive refinement of methods of psychological investigation of normal integrated brain function. Because of the sophistication of experimental design used in these studies the information it has revealed about schizophrenia, taken in its entirety, is likely to be an accurate pointer to the underlying disturbances of information processing in schizophrenia, despite difficulty in interpretation. (iii) The results of the above investigations, applied to schizophrenia, are expressed using psychological concepts, which provide a concise summary (or “model”) of results within the discipline of psychology. As an early example of this, Eugen Bleuler was concerned with the underlying theory of schizophrenia, but this was formed entirely in terms of psychological concepts. He had no idea of its neurobiological basis. A truly explanatory argument, on the other hand, is one which crosses levels, by explaining findings at the psychological level in terms of underlying neurobiology. There is information now available on a wide range of neurobiological measures in schizophrenia. This constitutes the third large block of knowledge about schizophrenia, essential in theory construction. It includes a rich literature on structural deviations from the norm, found using CT or MRI scanning; a smaller, but intriguing literature using neuropathological investigations on postmortem brains; functional brain imaging, which reveals unusual patterns of cerebral activation; neurochemical imaging of an increasing variety of transmitters, receptors and other chemical markers; electrophysiology, including EEG power spectra, evoked and event-related potentials. These, and many other approaches, provide insight into abnormalities at the brain level in schizophrenia. Such knowledge about schizophrenia has arisen as part of the developing history of our understanding of normal psychology and normal brain function and structure, both in humans and in experimental animals. In the last generation, knowledge in these areas has increased enormously. Such analysis has probed at a deeper level for animal brains, than in the human brain, and more deeply into normal structure and normal neural or psychological function than in the abnormal situation of schizophrenia. The insights from the normal case, and in animals, are of vital importance in interpreting the evidence we have about schizophrenia. For the normal situation studied in experimental animals, a new discipline has emerged, in which true explanations of psychological and behavioral data in terms of underlying brain biology are created. This is the integrated science of brain and behavior. The challenge we face is to extend this approach to human cerebral processes and to the abnormal situation. The issues are not trivial. Of course the structure of the human brain follows the basic plan of all mammalian brains. The forebrain consists of the same structural components cerebral neocortex, striatum, thalamus, hippocampus etc with cell types in each structure being similar in humans and experimental mammal species. Because of the ethical limitations on human experimentation, knowledge about 16 patterns of axonal connectivity, and ultrastructure of the human brain is at a backward state compared with equivalent data in animals. Nevertheless, ideas about the interplay between the different components of the forebrain, put forward with reference to animal brains, are likely to apply, with some changes, to the human brain. Most obvious of the biological differences is the fact that the human brain is much larger than that of even the most advanced subhuman primates, with regions such as the prefrontal cortex showing special expansion compared to all other species. While biological knowledge of the human brain is not as good as that of the animal brain, psychological studies are, on the whole, more advanced than in any animal. For example, humans can be given more explicit instructions in psychological testing. Many psychological tests devised for humans are inapplicable to experimental animals. However, an increasing number of tests are being devised which have equivalent versions for humans and various subhuman species. The results of such work give support to the developments at the biological level inferring close parallels between the functioning of human and animal brains. Given this, it is also clear from psychological investigations that hemispheric specialization is an important principle in the human brain. Somewhat similar lateral specialization may exist in a variety of subhuman mammalian species, but has had less attention from experimentalists than that in humans. Lateral specialization may be more important in humans than in most subhuman species. The neurobiological basis of hemispheric specialization in humans has been largely a matter of conjecture and hypothesis, rather than established fact. However, drawing on morphological, physiological and large amounts of psychological evidence, an overall theory for the neurobiological basis of human cerebral lateralization was recently advanced (Miller, 1996a). This fits much evidence. More critical tests of it have been suggested, for which results are not yet available. Thus, despite constraints on biological investigations of the human brain, explanatory principles first put forward for animal brains are coming to be applied to the human brain. The integrated science of brain and behavior, where true explanatory arguments may be made, first developed with reference to animals, is beginning to have impact on the study of the human brain and human psychology. In developing a theory of schizophrenia, the task is therefore to use the increasingly coherent body of information and ideas from normal animals and normal humans, explaining psychological and behavioral data in neurobiological terms, to elucidate the relation between brain abnormalities and the symptoms and abnormal psychology in that illness. The challenge is to explain the abnormalities at the psychological and symptomatic level in terms of underlying neural activity. To this author, this is at present a more promising arena in which to construct explanatory arguments than that spanning from genetic factors, developmental abnormalities and the eventual manifestations of schizophrenia. History and Philosophy 1.6. illness. The neurodynamic concept of mental Given these directions for theory construction, this book focuses on a version of the medical model of disease which does not apply outside the brain, and has its special application almost entirely to the human brain: This is the “neurodynamic” model of illness. It has application to some neurological disorders but is viewed as having more general application to mental illnesses of various types. What are the characteristics of this class of illness? Conceptually this class of illness is defined by a disturbance of the dynamic fluctuation of activity in the brain, rather than a deficit due to gross structural damage or cellular loss. In simplest form these dynamic fluctuations can give rise to symptoms which change rapidly, even on a second-by-second basis, in contrast to structural damage which tends to cause stable deficits in function. In analogy, one may liken such dynamic disturbance to disturbed weather patterns in the atmosphere, in contrast to the solid terrain on which rain falls. These two sorts of disturbance in the brain are not, of course, entirely separable. Structural damage to the brain sometimes causes rapidly fluctuating symptoms (e.g. abnormal movements in Huntington’s chorea). Moreover, a disturbance which arises essentially from the fluctuating dynamics of nervous activity, if often repeated, might lead to brain cell loss, a structural rather than a dynamic abnormality, as in some types of epilepsy. Nevertheless, in a broad sense, this distinction is useful. For illnesses which arise from disturbed brain dynamics, one expects little evidence for actual structural abnormality, such as cell loss produced by identified pathological processes, or tissue damage. This statement is readily accepted for most mental illnesses. It is debatable whether it applies to schizophrenia (an issue discussed in detail in Chapter 12). For the time being it is noted that solid evidence of pathological processes at the level of nervous tissue must at present come from study of post-mortem brains, rather than from morphological brain scanning. This is necessarily conducted when patients die at an advanced age, rather than at the age at which schizophrenia has its onset and most dramatic manifestations. Moreover, study of post-mortem brain is exceedingly slow work. While there are a number of intriguing post-mortem findings in the literature, they are remarkable more for their diversity than for their uniformity. There are relatively few attempts at replication, and even fewer successful replications. The findings that have been made are thus a rather heterogeneous collection, including evidence of abnormal cellular architecture, and deficits in cell numbers in some cases. In such work it is seldom clear at what stage of life these abnormalities first appear. There is no evidence that either a reduction in cell numbers, or changes in cellular architecture are present when the illness is first manifest, in late adolescence or early adulthood. On the other hand, morphological evidence acquired by brain scanning does provide evidence of structural deviance of the brain in schizophrenia, and this is detectable right at the start of the illness, as soon as patients are identified. Generally such evidence concerns the size of the brain and its subdivisions, relative to control groups. Change in brain size does not necessarily imply abnormality of brain tissue as a pathologist would detect it. Differences in the size of the brain is also seen in comparisons between male and female. In quantitative terms, these are much greater than those between normal and schizophrenia. For this reason the word “deviance” (in a statistical sense) rather than “abnormality” is preferred. The changes in size of brain components seen in schizophrenia, could, in themselves, be no more pathological than in these normal variants. However, the existence of deviation from normal in volume of brain components turns out to be an indication of much more important differences from normal. This book develops a theory of the cellular basis for these volume differences. In a strict sense, these cellular changes do not represent pathology as a neuropathologist would understand the term. However, the book also shows how they are reflected in abnormal dynamics of brain function, which are themselves more directly related to the manifestations of illness. The most striking symptoms of schizophrenia have a number of characteristics in common which can more plausibly be attributed to dynamic disturbance of the brain, than to structural damage: These symptoms are mainly internal experiences rather than objective signs. Positive symptoms (delusions, hallucinations and passivity experiences) are more distinctive and pathognomonic of this illness than are negative ones (signs of functional loss)(Klosterkötter et al, 1995). Such symptoms are often highly structured, even creative, and are subjectively meaningful to patients, perhaps abnormally so. All these things imply a degree of integrity of brain mechanisms, although those mechanisms are used in an abnormal manner. The meaning associated with symptoms is distinctively human, as are the illnesses themselves as a whole. This implies some degree of integrity of distinctively human cognitive processes, specifically those underlying linguistic, semantic and conceptual processing of information. There is another specific implication of these highly structured internal experiences which convey such powerful meaning to the subject (spurious as it may be): In a general theoretical account of mammalian forebrain function, Hebb’s concept of cell assemblies is of central importance (Hebb, 1949). Cell assemblies are considered to be distributed nets of nerve cells selected from a much larger number of cells in the cortex and other parts of the forebrain. When activated they, rather than single cells, are considered to be the vehicle for representing meaning. Since the most distinctive symptoms of schizophrenia are often highly meaningful, it must be envisaged that the distributed cell assembly configurations of the normal brain are still in operation, though the dynamics of their operation is far from normal. In this respect, major mental illness, such as schizophrenia, may be separated from epilepsy, where often there is an identifiable discrete focus of activity - something very different from a cell assembly - and, apart from an initial aura, a seizure is characterized by lapses of consciousness, rather than creation of spuriously meaningful mental images on a background of a fully alert (even hyperalert) state of consciousness. The negative symptoms of schizophrenia are more difficult to deal with from a theoretical point of view. This is mainly because it is difficult to separate a variety of quite 17 History and Philosophy separate origins for these symptoms (see review in Carpenter et al, 1988). Some of the negative symptoms may arise directly from the disturbed brain dynamics as on-going traits, and be capable of rigorous explanation in these terms. Other origins to such symptoms may be self-protection from overstimulation, a concomitant of psychosis, a reflection of postpsychotic depression, depression as a reaction to adverse social events as patients attempt to make their way in the world, or to excessive doses of medication (etc). With such complexity, the negative symptoms in themselves are not a secure guide to start theory construction. However, there is also a large experimental literature on experimental findings associated with the negative symptoms and related psychological deficits. Thus, although the negative symptoms in themselves are difficult to deal with in a theoretical sense, the general area of the enduring traits, present before as well as after any psychotic episodes, is one where good theoretical arguments relating disturbed brain dynamics to symptoms and abnormalities in experimental psychology can be sought. One may expect these traits to be mainly functional impairments. An important finding however, is that some of them can be seen as performance which is sometimes superior to normal (see Chapters 6-10). In previous generations, the concept of “psychodynamics” was much employed in relation to mental illness, but without any clear relation to brain function. In the present formulation of the concept of schizophrenia as a neurodynamic illness, the “dynamics of the mind” is also of considerable interest, with respect to both positive and negative symptoms. However, this is totally different from the older “psychodynamics”: The development of the concept of neurodynamic illness will, it is hoped, permit the emergence of a new psychodynamics closely related to observable or inferable dynamic fluctuations in the brain. Assuming that the underlying cause of schizophrenia is disturbed brain dynamics, one would not expect to find localizing signs, as commonly found in neurological disorders. Minor, and un-localized nervous system abnormality may be present, before an illness becomes manifest, indicative of some sort of functional imbalance in the brain. The departures from normal expected in a neurodynamic illness would occur in global measures of brain function such as electrographic recording (including various methods of analysis of EEG, AEP and ERP), and brain activation as assessed by functional brain imaging or transmitter turnover. Apart from these features of neurodynamic illness, psychosocial influences are expected to play a larger part than in neurological disorders of the brain, relating not only to outcome of an established illness, but possibly also to its initiation. The topic is discussed in detail in Chapter 4 (and again in Chapter 13). As a whole, the influence of psychosocial environment on neurodynamic disorders is what one would expect from the “stress/diathesis” model, the broader framework within which the neurodynamic category of illness is cast. 18 1.7. Implications of the “neurodynamic” concept for taxonomy of schizophrenia and related disorders. Dynamic neurology, advocated in the previous section, as a model for schizophrenia, must be based on the interplay of a host of factors which may be balanced (or be in imbalance) in a variety of ways. If one does not assume an origin to such illnesses as discrete “essences”, these interacting factors are likely to be mainly quantitative divergences from normal rather than qualitative ones. Thus, on theoretical grounds, the neurodynamic model of mental illness does not suggest categorical classification, unless there is a clear indication that the dimensional interactions lead to a sharp bifurcation between the characteristics of different disease or between them and normality. As discussed above, all systems of psychiatric typology so far devised have been categorical, not dimensional. However, empirical studies of the psychometric aspects of mental illness, and specifically the functional psychoses, do indeed suggest that dimensional typology is a better way of representing them than categorical ways. Claridge (1972) stressed that clinically and genetically there are no sharp dividing lines amongst the functional psychoses which might be used to define schizophrenia. He suggested that schizophrenia might be conceived as the extreme of a personality variable, for which there is complete continuity (over a population of people) between normal health and severe pathology. Specifically he compared the personality background from which schizophrenia emerges as similar to the “creativity” dimension of personality. He also noted a number of unusual correlations in schizophrenia, between different psychophysiological measures. He took these to indicate that abnormal organization of mechanisms for arousal and attention are the neurobiological basis of the relevant personality variant. Fifteen years later Claridge (1987) revisited this issue, reviewing more recent evidence that schizophrenia as an illness can be related to dimensions of personality as studied in normal populations. A variety of personality scales have been used showing that the ways in which people with schizophrenia differ from normal also identify a proportion of people in the healthy population without definite mental illness. There appears to be no single coherent personality dimension for representing such similarity: Different dimensions are tapped by the different scales, and these do not correlate with one another. Claridge also reviews more recent data trying to specify the biological substrate of personality dimensions related to schizophrenia. This includes psychophysiological and neuropsychological studies, as well as studies of hemispheric laterality. The suggestion that personality variants have a basis in styles of information processing related to physiological function of the brain goes back as far a Pavlov (1941). However, Claridge admits that “a unifying theme has yet to emerge” for the attempts to give a biological underpinning to the personality dimension aspects of schizophrenia. Another type of empirical evidence from which a dimensional representation of schizophrenia and related disorders may be inferred is from the statistics of clustering of symptoms. It was part of the Kraepelinian dichotomy that History and Philosophy the symptoms of manic-depressive illness should be separable from those of dementia praecox, and it has been argued that such a bimodal distribution of symptoms, with a rarity of mixed forms, would indicate a genuine split between two disease entities. However, surveying modern research Kendell and Brockington (1980) write: “No-one has ever succeeded in obtaining unambiguously bimodal distribution which has been replicable on a second series of patients. Either an obstinately unimodal distribution has been found, or a bimodal distribution has been claimed but not been reproduced by other workers, or the shape of the curve has been ambiguous and not clearly either uni- or bimodal.” They cite two studies referring specifically to the distinction between manic-depressive illness and schizophrenia, as supporting detail for this statement: Kendell and Gourlay (1970) using discriminant function analysis of a 38-item description of groups of newly-admitted patients diagnosed as schizophrenic and manic-depressive, failed to show a true bimodal distribution of symptoms between schizophrenia and manic-depressive illness. In a later study, Brockington et al (1979) applied a discriminant function analysis to information on psychotic patients which included history, present symptoms and follow-up data. While a function was derived from a first group of patients (mainly based on follow-up symptoms) which gave a bimodal distribution, it did not carry over to another group. The authors conclude that these patients did not fall naturally into two groups. Grayson (1987) indeed argues on statistical grounds that even if such bimodality of symptom distribution was demonstrated it need not indicate a binary split between disease entities. Cloninger et al (1985) performed an analysis of symptoms in 1739 persons from a psychiatric out-patient clinic, 56 of whom had the “definite” diagnosis, and 33 the “probable” diagnosis of schizophrenia. They found that a cluster of four symptoms (persecutory delusions, delusions of control, auditory hallucinations and mood-incongruent delusions) tended to occur as a stable syndrome throughout a 6-12 year follow-up period. Scores for 2 or more on this cluster (3 or more if there were also spending sprees during a period of elation) were highly discriminating for a diagnosis of schizophrenia. Notably, the distribution of scores for this cluster was bimodal, across the whole sample, and the authors considered this the first demonstration of schizophrenia as categorically separate from other psychiatric patients. However, their claim was that schizophrenia has “natural boundaries” distinguishing it from “other psychiatric patients”. They did not demonstrate a categorical separation from “affective psychosis”, or other disorders in the schizophrenia spectrum, a task which is inherently more difficult. Another way of assessing whether dimensional or categorical representations of functional psychoses are preferable, deriving from Kraepelin’s outcome criterion of classification, is to determine whether the split in terms of symptoms gives categorically different predictions of outcome. If there really is a separation of disease entities between manic-depressive illness and schizophrenia, there should be a non-linear relation between symptom profile and outcome with an area of the symptom dimension for which outcome changes more abruptly as the symptom profiles changes than within the symptom profiles of the presumed more “typical” examples of the two main entities. However, in terms of correlation between symptoms and outcome in patient groups with schizophrenia and manic-depressive illness, Kendell and Brockington (1980) found no evidence of such discontinuity. Van Os et al (1996c) compared the use, for prediction of outcome, of categorical representations of functional psychoses as found in DSM-III-R or ICD-10, with their own dimensional representation, obtained by factor analysis. The dimensional data gave far better correlations with most outcome measures than the DSM-IIIR or ICD-10 categories. As stated in the introduction to DSM-IV, it is at present quite uncertain what should be the dimensions along which mental illness in general, and schizophrenia in particular are best described. The best way of characterizing personality dimensions would be for each dimension to correspond to an explicit biological variable. The start of modern personality typology, in the work of Pavlov on dogs (Pavlov, 1941), was indeed supposed to be based on variations in brain biology, that is the balance between (and stability of) processes of excitation and inhibition. Pavlov refers several times to schizophrenia in this context. However, his suggestions were not very detailed. The personality inventories of Eysenck, which led to the sort of typology advocated by Claridge also had little explicit biological underpinning, and Claridge’s own work, though including psychophysiological measures, does not tie the personality variable down to fundamental biology of the brain. From what we know of the dynamics of the brain, there is a very large number of biological factors whose quantitative value in an individual brain might be reflected in personality. These include a wide variety of structural characteristics (e.g. the richness of cortico-cortical connections - which might determine associations - and their conduction delays), the activity of various neuromodulators or neurotransmitters (e.g. any of the monoamines or neuropeptides), the average amplification factor for synaptic transmission in a wide variety of pathways in the brain, and the balance between major entities in the forebrain (cortex and hippocampus, cortex and striatum, thalamus and cortex, left and right hemispheres). Thus, even though we have reason for believing that dimensional typology of mental abnormalities is in general better than categorical classification, there is at present a degree of subjectivity in the choice of definitions of personality variables. This will continue to be the case, until we can establish a logical relation between key biological variables controlling brain dynamics and the personality or psychopathological characteristics which emerge as a result. Only then can the notion of dimensional typology be expressed in such a way as to give an objective typing of mental illness, one that can command a consensus over time, and between countries and cultures. Again we realize the need for the complex and coordinated reasoning within a psychobiological theory of mental illness. 1.8. Summary. This chapter has reached the conclusion that the illnesses included under the term “schizophrenia”, and those 19 History and Philosophy related to them, are best conceptualized in terms of a continuously-variable dimension, or a combination of several dimensions. In such a framework, these illnesses are likely to occupy relatively uncommon extreme positions on the relevant dimensions, with the range of normality being somewhere distant or even at the other end of the relevant dimensions. The idea of these illnesses being categorically different from normality, though embodied in almost all diagnostic schemes, is not supported by a range of empirical evidence, and also is unlikely from inferences which can be made from various features of these illnesses, about the underlying disturbance of the brain. Given this, the best model of these illnesses, within which a disease theory might be constructed, is the biomedical model, rather than any alternative which does not include details of brain biology. Slightly more specific than this, schizophrenia can plausibly be viewed in terms of the stress/vulnerability model, where expression of the illness requires both constitutional abnormalities in the brain, and stress factors. The latter might be either of physical (biological) nature or psychosocial stressors. The constitutional abnormalities in the brain can themselves be regarded as in some sense developmental in origin. However, neither the stress/vulnerability model nor the neurodevelopmental concept are at present likely to be very useful in constructing a closely-reasoned disease theory. Therefore within these broad models, it is probably necessary to adopt a version of the biomedical model different from any of those used for constructing all classical disease theories, which apply to other species and to diseases other than those included in psychiatry. Various features of schizophrenia and related illnesses suggest that these versions of the biomedical model can be designated as disturbances of “neurodynamics”. This is a new version of the biomedical model, and although it may have application to some neurological disorders, its real province is within the disorders studied in psychiatry. Even given a dimensional concept and this more specific neurodynamic framework for studying schizophrenia, a succinct definition of the illness escapes us at the start of this work. The dimensions along which schizophrenia is to be plotted are uncertain, and therefore so is the definition of schizophrenia. In this context it is appropriate to quote from a recent lecture by N.McI.James (1992), commenting on the recent trend, embodied in DSM-III and similar schemes, towards operationalized diagnosis. He writes: “Despite more than fifteen years of usage of this relatively refined and confined picture of schizophrenia, we have not, I believe, come very close to the etiology or pathogenesis of the illness. What then has gone wrong with this line of research that is so fundamental to the very basis of all other approaches? For if we cannot define what it is that we are studying, how can we ever begin to do so? It is a melancholy fact therefore that the very definition of what we are attempting to research is still so unsatisfactory. Have we barked up the wrong tree, gone out on a limb, or is the trunk itself rotten?” 20 With respect, this author suggests that the problem is not any of these three. The problem is a misconception of the relation between definition and explanation. A simpleminded view suggests that the former must always precede the latter. So it is when a disease entity is defined by a one sharply-abnormal feature, or a small number of such features, which covary very well. In these cases, the definition is clear at the start, and the problem of explanation can then proceed from that definition. But consider another example, the illness of syphilis and its many sequelae. This is quite an apt model, since its elucidation was a major medical advance at the time Kraepelin formulated his influential concept of dementia praecox. In this case manifestations of the illness were many, varied and endlessly complex. In this case, the definition of the illness as one, rather than a variety of quite separate entities was not achieved until the causal agent, the spirochete, had been discovered. Here explanation came before definition. Another example, from outside medicine, is perhaps even more germane. Two hundred years ago, studies by alchemists focused around a complex and debatable concept called “phlogiston”. This was somehow related to many chemical reactions, to fire, to the commonplace notion of “hotness” which at that time did not have a proper scientific definition, and, in medicine, to fever. Nowadays the concept of phlogiston is long abandoned. In its place are truly scientific concepts, heat energy, temperature (properly defined), and the energy changes occurring when atoms and molecules take part in chemical combinations. These concepts, unlike “phlogiston”, were integrated and closely linked with the preceding corpus of scientific knowledge and ideas. In particular these newer concepts were derived from the concept of energy as it had been defined in earlier years of scientific history, when the focus had been on mechanics rather than chemistry. Our current concept of schizophrenia is in some ways similar to that of phlogiston two hundred years ago. It is not complete nonsense. Likewise, phlogiston represented a groping towards an adequate concept which most scientists at the time knew was there to be formulated, if only they were clever enough. Schizophrenia also is generally accepted as a very real concept underlying urgent medico-social problems, even though we cannot quite grasp that concept in adequately precise terms. However our concept of schizophrenia, like phlogiston in the eighteenth century, while not nonsense, cannot at present be characterized as totally coherent sense. In particular it has been defined mainly with a language that is not integrated with the current corpus of scientific knowledge and ideas. It is defined only within its own domain. There are thus inevitable circularities, and endless debate about what schizophrenia “really” is. The situation is only resolvable when we find the underlying causes of schizophrenia. The criterion for a scientificallyvalid definition is that it will support comprehensive and rigorous explanatory arguments. As argued above this is likely to be by the definition of appropriate dimensions for analysis, rather than of sharply distinct categories. Those dimensions need to be rooted in the wider corpus of contemporary scientific knowledge, and especially in brain History and Philosophy biology. The present definitions of schizophrenia are likely to remain relevant, but we will know their real importance only when we can define the illness in a language common to other domains of science, permitting rigorous explanations. In other words, as with the demystification of “phlogiston”, or the unraveling of the concept of syphilis, definition will follow rather than precede explanation. To spell out the problem in this way is not intended to make it more difficult. It is intended to make clear that the issues are far more fundamental than in routine science. We have not only to unravel the cause of schizophrenia, but as part of that process, we have to discover the best conceptual language for formulating its cause. The two processes must proceed together, success in one establishing and validating the other. This is not pseudoscience, as the analogy with alchemy might suggest: It is really fundamental science, more difficult perhaps, but also far more challenging than the routine application and extension of an established language within a well-developed area of scientific enquiry. 1.9. Provisional definition of “schizophrenia and related disorders”. We may accept the conclusion of section 1.8. that, for complex illnesses such as schizophrenia “definition follows rather than precedes explanation”. Nevertheless, we must have a provisional, rather loose definition of the subject matter of concern to us before we tread the road towards explanation. The provisional definition adopted here for schizophrenia is as follows: Our primary concern is to explain those illnesses which have three characteristics: (i) They exhibit characteristic periods of severe mental turmoil, which we refer to as “psychosis”. In broad terms psychosis involves a break with a patient’s grasp of reality, as generally understood, and can be resolved to greater or less extent with appropriate medication. Psychosis is discussed in detail in a later chapter. (ii) They also have longer standing symptoms, mainly impairments, of a less distinctive kind, which are associated with psychological and social impairment seen before and after these psychotic episodes, and which also tend to occur in relatives of those who are prone to the episodes of psychosis mentioned above. (iii) Illnesses included in this provisional definition are usually long-lasting, with onset in late adolescence or early adulthood. For this broad area of illness we could systematically use the phrase “schizophrenia, and related disorders”. This usage would then not be applied for more specific subdivisions within the broad category designated by this phrase. However, it would be cumbersome and pedantic to add “and related disorders” whenever this meaning is intended. Since the distinction between the two usages is generally implied by the context, the word “schizophrenia” is used mainly, in what follows, and more specific diagnoses other than schizophrenia are specified only when necessary. It needs also to be emphasized that both the symptoms of psychosis and the longer-standing but less distinctive abnormalities which are the twin elements of this provisional definition, are themselves complex, each requiring a great deal of analysis. It is emphasized at the outset that it is not assumed a priori that schizophrenia is a totally different category of illness from affective illness. Nevertheless the widespread feeling amongst psychiatrists that they are distinct is respected, if not adopted unequivocally 21 Synopsis of the Theory Chapter 2. Synopsis of the Theory 2.1. illness. Life-time trajectory of schizophrenic A complicating factor in any attempt to understand schizophrenia is that the disorder has different manifestations at different stages of a person’s life. The most dramatic and severe expression of the disorder, seen as episodes of active psychosis is evident in late adolescence or early adulthood. The assumption that psychosis at this stage of life is the “age of onset”, was the fact which led Kraepelin to call the disorder “dementia praecox”. The same assumption is made, as the third of the criteria (end of Chapter 1) used for “provisional definition” of the disorder dealt with here. Only rarely does this apparent onset occur in early adolescence, and the existence of “childhood schizophrenia” is an unresolved controversy (see Footnote, Sect 13.7.). However, by no means does this exclude that there be impairments earlier in life than this designated time of “onset”. A number of studies have documented lesser degrees of impairment during childhood and early adolescence. Clinically these impairments include poor social competence and emotional adjustment, poor motor coordination and poor development of visual abilities (Roff et al, 1976; Done et al, 1994; Crow et al, 1995). Children who later develop schizophrenia present to child guidance clinics more commonly than normal (Roff et al, 1976). From study of home movies, an excess occurrence of neuromotor abnormalities in those who later develop schizophrenia, is detectable as early as 2 years of age (Walker et al, 1994). More detail on these early impairments, as documented in specific psychological tests, is discussed in some of the later sections, dealing with children at elevated genetic risk, but before the usual age of greatest risk of onset (e.g. Sects 7.3.3, 9.2.2.3., 9.2.4.3., 9.3.5.2., 10.2.2.2., 10.3.7.2.). Later in adolescence, in the lead-up to the first psychotic episode, a distinct “prodromal syndrome” has been described, associated with overall fall-off in school performance, which has been correlated with increasing impairment in specific cognitive tests (Niendam et al, 2006), fluctuating mood, negative symptoms and attenuated positive ones (Yung and McGorry, 1996; Cornblatt et al, 2003). This period is of great importance for early intervention programs. In the present work it features in the discussion in Chapter 12 (Sect. 12.7.3.), in relation to change in brain morphology. The symptoms and mechanisms of the psychotic episodes themselves are discussed in detail in Chapter 5. Of particular importance for the present work is the time-course, and process of recovery from psychosis. Later on in the course of an established schizophrenic illness a variety of trajectories have been described (Ciompi, 1980). The particular emphasis for the present work is that non-psychotic traits may often be seen without the confounds of concomitant psychosis, 17 especially if recovery from psychosis is relatively good. For long-established illness, a group of patients on whom research efforts have been specially focused are those with severe and lasting impairments, corresponding to what is sometimes called the “defect” state or “Kraepelinian” schizophrenia (mentioned in Sects. 4.1, 8.7.1., 9.6.2., 12.1., 12.5.4.2, 12.7.4.0., 12.11.3.) These patients have tended to become long-stay institutionalized in-patients, and many of them spend their last years in institutional care. In neuropathological studies, the brains of these patients are likely to be overrepresented. The substantial proportion of cases who recover completely (or nearly so), or who show only mild impairment, with or without the need for continuing medication, are often seldom seen in psychiatric practice, and are not well researched. The emphasis of the present work is to develop a theory of the fundamental causes of schizophrenia. The focus is then on psychosis, and (especially) on the enduring traits seen in the more typical cases, before during and after resolution of psychosis. In patients with illness of long standing, especially if the impairment is severe, factors in addition to these fundamental causes are likely to complicate the profile of functional impairments. These factors include prolonged under-activity of the nervous system, associated with profound, long-lasting negative symptoms, under-stimulation, and other effects of institutionalization, as well as the effects of prolonged high-dose medication, or (for patients hospitalized before the neuroleptic era), the effects of insulin coma therapy, as well as ECT. 2.2. Contributions of inheritance schizophrenia and related disorders. to If we sidestep the complications arising from the many stages of illness and concentrate on schizophrenia as a whole, one of the immediate issues to consider is its genetics. Studies of inheritance of schizophrenia leave no room for doubt that genetic influences play an important role in its causation. The evidence includes studies in first, second and third degree relatives of probands with schizophrenia, twin studies and adoption studies (3.2.). Adoption studies indicate that genetic factors have an influence which prevails over family environmental ones. However, strong evidence for inheritance is not the same as evidence for strong inheritance: The genetic influence is important, but by no means overwhelming. There is plenty of room for environmental or other non-genetic factors. The pattern of inheritance is not of a simple unifactorial Mendelian nature, nor does it suggest that different genetic factors are widely involved in different pedigrees (genetic heterogeneity), although rarer conditions similar to schizophrenia may be genetically distinct. The evidence fits better a polygenic manner of inheritance (3.3.). The fact that the heritability of schizophrenia is a graded function of illness severity (measured in several ways) in a Synopsis of the Theory proband (3.3.4.) also suggests polyfactorial inheritance. Since schizophrenia is associated with a substantial fertility disadvantage (3.3.5.), it is unlikely that there is any one (or few) genes of dominating importance. If there were, they would be selected out, and schizophrenia would not be the common disease that it is. Several arguments based on classical evidence converge to suggest that multiple genetic factors are involved, probably involving the collaboration of many common genes, all with small effects, none of which is, by itself, pathological. Studies of cross-prevalence (the prevalence of one disorder in first degree relatives (FDR) of probands with another disorder) show a complex variety of interrelations (3.4.1. and 3.4.2.): The classical subtypes of schizophrenia are not genetically distinct, and “simple schizophrenia” (Bleuler’s addition to the Kraepelinian subtypes) is genetically linked to the other subtypes (3.4.1.). The major conventionally-defined entities in the broader spectrum of disorders do not “breed true” (3.4.2.), but a few less-common phenotypic variants do so. Schizophrenia has a puzzling asymmetric genetic relation with affective disorder, especially with major depression (3.4.2.3.). In other words, schizophrenia in probands does not increase the prevalence of affective disorder in FDR, but presence of affective disorder in probands does increase the prevalence of schizophrenia in FDR. This is probably explained by the fact that major depression is heterogeneous, schizophrenia sharing genetic factors with psychotic depression, and to a much lesser degree with non-psychotic depression (3.4.2.4.). Bipolar disorder appears to be closely related to unipolar affective disorder, but the genetic relation between the two is again asymmetric (3.4.2.4.). In other words, FDR of bipolar subjects have an elevated risk of unipolar depression, but FDR of unipolar subjects have only a slightly elevated risk of bipolar disorder. This may be because bipolar disorder has genetic factors in addition to those needed for the appearance of unipolar disorder. Bipolar disorder has the best claim of those considered here to be genetically distinct, but nevertheless has some genetic kinship with schizophrenia, which requires to be clarified (3.4.2.3., 3.4.2.4.). Schizoaffective disorder is a hybrid, with greater genetic relation to either schizophrenia or affective disorders (both unipolar and bipolar) than to itself in FDR (3.4.2.3., 3.4.2.4.). Brief periods of schizophrenia-like illness (schizophreniform disorder or “reactive psychosis”) do not carry the same risk to relatives as schizophrenia fulfilling the “six-month criterion” of DSM-III, though they may predispose to affective illness, and perhaps to similar shortlived illness in FDR (3.4.2.5.). Post-partum psychosis probably falls in the same category. Various personality variants (“schizotypal personality” defined in several ways, and “paranoid personality”) have a genetic kinship with schizophrenia (3.4.2.6.). Opinion is divided on whether lateonset schizophrenia-like illness (“late paraphrenia”) is genetically part of the schizophrenia spectrum (3.4.2.7.). Overall, the inheritance evidence better fits a dimensional than a categorical conceptualization of most of these disease entities, according to any definitions in current use: Many genetic factors confer graded vulnerability to the illness. However, in the broad schizophrenia/affective disorder spectrum, more than one dimension is needed to capture the genetic relations (3.4.2.8.). It is likely that more than one underlying disease process, as well as different thresholds are required to meet diagnostic criteria for the different conditions. The different disease processes cannot be distinguished categorically on the basis of symptoms alone. In the last twenty years attention has been drawn to a variety of possible anomalies in inheritance of schizophrenia, not predicted by classical genetic models. Attempts have been made to relate these to recently-discovered information about behavior of chromosomes. They include: stronger genetic transmission of schizophrenia from female than male probands (3.5.1.) possibly indicating sex-linkage; increasing severity or decreasing age of onset of schizophrenia-spectrum disorders over generations in a multi-affected pedigree (3.5.2.) possibly indicating accumulation of dynamic mutations in the form of trinucleotide repeats; an excess of same-sex concordance in schizophrenia (3.5.3), perhaps implying a pseudoautosomal factor predisposing to schizophrenia; and an excess of schizophrenia in people of consanguineous parentage (3.5.4.) which would suggest recessive Mendelian factors. Many biases confound the collection of reliable statistics to establish these anomalous patterns of inheritance. They have not withstood close scrutiny. Molecular genetic studies of schizophrenia have been pursued with great energy especially in the last ten years (Sect. 3.6.), but have not yet fulfilled their promise. It is possible that, by combining methods of genetic analysis with those of gene expression in specific tissues (notably brain), specific genetic factors can be identified. However, it is clear from work carried out to date that no genetic factor of major effect (conferring an “odds ratio” for the disorder >2.5) is present in most cases (though such factors may be present in particular pedigrees). Identifying multiple genetic factors each of rather weak effect is very expensive, and may still elude the best efforts of molecular geneticists. Identification of specific genes would be aided if there was more deliberate work on theory construction. In this context the finding that genes related to myelin formation and oligodendrocyte function are abnormally expressed in brain tissue obtained post-mortem from persons with schizophrenia. This finding may be important, since it corresponds well with the central premise of the theory to be developed in later chapters of the present work. 2.3. Synopsis of contributory environmental causes for schizophrenia and related disorders. Various aspects of life and environment have been shown to correlate with the occurrence of schizophrenia, and have been taken as indicators of contributory causes of the condition, which are environmental in nature. Both biological and psychosocial factors are implicated. However, interpretation of the evidence is not straightforward, there being uncertainties sometimes on whether the observed correlations do indeed indicate causal effects, and if so, whether they arise from genetic or environmental causes, and sometimes whether an environmental cause is in the biological or the psychosocial realm. 18 Synopsis of the Theory 2.3.1. Contributory causes from the biological environment. It has often been observed that there is an excess of roughly 8-10% in incidence of schizophrenia in people born in winter months, especially where there are seasonal variations in climate (4.1.). It has been proposed that some seasonal environmental factor (such as common infections) acting during pregnancy increases the risk for the disorder. However, predictions from this proposal, that familiality should be less in winter-born cases, or that winter-born cases have distinctive features not shared by cases born at other times of the year are not consistently supported by available evidence. An alternative possibility is plausible, and is supported by some evidence, namely that seasonal patterns of conception differ between those who, for genetic reasons are likely to have offspring with schizophrenia, compared to the rest of the population. Direct evidence has been sought that prenatal infections, especially influenza, predispose offspring to schizophrenia later in their life (4.2.). Any such effect is, at most, quite a small one, demonstrable to a significant degree only in studies of large populations, and accounting for no more than 1-2% of all cases of the disorder. The smallness of the effect means that prenatal infections can contribute to the season of birth effect only in a small way, if at all. Nevertheless, there is some consistency in the evidence, in that the middle third of pregnancy is usually identified as the period of risk for prenatal infections. This period of vulnerability is also identified by studies of prenatal famine, and of some minor physical anomalies which occur with increased frequency in schizophrenia, and have their origin in this period of fetal development (4.3.). These developmental anomalies need not represent definite deviations in genetic programming, nor environmental causes: They might reflect quasi-random instabilities in the developmental program. Nevertheless, in Sect. 12.3.3., evidence on cellular development is mentioned suggesting reasons why the mid-trimester may be critical in the developmental processes which lead to schizophrenia in young adults. There is a clear statistical association between obstetric complications (OC) and later development of schizophrenia. This does not necessarily reflect a causative role for OC. Nevertheless, in several studies the evidence has withstood attempts to explain away the statistical association in terms other than those of a direct (contributory) cause. OC as a whole are elevated for schizophrenia births even when siblings are the controls, so the association is not simply a reflection of a general tendency to OC in the mothers of schizophrenia patients. There are also a few studies demonstrating an excess of OC in schizophrenia births when unaffected co-twins are controls, so the association is probably not due entirely to aspects of maternal lifestyle at the time of that pregnancy (which would affect both co-twins). When a schizophrenia birth is accompanied by OC the illness tends to be one of the more severe forms of schizophrenia, or there is an increased incidence of schizophrenia compared to other less severe diagnoses. In such cases, schizophrenia tends to occur with earlier age of onset, less responsiveness to antipsychotic medication, and possibly with more abnormality of brain morphology. Familiality does not differ reliably 19 between patients with and without OCs, but familiality is a poor guide to genetic loading (see introduction to Chapter 4). Complications both before birth, and during delivery and the immediate post-natal period have been found to increase the risk of schizophrenia. Specific OCs which have been linked to later emergence of the disorder include aspects of maternal lifestyle, reduced birth weight and/or prematurity, and asphyxia/hypoxia (both during pregnancy and during the perinatal period). Some studies have shown that the excess of perinatal asphyxia/hypoxia in schizophrenia births applies even when unaffected siblings or twins are used as controls, although this does not exclude the possibility that at least some of the excess is due to lifestyle variables, applying to the particular pregnancy. Several studies show that perinatal asphyxia is associated with more severe types of schizophrenia, or cases with early onset. The association with early onset illness remains significant even after co-variation for several other possibly-confounding factors. This suggests that perinatal asphyxia is a contributory cause, not just a correlation arising less directly. However, in the total picture the contribution of direct causal influences to the observed correlation between schizophrenia and OC has not been resolved. Relative risk of schizophrenia for those with OCs as a whole vs those without, has been estimated as ~2, and for some specific OCs the relative risk can be much higher (7 for diabetes during pregnancy; 4.5 for total fetal/perinatal hypoxia scores). However, in translating such values to give the fraction of cases in the population attributable to OCs (or to specific OCs), one has to bear in mind also the relative frequency of the latter, which may be quite low for specific OCs. Estimates that as many as 20% of cases are due to OCs are, for various reasons, likely to be exaggerations. Nevertheless, OCs are significant contributory causes, more important than pre-natal infections. They are not primary causes, but may “tip the balance” or increase the severity of an underlying problem, so that the diagnostic criteria for schizophrenia are met, when otherwise they might not be. They are in operation over a longer stage of gestation than (apparently) is the influence of prenatal infection. Whether the effect of OCs can be incorporated in any specific and detailed way into an overall theory of schizophrenia, depends on the form such a theory takes, based on much other evidence (see also 12.3.3. and 12.9.4.). Of the risks during childhood and adolescence, head injury probably has a negligible influence, although CNS infections may have a larger effect (4.5.). The relevance of cannabis has been much debated. Recent evidence clarifies its role: It appears to be not only a precipitator of schizophrenia-like illnesses in persons who are already vulnerable, but also a significant contributory cause, producing illness in persons who would otherwise not be affected (4.6.). The effect of other street drugs is mentioned in Chapter 5. 2.3.2. Contributory causes in the psychosocial domain. It is well known that increased prevalence of schizophrenia occurs in association with low socio-economic status (4.7.). In large measure this is due to downward drift in social status and failure of upward mobility, not only in people who already have the illness but also in the years before onset of illness. Some degree of actual causation by Synopsis of the Theory social factors cannot be excluded. Urban birth and upbringing, produce substantial increases in risk of schizophrenia, a risk which increases with the duration of life during adolescence spent in an urban environment (4.8.). This suggests that a definite environmental factor, either in the biological or social realm, associated with urban life increases the risk of schizophrenia. Most important, immigration produces a very variable, but sometimes very large increase in incidence of schizophrenia (4.9.). Rather than being a biological effect, this seems to be a psychosocial one, acting over a long period, probably during a child’s formative years. However, it is most pronounced in those who also have a genetic predisposition. This effect can be so large, that it overshadows completely the small effects of prenatal infections, obstetric complications or CNS infections during childhood, which can presumably be detected only when psychosocial factors are relatively constant or slowly changing. Some modern evidence suggests that adverse family social factors may predispose to schizophrenia, especially in those who are at genetic risk (4.10). This evidence includes an adoption study where disturbed dynamics in the adoptive family, as well as genetic risk are identified as risk factors. Shared environmental factors within families (probably psychosocial in nature) have also been identified in family studies as contributors to schizophrenia, although only in a small way. Some evidence also implicates the number and relative age of siblings. There is however, little evidence that divorce and family separation predispose children to schizophrenia. The evidence of major contributory causes in the psychosocial domain (especially the effect of immigration) has wide impact on schizophrenia research (4.11.). It implies that the proportion of the population who carry the genetic diathesis for schizophrenia is much larger than otherwise suspected – of the order of 10-20% - and for many people with this diathesis it is only the combination with psychosocial adversity which brings this genetic loading out into the open. If this is true, it makes more difficult the task of molecular geneticists in their search for the exact genetic factors underlying schizophrenia. This evidence also has impact on one’s interpretation of the relation between druginduced psychoses and schizophrenia, as well as the international studies comparing prevalence of schizophrenia in different countries and cultures. Most important for the present work, this evidence defines one of the criteria by which any comprehensive theory of schizophrenia should be judged: If a neurodynamic theory of schizophrenia is to be upheld, it will need to encompass psychosocial influences as well as underlying biological substrates for the disorder (see Chapter 13). 2.3.3. Genetic liability, environmental influences and concepts of schizophrenia. The range of causative factors, genetic and environmental, which contribute to schizophrenia is very broad. Their sheer diversity raises uncomfortable questions about the very concept of schizophrenia. It could be said that the concept is fundamentally unsound, an arbitrary human creation with a shaky foundation in a motley collection of antecedent correlations, rather than a real disease entity. Alternatively, “schizophrenia” might be conceptualized as a very non- specific result of multiple hazards, including diverse genetic liabilities, biological insults and psychosocial adversity. To this author, such viewpoints are unduly cynical. Nevertheless, a challenge is posed for the rest of this book, namely to re-cast the definition of schizophrenia in terms of a theory which encompasses all these factors. A few guidelines can be suggested for such a reformulation: Genetic contributions can presumably produce a brain which has certain propensities biasing it towards schizophrenia. It might then be possible to define a causal hypothesis, based on innate brain mechanisms, applying in the first instance just to those cases where the environmental insults to the brain and the psychosocial influences on its functioning in childhood and adolesence are not important. To these are then added non-genetic biological factors acting at an early stage of development. Although these are of small overall impact, they help to demarcate the time during development at which the brain becomes committed to the developmental program leading to schizophrenia. This appears to be the mid-trimester of pregnancy. Factors such as obstetric complications acting at this and later stages of pregnancy and later in biological development can be seen as complicating factors, sometimes substantial, but not the core of the problem. Then, added to this, one should consider, how adverse psychosocial factors might interact with genetic and developmental ones to produce the manifest illness. In this regard, it is clear that in post-natal life, the dynamic potential of the brain is determined not only by early biological development: It is also “shaped” by the information patterns to which it is exposed in post-natal experience. Current knowledge establishes this best for the sensory and motor systems. However, there is no reason why it should not also apply to the higher functions of the brain, which are particularly implicated in schizophrenia. These are more closely linked to the social environment than to immediate sensory input. There is thus the possibility that the psychosocial environment plays a part in determining the dynamic functioning of the adult brain: Adverse psychosocial influences could contribute to producing the disturbed brain dynamics shown in schizophrenia. These influences include those encompassed by the concepts of “reward”, “punishment” and “positive or negative reinforcement”. There is a variety of terminology to chose from (as discussed in Chapter 5.), and these terms are used in a very broad sense. Whichever terminology is chosen, these concepts bridge not only between biology and psychology, but also, in humans, between biology and factors in the social environment. Development of normal brain dynamics and normal information processing in humans might depend at least in part on the long-term history of such influences. Prolonged absence of reward, presence of punishment or negative reinforcement, might well change the overall dynamics of the brain. These conceptualizations are quite compatible with previous models put forward for schizophrenia. The genetic and developmental evidence is compatible with the “neurodevelopmental model”. The psychosocial influences fit well within the “stress-diathesis model”. However, in Chapter 1, it was suggested that schizophrenia might be conceived more exactly as a “neurodynamic” disorder. Such a model of 20 Synopsis of the Theory disease can hold together all the strands of causation, within a single set of causal premises. In this formulation abnormal brain dynamics in the adult determine abnormal patterns of information processing, reflected in symptoms. Abnormal adult brain dynamics could themselves be determined by abnormal cellular architecture in brain tissue. This in turn would be mainly under genetic control, unfolding during the expression of a complex developmental program. During this unfolding, harmful biological influences, especially those acting in the prenatal period could modify the developmental process to increase the likelihood of the adult brain’s dynamic capabilities becoming abnormal. Regardless of this however, the dynamic capabilities of the brain develop post-natally, under the influence of the information patterns to which the brain is exposed, and the rewards, punishments, meanings, purposes, and contexts which determine our social life. In this way one can conceive of psychosocial influences shaping the dynamic brain functions underlying higher cognitive function, in a way similar to the influences at the sensorimotor level which create plastic changes in sensory or motor systems at an earlier stage of postnatal life. Most epidemiological studies of causal effects on schizophrenia are committed in advance to genetic causation, or if environmental, to either biological or psychosocial causation. Few studies have attempted to compare quantitatively the relative influence of these two. One such is that of Mortensen et al (1999): Relative risk, if there was an affected FDR, ranged from 7—9.3 (varying with the class of FDR), 2.4 if there was urban birth, but only around 1.1 (i.e. 10% increase) if there was a winter birth. The overall proportion of cases attributable to each of these risk factors was 5.5% for affected FDR, 34.6% for urban birth, and 10.5% for winter birth. The total contribution of genetic factors to schizophrenia is however likely to be larger than 5.5%, because, given that genetic factors are often not expressed, overt family history is an underestimate of true genetic contribution. With a formulation such as that presented above, there is no need for biological and psychosocial concepts of schizophrenia to be pitted in opposition to each other. However, much work is needed to develop such a general shape of a theory into a theory providing detailed explanations. 2.4. Dopamine and the theory of psychosis. Psychosis is defined here as a state where a patient loses contact with everyday reality, this state being characterized by delusions, hallucinations, Schneiderian symptoms and other signs of severely disturbed cognitive processes. It is the most obvious and dramatic departure from normality in schizophrenia, but it is not synonymous with schizophrenia: Psychosis can arise in many other ways, and schizophrenia includes many other less dramatic but enduring abnormalities. However, as the most obvious surface indication of schizophrenia, it is important to develop a theory for psychosis, so that the underlying core of abnormality can, in turn, be better understood. At a biological level, a theory of psychosis based on overactivity of the forebrain transmitter dopamine is compelling (5.2.). This theory develops from the well-documented actions 21 of antipsychotic drugs as dopamine antagonists, the similarity of their motor side effects in humans to the symptoms of parkinsonism, the psychosis-producing effects of stimulant drugs, which release dopamine in active form, and the similarity between stimulant-sensitization in animals and psychosis-proneness in humans. Recent evidence obtained using various PET methods has demonstrated that forebrain dopamine systems are overactive (that is, they release an excess amount of transmitter). Indirect evidence suggests that such excess release of dopamine is a consequence of excess impulse traffic in the midbrain dopamine neurons and their pathways. The cause of this excess impulse traffic is one of the deeper questions about the pathophysiology of schizophrenia, dealt with at a later stage of exposition of the present theory (9.6.9.3., 11.2.2.6.). 2.4.1. The long time-course of therapy with dopamineblocking drugs. At the psychological level, it is suggested that a key feature of psychotic states of schizophrenia, critical for shaping an explanation, is the relatively slow pace of recovery from psychosis when a patient is treated with antipsychotic medications (5.3.1.1). The slow recovery is particularly notable for the symptom of delusions. Various clinical features of the recovery process (the phenomenology of recovery, and the fact that the completeness and speed of recovery may depend on baseline personality, or duration of prior untreated psychosis) suggest that complex psychological processes intervene between reduction of dopamine’s activity and eventual abatement of symptoms. Attempts to explain this in purely biological terms have been made by Grace and Bunney (1985)(5.3.1.2.). They base their account on the fact that chronic regimes of neuroleptic drugs in animals silence the impulse firing of midbrain dopamine neurons, by a process identified as “depolarization block”. This finding, and its interpretation as depolarization block are not challenged here. However, depolarization block appears to be dependent on the effect of chronic regimes of neuroleptic drugs as revealed in anesthetized animals. It does not occur in freemoving ones (as demonstrated by a number of different methods). Thus, depolarization block cannot apply to the circumstances of therapy with antipsychotic drugs in humans, and is inadequate as an explanation of the long time course of antipsychotic therapy. What is needed for a satisfactory explanation is a form of reasoning which crosses levels between the biological and the psychological descriptions of psychosis. 2.4.2. Psychobiology of dopamine. To develop such reasoning, it is necessary to understand the psychobiology of what is termed the “reward/incentive function” (5.3.2.). Starting from Thorndike’s celebrated “law of effect” many studies have analyzed the behavioral aspects of reward-related learning (5.3.2.1.). Events which are “rewarding” in relation to an animal’s motivational systems can enhance the attractiveness of stimuli with which they are associated, or can enhance the vigor of responses when those responses lead to the rewarding stimulus. Under appropriate circumstances these two can be combined, so that a rewarding event strengthens specific stimulus-response links. These Synopsis of the Theory relationships are defined in relation to overt behavior in experimental animals. However, it is very likely that formally similar processing of information occurs in humans, serving covert mental processing (“thoughts”), such as those which are disturbed during periods of active psychosis. Both in animals and humans, the rubric of reward-related learning implies that there be an internal signal in the brain which acts as a reinforcer. This signal mediates the effects of rewarding events on behavior or thought. A large weight of evidence contributes to the conclusion that forebrain dopamine (especially that in the pathway from midbrain dopamine cells to the striatum) is a major component of the internal reinforcement signal implicit in reward-related learning (5.3.2.2.). Intensive investigation of the role of dopamine in reinforcement enriches the psychological descriptions of reward-related learning. In some experimental designs dopamine over-activity not only exaggerates the reinforcement effects mentioned above, but can broaden the “span of attention”. Thus in terms of psychobiological theory, selective attention is not totally separate from the reward/incentive function. In addition, in the inputs to the internal reinforcement system (i.e. afferent pathways of the midbrain dopamine neurons), information processing occurs such that the dopamine neurons respond not so much to the absolute magnitude of a rewarding event, but to the differential between that, and what is expected on the basis of other recent events. At a more fundamental level, recent evidence indicates that the reinforcing actions of dopamine depend on a type of synaptic modification, which strengthens selected excitatory synapses in the striatum, and for which dopamine is an essential co-factor (5.3.2.3.). The abnormalities of selective attention occurring in high-dopamine states appear to arise because principal neurons in the striatum are engaged in mutual inhibition at a population level. When dopaminemediated synaptic strengthening is excessive, excitatory inputs to these striatal neurons overwhelm the inhibitory interactions between them which normally limit the number of simultaneously active cells. The sensitivity of the dopaminergic reinforcement mechanism to the differential between actual and expected size of rewarding stimuli appears to be a function of neural processing in the input to the dopamine cells, notably in the amygdala. For the cognitive equivalent of reward-related learning, likely to be important in humans, control of midbrain dopamine neurons probably depends more on afferent pathways from the cortex, which may be direct, or indirect via the amygdala, superior colliculus or subthalamus. Dyscontrol of dopamine neurons in psychosis is likely to depend on abnormal activity in these pathways from the cortex. normal beliefs, are strongly reinforced, and, at least temporarily, become incorrigible delusions. When the medications take effect, they stop further accumulation of such distorted and exaggerated beliefs, but do not of themselves eradicate those already stored in memory banks. However, by “taking the pressure off” a person’s total cognitive apparatus, it is possible for the person to start to “work through” the conflicts of belief set up during the period of active psychosis. An equivalent description, using the language of learning theory, is that delusional beliefs are gradually “extinguished”. To complete this process takes some time (weeks or months). It is to be expected that this process takes longer if there has been a long duration of untreated psychosis. In addition, persons with a general tendency to rigid retention of belief structures may have slower and less complete elimination of psychotic beliefs than those who, inherently, can change beliefs in a more flexible fashion. 2.4.3. Hypothesis to explain the slow action of antipsychotic drugs. This account of the psychology and physiology of forebrain dopamine forms a basis for explaining the slow time-course of recovery of psychosis (especially of the symptom of delusions) during therapy with antipsychotic drugs (5.3.2.4.). In the active phase of psychosis, when dopamine systems are overactive, patterns of cognitive information, which are distortions and exaggerations of 2.4.5. Therapy with antipsychotic drugs and dopamine receptors. The theory of psychosis based on the reinforcing actions of dopamine contains a major discrepancy, related to the pharmacological receptor type upon which the actions of antipsychotic drugs depend (5.4.1.). The therapeutic effects of these drugs is proportional to their blockade of dopamine D2 receptors. However, the psychological function of reinforcement, identified as that which mediates the 2.4.4. Explanation of phenomenology of psychosis. The account of dopamine as a reinforcing agent also makes possible a wider explanation of the phenomenology of psychosis in schizophrenia (5.3.2.5.). Excessively vivid perceptual experiences (common at the start of a psychotic episode) probably signify exaggeration of the incentive functions of dopamine. Many hallucinations probably represent, in part, an exaggeration of normally-subliminal perceptual experiences associated with cognitive processes, to the point where they seem like perceptions of external origin. Abnormalities of attention may play a part in generating psychotic symptoms (including Schneiderian symptoms) both by blocking attentional focus on the desired items and by generating intrusions of unwanted material. The specific content of delusions can be explained as exaggeration of the motivational significance of events. This applies to “visceral” motives, leading to delusions on themes of wealth, power, love, sex etc. It also applies to “cognitive motives”. In the latter case, ideas which provide all-encompassing, but spurious “explanations” of everyday events are a particular focus of delusions, because reinforcement normally provided by an apparent explanation is exaggerated. This may explain why psychotic delusions often focus on topics rich in associations, or “explanatory power” (such as the paranormal, the occult, and ideas of philosophy, religion etc). The principle that dopamine systems are controlled by the differential between actual and expected value of motivationally-significant events, rather than their absolute value can provide an account of why psychotic delusions exaggerate the negative as well as the positive motivational valence of mental images. 22 Synopsis of the Theory therapeutic effects is known (on the basis both of psychopharmacological evidence and recent physiological experiments on synaptic change) to depend on the actions of dopamine at D1 receptors. This apparent paradox could be explained if actions at D2 receptors achieve their effects indirectly, with reduction of the effects of D1 receptors being the ultimate target. Such an indirect effect could be produced via cholinergic mechanisms in the striatum. Cholinergic neurons in the striatum are normally inhibited by dopamine acting at D2 receptors, so that blockade of D2 receptors leads to these neurons becoming overactive. Activation of the socalled M4 muscarinic receptors in the striatum has effects similar to and synergistic with those of blockade of dopamine D1-receptors (vis: reduction of cAMP formation, known to be involved in dopamine-mediated synaptic change). In antipsychotic treatment in normally-responsive patients, D2 blockade will enhance acetylcholine release in the striatum, increasing activation of M4 receptors, and producing effects equivalent to those of D1 blockade. Support for this comes from evidence on the special effects of clozapine in psychotic patients refractory to treatment with other medications. Such refractoriness probably arises because of a relative scarcity of cholinergic neurons in the striatum. However, clozapine itself, amongst other effects, probably has an agonist action at muscarinic M4 receptors, and thus can reproduce the effects of natural cholinergic activation even when there are few cholinergic neurons in the striatum to release acetylcholine after D2 blockade. One of the critical tests of the hypothesis that D1 blockade and/or reduced cAMP formation are the final target of antipsychotic mediations of all classes is that D1-blocking agents should have antipsychotic effects. Clinical trials of D1-antagonists conducted so far have failed to show this, but have a number of methodological shortcomings. More rigorous clinical trials are needed. 2.4.6. Psychosis and the “limbic striatum”. There is a widespread belief that dopamine blockade in the so-called “limbic striatum” is critical for the actions of antipsychotic drugs (5.4.2.). This belief is based almost entirely on studies in animals. Such evidence has suggested regional differences in behavioral effects of dopamine blockade (motor side effects in the neostriatum/substantia nigra; cognitive/motivational effects in ventral tegmental area/limbic striatum). Attention has also been drawn to region-selective patterns of development of tolerance to neuroleptic drugs, which is relevant to the fact that tolerance does not develop in human therapy. Regionally-selective production of depolarization blockade of dopamine neurons with chronic regimes of antipsychotic drugs has also been thought to indicate a special role for the limbic striatum. Apart from some weaknesses in the detail of each of these arguments, they all draw uncertain parallels between the striatal complex of laboratory animals (especially rats), and humans (where the “limbic striatum”, or the “nucleus accumbens” has rarely been properly defined in clinical studies). The conceptual status of the “limbic system” itself has also come under recent criticism. It is more likely that over-activity of dopamine anywhere in the striatal complex can lead to psychotic symptoms. The details of the psychotic 23 symptoms then depend on the locations at which dopamine exerts its excessive influence. 2.4.7. Psychosis, schizophrenia and transmitter glutamate. Much recent theorizing about psychosis and schizophrenia has implicated transmitter glutamate and its receptors. It has been claimed that NMDA-receptor antagonists (PCP, ketamine) produce a psychosis resembling that of schizophrenia more closely than that produced by stimulants, in that they reproduce negative as well as positive symptoms (5.4.3.). Scrutiny of the evidence does indeed support the view that these agents can mimic negative symptoms. However, in the few studies where they have been administered to healthy volunteers, they do not reproduce the positive psychotic symptoms as well as do the stimulant drugs. Studies where positive symptoms are reported are generally those of subjects hospitalized after an adverse reaction (a “bad trip”), and are probably not representative of the effects of these agents generally. Some of the recent theorizing about schizophrenia draws on evidence of interactions in the striatum between transmitter glutamate and dopamine (5.4.4.). Grace (1991) uses evidence that glutamate in the striatum enhances dopamine release. He has proposed that reduction of glutamate release there leads to reduction of tonic dopamine release (unrelated to impulses) which sets into action compensatory processes which enhance phasic (impulse-associated) dopamine release. This hypothesis is proposed as an explanation of both the negative symptoms and cognitive impairments (due to reduced glutamate activity) and the positive symptoms (due to increased phasic dopamine activity). While some evidence supports these ideas, there are many discrepant findings. The interaction between glutamate and dopamine in the striatum is probably mediated indirectly in a variety of ways, which undermines the plausibility of this hypothesis. 2.4.8. Relations between cortex and subcortex and theories of psychosis and schizophrenia. Another proposed explanation of the relation between positive and negative symptoms in schizophrenia is based on levels of neural activity in cortex and subcortex, rather than on interaction between transmitter systems (5.4.5.1.). It is based on evidence that the prefrontal cortex normally exerts inhibitory control over subcortical dopaminergic activity. From this, it is proposed that, in schizophrenia, cortical underactivity (especially in prefrontal regions, and perhaps specific to dopamine systems there) is associated with, and leads to, dopaminergic over-activity in the striatal complex. This hypothesis gives a consistent account of the relation between positive symptoms and cognitive impairment/negative symptoms, and has much evidence in its support. However, one body of evidence is difficult to reconcile with this hypothesis, namely that in schizophrenia, measures of neural activity in the cortex, though generally below normal, are usually found to be positively correlated with positive (psychotic) symptoms. The hypothesis would have predicted a negative correlation. In addition, there is a great deal of evidence about trait impairments in schizophrenia (reviewed in Part IV), which has not been incorporated into this Synopsis of the Theory hypothesis. Furthermore, cognitive trait impairments and negative symptoms may occur at different times from positive symptoms, and may be present in subjects (for instance in relatives) who never show positive symptoms. Thus, although this hypothesis is plausible, one is left searching for a better one. Following from Weinberger’s neurodevelopmental hypothesis, a number of studies in animals have shown that a lesion in the hippocampus or other regions, sustained early in life, can lead, when the animal becomes mature, to signs of dopamine over-activity (5.4.5.2.). In a general way this may be relevant to the fact that schizophrenia in humans emerges only in late adolescence or early adulthood. However, this work leaves unanswered a major question about the nature of the “lesion” in humans, which could be the equivalent of the lesions produced in animals. There is no clear evidence of such a focal lesion in human neuropathological studies of schizophrenia. Of particular relevance to the theory developed in this book, a number of studies has shown that lesions in animals may have different effects on dopaminergic and noradrenergic activity according to the side of the lesion (5.4.5.3.). Rightsided cortical lesions have a greater effect in amplifying behavioral activity related to these transmitters than left-sided ones. This intriguing evidence is referred to later as the theory of this book unfolds. 2.4.9. General comments on the theory of psychosis. While the actions of dopamine can provide a good explanation of many of the key features of the psychoses of schizophrenia, they cannot account for the whole of this disorder, including the enduring trait abnormalities. Attempts made so far to provide more complete accounts including the negative symptoms and cognitive trait abnormalities, as well as positive symptoms have some merit. However, they do not incorporate the large bodies of evidence, on abnormal psychological traits, and electrophysiological or brain morphological abnormalities, into a coherent theory. The evidence covered in Chapter 5 reveals several sources of confusion. “Psychosis” has often been equated with the whole clinical picture of schizophrenia. Several blind alleys, have grown to prominence because the research has been guided by findings in animals, rather than those in humans. Animal research certainly is relevant to understanding psychosis, but requires careful consideration of the conceptual shifts involved in making the leap from laboratory animals to human psychopathology. Some of the blind alleys have arisen because correlation has taken the place of true scientific reasoning. Others have arisen because the disease model adopted for schizophrenia assumed that there are qualitative or categorical differences between normality and schizophrenia (e.g. hypotheses of abnormal receptors, or other molecules or genetic factors). In so far as we understand the basis of the psychotic episodes of schizophrenia – that is, in terms of excessive neural traffic in the midbrain dopamine neurons – the abnormality is not fundamentally qualitative or categorical in nature. Rather it is a quantitative extension of the normal psychobiology of dopamine. Admittedly there comes a point in the transition to active psychosis where, in psychological and social terms, there is a true categorical “break with reality”. Such a categorical break probably does not apply when considering the whole picture of schizophrenia, although some symptoms involving such a “break with reality” may be enduring traits rather than linked just to transient episodes. A general issue is whether theories based on relative excess or deficit of neurochemical factors such as transmitters or their receptors can be adequate. They may be very useful to explain the psychotic state, but less so for the enduring abnormal traits. In any case, from the point of view of humane understanding of schizophrenia, it is wise to emphasize the psychological features in common between the psychoses of schizophrenia and normality – to understand abnormality in relation to normal function. The account of psychosis given in Chapter 5 attempts to do this. 2.5. Introduction to the survey of trait abnormalities in psychological and psychophysiological functions, and in brain morphology. A major component of the theory developed in this book is that, in so far as brain mechanisms are concerned, the fundamental basis of schizophrenia is an abnormal variant of the cerebral asymmetry present in the normal human brain. Cerebral asymmetry of function has been documented for 150 years, and before that could be inferred from the phenomenon of handedness. The idea that there is something unusual about cerebral asymmetry in the functional psychoses has developed over the last 35 years, starting with studies of Flor-Henry (1969, 1972). These showed that temporal lobe epilepsy was associated with schizophrenia-like psychoses with paranoia if the focus was in the left hemisphere, and with affective psychosis or depression if it was in the right hemisphere. In the following 15-20 years a few studies pursued the relation between laterality and schizophrenia, and three books (Gruzelier and Flor-Henry, 1979; Flor-Henry and Gruzelier, 1983; Takahashi et al, 1987) reviewed the topic. Subsequently very many papers have reported both functional and brain morphological data about differences from normal cerebral asymmetry in schizophrenia. Several specific suggestions have been made about the nature of the abnormalities of asymmetry in schizophrenia (see Cutting, 1985 [pp 151-160], 1992), including left hemisphere over-activity (Gur et al, 1983), left hemisphere impairment (Guenther et al, 1985), loss of normal asymmetry (DeLisi et al, 1997b), and right hemisphere impairment (Cutting, 1992). However, none of these ideas has been developed into a coherent theory encompassing a wide range of evidence. In the view of the present author, this failure has been a consequence of two other inadequacies in research in this field. First, it has not been realized that different theoretical frameworks are needed for active psychosis and for the enduring functional trait abnormalities in schizophrenia. However, if this is so, it would permit the possibility that different laterality effects are seen in these two situations. In the present work, an attempt is made to separate evidence pertaining to the active psychotic state from that reflecting enduring traits. As discussed in Chapter 5, there are theoretical grounds for suggesting that these two are largely separate, although not all psychotic manifestations are limited 24 Synopsis of the Theory to acute episodes. The methods for separating empirically between active psychosis and enduring traits are also not entirely clear-cut, and are discussed below. 2.5.1. Axonal conduction time as a critical variable for the theory of normal cerebral asymmetry. The second reason why a coherent explanatory theory of schizophrenia, based on the idea of an abnormality of cerebral asymmetry, has not been constructed hitherto is that a prerequisite for such a theory is that a similar theory should be available for normal asymmetry, perhaps in terms of cellular or biochemical differences between the hemispheres. Until recently, there has been no such theory. However, Miller (1996a) published such a theory. This attempts to explain normal cerebral asymmetry of function in terms of a “central hypothesis” about conduction time in cortico-cortical axons. Axons are of two morphological types, unmyelinated and myelinated. The former are basically a long cylinder of . axoplasm surrounded by a cell membrane. In the latter type, the axon is surrounded by a myelin sheath, made mainly of lipids (multiple cell membranes). The myelin sheath increases the conduction velocity for impulses, by the process called “saltatory conduction”. Even discounting the myelin sheath, myelinated axons are of larger caliber than unmyelinated ones. However, for our cortico-cortical axons of both morphological types, caliber varies greatly, by more than tenfold, within a population of axons. The two types, and their wide range of calibers are shown in an electron micrograph of subcortical white matter from the rat (Figure 2.1.). It is seldom possible to do electron microscopy of the human brain, for a combination of ethical and technical reasons, but there is little reason to doubt that hemispheric white matter in humans also consists of axons of both types, of widely varying caliber. Figure 2.1. Electron micrograph of a portion of white matter under the cerebral cortex in rat. This shows the difference between umyelinated and myelinated axons (running in different directions, but mainly cut in tranverse section), and for each type shows the wide range in caliber. Myelinated axons have prominent sheaths (ring-like in transverse section). Unmyelinated axons (e.g. cluster indicated by arrow) are smaller, less prominemt, but (in rats) more numerous (making up 75-90 % of all axons, according to Partadiredja et al [2003]). Their numerical proportion in humans is not known. Most of the axons shown are probably cortico-cortical ones (Electron micrograph prepared by G. Partadiredja, reproduced here with thanks). Since the basic facts about conduction time in corticocortical axons are central for all the theory that follows in this book, it is necessary to present some detail. Conduction time in single axons of the CNS cannot be studied in humans, for clear ethical reasons. In experimental animals, the most direct 25 method available is to conduct single cell recording, and activate each neuron’s axon at a distance from the cell body. An impulse is then conducted in a direction opposite to that occurring in normal physiological circumstances (antidromic conduction). The advantage of this is that it allows direct Synopsis of the Theory measurement of the latency of conduction in a manner not confounded by the complications of synaptic transmission. Antidromic responses after stimulation generally have a very constant latency (varying by no more than a tiny fraction of a millisecond on successive stimulations). Study of a population of neuronal responses in this way gives information about conduction times in a population of axons. Experiments conducted in the 1970s in anesthetized cats (Miller, 1976), and later in rabbits (Swadlow and Weyand, 1981; Swadlow, 1989, 1990, 1991, 1994) showed that cortico-cortical axons have conduction times (for distances ranging from a few mm [Swadlow] to about 1 cm [Miller]) which vary greatly between axons, ranging from less than 10 msec to several tens of milliseconds (Figure 2.2.). QuickTime™ and a TIFF (U ncompressed) decompressor are needed to see this picture. Figure 2.2. Composite diagram showing latency histograms for antidromic responses in ipsilateral and callosally-projecting long cortico-cortical axons. Upper left: Callosal neurons in cat primary somatosensory cortex (from Miller, 1976). Upper right: Neurons in cat primary somatosensory cortex projecting to second somatosensory area (from Miller, 1976). Lower left: Callosal neurons in rabbit visual cortex (from Swadlow, 1974). Lower right: Neurons in rabbit visual area V-1 projecting to ipsilateral area V-II (above) and across the callosum (below)(from Swadlow and Weyand, 1981). Redrawn from originals: lower left: Reprinted from Experimental Neurology, vol 43, no 2, H.A.Swadlow; Properties of antidromically activated callosal neurons and neurons responsive to callosal input in rabbit binocular cortex, pp. 424-444, Copyright Elsevier Ltd., © 1974, with permission from Elsevier. lower right: H.A.Swadlow and T.C.Weyand, 1981, with permission from John Wiley & Sons Inc.). Conduction time for a given length of axon is the reciprocal of conduction velocity, and this depends on axonal morphology. From studies based on the peripheral axons, Rushton (1951) concluded that conduction velocity was directly proportional to axon caliber for myelinated axons, but to the square root of caliber for unmyelinated ones (see also: Goldman and Albus, 1968; Matsumoto and Tasaki, 1977). While the scaling factors are different in the central nervous system, the basic relationships appear to be similar (Waxman and Bennett, 1972). In cortico-cortical axons, the wide variation between axons in conduction times, for similar conduction distances (matching the wide variation in conduction velocity, over a more-than-tenfold range), is well accounted for by variation in caliber and type of these axons. There is a variety of sampling and other biases on the data presented in Fig. 2.2. (Miller, 1994; Swadlow, 2000), all of 26 Synopsis of the Theory which favor recording from neurons with more rapidlyconducting axons, or which underestimate the true conduction time from soma to synapse. Thus the proportion of corticocortical axons with the longer conduction times are certainly under-represented in the histograms of figure 2.2. In addition, the experiments on which those results are based were conducted in animals with small brains, where conduction distances are not much more than 1 cm. In humans, the length of cortico-cortical axons may often be 10 cm or more. No empirical data exist on their conduction times or velocities. However, a simple extension from these animal data to the situation in humans, suggests an important conclusion: There is a major proportion of cortico-cortical axons with conduction times from soma to synapse of 100 msec, 200 msec, or even more (Swadlow et al, 1979; Miller, 1994). In Chapter 1, it was suggested that a truly explanatory theory of schizophrenia needs to be based on cross-level reasoning, explaining the psychological manifestations of the disorder in terms of neuronal dynamics. In basic neuroscience there already exist some such explanations. Perhaps the most influential concept is Hebb’s (1949) notion of the cell assembly, which constitutes a “strategic bridge” between brain function studied at the behavioral and at the neuronal levels. However, at the time Hebb’s ideas were formulated, little was known of the detailed functioning of neurons. Since then, the physical basis of action potentials, synaptic potentials, and other aspects of neuronal biophysics has been revealed in elaborate detail. We therefore should be in a much better position to “put flesh on the bones” of Hebb’s theory. This should be of immense value in our task, that of creating a psychobiological theory of schizophrenia. However, the one neuronal variable which has been severely neglected in basic neuroscience is that just emphasized, namely axonal conduction time. The author of this work believes that, if this variable is included along with other neuronal variables, many new avenues of theoretical research will become possible, in the attempts to explain psychological findings in neuronal terms. This applies not only in the basic neurosciences, but also, as here, in the theory of mental disorders. With regard to normal cerebral asymmetry in humans, the “central hypothesis” of Miller (1996a) proposes that these axons differ between hemispheres in their range of conduction velocities. Specifically, it was proposed that a typical population of axons in the normal right hemisphere has a relative preponderance of rapidly conducting axons, whereas a similar population of axons in the left hemisphere has a relative preponderance of slowly-conducting axons. As far as the cybernetics of nervous tissue goes, the implication from this hypothesis is related to axonal conduction time: In the right hemisphere it is envisaged that a high proportion of cortico-cortical axons have conduction times from soma to synapse less than the integration time in a typical cortical pyramidal cell (~10 msec). Activity in such axons converging on a pyramidal cell would then encode no information about 27 temporal patterning of the converging signals, since, as far as the post-synaptic neuron goes, they indicate nearsimultaneous firing of the various presynaptic neurons (see Figure 2.3A). In the left hemisphere, it is envisaged that a high proportion of connecting axons have conduction times substantially longer than the neuronal integration time, and (in absolute terms), have widely varying conduction times. Activity in such axons converging on a pyramidal cell would then still activate the postsynaptic neuron only if they all arrive within a single integration time. However, this implies that the activation of the presynaptic neurons was at substantially different times (Figure 2.3B). While this central hypothesis is framed in terms of axonal conduction time (or velocity), it also has clear implications for morphology, since slowly-conducting axons are of finer caliber, are more commonly unmyelinated, or, if myelinated, have thinner myelin sheaths than rapidly-conducting ones. This “central hypothesis” originated by inference from indirect evidence, about lateral specializations for perceiving different sorts of stimuli in humans. The right hemisphere (in typical right-handers) is known to be superior for perceiving visual patterns (e.g. faces), all of whose components are present in the same instant of time. The left hemisphere however (for right-handers) is superior for perceiving stimuli (such as basic speech sounds) whose components occur nonsynchronously in accurately-timed sequence within a duration of the order of 100 msec. From a strictly scientific point of view, it is, of course highly desirable that direct evidence be provided to evaluate this central hypothesis. This would involve either single unit electrophysiological experiments (such as those conducted in cats or rabbits) or electron microscopy to discover the range of calibres and proportion of myelinated to unmyelinated axons. Overwhelming ethical considerations preclude such electrophysiological experiments in humans. In addition, electron microscopy of brain tissue is very difficult in humans, for a combination of ethical and technical reasons. Tissue can seldom be obtained in humans soon enough after death, or in a state of adequate fixation for good quality electron micrographs to be prepared. In rare circumstances they can be prepared (e.g. Uranova et al, 2001) but the methodological limitations then still preclude systematic and quantitative electron microscopy in humans (including stereology), such as is possible in laboratory animals. Hence evaluation of the central hypothesis of Miller (1996a) must rest on accumulation of evidence more-or-less indirectly related to the basic postulate, mainly examples of what the central hypothesis will explain. In such circumstances, the greater the number of indirect tests which turn out to be consistent with the hypothesis, the more firmly is it supported. This strategy has many parallels in earlier scientific history (e.g. Dalton’s “atoms”; Gregor Mendel’s genetic “factors”), where a postulate is initially justified in terms of what it will explain, and only later, as adequate techniques become available, is the postulate confirmed by direct evidence. Synopsis of the Theory Figure 2.3: Principles linking axonal conduction time to neurocybernetics. These are “space-time” diagrams with time elapsing from left to right, and “neuronal integration time (~10 msec) indicated by pairs of vertical parallel lines with shading. A:- Hypothetical pathway in right hemisphere, where conduction time is short, and temporal dispersion does not exceed a single neuronal integration time. B:- Hypothetical pathway in left hemisphere, where mean conduction time is slower, and temporal dispersion in the population is greater than the neuronal integration time. If signals in different axons are initiated at the same time, only limited post-synaptic convergence occurs within a single integration interval (left). If optimal post-synaptic convergence is to occur, signals must be initiated at different times (right), so that the post-synaptic neuron responds to a specific temporal pattern. In the monograph of Miller (1996a) indirect evidence was reviewed of morphological, electrophysiological, and especially psychological nature. The morphological evidence included data that the volume ratio of white matter to grey matter was lower in the left hemisphere than the right, this being the same for all four lobes of the hemispheres. In quantitative terms, the differences between right and left often failed to reach statistical significance, but nevertheless almost always pointed in the same direction. The methods used in different studies were quite varied, so pooling of data across studies, followed by quantitative meta-analysis was not possible. However, recent studies tend to confirm the conclusions made in 1996 (Gur,R.C. et al, 1999; Carne et al, 2006). Electrophysiological studies using EEG methods provided some support for the central hypothesis in that EEG coherence between electrode pairs was generally higher, and phase delays less in the right than the left hemisphere (although these approaches need to be used much more extensively to make a convincing case). A psychophysiological measure (simple reaction time: RT) provided strong, and fairly direct confirmation of the central hypothesis. The experiment here involves comparing “crossed” reactions (e.g. right visual fields and left hand) with “uncrossed” ones (e.g. right fields and right hand), the former situation giving longer RTs because it involves an additional relay across the corpus callosum. This experiment can be carried out for either right-to-left or left-to-right transmission across the corpus callosum. Strikingly, the reported transmission times are longer for left-to-right than for right-toleft callosal transmission. Since callosal axons originating in one hemisphere are really a subset of all the long corticocortical axons of that hemisphere, this result shows a significant tendency for transmission to be faster for right than for left hemisphere axons, as predicted by Miller (1996a). The largest and most complex body of evidence reviewed by Miller (1996a) was related to psychological predictions from the central hypothesis. Evidence consistent with the hypothesis included the facts on perceptual processes, namely that perceptual integration occurs more rapidly in the right than the left hemisphere; on motor control, where control by sensory guidance is faster and more accurate if the right hemisphere is involved than the left; on semantic decoding of incoming language, which is accomplished better by the right than the left hemisphere; and on sustained attention/vigilance, where the right hemisphere is superior to the left. This survey does not by any means exhaust the evidence relevant to Miller’s “central hypothesis”, there being many other paradigms where the hypothesis is accessible to test, and much relevant evidence published since 1996. The measure which is centrally placed between neurocybernetics and psychology on the one hand, and axonal properties and microscopic or gross morphology on the other is axonal conduction time. The evidence on this surveyed by Miller (1996a) can be supplemented by a number of 28 Synopsis of the Theory electrophysiological studies showing, as does the RT data, that transmission across the corpus callosum is faster from right-to-left than from left-to-right (11.3.3.). One would also expect that the latency of evoked potential components in the right hemisphere should be less than that in the left hemisphere. Since increased conduction time means increased temporal dispersion amongst a population of axons, and therefore less opportunity for temporal summation in postsynaptic neurons, one would also expect lower amplitude for evoked potentials in left compared to right hemispheres. There have been few attempts at accurate comparison between hemisphere on these measures, but there is a little evidence for these predictions (see for example, 11.4.2.1., on mismatch negativity). 2.5.2. Axonal conduction time and the origin of the “central hypothesis” for the trait abnormalities in schizophrenia. The “central hypothesis” for normal cerebral asymmetry becomes relevant to understanding trait abnormalities in schizophrenia in the following way: A number of the enduring traits in schizophrenia appear to be impairments of functions normally preferred by the right hemisphere. These include the following: impairment compared to normal in perceiving visual patterns such as faces; impairment in motor control by sensory guidance (shown most often with respect to smooth pursuit eye tracking); a marked tendency to lapses in vigilance; impairment in higher-level aspects of language (semantic decoding). In addition, one of the classical symptoms of schizophrenia - referred to as “flattened affect” – can be analyzed in terms of three neuropsychological deficits reduced facial expressiveness, reduced communication by gesture, and reduced “prosody” in vocal expression - all of which are normal functions accomplished better by the right hemisphere. These pieces of evidence are, at this stage, no more than clues linking schizophrenia traits to an abnormality of cerebral asymmetry. However, taken at face value, they allow us to frame an initial hypothesis for the broader range of abnormal traits. As such they have the potential to be truly explanatory – explaining psychological dysfunctions in terms of fundamental biological (i.e. cellular) differences between normal and schizophrenia, just as Miller’s (1996a) central hypothesis allowed explanatory arguments to be constructed linking axonal properties to differences between left and right sides in normal subjects. The “central hypothesis” for schizophrenia-related traits can then be stated as follows, that there is a relative absence of rapidly-conducting corticocortical axons in schizophrenia, compared to normal. Since rapidly-conducting axons are likely to give the normal right hemisphere its special functional properties, one may expect that the enduring trait impairments of schizophrenia will be largely in functions preferred by the normal right hemisphere, although they may not be exclusively covered by this concept. As a broad slogan, one might then capture the trait impairments of schizophrenia in the phrase “two left hemispheres”. This has the additional implication that sometimes there may be an exaggeration of functions normally attributed to the left hemisphere. To introduce the full exposition of the theory of schizophrenia traits, a list of these traits is given in Table 2.1. Two points are worth noting: First, they are not all impairments: For instance, under some circumstances, the excessive awareness of associations may be an advantage. Second, the last in the list of traits (“vulnerability to psychotic breakdowns”) raises what has already been identified as one of the deepest problems for a comprehensive theory of schizophrenia. Added to this list, there is much other evidence to be explained by a comprehensive theory, including psychophysiological evidence (notably that using methods of clinical electrophysiology), and much morphological evidence. The whole range of topics is explored step-by-step in Chapters 612. Table 2.1. List of Schizophrenia Traits Impairment in perception of Gestalts (in visual, auditory and somesthetic modalities) Impairment in motor control by sensory guidance Impairment in simultaneous motor coordination of many effectors Impairment in rapid coordination between the two hemispheres Impairment in sustained attention/vigilance Impairment in semantic decoding of incoming language (sentences and longer) Impairment in planning of semantically-coherent outgoing discourse (part of “thought disorder”) Super-normal awareness of semantic and other associations Excessive vulnerability to distractions in various sensory modalities, and to “sensory overload” Impairment in tasks where multiple sources of information have to be dealt with Impairment in tasks involving shift of attentional focus Impairment in acquisition of information from lists, etc (“rote learning”) Vulnerability to psychotic breakdowns 29 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia It should be stated here that the two “central hypotheses” (respectively for normal cerebral asymmetry and for schizophrenia), carry the assumption that axonal conduction time, in the adult, is a stable “structural” aspect of brain organization. However, there is evidence that the degree of myelination in hemispheric white matter, is influenced by the prevailing environment. For instance, environmental enrichment leads to increase in myelination or calibre of axons in the corpus callosum in rats (Juraska and Kopcik, 1988) and increased size of the callosum in monkeys (Sánchez et al, 1998). In humans, diffusion tensor imaging (see Chapt. 12), has shown that the degree of myelination inferred in hemispheric white matter tracts in pianists is positively correlated with the number of hours spent practicing in previous years (Bengtsson et al, 2005). These findings suggest that adaptive plasticity affects not only synapses but also the degree of myelination of axons. Evidence currently available suggests that such processes influence the degree of myelination during development when myelination is not yet complete. It has not yet shown that such processes in mature adults lead either to further myelination or to demyelination, in an adaptive sense. Therefore, there is as yet no basis for questioning the assumption that axonal conduction time in adults is a stable “structural” feature of hemispheric organization. Developmental aspects of myelination in relation to schizophrenia are discussed in Chapter 12. 2.5.3. System adopted for presenting theory and reviewing evidence about trait abnormalities (Chapters 612). With such a large amount of evidence to be reviewed, it is necessary to bring some system to its presentation. The series of detailed reviews of empirical evidence on trait aspects of schizophrenia is covered in Chapters 6-12. In the remaining subsections of the present chapter, summaries of each block of empirical data will be presented, but without detailed referencing except to the later chapters where each detailed review appears. Thus, the remaining sections of the present chapter should allow the reader to get a synoptic overview of the complete theory of the trait aspects. In Chapters 6-12 evidence of psychological abnormality will be dealt with before that on brain function and morphology. This is because the primary way in which the concept of schizophrenia has arisen is from psychological rather than biological brain abnormalities. The morphological evidence, taken by itself, is difficult to interpret without ambiguity and so is left to a later stage of the argument, when some of the emerging picture has already been clarified. However, with that emerging picture as a context, the morphological evidence includes more direct tests of the “central hypothesis” than does much of the functional evidence. The functional evidence to be considered includes both purely psychological data and psychophysiological data (such as studies using electroencephalography). Some areas of evidence (such as the detailed study of eye movements) cross between these two disciplines. The main functional subdivisions to be covered are as follows: Perception (in major sensory modalities, and also including subsections dealing with inter-hemispheric and inter-modal interactions with sensory stimuli)(Chapter 7); Motor control (Chapter 8); Vigilance, mental association, selective attention, short-term memory, rote learning, and shift of attention (Chapter 9); Language and Communication (Chapter 10). Chapter 11 deals with findings using EEG, evoked potential and some metabolic/blood-flow scanning methodologies. Chapter 12 is a long and complex one, in which brain morphology is discussed from various aspects. In introducing most sections within Chapters 6-12, aspects of normal function or structure need to be reviewed, before discussing the abnormalities in schizophrenia. These introductory sections often include some expansion of the theory already published about normal cerebral asymmetry, in the case of paradigms not already considered by Miller (1996a). In some cases this discussion also shows that the “central hypothesis” for schizophrenia traits needs elaboration. Results inconsistent with the hypothesis are not ignored in presenting the theory. Chapter 13 is a final summary chapter, using the whole body of information to give a synoptic view of the overall concept of schizophrenia which emerges. It makes explicit the implications of the theory for classification of disorders in the schizophrenia spectrum, and concludes with some of the implications of the theory for individual healthcare and public health measures related to schizophrenia. Many data are reported in empirical studies about correlations between different trait measures used to differentiate normal subjects and those with schizophrenia. However, correlations can arise as a result of causal relations which may range from being quite direct to very indirect. Specifically, in relating functional abnormalities to the theory based on the relative absence of rapidly-conducting corticocortical axons, correlations between trait measures may arise because they are different manifestations of abnormality in the same axonal pathway, or because the conduction properties of different cortico-cortical pathways are themselves correlated (due perhaps to a common genetic influence). As a result of these uncertainties comprehensive review of all reported correlations is not attempted here. Correlative data will be drawn upon when specific questions need to be resolved (e.g. about whether two aspects of functional abnormality arise from the same or from different mechanisms). Nevertheless, because of the problem of interpreting correlative data, they will not be called upon to bear the whole burden of proving a particular point in the theory. Moreover, the strength of an argument based on correlation depends on the value of the correlation coefficient in individual studies, and the consistency of correlation across studies. Therefore, arguments from correlations become more relevant, and are given more attention, when a number of studies have assessed correlation between similar pairs of variables, and give similar results across studies. In this context, an important focal point for discussion of trait abnormalities is the association and dissociation of symptoms of schizophrenia as encountered in the clinic, and as revealed by the statistical method called factor analysis. This topic is covered prior to discussion of evidence obtained with experimental methods, in the short Chapter 6. The important conclusion emerging from this chapter is that the symptoms of chronic schizophrenia fall into three groups, 30 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia statistically independent each other. Following Liddle (1987) these three factors are referred to here as Psychomotor poverty (a collective term for negative symptoms), Disorganization (a symptom group dominated by thought disorder) and Reality distortion (a collective term for symptoms related to actual psychosis). Obviously a major conceptual distinction for the present book is that between “active psychosis” and the enduring traits. While this distinction is based on theory, in reviewing evidence by which the theory is to be evaluated, it is necessary to have other independent methods of making the distinction empirically. Clearly “trait abnormalities” should be present in well-stabilized patients who do not show psychotic symptoms. However, as discussed in Chapter 5 (see also 2.4.), psychotic symptoms may be sustained in attenuated form as “cognitive habits” by memory processes. Therefore the presence of psychotic symptoms is not in itself a sure criterion for recognizing “active psychosis”. Ideally, the distinction should be made by closer assessment of the dynamic aspects of the psychotic symptoms (e.g. the time course of their formation, persistence and extinction). A recently-devised rating scale allows such assessment to be made on individual patients (Chouinard and Miller, 1999a,b). Since this has been introduced only recently, a less rigorous distinction must be made pragmatically to make sense of the existing literature: In classifying the state and stage of illness of patient groups, it is likely that one is dealing with an active psychotic process if there is a specific statement that patients are “floridly psychotic” or in “acute exacerbation” or are “recent admissions”. When patients are described as suffering from “acute schizophrenia”, this does not clearly indicate “active psychosis”, because the usual definition of this term, especially in older papers, has been “duration of illness two years or less”. Likewise a phrase such as “acute illness, attending day hospital” does not identify “active psychosis”. In some chronic cases of schizophrenia, especially in patients in long-term institutional care, psychotic symptoms may not have responded to drug treatment, this being the reason for continuing in-patient care. In such cases, if psychotic symptoms are present it is likely that they do represent an active and persisting process of psychosis, rather than a “memory effect” lasting from previous periods of active psychosis. However, it is acknowledged that rigorous separation between chronic cases where active psychosis persists, and other chronic cases where psychotic symptoms endure merely as a memory effect is not possible in many published reports. Apart from exclusion of active psychosis in schizophrenia patients there are other ways in which particular impairments can be identified as enduring traits: The trait abnormalities found in stabilized patients should also be present (perhaps less severely) in subjects identified as having personality variants related to schizophrenia (“schizotypy”, or “schizotypal personality disorder”), without clear evidence of active psychosis. Similarly, the same traits should be present in high-risk adolescents (offspring of those with the schizophrenia diagnosis), or other FDR of schizophrenia probands. In each section reviewing empirical data in Chapters 6-12, material will be covered in approximately the same sequence. First, before considering comparisons between normal and 31 schizophrenia, it will usually be necessary to consider normal aspects of function or morphology by themselves, including evidence on normal lateralization. In addition, in dealing with each aspect of function or morphology a preliminary account may be needed of the methodologies used in that context. After these preliminaries, the basic findings comparing normal with schizophrenia will be presented, including details of right- vs left-sided effects, where relevant. To clarify the status of these basic findings, evidence will then be considered on possible confounds from the immediate effects of medication, or of psychotic exacerbation. The extent to which each functional abnormality is present in stablymaintained patients can thus be ascertained. Further evidence that one is considering true traits comes from considering the extent to which the relevant impairment is present in different subtypes of schizophrenia, in later stages or more severe variants of the illness, in, subtypes defined by prognosis, in schizophrenia-related personality variants, and in FDR. In addition available evidence of functional impairment or morphological abnormality in disorders other than, but related to schizophrenia (including the overlap with affective disorders) is considered. In those areas of abnormality which have been most intensively investigated, there is often evidence on all the above topics. However, for some of the less-well studied aspects of function and morphology the limited evidence available document only the basic findings in schizophrenia. 2.6. Factor structure of enduring symptoms of schizophrenia. From around 1980 it became common to divide the symptoms of schizophrenia into “positive” and “negative” groups, the former abnormal by the presence of psychological features not normally present, the latter being abnormal because normal psychological features were absent. However, factor analysis of the symptoms of chronic schizophrenia revealed a more complex subdivision of symptoms (Chapter 6). There are at least three, and perhaps more symptom factors, each statistically independent of each other. The first two of these were given the names “Reality distortion” and “Psychomotor Poverty” by Liddle (1987), the former including many positive symptoms the latter most negative symptoms. The third factor was called “Disorganization” whose most characteristic symptoms were some of those included in the rather imprecise term “thought disorder”. This three-factor analysis of the symptoms of chronic schizophrenia has been widely replicated, although more complex factorizations sometimes emerge, especially when a wider body of symptoms is used than in Liddle’s analysis. It is found regardless of the stage of illness, or the presence/absence of medication, although scores on the three factors are affected by these influences. These factor analyses have been used to subdivide schizophrenia into mutually exclusive subtypes. However, more properly, factor analysis defines statistically independent or “orthogonal” dimensions for description of symptoms, without inferences necessarily being made about how patients fall into discrete subgroups. Given this, the results of factor analyses raise important theoretical issues, serving as pointers to separate mechanisms Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia underlying each of the independent factors. The component symptoms of the Reality Distortion factor are most (but not all) of those recognized as aspects of active psychosis. That they make up a coherent factor in chronic schizophrenia can easily be understood from the theory of psychosis developed in Chapter 5, since many psychotic symptoms (especially delusions of various sorts) persist as a “cognitive habit” or “memory effect” long after the most acute aspects of psychosis have remitted. This factor may also have its origin (in part) in active psychotic symptoms shown by patients who are refractory to treatment with antipsychotic medication. The other two major factors (Psychomotor poverty and Disorganization), are enduring traits in a more fundamental sense than is the Reality distortion factor. The underlying neurodynamic processes, and the reasons why they are statistically independent, emerge as the evidence and theory of these traits is discussed (Chapters 7-10). 2.7. Abnormalities of sensory perception in schizophrenia. Chapter 7 deals with perception in schizophrenia in the three main modalities - vision, hearing and somatic sensation (including proprioception). Olfactory sense is dealt with in a different Sect. (9.4.2.4.). There is almost no evidence comparing normal subjects and those with schizophrenia on taste or vestibular sense. In the three main sensory modalities, any abnormalities in schizophrenia are set against the background of normal perceptual processes. These include the integration of intensity over time (for short stimuli - up to a few 100 msec) and lateral differences in perceptual capability. In general the right hemisphere is superior for integration of Gestalts or spatial patterns, all of whose components are present together in the same moment, while the left is better for sensory patterns extended briefly in time. In the visual sense two additional normal aspects of perception need to be borne in mind - the distinction at the subcortical level between transient and sustained channels, and that within the cortical visual areas between the so-called dorsal and ventral streams of processing. 2.7.1. Visual perception in schizophrenia. In the visual sense, many of the most precise tests of perception use very brief (tachistoscopic) stimuli. In nonlateralized tests of this sort (7.2.2.), there is abundant evidence in schizophrenia of impairment in functions normally giving a right hemisphere advantage. In particular, in schizophrenia a stimulus needs to be of longer duration than normal to be recognized (lengthened “critical stimulus duration”), and, once a perceptual trace is formed, it appears to persist longer than normal. As a result, masking stimuli can prevent assimilation of perception for a longer-than-normal period post-stimulus in schizophrenia. The contrast in this respect between schizophrenia and normal is similar to that between the left and right hemispheres (respectively) within normal subjects. These abnormalities indicate a relative sluggishness of visual processing in schizophrenia, which can be explained on the assumption that axonal pathways conduct more slowly than normal and so produce greater-than-normal temporal dispersion of visual signals as they are distributed in the cortical pathways. In some tests, such as those of subliminal perception, subjects with schizophrenia appear to be better than normal. There is also differential preservation, despite overall impairment, for some functions, such as perception of local as opposed to global visual patterns. Likewise when much information needs to be derived from a brieflypresented stimulus array, patients with schizophrenia are minimally impaired, or even supernormal, because the perceptual trace lasts longer than normal, allowing more extensive processing than normal before the trace fades. It is also be predicted that when components of a stimulus presented at slightly different times need to be integrated, schizophrenia patients would be able to accomplish this for greater temporal separations than normal subjects. Evidence presented to date does not support this prediction. Nevertheless, overall, the functions which are relatively preserved or supernormal are those normally accomplished better by the left hemisphere, specializations which are favored by temporal dispersion of visual signals. There is some indication that functions normally performed by the dorsal cortical stream, such as rapid visual location of a stimulus, are impaired more than those preferred by the ventral stream of cortical visual processing. While some of this evidence could be interpreted as indicating impairment of the transient visual system at a subcortical level, the evidence is more parsimoniously viewed as showing a relative loss of rapidly-conducting axons within cortical pathways. This idea fits the tendency for particular impairment in functions mediated both in the right hemisphere and in the dorsal visual stream. Indeed, for one function of the dorsal stream - detection of motion in slowly-moving stimuli the evidence fits well the idea that there is loss of rapidlyconducting axons in a specific pathway, that from area V1 to area MT (V5), which is normally specialized as rapidly conducting. Some of the above impairments (lengthened critical stimulus duration for detection, prolonged visual backward masking) are documented as being correlated with the negative symptom group. However, there is no direct correspondence between these symptoms and the laboratory measures, since negative symptoms are expressions more of behavior than of perception. When lateralized visual tests are performed (7.2.3.), with right-hemisphere-preferred material it is generally found that right hemisphere (left field) performance is impaired, while left hemisphere (right field) performance remains more intact. As a result, there is a loss of the normal asymmetry. With lateralized presentation of left-hemisphere-preferred material, there is often no major impairment in schizophrenia. When there is, left hemisphere impairment is usually accompanied by right hemisphere impairment for the same material. This may reflect that fact that, normally, optimal function of the left hemisphere depends on “boosting” from the more easilyactivated right hemisphere. In schizophrenia, along with impairment of the right hemisphere, this boosting of the left hemisphere appears to be lost (7.2.5.). In non-tachistoscopic visual tests (e.g. in perception of facial identity or facial emotion) subjects with schizophrenia are generally impaired (7.2.4.). Such tests also assess functions normally preferred by the right hemisphere, but exact interpretation is confounded 32 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia by several factors other than perception. Overall, there is compelling evidence from visual studies that functions normally preferred by the right hemisphere are impaired in schizophrenia. 2.7.2. Auditory perception in schizophrenia. Detection thresholds for maintained auditory stimuli are generally higher than normal in schizophrenia, more consistently so for left ear/right hemisphere stimuli than for right ear/left hemisphere ones (7.3.1.). The left hemisphere is more variable than the right, with impairment in the former perhaps being related to active psychosis. In schizophrenia integration of auditory perception takes longer to be complete than in normal subjects, this being reflected in a steeper-thannormal fall of threshold intensity as stimulus duration is increased. As with visual perception, this suggests that convergence of signals can occur across a wider-than-normal time interval, as expected when rapidly-conducting axons are substituted by a range of more slowly-conducting ones. Auditory stimuli with relatively slow acoustic transients (similar to the prosody in speech) are normally preferred by the right hemisphere, and the evidence is consistent that perception of such stimuli is impaired in schizophrenia (7.3.2.). Perception of sounds with faster transients (such as the rapid sequence of acoustic events which makes up a consonant speech sound) are normally preferred by the left hemisphere. Contrary to expectation from the slogan “two left hemispheres”, perception of such sounds is also sometimes found to be impaired in schizophrenia. However, this impairment is limited to subjects experiencing auditory hallucinations (7.3.2.). In dichotic listening tasks (competing CV stimuli to the two ears), studies of schizophrenia generally report loss of normal asymmetry, if the experimental design limits auditory processing to purely perceptual factors. This result is ambiguous since it could reflect either relative impairment of the left hemisphere or relative lack of impairment in the right. A single lateralized study using monaural stimuli favors the latter idea, suggesting that the right hemisphere in schizophrenia may have some of the specialization of the normal left. However, this may not be the whole explanation of abnormalities of auditory perception in schizophrenia, since the loss of right ear advantage has been associated in several studies with presence of auditory hallucinations. In dichotic tasks with a working memory/vigilance component, an increased right ear advantage is commonly seen, especially if subjects are actively psychotic. This may reflect the fact that, despite a general trend to impairment, the left hemisphere can function normally if overall levels of activation are high. The impairment in auditory perception for lefthemisphere-preferred stimuli, the loss of right-ear advantage in dichotic listening tasks, and (especially) the association between each of these and the presence of auditory verbal hallucinations, leads one to consider the mechanisms behind such symptoms. Unlike other hallucinations, auditory verbal ones (“hearing voices”) are in part an enduring trait, not entirely eliminated by antipsychotic medications (5.5.). Theory is developed in Sect. 7.3.4. based on the supposition that normal perception of speech sounds depends on integration of representations of the acoustic aspect of a 33 speech sound with that of the vocal motor program required to produce the same sound. This in turn requires rapid coordination of cell assemblies spread over relatively distant regions of cortex (including both Wernicke’s and Broca’s areas). If there is a relative absence of rapidly conducting cortico-cortical axons (our “central hypothesis” for schizophrenia), this widespread integration of cell assemblies may fail. As a result, internal speech (“verbal thoughts”) can no longer make up integrated perceptuo-motor abstractions, but may be experienced as more similar to sensory perceptions, that is, ones originating from an external source. This hypothesis for verbal auditory hallucinations has definite morphological implications, which are considered in Sect. 7.3.4., summarized also in Sect. 12.8. and Sect. 2.13.6. of the present chapter. 2.7.3. Somatic perception in schizophrenia. In schizophrenia, a number of tests of somatosensory perception show impairment (Sect. 7.4.). In lateralized tests (such as the “quality extinction test”) an excess of left-sided extinction has been reported several times. Since this abnormal asymmetry correlates with impairment in other tests of right hemisphere function, and since another right hemisphere function - stereognosis - is often found to be impaired in schizophrenia, it probably reflects impaired right hemisphere rather than enhanced left hemisphere perceptual abilities. Studies of tactile discrimination during active psychotic states tend to find left rather than right hemisphere impairment, and this normalizes as treatment takes effect. The lateralization of abnormality in active psychotic states thus seems to be in different directions comparing auditory and somesthetic modalities. 2.8. Interhemispheric transfer. and cross-modal In each of the three major sensory modalities there is evidence for reduced or impaired coordination between the two hemispheres, although there is also a number of studies which fail to find this. In the visual sense this has been detected as impairment in matching stimuli presented in opposite visual fields, in loss of bilateral advantage when the same stimulus is present in both fields, in reduced interference when different stimuli are presented in opposite fields, and in reduced right-to-left transfer involved in rapid naming of color stimuli presented in left fields. In the auditory sense, loss of bilateral advantage in comprehension of speech is well documented. In the somesthetic sense, studies involving matching of shapes presented to each hand is impaired in schizophrenia, especially when “nonsense” shapes are used which cannot be recoded in linguistic form. There are many studies which do not show such impairments. However, overall, when impaired inter-hemispheric coordination is seen, it is in circumstances where rapid coordination is required. The impairment in inter-hemispheric coordination can thus best be interpreted as due to slower-than-normal callosal conduction, a probable reflection of a relative absence of rapidly-conducting callosal axons. A single study in the visual sense directly demonstrates increased callosal conduction time in schizophrenia. Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia Slower-than-normal cortico-cortical transmission should also lead to impairment in coordination between different sensory modalities, since the cortical regions for the different modalities are relatively distant from each other. There is some evidence for this, mainly concerning coordination between the visual and the vestibular or proprioceptive senses. There are many predictions about other combinations of sensory systems awaiting evaluation in this area. 2.9. Abnormalities of motor coordination in schizophrenia. The best-known normal aspect of cerebral asymmetry in the domain of motor control is handedness. There is considerable evidence that in schizophrenia non-righthandedness is more common than normal, and there also appears to be a shift away from right-eyedness and footedness. However, many people with the diagnosis are clearly right-handed. There are many problems with obtaining estimates of anomalous handedness which are precise and objective. Thus the evidence of an excess of anomalous handedness in schizophrenia is not robust enough to become a major consideration for theory development. In more detail, motor control can be subdivided into two varieties, closed-loop control, under moment-by-moment sensory guidance, and open-loop control, preplanned a few hundred msec in advance. In normal subjects the former is carried out better in the right hemisphere, presumably because of more rapid sensory-motor feedback, the latter by the left hemisphere, presumably because of a richer repertoire of long axonal delay lines, used for coding delays in the “plan”. A number of studies of sensory-motor closed-loop control have been conducted in subjects with schizophrenia. In the form of visuo-manual control it is clear that schizophrenia patients are impaired, suggesting sluggish sensory-motor feedback, while there is little evidence of impairment in preplanned open-loop manual control. In addition, the synergy of several parts of the motor apparatus in simultaneous action (a motor “Gestalt”), normally coordinated by the right hemisphere, shows impairment in schizophrenia. These results support the central hypothesis for schizophrenia of a relative absence of rapidlyconducting cortico-cortical axons, hypothetically typical of the normal right hemisphere. With these results as a background, it is likely that the loss of asymmetry in handedness in schizophrenia arises because the right hemisphere comes to have characteristics normally typical of the normal left hemisphere. There is some direct evidence that the left hand in schizophrenia is superior to that in normal subjects in tasks normally preferred by the left hemisphere (right hand). 2.9.1. Eye tracking. In the first half of the twentieth century, abnormalities of eye tracking were reported several times in schizophrenia (a.k.a. “dementia praecox”)(7.4.1.). Systematic study of this did not start until a seminal paper of Holzman et al (1973) who reported an excess of velocity arrests and of “catch-up saccades” during tracking of continuously-moving targets. A large literature on eye tracking in schizophrenia has accumulated since then. To interpret such evidence, mechanisms underlying eye tracking in normal subjects must first be considered. 2.9.1.1. Physiology of normal eye tracking. Eye movements can be divided into two main types (7.4.4.1.). Saccades are rapid step-like movements which succeed in “catching” on the fovea the image of an object moving in a similar step-like fashion. In contrast, smooth pursuit eye movements (SPEM) succeed in matching eye movement to continuous movement of the target. SPEM is found only in primates. Saccades are of several types. Those which occur to supplement SPEM (mainly catch-up saccades [CUSs]) are of most interest in relation to schizophrenia. SPEM reflects sensory guidance of eye movement by visual stimuli. However, unlike visuo-manual control (considered above) the control is exerted largely by disparity in the respective velocities of eye and target, with lesser effects achieved as a result of position disparity. Steady eye fixation also involves feedback control by visual stimuli, but in this case, control is entirely by position disparity. In addition to control of eye movement by sensory guidance, there are mechanisms (referred to as “velocity memory”) which tend to sustain eye movement at the current velocity, at least for a few 100 msec. Furthermore, predictive or anticipatory control is possible, and has an influence on both SPEM and saccades. CUSs occur when the current velocity and position disparity predict that eye and target trajectories will not intersect in the next 180 msec. The combination of SPEM and CUSs, guided either by sensory feedback or by prediction ensures that normally both velocity and position of the eyes match those of the target quite well. Movement of a visual image with respect to the retina is detected in cortical area MT, and more complex whole-field patterns of image movement are represented in area MST (7.4.4.3.). These areas are involved in control of SPEM, the former in the initial phase of movement, the latter during SPEM maintenance. However, the cortical area most directly involved in generating the signals for change of eye velocity is the frontal eye field (FEF)(7.4.4.3.). Damage to this area impairs SPEM gain as well as predictive and anticipatory control of eye tracking. Lesions to any of the above three areas fail to prevent corrective (catch-up) saccades. Hence, the impairment of SPEM gain after lesions in FEF is compensated by increased CUS frequency. Since these CUSs are usually accurate, the predictive computations in themselves are probably intact after such lesions. The “velocity memory” referred to above depends on mechanisms in cerebellum and brainstem. Since both SPEM and CUS involve feedback control by visual signals, cortico-cortical pathways are likely to be involved, whose conduction time will influence the speed and accuracy of eye tracking. A variety of such pathways could be suggested, that from MST to FEF being probably most important for feedback control by velocity disparity. The fact that feedback control of the eyes tracking a moving stimulus is faster than that of eye fixation may be explained by the unusual rapidity of conduction in the pathway from V1 to MT (the area primarily responsible for detecting velocity of image movement over the retina)(7.4.4.4.). 34 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia 2.9.1.2. Eye tracking in schizophrenia. From the central hypothesis of relative absence of rapidlyconducting cortico-cortical axons, a number of predictions can be made (8.4.5.1.). The different predictions interact with one another, so it is difficult to evaluate them individually. Overall, however, it is predicted from theory that eye tracking and visual fixation in schizophrenia will be less accurate than normal, gain for tracking constant-velocity targets will be below normal, and latency for eyes to reach target velocity at the start of movement (and when velocity changes) will be greater than normal. In addition catch-up saccades, though normal in themselves, should occur with excessive frequency as a corrective response to the primary abnormality. Considerable evidence (8.4.5.2-8.2.5.4) supports each of these predictions. Abnormalities in SPEM tend to be associated with negative symptoms, although this is clearer for schizotypal personality disorder (SPD) than for schizophrenia itself (8.8.). Correlations with positive symptoms or symptoms of the Disorganization factor are inconsistent between studies. CUSs compensating for low pursuit gain use a variety of strategies (different combinations of increased frequency and amplitude), but the mechanisms generating CUSs appear to be normal. The theory developed relating normal cerebral asymmetry to motor control (Miller 1996a [Chapts 8 and 9]) suggests that the left hemisphere is superior to the right in predictive or anticipatory control. Similar reasoning suggests that in schizophrenia such control should be better than normal. In investigations of eye movement there is indeed substantial evidence for this: Programming of eye movements appears to be planned further ahead (by ~60 msec) than in normal subjects, a difference readily explained in terms of a richer repertoire of cortico-cortical delay lines. There is also a suggestion that anticipatory saccades are more frequent than normal in some schizophrenia patients. However, not all evidence fits the prediction, and the circumstances in which supernormal predictive control of eye movements occurs is not yet well defined. Nevertheless this evidence is important, because, like some of the evidence on perception, it refutes the idea that abnormality in schizophrenia is merely a nonspecific deficit. From theory it is predicted that impairment in normal functions in schizophrenia should apply more to right than left hemisphere, since the functions showing impairment are held to depend on the rapidly-conducting pathways typical of the normal right hemisphere. Specifically it would be expected that right hemisphere control of SPEM (vis: in rightward tracking) would be more severely abnormal than left hemisphere control (in leftward tracking)(8.4.7.). This prediction is not well supported by available evidence: What evidence there is finds either no asymmetry of the impairment in tracking in schizophrenia, or greater impairment for leftward than rightward tracking. However, in accord with theory, several studies find that for control of predictive eye movements in schizophrenia, the right hemisphere acquires some of the special ability of the normal left hemisphere. One further abnormal aspect of asymmetrical eye movements remains unexplained. Some saccades have unusually short latency (“express saccades”), and are thought to arise from loss of inhibitory control of the prefrontal cortex over the 35 superior colliculus. These are more common than normal in schizophrenia, especially when targets are presented in the right rather than the left visual fields. Despite the abnormal features, many aspects of eye movement are normal in schizophrenia (8.4.8.). Brainstem reflexes controlling eye movement (vestibulo-ocular, oculocephalic, optokinetic) are normal. Refixation saccades (locating the image on the fovea after a step target movement) sometimes show abnormalities in amplitude or velocity, but the correlation of these two remains normal, suggesting that saccadic control is basically normal. SPEM impairment in schizophrenia can be reduced somewhat by strategies to focus attention on the target, but significant impairment remains even after these strategies have been employed. In normal subjects, distraction by irrelevant stimuli does not accurately reproduce the impairment in schizophrenia. Thus this impairment is not simply a byproduct of impairment of focused attention (8.4.9.1.). Many studies have concluded that the SPEM abnormality in schizophrenia is not a consequence of neuroleptic medication (8.4.9.2.). The pursuit abnormality is also not reproduced in normal subjects by stimulants, even in cases of stimulant-induced psychosis. SPEM abnormality is not associated with active psychosis, and may even be reduced in this state (8.4.9.3.). A number of studies have examined the effects of anesthetics, especially ethanol (8.4.9.2.). These produce impairments somewhat similar to those in schizophrenia. Dissociative anesthetics (NMDA antagonists) reduce SPEM gain and open-loop acceleration, and increase the frequency of CUSs in normal subjects. They also make eye fixation unsteady. These impairments are similar to those in schizophrenia. However, the slowed latency characteristic of schizophrenia is not reproduced by NMDA antagonists. Tardive dyskinesia is associated with irregularities of eye movements which are distinguishable from the tracking impairment of schizophrenia. The eye tracking abnormality and the unsteadiness of fixation in schizophrenia (like that for visuo-manual control) fit well the predictions based on the relative absence of rapidly conducting axons (8.5.). Likewise the relative intactness (or even super-normality) of predictive tracking accords well with theory. The tracking abnormality is not the same as that produced by lesions in any of a number of relevant cortical areas, and is not exactly reproduced by blockade of glutamate receptors involved in cortico-cortical transmission. The best parallel to the abnormality in schizophrenia may be eye tracking in normal children, where it is also likely to be explained in terms of a relative absence of rapidly-conducting cortico-cortical axons. Alternative hypotheses have been proposed for the abnormalities in schizophrenia, including the idea that there is a loss of inhibitory control over a variety of eye movements. However, these hypotheses do not give such a comprehensive account of the relevant phenomena, and are not framed in terms of fundamental (e.g. axonal) differences between normal subjects and those with schizophrenia. Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia 2.9.1.3. Eye tracking and inheritance of schizophrenia. Eye tracking is under substantial genetic control: Studies of normal twins show strong concordance between members of MZ but not DZ twin pairs. In MZ twins discordant for schizophrenia abnormal eye tracking shows strong concordance, stronger in most studies than the schizophrenia itself. Thus SPEM disorder may be a more certain guide to the genetic diathesis underlying schizophrenia than the manifest disorder. Many (but not all) studies of FDR of schizophrenia probands show SPEM dysfunction, although it may be less severe than in the probands, and minor qualitative differences from the probands have been described. No clear picture is currently discernible on whether different classes of FDR are more prone to SPEM dysfunction. Several studies, in populations of either schizophrenia probands or their FDR have shown bimodal distributions in SPEM measures, and this has been suggested as indicating a sharply-categorical genetic factor underlying this abnormality. However, there are serious flaws in this inference. It has nevertheless led to the postulate that the SPEM disorder is controlled by a single dominant gene. Formal genetic models have been developed, combining this idea with that of different penetrances for the SPEM disorder and schizophrenia itself (higher for the former than the latter). While these could account for several aspects of inheritance of these two related traits, they fail to account for the near-50% MZ twin concordance of schizophrenia itself. The idea of a single gene, or a single gene of major importance is not consistent with whole-genome studies (3.6.2.). presented amongst distracters. This is the case whether the distracters are presented simultaneously (e.g. on a sheet of paper; 9.2.1.), or sequentially in an extended series, usually of visual stimuli (9.2.2.). Many studies of target detection in extended series have been reported in the various versions of the Continuous Performance Test (CPT). Some of these versions also involve a degree of manipulation of stimuli within working memory (WM), but the basic findings in schizophrenia are similar whether or not WM is involved. Performance may be impaired in the short term by neuroleptic administration, but tends to improve with prolonged treatment. Even in well-stabilized medicated patients, performance is impaired compared to normal subjects. This impairment correlates with presence of negative symptoms or scores on the Psychomotor poverty factor, but not with scores on the Reality distortion factor, and inconsistently with Disorganization factor scores. A lesser degree of impairment is present in FDR of schizophrenia probands. Impairment is also found in affective disorder including both mania and depression, more so in psychotic depression, but even during remission. Impairment is also found in schizophreniaspectrum personality disorder (as defined both psychometrically and clinically). The impairment in target detection tasks implies a reduction of the ability to selectively bring particular cell assemblies close to ignition threshold, and to sustained them above threshold. This in turn is predictable if there is a relative absence of rapidly conducting cortico-cortical axons, with increased temporal dispersion of signals and a reduced degree of post-synaptic summation. 2.9.1.4. Eye tracking impairment in conditions related to schizophrenia. SPEM abnormality does not differ between clinical subtypes of schizophrenia, though it may be more prevalent in illnesses which, clinically, are more severe. It occurs more commonly than normal in subjects with personality characteristics related to schizophrenia. This is clearer for the clinically-determined schizotypal personality disorder (SPD) than for psychometrically-determined schizotypy. Sometimes the SPEM impairment in SPD is found to be limited to subjects who also have a positive family history for schizophrenia, or who are impaired sufficiently to merit treatment. SPEM abnormality occurs in affective disorder, including both bipolar and unipolar disorder. It is difficult to compare the severity or prevalence of the SPEM disorder between schizophrenia, and bipolar or unipolar affective disorders because of confounding state variables. Lithium treatment impairs SPEM, but affective patients have an impairment regardless of this. FDR of affective probands, like those of schizophrenia probands probably do have increased SPEM abnormality, although quantitative measures rather than the less sensitive categorical ratings are needed to show this. 2.10.2. Reaction-time crossover. In reaction time (RT) tests, normal subjects benefit from an advance warning signal if it occurs at a regular time, up to 20 sec ahead of the imperative signal. Subjects with schizophrenia do so too, but only for shorter preparatory intervals. As preparatory interval is lengthened, RT with irregular warning stimuli may actually become less than that with regular warning stimuli, giving a “cross-over” in the plot of preparatory interval vs RT (9.2.4.). This commonly occurs at shorter preparatory intervals in schizophrenia than in normal subjects (9.2.4.2.). Two processes appear to contribute to the RT cross-over effect (9.2.4.2.). The benefit from a warning stimulus if it is regularly timed is presumably an indication that activity in a cell assembly activated by the warning stimulus can be transferred to that activated by the imperative stimulus, so speeding RT. In schizophrenia, relative absence of rapidlyconducting axons, with consequent temporal dispersion of signals, impairs the sustaining of activity in the first cell assembly, so that the RT benefit from regularly-timed warning signals disappears at shorter-than-normal preparatory intervals. In addition to this, when preparatory interval is lengthened over successive trials, RT is speeded. This effect occurs to more-than-normal degree in schizophrenia. In the usual designs of RT cross-over experiments, long preparatory intervals in irregular series are, on average, longer than in preceding trials. This results in RT speeding. This occurs to more-than-normal extent in subjects with schizophrenia, so that, at the longer preparatory intervals, RT in irregular series 2.10. Abnormalities in schizophrenia in the realm of cognitive psychology. 2.10.1. Target detection and vigilance. Persons with schizophrenia are impaired in tasks requiring focused or sustained attention for detection of target stimuli 36 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia becomes less than that for regular series. In terms of neurodynamics, the tentative explanation of this is related to one of the conclusions derived from the evidence on SPEM, namely that anticipatory eye movements can be planned further in advance in schizophrenia than is normally the case (2.8.1.2.). In the RT cross-over paradigm, this could mean that in schizophrenia, better advantage can be taken than in normal subjects of the imperative signal occurring later than expected. In either case, the supernormal preparatory planning can be explained by there being a richer repertoire than normal of long axonal delay lines. Evidence on abnormalities in the RT cross-over paradigm in FDR and disorders related to schizophrenia is not abundant (9.2.4.3.). Available studies show that FDR sometimes show abnormalities similar to, but smaller, than those in schizophrenia. In affective disorder, abnormalities are slight, whether patients are currently depressed, manic or stabilized. Normal subjects scoring high on schizotypy scales show abnormalities of lesser degree than those with schizophrenia. 2.10.3. Associative processes, cognitive inhibition and processing resources in schizophrenia. 2.10.3.1. Associative processes. The idea that people with schizophrenia have an abnormality in the process of mental association has a long history (9.3.1.) and figured prominently in Bleuler’s writings. It has been a matter of debate whether this abnormality consists of disorganization of association, or rather heightened awareness of associations, especially of the more remote ones. For the pioneers, the issue was clouded by their inability to separate aspects of psychosis from true traits. More recently it has become clear that heightened awareness of associations is indeed an enduring trait in schizophrenia, shown in sorting tasks, word association tests and non-verbal assessments of generalization gradients (9.3.2.). Hyperactive processes of association are shown most precisely in modern work on semantic priming (9.3.3.), using tachistoscopic stimuli, where semantically-related primes accelerate RT to target stimuli in lexical decision tasks. At first sight the literature on this has many contradictions, but these are mainly resolved when account is taken of the fact that shortduration primes (less than ~150 msec) are not properly encoded in schizophrenia (see analysis of perceptual processes, in Chapter 7). Therefore, the semantic priming design is a valid test of associative processes only when prime duration is longer than this. Given this complication, semantic hyper-priming is associated with the clinical symptom of thought disorder. Evidence is insufficient to reach conclusions about whether the heightening of associations applies to FDR of schizophrenia probands. Most studies of affective disorder find only a small degree of abnormality, and evidence on schizotypy is too scanty to reach firm conclusions. 2.10.3.2. Cognitive inhibition and reduced “processing resources” in schizophrenia. The mirror image of heightened associative processes in schizophrenia is increased difficulty in shutting out mental images irrelevant to the task requirement (9.3.4.). The pioneers were well aware of this impairment (9.3.4.1.). More recently the impairment has been shown in many studies of 37 distractibility, which is increased in states of active psychosis, and also, but to a lesser extent, in stabilized patients with schizophrenia (9.3.4.2.). Experiments attempting to show impairment in shutting out distracters using tachistoscopic methods (“negative priming”) are not very conclusive, because the predicted lack of negative priming can often be given an alternative explanation: Priming stimuli, with durations less than 150 msec, are not long enough to be properly encoded in subjects with schizophrenia, and may fail to show negative priming for this reason alone (9.3.4.3.). A likely corollary of the increased vulnerability to distraction in schizophrenia is that fewer test items can be handled independently than is normally the case. This corresponds to the psychological finding of reduced “processing resources” for cognitive operations. There is abundant evidence for this in schizophrenia, including a steeper-than-normal gradient for RT as a function of increasing task complexity, and differential impairment in target detection as the complexity of a stimulus array increases. In formal dual task paradigms, subjects with schizophrenia are also differentially impaired, compared to their performance in the various tasks considered singly. Distractibility, reduction of negative priming, or reduction of processing resources tend to be associated with increased scores on the Disorganization factor, or on thought disorder, but not with scores on the Negative symptom factor. 2.10.3.3. Theory: Axonal conduction time in relation to associative processes, cognitive inhibition and processing resources. The three abnormalities considered above - excessive ease of mental association, increased vulnerability to distraction and reduced processing resources - are closely related in that they can all be derived from the same theory based on a relative absence of rapidly conducting cortico-cortical axons, Consider first a cortical network with the normal complement of rapidly conducting axons. When a focus of activity appears in the cortex, it may transmit activity to other sites, and this will occur rapidly and with minimal temporal dispersion. There will then be enough post-synaptic summation for activation of the neurons in the recipient site, followed by strong rebound inhibition. However, in networks where the rapidly conducting axons are fewer in number, replaced by slowly conducting ones, there will be considerable temporal dispersion before signals reach their destination, and consequently less post-synaptic summation, less suprathreshold activation, and less rebound inhibition. Instead there will be a large “subliminal fringe” of subthreshold activation of axons (but not of the post-synaptic neurons). The subliminal fringe, little diminished by rebound inhibition, will be available for summation with subliminal activity from other sources. It therefore represents the capacity of the cortical network for associative processes, as detected, for instance, in semantic priming experiments. In addition stimuli irrelevant to the task in hand cannot be shut out as easily as normal. This is because the cell assemblies representing the target stimuli do not generate such a large surround of inhibition, to suppress awareness of potential distracters. Similarly, if, in schizophrenia, cell assemblies can associate more freely and interfere with one another more than normal, Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia the number of cell assemblies which can function independently will, by the same token, be reduced. This reduction corresponds at the psychological level to the observed reduction in “processing resources” in schizophrenia. The explanation of the ease of association, and vulnerability to distraction is based on an assumption which should not be overlooked: Interactions between cell assemblies will occur only if the cortical network as a whole is in a state of relatively high activation, with the membrane potential of member neurons poised not far below threshold for firing. This assumption is not needed to explain impairments in schizophrenia in other experimental paradigms considered so far: In these cases it is implicit that membrane potential in member neurons is a long way negative of threshold, so that convergent activation of many afferent synapses is needed to fire them. The impairment in schizophrenia then arises because temporal dispersion of the activation in these synapses reduces the degree of postsynaptic summation. This distinction between two classes of impairment follows from a basic bimodality in the operation of the cortex, discussed more fully in Chapter 11, in the context of electroencephalography. The expression of this bimodality as two types of abnormality in experimental studies of schizophrenia may indeed have a counterpart in the symptoms of schizophrenia as documented in the clinic: Negative symptoms (or scores for the Psychomotor poverty factor) correlate with and are probably another expression of the impairments in the cortex when it is at a low level of activation. Thought disorder (or scores for the Disorganization factor) correlate with abnormality in the semantic priming task, and is probably another expression of the abnormal dynamics of the cortex in schizophrenia when activation level is relatively high. 2.10.4. “Short term memory” and “working memory” in schizophrenia. The phrases “short term memory” (STM) and “working memory” (WM) are often used rather inconsistently. In this book the former term is used to emphasize the holding of information “on-line”, and available for further processing for periods of up to one minute. The term “working memory” requires this, but also places emphasis on the manipulation of information held in such an activated form. Given these definitions psychological analysis of STM (following Baddeley9) has revealed two components, the “phonological loop” which copes well with lists of (usually auditory) material, and the “visuospatial sketch pad” which prefers spatial patterns of visual material. Tentatively these correspond respectively to STM functions preferred by the left and right hemispheres. In schizophrenia there is little evidence of impairment in the use of the “phonological loop”, except when distraction tasks are employed during the retention interval (9.4.2.1.). Vulnerability to distraction alone can account for observed impairments. In contrast, impairment in holding visuospatial material “on line”, in the “sketch pad” for STM intervals is impaired in a wider variety of conditions, and is not just a function of vulnerability to distraction 9 Baddeley actually uses the term “working memory”. (9.4.2.2.). These results can be accounted for in terms of the central hypothesis for schizophrenia, that there is a relative absence of rapidly-conducting cortico-cortical axons. The relative intactness of the “phonological loop” indicates that the special functions normally performed by the left hemisphere, such as a preference for verbatim recall of temporal sequences, are not fundamentally affected. Impairment in the “visuospatial sketch pad” indicates that the special function of the normal right hemisphere are compromised, as expected from the hypothesis, assuming that the right hemisphere normally owes its special properties to an abundance of rapidly conducting axons. Under normal circumstances this allows cell assemblies to “ignite” easily and remain for a while in active state without decrement. In schizophrenia these functions are impaired. In this context it is relevant that identification of odors is often impaired in schizophrenia (9.4.2.4.), a fact which cannot be attributed either to the effect of neuroleptics or smoking on olfactory perception. The olfactory sense is unique in that its pathways do not involved relay through the thalamus, and, related to this, do not permit analysis of patterns with fine resolution in time. Representing a particular odor is thus, in neurocybernetic terms, closely similar to representing visuospatial patterns (or a variety of other types of pattern without temporal structure). What evidence there is suggests that olfactory identification is preferred by the right hemisphere in normal subjects. The impairment in schizophrenia thus fits the generalization that righthemisphere-preferred functions are most affected. In tasks involving organization or manipulation of material within STM (the “work” of working memory), people with schizophrenia are substantially impaired, under a wide variety of conditions, and whether the material used is preferred normally by right or left hemispheres (9.4.3.). WM tasks often involve a number of “hidden” steps, and so place great demands on processing resources. That this is the real reason why people with schizophrenia are impaired on WM tasks is shown in a number of studies where performance declines more steeply than normal as the complexity of the WM task increases. Although WM impairment is held by some researchers to be a central feature of schizophrenia, it does not have such importance in the present work, because it is seen to be a compound of several more fundamental impairments, dealt with in earlier chapters. “Working memory” in itself, is not a sufficiently unified concept to be directly related to the basic abnormality proposed here as fundamental to schizophrenia. However, it is a very useful concept in accounting for psychological dysfunction at a higher cognitive level (especially in higher levels of language processing - see Chapter 10). 2.10.5. “Rote” learning in schizophrenia. Learning of material presented without reinforcement (“rote” learning of lists of words, sentences, patterns, or pictures) involves fundamental processes of “learning by stimulus contiguity”. In modern views, this is thought to be mediated in part by Hebbian processes of synaptic modification. However, it is a large jump from the synaptic level to the level of learning experiments conducted in intact humans. To make inferences about fundamental Hebbian 38 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia processes from such experiments, many confounds, at higher levels of organization need to be eliminated or controlled. In learning experiments in humans an important confounding factor is the subject’s ability to organize memoranda in a way which aids retrieval. This is certainly impaired in schizophrenia, presumably as a result of impairment in WM at the time of encoding. However a variety of experimental designs indicate that there is impairment beyond that due to failure of organization (9.5.). These designs include use of learning tasks where there is minimal possibility for organization of memoranda, measurement of retention under conditions where this plays little part (recognition, or cued recall, rather than uncued recall), or co-variation of recall scores for scores on independent tests of organization within WM. Furthermore, when learning curves are plotted, it is usually found that schizophrenia patients require more trials to criterion than normal subjects, a finding not usually explained by impaired organization of material. Apart from the process of learning, there is no evidence that long-term retention is impaired in schizophrenia, except in severely disabled longterm inpatients. Overall, there is a substantial case to be made that there is an impairment in the fundamental Hebbian process of learning. The theoretical significance of this arises from the fact that recruitment of Hebbian processes of synaptic modification depends on convergence of the influence of several synapses within a single neuron, much as does the actual firing of the post-synaptic neuron, and the “integration time” appears to be similar. Therefore, when there is a relative absence of rapidly-conducting corticocortical neurons, with resultant increase of temporal dispersion of signals generated by a phasic stimulus, the summation needed to trigger Hebbian processes will be reduced. Full synaptic strengthening will then require a larger number of repetitions than in a network with a higher proportion of rapidly-conducting axons. 2.10.6. Shift of attention in schizophrenia. People with schizophrenia sometimes have difficulty in shifting the focus of their of attention: Their attentional “set” may persist when it is no longer appropriate, that is, they perseverate. Early indications of this came from a variety of tasks, especially from study of the sequence of subjects’ choices in guessing tasks (9.6.2.). 2.10.6.1 The Wisconsin Card Sort Test. The largest body of evidence pointing to an abnormal persistence of attentional “set” uses the Wisconsin Card Sort Task (WCST)(9.6.3.). In this task, cards can be sorted according to one of several principles (number, color or shape of the designs on each card). Which principle is in operation for correct sorting is not stated explicitly: Subjects have to discover this from the investigator’s responses after each of the subject’s choices (“correct” or “incorrect”). Periodically the principle for sorting is changed, and subjects have to recognize that a change has occurred and discover the new principle for correct sorting. This is a complex task recruiting several psychological faculties. Performance is determined partly by the subject’s IQ and level of education. A variety of impairments are seen in schizophrenia (9.6.3.2.), some of which can be remedied by training, although persisting 39 improvement has not been shown as a result of training. Perseveration (“persistence of set”) after change of the principle for sorting is a prominent aspect of this impairment. In factor analyses of the various measures of WCST performance, perseveration emerges as a major component of the dominant factor. This impairment occurs in all states and stages of schizophrenia, and is not a function of medication status. Part of the WCST impairment in schizophrenia arises from deficits in WM, and especially from a difficulty in keeping track of the relation between responses and outcomes for a sufficient number of trials to recognize shifts of sorting principle (9.6.3.3.). However, several analytic studies using tasks related to WCST have shown that perseveration in schizophrenia also depends on a relative difficulty in shift of attention (“persistence of set”)(9.6.3.4.). Performance in the WCST, unlike that in several other experimental paradigms correlates with scores on the Disorganization factor scores more consistently than with negative symptoms or Psychomotor poverty factor scores (9.6.3.6.). When WCST impairment does correlate with negative symptoms, it may reflect relatively mild symptom scores while more intense negative symptoms are independent of WCST performance. WCST performance does not correlate with Reality distortion factor scores. Impairment in the WCST is also found in FDR of schizophrenia probands (9.6.3.7.), but nevertheless appears to transmit to FDR significantly less strongly than do some other trait features of schizophrenia (notably the CPT and - at trend level - SPEM). The WCST thus appears to identify people who not only have non-psychotic trait characteristics of schizophrenia but also are vulnerable to psychotic decompensation. In affective disorder there are too few studies using the WCST to draw strong conclusions, but it is probable that bipolar or unipolar patients, especially when studied in remission are much less impaired than those with schizophrenia (9.6.3.8.). Actively manic or depressed patients may have more definite impairment. Impairment for schizophrenia-related personality variants has been shown more consistently than for affective disorders. 2.10.6.2. The Stroop test and other set-shift tasks. In the Stroop task (9.6.4.), subjects are presented with a word which may designate a color, and which may also be printed in colored ink. The critical measure of set shifting is the ability to suppress the dominant tendency to read a color word, and instead to name the ink color. Here a color word interferes with hue naming. The test may be presented as a list of items presented on paper, when total time for the list is the dependent measure, or in computerized form, when RT on each trial is the dependent measure. In schizophrenia, interference effects appear to be greater than normal, but this has been shown more consistently with the list than with the computerized version (where confounds in the usual design have seldom been eliminated). As with WCST perseveration, interference measures correlate more consistently with Disorganization factor scores than with scores on the Psychomotor poverty or Reality distortion factors. Several studies with the Stroop task have been reported in FDR of schizophrenia probands, but too few report true interference Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia measures to permit firm conclusions to be made. However Stroop interference is elevated in subjects with psychometrically-defined schizotypy. In the antisaccade task (9.6.5.), subjects have to suppress a dominant tendency to produce a saccadic eye movement towards an object appearing off-centre in the visual field. Instead they have to produce an eye movement away from the newly introduced object. Since vision is the dominant sensory modality, and given that motor control of saccadic eye movements is unimpaired, it follows that saccades are an indication of attentional focus, and antisaccades reflect ability to switch attention. People with schizophrenia are impaired on the antisaccade task, producing more errors (saccades rather than antisaccades). This is not a side effect of medication. It is under some degree of genetic control, as shown in studies of twins and FDR. In affective disorder, similar though milder impairment is seen, which may be more obvious in psychotic depression and bipolar disorder than non-psychotic unipolar depression. Subjects with psychometrically-defined schizotypy are also usually found to be impaired, more consistently than those with the clinically-defined SPD. Of the various symptom groups, antisaccade errors correlate most consistently with Disorganization or thought disorder rather than with other positive symptoms or with negative symptoms. In RT studies, shift of the stimulus modality slows RT, more conspicuously in subjects with schizophrenia than in control subjects (9.6.6.). The differential impairment in schizophrenia is seen more consistently for shift from the visual to auditory modality than in the reverse direction. This is not due to medication effects. What little evidence there is fails to show transmission of this effect to relatives of schizophrenia probands, but does show similar impairment in patients with mood disorder. Correlations with symptom groups are reported too rarely to reach any conclusion. Another attention shift paradigm, involving shift of focus from one visual field (i.e. hemisphere), originally developed by Posner, is beset with too many problems of interpretation to allow any definite conclusion to be reached (9.6.7.). The Trails test (notably the impairment specific to the Trails “B” version) provides further evidence of impairment in attentional shift in schizophrenia. A seldom-used test of alternation of semantic categories in word generation also provides suggestion of similar impairment in schizophrenia. 2.10.6.3. Theory of excessive “persistence of set” in schizophrenia in attention-shift paradigms. The evidence showing problems in “set shifting” in schizophrenia in the various paradigms discussed in Sect. 9.6. reveals impairment of a nature different from that for many of the other paradigms discussed in Chapters 7-9. Impairment in these tasks tends to correlate with scores on the Disorganization factor or with thought disorder. This is a contrast with impairments such as the lengthening of CSD, extended vulnerability to backward masking, as well as impairments in SPEM, the CPT and visuo-spatial WM, all of which are associated with negative symptoms or Psychomotor poverty factor scores. However, one other experimental measure - semantic hyperpriming - also shows an association with thought disorder. Further indications that attention shift impairment in schizophrenia has an origin different from some other trait impairments is that it transmits less strongly to FDR than does impairment in CPT measures, and, possibly than that for SPEM Can the impairment in attentional shifting in schizophrenia be encompassed within the same theoretical framework used to account for other trait impairments, despite the fact that scores on the Disorganization and Psychomotor poverty factors are, by definition, statistically independent? Specifically can both sorts of impairment be derived from the central hypothesis developed here, that, in schizophrenia, there is a relative absence of rapidly-conducting corticocortical axons? These questions are addressed in 9.6.9.2., and as follows. The normal cortex, in the waking state, exhibits two overall regimes of dynamic activity. This is shown on the large scale in EEG recording, where there appears to be a bistability between a state where the classic alpha rhythm dominates, and another state characterized by “low voltage fast”, “desynchronized” or “beta/gamma” activity. At the level of single neurons this bistability corresponds to a “down state” where membrane potential of the principal neurons is held far negative of threshold for firing, and an “up state”, when membrane potential appears to be stabilized and poised just a few millivolts below firing threshold. More detail on these two dynamic regimes is presented in Chapter 11 (dealing with clinical electrophysiology of schizophrenia). Here it is necessary to point out that in the “down state”, coincidence of many co-active synapses on a neuron is needed to produce impulses which will transmit to other cortical sites. In the normal brain, where, hypothetically, there is an abundance of rapidly conducting cortico-cortical axons, the population of axons transmitting from one locus to another will produce relatively little temporal dispersion of a signal generated by a phasic event (such as a tachistoscopic visual stimulus). Summation of effects within a single neuronal integration time sufficient to fire the neurons is thus not compromised. However, in schizophrenia, when the “down state” prevails, temporal dispersion is envisaged to be greater, due to the repertoire of axonal conduction delays being shifted to slower conduction. There will then be a significant problem in activating post-synaptic neurons, especially when transmission over long distances is involved (which would increase temporal dispersion). This, it is envisaged, leads to many of the abnormalities in experimental measures in schizophrenia which clearly are impairments (loss of normal abilities), and is also likely to be the basis for most negative symptoms. Consider what happens in the alternative modus operandi for the cortex, the “up state” as seen in single unit recording in animals. A cortical locus activated by a phasic stimulus will transmit signals to other loci. Again the signals will be temporally dispersed more than normal in schizophrenia, and will therefore be incapable of such a high degree of summation at their destination. Since membrane potential is close to threshold, such a high degree of summation is not required, and, in schizophrenia many recipient neurons will still be activated above threshold. However, in schizophrenia, in any one locus, if several neurons are activated, their activations will not be confined to the same integration 40 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia interval. Synchronized rebound inhibition will therefore be relatively weak compared to normal. Since the up-state prevails widely across the cortex, it will be possible for activity to pass from one locus to others, as a network of reverberatory activity. There may be sequences of persisting activity, corresponding subjectively to “long trains of thought”, and to perseveration in experiments designed to assess shift of attention. In addition, foci of activity may arise from combination of subthreshold activation from more than one source. In psychological terms this corresponds to hyperpriming in semantic priming experiments, or to some aspects of thought disorder (although in this case the items being associated cannot be identified). This account of the dynamics of the hemispheres in schizophrenia when the “up state” prevails suggests a way of answering what is referred to above (2.5.2.) as the “deepest question” about schizophrenia (9.6.9.3.): Why are people with all the trait characteristics of the disorder also vulnerable to episodes of psychosis? Since the transition to psychosis involves over-activity of the midbrain dopamine neurons, this question can be transformed into another: How can it be that hemispheres with a relative abundance of slowly conducting axons are prone, periodically, to over-activity of the midbrain dopamine neurons? There is a variety of animal evidence, both anatomical and functional, that the cortex can exert control over the midbrain dopamine neurons. One can therefore suggest that, in the up state, when persisting activity tends to reverberate around the cortex, an unusual degree of excitation is transmitted from the cortex to the midbrain dopamine neurons. This, it is suggested, is the condition under which transition to psychosis occur. This suggestion fits several other pieces of information: First, the conclusion that impairment in the WCST identifies people who are vulnerable to actual episodes of psychosis fits the reasoning just presented, since WCST perseveration, and scores on the Disorganization factor or thought disorder with which it is associated are also linked theoretically with the activated “up state” of the cortex. Second, the activated state of the cortex is likely to be generated in part in response to environmental circumstances - major life events or psychological traumata and these are known to be significant predictors in schizophrenia of episodes of psychotic relapse. Third, referring again to evidence from animals, it is mentioned in Sect. 5.4.2.3. that lesions of the right, but not the left hemisphere in rats leads to behavioral and neurochemical signs of overactivity of forebrain dopamine systems. Assuming that cerebral asymmetry in rats has some similarity to that in humans (for which there is some evidence), the right-hemisphere-lesioned rat may be dominated by lefthemisphere-type cortical dynamics, which would favor periods of dopaminergic over-activity. Several lines of evidence indicate that WCST performance in normal subjects depends strongly on intactness of the frontal lobes (9.6.3.5.), probably with right side dominance, and perseveration in schizophrenia also probably depends on impaired function of the frontal lobe. Likewise the frontal lobe is implicated in performance in the Stroop task (9.6.4.), and in the impairment in schizophrenia in this task, shown as excess interference scores. However, in view of the complex and rather global requirements for adequate performance in 41 these tasks, it is likely that the impairments in schizophrenia arise from widespread loss of rapidly-conducting axons rather than loss in discrete definable pathways. 2.11. Language and schizophrenia. Language functions can be subdivided into syntax/grammar and semantics. Both of these can be considered in relation either to decoding of incoming language (10.2.) or to planning language output (10.3.). Syntax and grammar are concerned with the exact sequencing of words and word endings, and on a larger scale, the embedding of clauses, to define the meaning inherent in a sentence. Semantics is concerned with the representation of meaning itself, regardless of its coding in exact word sequences. Small scale aspects of semantics (meaning of individual words) have been considered already (9.3.3.; synopsis in 2.10.3.1.). Larger-scale semantics, as well as syntax and grammar raise issues of laterality, for the normal brain. Syntax and grammar, involving timing and exact sequence, are preferentially dealt with by the left hemisphere, while higher-level semantics appears to be right hemispherepreferred. In schizophrenia, a major issue is whether the disturbance of higher aspects of language function arises fundamentally from impairment in larger-scale aspects of semantics, or in the domain of syntax and grammar. The issue is not straightforward, because primary impairment in one is likely to have secondary impact on the other. An additional high-level aspect of language function is its “pragmatics”, that is the adjustment of language output to meet the needs of listeners (10.3.8.). For all the above functions, a proper theoretical account needs to place linguistic functions in the context of broader concepts for cognitive psychology. Potentially this can allow language dysfunction in schizophrenia to be related to the “central hypothesis” concerning axonal conduction properties. 2.11.1. Decoding of language input in schizophrenia. A variety of methods are available to assess subjects’ awareness of syntactic structure. In schizophrenia there is no deficit in this, provided the measure is truly of this, rather than of the meaning derived from that syntactic structure (10.2.1.). However, there may be a deficit in comprehending syntactically-complex sentences, due to information overload in WM. In contrast, there is considerable evidence that decoding of semantic aspects of sentences is impaired in schizophrenia (10.2.2.). This has been shown by the failure to benefit from semantic organization in word- or sentence-recall tests, and by reduced semantic organization of the recalled material (10.2.2.1., 10.2.2.2.). In the “cloze” procedure (10.2.2.3.), subjects are presented with written sentences, and are required to guess deleted words from the surrounding context. Subjects with schizophrenia are less efficient at guessing than control subjects, and use a smaller context of surrounding words. In other tests it is shown that such subjects are often impaired in interpreting indirect inferences, metaphorical usages of language, or proverbs (10.2.2.4.). In reading aloud, their fluency is impaired, probably because they gain less than normal benefit from comprehension of the passage to be read (10.2.2.6.). Overall, subjects with schizophrenia appear to have difficulty in assimilating Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia meaning across the span of a sentence or longer passage. In addition, it has been suggested that such subjects have difficulty with comprehending abstract meanings (“concretism”: 10.2.2.5.), and in inferring mental states in another person (“Theory of Mind” deficit: 10.2.2.7.). The evidence on these topics is not convincing, although theory of mind deficits may be present in states of active psychosis. 2.11.2. Organization of language output in schizophrenia. Disorder of language output in schizophrenia has been noted since the earliest studies (10.3.1.). There has been a debate whether this is to be understood using models of aphasia derived from neurology, or has a quite different basis. Many blind alleys have been investigated, some based on psychoanalytic reasoning. There appear to be problems in articulation in some patients (10.3.2.), including restriction in prosodic modulation, but these are not primarily linguistic. “Delayed auditory feedback” which disturbs speech in normal subjects does so more severely in schizophrenia, in some studies, and the delay producing maximum effect is longer than normal (10.3.3.). This suggests that advance planning of words-to-be-uttered occurs in longer segments in schizophrenia than in normal subjects, although more work is needed to corroborate this, and it is not clear whether the disruption is of syntactic or semantic planning (or both). Pauses within utterances have been taken as another measure of speech planning, and tend to be more frequent and longer in schizophrenia (10.3.4.). Probably they are an index of WM processing limitations during discourse planning. Modern studies comparing disordered speech in schizophrenia with that in aphasia (10.3.5.) find important differences. In particular, speech from subjects with schizophrenia does not show the prominent word-finding difficulty typical of Broca’s aphasia, or the problem with syntactic organization, typical of Wernicke’s aphasia. The abnormality seems to be at a level beyond that of individual words, in aspects of meaning. Moreover, “thought disorder” in schizophrenia tends to be less when subjects are not under time pressure, or communicate in writing rather than vocally. The problem may therefore not be fundamental to forming semantic representation in sentences per se, but in doing so at the speed at which speech normally has to be uttered. Direct studies of syntax in speech from schizophrenia patients have reported abnormalities, consisting of syntactic simplification (10.3.6.), but since these are related to age of onset of the disorder, they are probably an indication of arrested development of adult language capability, rather than a fundamental characteristic of the disorder. In contrast, direct studies of semantics of speech in schizophrenia have revealed a number of problems which are probably more basic. When such speech is submitted to the “cloze” procedure with normal raters (10.3.7.1.), it is often found to be more difficult than for normal speech to guess the deleted words. Guessing the deleted words relies on more closely neighboring words than for normal speech. When sentence order in a paragraph is randomized, and normal raters have to reconstitute the original order, it is found that speech from subjects with schizophrenia loses its organization across sentences more than within them. The most interesting evidence on this topic uses a method assessing links within and between sentences, which tie together ideas in the discourse (10.3.7.2.). In schizophrenia, the use of such ties are looser and weaker than normal, and, although the abnormalities are not common, when they occurred, they are very disruptive for the listener. Occurrences of these abnormalities are associated with clinically-rated thought disorder, and probably are a major component of this symptom. This abnormality is more severe in acutely ill patients, but is also present to lesser degree as an enduring trait. The abnormality is also present to some extent in FDR of schizophrenia probands. Another way in which high-level discourse planning has been analyzed is in terms of the “hierarchy” in which ideas are delivered. It is suggested that discourse from normal subjects has a strong hierarchy, which breaks down in schizophrenia (10.3.7.3.). However, it is very difficult to reduce these proposals to an objective method of analysis, and so they remain unsubstantiated. In the “pragmatics” of language output (or “effectiveness” in communication) the speaker “puts himself in the listener’s shoes” in planning discourse (10.3.8.). This overlaps with the use of cohesive ties and other planning devices for integrating discourse. It is also closely related to deployment of “theory of mind” in understanding the more complex aspects of incoming speech. There is evidence (mainly quite old) that this function is impaired in schizophrenia. These various impairments in discourse planning in schizophrenia are likely to derive from more basic abnormalities in cognitive processes (10.3.9.). Many of them reflect limits on “working memory”. However, the real limit is in processing resources, in the complex operations of linguistic planning. This is likely to account for the impairments both in decoding incoming semantics and in planning semantic aspects of speech output (discussed in 10.4.). 2.11.3. Language dysfunctions in schizophrenia and the “central hypothesis”. How do the various language abnormalities in schizophrenia relate to the abnormality in cerebral asymmetry, and the “central hypothesis” proposed as the essential basis of schizophrenia? Normal language processing, whether of input or output, requires two separate processes, and requires them to be exactly coordinated. First, speech must be planned syllable-by-syllable and word-by-word, with attention to syntax and grammar. These are matters of exact timing and sequence of word endings, words, and clauses. They are presumably left hemisphere functions. On the other hand, such time-structured output needs to be guided on a longer time scale, phrase-by-phrase, sentence-by-sentence, and paragraph-by-paragraph, according to the intended meaning. It is likely that the slow-moving blocks of meaning (“semantic Gestalts”) which constitute “deep semantic structure” are embodied by right hemisphere-type assemblies, held in a state of heightened activation for STM intervals. Interpretation of long segments of incoming speech requires coordination of a variety of such right-hemisphere-type assemblies. Likewise production of comprehensible emitted discourse requires coordinated deployment of such assemblies, activated in planned sequence. 42 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia These two high-level aspects of language - involving finegrained temporal structure, and slower longer-term semantic representations - need to be well coordinated in an intimate synergy if incoming speech is to be understood, and fluent and meaningful speech is to be produced. In comprehending incoming speech, the detailed syntactic structure needs to be translated into slower-moving semantic representation. Likewise, in planning speech output, deep semantic structure must be translated into a well-organized utterances, involving transformations to form verbal, phonetic and syntactic sequences. Since a particular deep structure can be expressed in a variety of superficial structures, these transformations must be more complex than simple one-to-one correspondence. In normal subjects, it is likely to involve complex collaboration between the two hemispheres, across the corpus callosum. In schizophrenia this collaboration breaks down, either because the right hemisphere aspect of decoding or discourse planning is impaired, or because the exactly-timed coordination between the two hemispheres is lost (or both may occur). In either case, the impairment can be explained in more fundamental terms by our central hypothesis, a relative absence of rapidly conducting corticalcortical axons. 2.11.4. Comment on author’s presentation of psychological evidence. The reader may notice a strategy, used throughout the discussion of psychological evidence on schizophrenia, in Chapters 7-10, to avoid strong emphasis on some of the highlevel psychological concepts used to “explain” psychological findings. These concepts include the distinction between automatic and controlled processing (often used in considerations of semantic priming and negative priming), the “central executive” (envisaged to be in charge of attentional shift), and to some extent the broad concept of “working memory”. This strategy is deliberate: The most powerful scientific explanations are “cross-level”, not “within-level” ones. Psychological evidence is crucial to understanding schizophrenia, but it should be explained in terms of neural dynamics, not in terms of psychological concepts which, through constant use become familiar, and appear “solid” and “reified”. Such concepts become really solid, not by constant use, but by their being translated, accurately and in detail into neurobiological terms. At this point, rigorous cross-level explanations will have been constructed. 2.12. Axonal electrophysiology schizophrenia. conduction time, and and functional imaging in The strategy adopted in presenting psychological evidence in Chapters 7-10 was mainly to present evidence, and then to show how it fitted (or failed to fit) the central hypothesis for traits of schizophrenia. However, since that lengthy discussion was fairly successful in supporting that hypothesis, a change of strategy is adopted in presenting the biological evidence in Chapters 11 and 12: Predictions from the hypothesis are usually made first, to be explicitly tested as the empirical evidence is reviewed. 43 2.12.1. The spontaneous EEG in schizophrenia. In the theoretical introduction to the topic of the EEG in schizophrenia, two themes underlying the normal waking EEG are described. First, the cortex is bistable: There are periods of “idling activity”(classic alpha rhythm), when neurons are hyperpolarized for most of the time, and when little active information processing is occurring. At other times the cortex is “desynchronized”, when many neurons have their membrane potential poised just below threshold for firing, cell assemblies are easily ignited, and active chains of neuronal firing may occur. Axonal conduction time in corticocortical axons has little relevance for the classic alpha rhythm, but the transition to the desynchronized state and the dynamic interactions in that state are influenced by conduction times. Specifically, in a cortex with a rich repertoire of delays lines, and hence with wide temporal dispersion of any phasic signal, it is difficult, in the idling state, to activate the cortex to the point where reverberatory activity occurs; but when this level of activity is reached, in the desynchronized state, reverberatory activity is sustained longer than in a cortex with more rapid axonal conduction, and less temporal dispersion. Metaphorically one could say that the hemispheres in schizophrenia have greater “inertia” than in the normal case, but once activated have greater “momentum”. From this it is predicted that in schizophrenia, especially when the cortex is in a state of arousal, the proportion of time spent in the desynchronized state will be higher than in the normal hemispheres. In power spectral analyses, this would correspond to reduced alpha power and increased beta power. The arguments here, framed in terms of electrophysiological variables, are a close counterpart of those framed in Sect. 9.6.9.6. (summary in 2.10.6.3.), to account for “persistence of set” in attention-shift paradigms. Moreover, it is important for understanding the transition to psychosis to remember that the midbrain dopamine neurons are under cortical control. Whether expressed in terms of physiological or psychological measures, periods of reverberatory activity in the cortex which are more prolonged than normal are the necessary precursor for the acceleration of firing of midbrain dopamine neurons. This in turn is the immediate trigger for destabilization to episodes of active psychosis. The additional prediction is therefore made that the increased duration of periods of EEG desynchronization (and, as a less direct measure, the increase in beta power in power spectral analyses) should be associated with the unmedicated state and states of active psychosis. The second theme refers to the details of the “desynchronized” state: This is not strictly desynchronized because it contains low amplitude activity in the beta and gamma bands. In addition, accumulating evidence has recently shown that the active cortex generates activity in the alpha band, related to concurrent information processing, though this is very different from the classic alpha rhythm. There is also evidence that there is an inverse relation between the frequency of EEG activity (ranging from gamma to alpha) during information processing, and the distance over which inter-cortical interactions are occurring. This is plausibly explained in terms of the conduction delays in cortico-cortical axons during inter-cortical interactions over various distances. Given this, and assuming that in schizophrenia there is a shift Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia to slower transcortical transmission, the prediction for schizophrenia is clear: Gamma activity should occur more rarely and be more difficult to detect with scalp electrodes than in the normal case. At the slower end of the range of frequencies generated by the active cortex, activity should appear not only at alpha frequencies but also in the theta band, or even at lower frequencies. Empirical evidence supports all the above predictions. Alpha power in power spectral analyses is generally reduced in schizophrenia (11.2.3.1.), and beta power is increased (11.2.3.2.). The latter increase is particularly associated with the unmedicated condition, shown both in group comparisons and longitudinal ones. While most recent studies on this are based solely on power spectra, a number of studies (mainly from before the era when automated analysis was routine) report the more specific finding that periods of desynchronization are longer than normal in schizophrenia, or occupy a larger proportion of recording time (11.2.3.6.). It is also reported that gamma activity is more difficult to detect in subjects with schizophrenia than in controls, although such comparisons are based on EEG reactivity to various task situations, rather than the spontaneous EEG (11.2.3.5.). Theta and delta activity are more prominent than in the normal case (11.2.3.3.), where these slow rhythms are seldom seen in the waking EEG. These findings fit the predictions made on the basis of neurodynamic theory. A finding not predicted from the central hypothesis is that the elevation of beta power in schizophrenia often occurs most prominently in the left hemisphere (11.2.3.4.) although the exact regions identified in this hemisphere differ between studies. This evidence forms part of a small body of evidence using other methods which does not fit with the simplified version of the central hypothesis, captured by the phrase “two left hemispheres”. Such evidence suggests that not all the abnormalities in schizophrenia amount to loss of right hemisphere-type functions. Predictions from theory can also be made about the coherence and phase relations between waveforms at particular frequencies recorded simultaneously in different hemispheric locations: Coherence should be lower than normal in schizophrenia, and phase delays should be larger (11.2.4.1). The available evidence (11.2.4.2.) does not provide strong support for the prediction about coherence, although a few recent studies provide promising hints, and the validity of the reasoning is supported by the fact that the normal left hemisphere has lower EEG coherence than the normal right hemisphere. Evidence on EEG phase delays in schizophrenia is very scanty, and does not yet permit any clear statement about the predicted differences from normal. 2.12.2. Levels of neural activity assessed by functional imaging (rCBF, rCGU or BOLD). Amongst psychophysiological indicators of cerebral activity, much recent work has used the methods of functional imaging, based on local measurement of regional cerebral blood flow (rCBF), glucose utilization (rCGU) or blood oxygen level differences (BOLD). These methods have produced much new information, in both normal subjects and a wide variety of clinical populations, establishing correlations between these measures of cerebral activity and many psychological variables. However, these methods, while providing high spatial resolution, have much coarser temporal resolution than the EEG. Moreover, elucidation of the exact neural basis of the signals used in such functional imaging is at an early stage, so that the relative role of excitation vs inhibition is unclear. It is also unclear if large signals in a particular region indicate that this region is performing its special function well, or, alternatively is over-activated because it is forced to perform a task for which it is ill suited. Given these limitations, it is difficult to use the correlative data obtained with these methods for true explanations in neurodynamic terms. Therefore not much of the evidence using functional imaging methods in schizophrenia is dealt with in this book. However, in one area, where predictions for functional imaging measures in the resting cortex are a close parallel to those in the spontaneous EEG, a brief review is included, The coverage of this evidence is limited to studies which report actual resting blood flow or glucose utilization measures (rather than measures normalized in various ways). A variety of results are reported, including both increases and decreases above normal levels of resting cerebral activity. The evidence becomes more comprehensible when medication status and symptom profile are taken into account. Unmedicated patients have higher levels of cerebral activation than medicated ones, the former usually above normal levels the latter usually below normal. In addition, these measures of cerebral activation are usually positively correlated with positive symptoms and negatively correlated with negative ones. These findings are similar to those obtained with EEG measures, where increased EEG desynchronization is correlated with positive symptoms or the unmedicated state. Therefore the functional imaging studies broadly support the theory developed in this book. Another popular hypothesis has suggested that schizophrenia is characterized by “hypofrontality” - a relatively low level of cerebral activation in the frontal lobes. However, this is not supported in the foregoing meta-analysis, for either medicated or unmedicated patients: Group differences, when found, are found equally in all regions of the hemispheres, although the large number of studies in frontal regions obscures this conclusion. 2.12.3. Evoked schizophrenia. and event-related potentials in 2.12.3.1. Latency and amplitude. When brief stimuli are given in major sensory modalities, a regular series of electrical waveforms - evoked potentials, or EPs - are produced. Those with latencies more than ~30 msec are of cortical origin. Because these waveforms tend to be obscured by spontaneous EEG waveforms in single traces, they are often studied after stimulus-locked averaging of many traces. However, this method of analysis makes it impossible to explore an alternative interpretation of EPs, namely that they are themselves a manifestation of the spontaneous EEG, emerging as distinct waveforms in averaged traces because their phase is reset by the stimulus, to give stimulus-locked waveforms. Hence other methods of analysis have been devised, including frequency-filtering of individual traces followed by frequency-selective averaging. 44 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia These two approaches to analysis of EPs may be complementary, so that predictions from neurodynamic principles using either approach do not contradict one another. These predictions concern latency and amplitude of the EP components. Assuming that the response components revealed by averaging are substantial realities, their latency is determined in part by conduction time in cortico-cortical axons. It would then be predicted from the central hypothesis about schizophrenia that latency should generally be longer than normal. If one makes the alternative assumption that EPs arise from phase resetting of the spontaneous EEG, there is a delay between the stimulus and the time of phase-resetting, again determined in part by conduction time in corticocortical axons. Thus the same prediction would be reached that, in schizophrenia, the potential emerging from averaging would have a longer than normal latency. However, the latency of EP components in averaged traces varies considerably between subjects. If EP components are defined using latency criteria, this may prevent group differences in latency being detected. The prediction can be better tested if EP components are defined by their intrinsic morphology rather than by latency criteria. Predictions about amplitude are as follows: If conduction times in cortico-cortical axons are extended, and signal transmission in a population of axons is therefore subject to greater temporal dispersion, post-synaptic summation at the site of EP generation would be reduced and so the EP components should be reduced in amplitude. If one adopts the assumption that EP components arise from phase-resetting, the impact of the stimulus would still undergo temporal dispersion in schizophrenia. Its influence on spontaneous EEG rhythms would then be less than in the normal case, so that the degree of phase-resetting would be reduced. Again one reaches the conclusion that amplitude should be reduced in schizophrenia. There is a complications to these predictions. Within 100 msec of a stimulus, direct transmission can spread its influence to any part of the hemispheres. Thus EP components longer than this probably reflect back-and-forth interplay, rather than direct transmission. Therefore the predictions are limited to EP components between ~30 and ~100 msec (“midlatency EPs”). Does the empirical evidence support these predictions? Most studies on mid-latency EPs (notably auditory P50 and N100 potentials) fail to document a latency prolongation in schizophrenia. However, this result is suspect, since latency criteria are used to define the EP components in most studies. In a single study where these EP components are defined by criteria independent of latency, the measured latency is found to be substantially prolonged in schizophrenia. More such studies are needed. The predicted amplitude reduction is however supported by many studies of both the auditory P50 and auditory N100 potentials. 2.12.3.2. Interhemispheric transmission time. There is one electrophysiological test of the central hypothesis for schizophrenia based on latency measures, which is not confounded by the use of latency criteria to define the response component. This is the measure of interhemispheric transmission time (IHTT). The central hypothesis 45 for schizophrenia predicts that this should be longer than normal. The corresponding hypothesis for normal cerebral asymmetry also has a clear prediction: Since callosal fibres are really a subset of the long cortico-cortical axonal projections arising in one or other hemisphere, one would predict that transmission from right to left would be faster than that from left to right. This prediction for directional asymmetry of callosal transmission in the normal brain is now well supported. Earlier estimates of callosal transmission times were based on RT measures, comparing crossed with uncrossed reactions. Although the data available with this method are rather variable, it is clear that when directional asymmetry is present, it always points to faster right-to-left than left-to-right transmission. Use of EP components provides a more reliable test of our hypotheses. Comparing the peak latency of EP components contralateral to a stimulus (the direct response) and ipsilateral to it (the indirect or transcallosal response) it is shown consistently in normal subjects, that transmission from right-to-left is significantly faster than from left-to-right. Two studies compare IHTT between normal subjects and those with schizophrenia, using EP components. Both find longer IHTT in the patient groups. One of these studies shows that left-to-right transmission (the slower direction in normal subjects) differs little between groups, but right-to-left transmission is slowed in schizophrenia. This fits well the concept that in schizophrenia the right hemisphere becomes more like the normal left hemisphere. This study also illustrates (but does not systematically analyze) another effect predictable from theory: The decrement in amplitude in transmission from contralateral to ipsilateral appears to be greater in schizophrenia than normal. This is predicted on the basis of greater-than-normal temporal dispersion of signals during transcallosal relay in schizophrenia. This method of analysis has rarely been applied, and might provide further critical tests of the central hypothesis for schizophrenia. 2.12.3.3. Paired-stimulus paradigms. Another way in which electrophysiological evidence can be used to evaluate the central hypothesis for schizophrenia is in the patterns of response to pairs of stimuli closely spaced in time. In principle the response to a second stimulus can differ from that to the first, or to a single isolated stimulus in either of two ways: It may be smaller than the first (suppression) or it may be larger (potentiation). Either effect is a function of the repertoire of delays in cortico-cortical axons (11.3.4.1.). If cortical relays leading to generation of the EP to the first stimulus are rapidly conducting, with little temporal dispersion, rebound inhibition will be strong. While that inhibition lasts, the response to a second stimulus will be suppressed. For cortical relays which are slower conducting, with substantial temporal dispersion, the late subthreshold influence of the first stimulus, relayed along the slowestconducting members of the axonal population may summate with the early response to the second stimulus, relayed along the most rapidly-conducting axons. Provided the two stimuli are close enough in time for such summation to occur, it will be manifest as paired stimulus potentiation. Which of these two effects occurs depends not only on conduction velocity, but also on conduction distance. For short distances, where Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia there is little opportunity for temporal dispersion of signals, paired-stimulus suppression will tend to occur (ceteris paribus), while for longer distance, paired stimulus potentiation will be favored. The predictions for schizophrenia (11.3.4.1.), based on the central premise (a relative absence of rapidly conducting cortico-cortical axons) are as follows: Under conditions where normal subjects show strong suppression, subjects with schizophrenia will show reduced suppression. This follows since there will be greater temporal dispersion in the relays generating the response to the first stimulus, with the result that its amplitude will be below normal and rebound inhibition less potent than in the normal case. Under conditions where normal subjects show potentiation, there may appear greater than normal potentiation. This would occur if, amongst the population of axons carrying the signal from the first stimulus, the proportion with exceedingly slow velocity was larger than normal. There would then be greater than normal summation of the effects of signals in these axons with those produced by the second stimulus. Empirically, in normal subjects, paired stimulus suppression is well documented, most commonly for the auditory P50 potential, but also for the auditory N100 potential. In agreement with predictions, in schizophrenia the amplitude of the response to the first stimulus is below normal, and the degree of suppression of the response to the second is substantially reduced (11.3.4.2.). Paired stimulus potentiation has also been described, for the N100 potential (11.3.4.5.), though it requires special settings of stimulus duration and interstimulus interval. Also in agreement with predictions, for the longer interstimulus intervals where potentiation can be detected in normal subjects, it can be greater than normal in schizophrenia. It is also notable, and in accord with the model just described, that the reduction of suppression is best documented for the P50 potential which is generated after relatively short-distance relay from the primary auditory cortex, whereas the potentiation effect is seen for the N100 potential, where longer distances are involved in relay from the primary auditory cortex. 2.12.3.4. Event-related potentials in oddball paradigms. A simple, but much-used paradigm in clinical electrophysiology involves comparison of averaged potential responses to “standard” stimuli in a series, with those to stimuli which are “deviant” in some way, interspersed among the “standards”. Some electrographic responses to the deviant (“oddball”) stimuli are larger than those to the standards. Early potential components showing such behavior in oddball designs exhibit enhanced negativity (“mismatch negativity” or MMN), which is found regardless of focused attention on the stimuli. A longer latency component - the P300 potential - is manifest as enhanced positivity to oddballs, this being found only with attentional focus on the stimuli. The latency of MMN potentials varies in differing circumstances, but, the shortest latency examples (seen in animal experiments with indwelling electrodes) are too early to involve interaction between different cortical regions. Longer-latency examples (typically studied in humans) do implicate relay between distant cortical regions. It is likely that there are local circuits at every locality in the cerebral cortex which detect deviant stimuli in that locus, by comparison with a “template” of familiar “standard” stimuli. This comparison is probably achieved by inhibitory feedback in each locus, from the representation of the template to earlier stages of cortical processing. Deviant stimuli are not recognized by this template, produce less feedback inhibition, and therefore produce larger responses. As a result, impulse traffic around the cortex generally gives emphasis to signal patterns which are novel or unusual. While there is no reason to suppose that the local processes of oddball detection are influenced much by conduction time in cortico-cortical pathways, the relay between distant regions will be. If rapidly conducting axons are replaced by more slowly-conducting ones, there will be greater-than-normal temporal dispersion of signals in a pathway, with loss of temporal summation at the destination. The result is that the strength of the “template”, representing what is familiar, formed in a non-primary area, will be reduced. Hence the feedback inhibition associated with standard stimuli would be attenuated. The consequence is that the difference between responses to standard stimuli (where feedback inhibition is recruited) and that to deviant ones (where it is not) would be smaller than normal. This difference - the MMN potential should thus be smaller than normal in schizophrenia. It is also predicted that the latency of this potential should be greater than normal. These predictions are largely supported by empirical evidence, although the predicted increase of latency is found only when a wide latency range is used as the defining criterion for the MMN. The reduction in amplitude is found in both medicated and unmedicated patients, and appears to be a trait characteristic, rather than an aspect of the psychotic state. The P300 potential, as expected from its long latency, arises from generators widespread throughout the neocortex. In addition. similar enhancement of averaged potentials to oddball stimuli in attended conditions are produced in the hippocampal formation. The latter contribute little to scalprecorded potentials, but nevertheless may control, or be controlled by, the generators of scalp potentials. While P300 potentials are generally studied in humans, the circumstances in which they are produced are rather similar to those which elicit the hippocampal theta rhythm in experimental animals. In such animals, the P300-like potential recorded in the hippocampus is in fact a single waveform at the theta frequency. Accumulating evidence shows that the hippocampus can engage in rhythmic interplay at the theta frequency with the neocortex, employing long axonal delay lines between the two structures. The neocortex itself shows little evidence of rhythmic theta activity, presumably because of temporal dispersion of signals generated in the hippocampus, as they influence the neocortex. There is only a little evidence on hippocampal theta activity in humans, but what there is indicates that, in the circumstances in which P300 potentials are elicited, the hippocampus produces only a short burst of two or three theta-frequency waveforms, dominated by just a single such waveform. It is suggested that temporal dispersion in hippocampo-neocortical relays would “smear” this waveform in the time dimension, the result being the broad waveform obtained with scalp electrodes, otherwise known as the P300 potential. With this as a basis, three 46 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia predictions about P300 potentials can be made for schizophrenia, based on the hypothesized replacement of rapidly conducting axons by more slowly-conducting ones in hippocampo-neocortical relays: First, the latency should be longer than normal. Second, the amplitude should be reduced, this being evident even in single traces (i.e. not simply a byproduct of averaging of waveforms which are less-thannormally synchronized). Third, because there would be greater-than-normal temporal “smearing” in schizophrenia, the P300 waveform should be extended more broadly in time than in normal subjects. The first two predictions are supported by abundant empirical evidence. The reduction in amplitude is seen in both averaged and single traces. In averaged traces the reduction is due partly to greater latency variability, but the reduction in single traces corresponds well to predictions. Medication status, whether studied in cross-sectional or longitudinal designs, has little effect on the differences between schizophrenia and control groups. The reductions in amplitude and prolongation of latency appear to be true traits. These abnormalities are not related to other prevailing cognitive abnormalities, such as increased RT variability, or decreased vigilance, and so probably derive from more fundamental aspects of schizophrenia. No published data are available with which to evaluate the third prediction, that the P300 waveform should be more extended in time. A further finding, made in several studies, which goes beyond the immediate predictions of the “central hypothesis”, is that P300 amplitude reduction in schizophrenia is more marked on the left than the right side, especially in the posterior temporal region. In Sect. 2.7.2. (and 7.3.4.) theoretical arguments were developed to show how loss of rapidly conducting axons in projections passing between Wernicke’s and Broca’s area could produce a tendency to verbal auditory hallucinations. It would therefore be interesting to know whether this unexpected abnormal asymmetry of P300 potentials correlates with such symptoms. This question has not yet been adequately explored. Various symptom correlates of P300 potentials have been documented: Significant associations with positive symptoms are rarely reported, while the majority of reports on negative symptoms do find an association. Strikingly, almost all studies reporting on the relation between P300 abnormalities and thought disorder find a positive correlation. This is to be expected from theory developed here, since the P300 potential is produced in conditions of focused attention, during which overall cortical activity levels will be high. Following the same reasoning, one would expected the reduction in MMN amplitude to correlate mainly with negative symptoms, since this ERP is produced regardless of focused attention. The few studies reporting on symptom correlates of reduced MMN do show this, although the subject has not been studied sufficiently to exclude a correlation with thought disorder (not expected from the same reasoning). 2.13. Schizophrenia and brain morphology. The earliest investigations of brain morphology in schizophrenia date from a time shortly after Kraepelin defined the concept of “dementia praecox” (12.1.). These studies made several findings which have been greatly amplified by more recent work. In the middle years of the twentieth century 47 studies using post-mortem brain produced quite inconsistent results. They were however supplemented by the technique called pneumo-encephalography (PEG) which allowed in vivo visualization of cerebral ventricles. This has now been superceded by brain scanning using computerized tomography (CT) and magnetic resonance imaging (MRI)(12.2.1.), although several findings on gross brain morphology were first made using PEG. Modern uses of MRI allow estimates of the volume of the brain and its several regions to be made. The success of these methods has led to a renewal of interest in studies of post-mortem brain, which have produced more reliable findings than in early work, at the level of both gross and microscopic morphology. An additional approach involves use of signal characteristics in CT and MRI to infer tissue characteristics. All these approaches to study of brain morphology in schizophrenia are surveyed in Chapter 12. 2.13.1. Volumes of cerebral and cranial structures. The volumes of the lateral and third ventricles and the external fluid spaces are all increased in schizophrenia (12.2.2.). Volume increase of the lateral ventricles is best documented, but is small quantitatively compared to the volume increase in external fluid spaces. Whole brain volume (WBV)(and combined hemispheric volume)(12.2.3.) is decreased in schizophrenia by ~3% (~35 cc), the effect being very similar in male and female patients, although in both control and schizophrenia groups volume is larger in male than female by 13-15%. These volume reductions are similar in left and right hemispheres, taking the hemispheres as a whole. However there are hints from the size and shape of the hemispheres that, in normal subjects, individual lobes are asymmetrical, the right side being larger in frontal and temporal lobes, the left being larger in parietooccipital lobes. In schizophrenia these asymmetries tend to be reduced (12.2.6.). Intracranial volume (ICV) is also reduced in schizophrenia (12.2.4.), but, in absolute terms, the volume reduction is less than 50% of that in the brain contained within the cranium. The difference in these two volume deficits is accounted for by the fact that ventricular and external fluid volume is larger than normal in schizophrenia. This implies that reduction in brain growth in schizophrenia occurs partly before, and partly after cranial size is finalized (at age about 10 years), and probably occurs progressively from infancy to adulthood (12.2.5.). From study of cases of schizophrenia with childhood or adolescent onset (12.2.5.), it is likely that, during adolescence, the fluid spaces expand more and brain parenchyma may even reduce, in schizophrenia compared to age-matched controls. This suggests that the volume expansion which normally occurs in childhood and adolescence is reduced as a precursor to emergence of schizophrenia. This probably reflects a combination of normal reduction in GM due to synaptic and axonal pruning, combined with less-than-normal expansion of white matter (WhM). Since expansion of WhM in childhood and adolescence is normally largely due to myelination, a plausible hypothesis for schizophrenia is that myelination occurs more slowly and less completely than normal. In each of the individual lobes, volume reduction is found in schizophrenia, as expected from the reduction in WBV Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia (12.2.7.). There is a tendency in the frontal lobe and a suggestion of one in the temporal lobe, for reduction to be greater on right than left side, and in parieto-occipital lobes (on the basis of rather few studies) reduction appears to be greater on left than right. Possibly across all lobes, normal asymmetry is reduced or reversed in schizophrenia, although, in the data sets available, the interaction between diagnosis and asymmetry does not reach statistical significance. It has been difficult to estimate the relative contribution of grey matter (GM ) vs white matter (WhM) reduction to the overall reduction of brain tissue in schizophrenia. There are substantial methodological problems, related to signal thresholding in MRI studies, which make accurate estimation of the volume of each tissue type difficult (12.2.8.). Many MRI studies have reported GM volume deficits. It has been less clear whether there are also deficits in WhM volume, but this may reflect a type II error, since coefficients of variation for WhM volume estimates are generally larger than for GM, so that statistical significance is harder to achieve in a single study. Meta-analyses over many studies confirm the GM volume deficit (of ~3% across both hemispheres)(12.2.8.2.). This is associated with reduction of cortical thickness (12.2.8.6.) rather than area. Meta-analyses also find a deficit of similar proportion for WhM (12.2.8.2.). Other approaches (reduction of the “radius of gyration” [12.2.8.2.]; reduction of the “gyrification index” [12.2.8.3]; reduction of the crosssection area of the corpus callosum [12.2.8.4.]; voxel-based morphometry [12.2.8.5.]) support the view that the volume of WhM as well as that of GM is reduced in schizophrenia. In individual lobes there is also reduction of both tissue types (12.2.8.7.). In frontal lobe, GM and WhM are reduced to similar extents (~5%). In the temporal lobe GM appears to be reduced more than WhM (4.6% vs 2.2%), while, from the limited data available on the parieto-occipital lobes, GM reduction (2.8%) is less than that of WhM (5.4%). This could signify that WhM deficit in the frontal lobe is due to reduction of mean axon calibre in both incoming and outgoing fibers, while that in the temporal lobe is mainly due to reduction in outgoing fibers and that in parieto-occipital lobes is due to reduction in incoming fibers (see 12.3.2.). The stage of development when these volume deficits arise is not well documented, especially for GM. However there is some evidence that progressive expansion of WhM occurs to lessthan-normal extent in schizophrenia, in early adulthood, and perhaps earlier (12.2.8.9.). Study of volume deficits in localized regions of cortical GM (12.2.8.9.) has shown that volume reduction in schizophrenia is not uniform across the neocortex, the percentage deficit being largest in the frontal lobe (especially its inferior parts) and the left superior temporal region. Other structures of the medial temporal lobe (amygdala, parahippocampal gyrus, and perhaps the hippocampus) also show large percentage reductions. However, the volume reduction in these structures does not account for the whole deficit in WBV. Primary sensory areas and the primary motor area, and most other cortical region show lesser volume reductions, although data is limited for many such regions. There is also a volume reduction in subcortical structures (thalamus and probably the caudate nucleus)(12.2.9.). The evidence on regional volume reduction does not support a strictly localizationist view of cerebral abnormality in schizophrenia. A regional approach to defining WhM volume reduction is not possible, since this tissue has no clear regional boundaries in MRI. Correlation between different volume measures (12.2.11.) reveals two significant features of the volume changes in schizophrenia. First, the decrease in WBV is correlated negatively with increase in ventricular spaces. Increase of ventricular volume may thus be developmentally related to reduction of brain parenchyma. Second, a correlation between volumes of frontal and temporal lobes, found in normal subjects, is lacking in schizophrenia. It has been suggested that there is relative fronto-temporal dissociation in schizophrenia, perhaps due to lack of mutual or common trophic influences. 2.13.2. Microscopic studies of post-mortem brain tissue. From the “central hypothesis”, that in schizophrenia there is a relative absence of rapidly-conducting cortico-cortical axons, predictions can be made for cytology of both WhM and GM (12.3.). For WhM one would expect a reduction in the proportion of large caliber or myelinated axons, and an increase in axonal packing density, compared to normal WhM, differences which would explain the overall volume deficits for WhM. Evidence on these predictions (12.3.1.) is scanty and inconsistent, partly because unmyelinated axons can only be identified using electron microscopy in well fixed tissue, and this is not possible for human tissues. The best stereological study, that of Marner and Pakkenberg (2003) produces data implying higher than normal axonal packing density in schizophrenia. Total axonal length in the hemispheres in schizophrenia was 6% below normal, a nonsignificant difference. From this, and the volume reduction for WhM, it might be concluded that mean axonal caliber is reduced. However, since unmyelinated axons are not considered, and since coefficients of variation for all estimates are large, it is not possible to use the data in this study for precise theoretical reasoning. Nevertheless, evidence of a different sort - showing reduced numbers of oligodendrocytes, which are involved in producing myelin sheaths - gives support to the idea that myelination is reduced in schizophrenia (12.3.3.). Predictions about GM are less direct. However, since it is generally true that the size of neuronal somata and their dendritic trees are proportional to the amount of axoplasm the neuron has to support, one would expect reductions in these measures, in parallel with a reduction in large caliber or myelinated axons. There is substantial evidence that neuronal soma size is reduced in schizophrenia in many (but not all) cortical areas (12.3.2.). These reductions occur most prominently in areas where overall GM volume reduction is most marked, and are of a magnitude which could explain such volume reductions. There have also been several reports that the number of dendritic spines on cortical pyramidal cells is reduced in schizophrenia (12.3.2.). It is less clear that this represents a stable feature of cytology, since in normal animals many transient influences can modify the number of such spines. There have also been suggestions that numbers of inhibitory interneurons in the cortex are reduced in schizophrenia 48 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia (12.3.2.), but not all studies show this, and some related results can be explained as a dynamic consequence of other functional abnormalities rather than a fundamental cytological difference from normal. 2.13.3. Characteristics of brain tissue revealed from signals used in brain scanning. Attenuation by biological tissues of the X-rays used in computerized tomography is determined by atomic composition of the tissues (12.5.1.1.). In brain tissue, attenuation is greater in GM than myelinated WhM, with unmyelinated WhM giving intermediate degrees of attenuation. Quantitative comparisons of attenuation by brain tissue between sides and groups is made difficult by several artifacts, especially “beam hardening” by the skull. Nevertheless, there is consistent evidence that attenuation in WhM is greater than normal in schizophrenia (12.5.1.2.), and some studies find this to be correlated with enlargement of ventricles or reduction of volume of brain parenchyma (12.5.1.3.). These results would be expected if myelinated WhM was partially replaced by unmyelinated WhM, with resulting reduction of tissue volume. The signals used for MR imaging distinguish between tissues on the basis of their water content, and thus can separate WhM from GM, due to the lower water content of the former (12.5.2.1.). Unmyelinated WhM has a higher water content than myelinated WhM, and therefore is more like GM. Most studies which have compared WhM between normal subjects and those with schizophrenia find the latter to have signal characteristics to be expected of reduced myelination (12.5.2.3.), although the regions in which group differences are seen vary greatly between studies. An elaboration of conventional MRI - magnetization transfer imaging (MTI) - makes use of the fact that myelinassociated water has special properties in MR, so that estimates can be made of the abundance of myelin-associated water, and therefore of myelin (12.5.3.). When this method is used to compare normal subjects and those with schizophrenia, the latter give evidence of reduced myelination in WhM, although again, there is wide variation between studies in the regions where group differences are found. Another method using MRI technology is diffusion tensor imaging (DTI) (12.5.4.). This method measures rates of diffusion of water, in a directionally-selective manner. In pure water, diffusion is the same in all directions, and in GM the same is true, because there is no preferred direction for cellular processes (although overall rates of diffusion are less than in water). In WhM, diffusion has directional biases (that is, it is “anisotropic”), as a result of the tendency to coherent bundling of axons running in parallel. In DTI, the degree of anisotropy is assessed in each voxel (~1 mm3). In schizophrenia, anisotropy in WhM has been found to be less than in normal subjects, although the group differences are found in different regions in different studies (12.5.4.2.). The explanation of this finding has been debated. It is suggested here (12.5.4.1.) that WhM in which mean axonal caliber is small will produce WhM which is more “finely woven” than if the axons are of larger caliber. As a result, it will be more likely that axons running is a variety of directions will be 49 integrated within each voxel, so that, overall, observed anisotropy will be less than in the normal case. 2.13.4. “Best quantitative estimate” of the extent of WhM changes in schizophrenia. In Sect. 11.3.4.5., dealing with paired-stimulus potentiation of the N100 potential, it was possible to make a tentative reconstruction of the axonal conduction time histograms needed to produce the observed results in normal subjects and in those with schizophrenia. This led to the estimate that in normal subjects the relevant pathway had 70% of axons with conduction velocity above 1 m/sec, the remainder below 1 m/sec. In schizophrenia, the respective figures were about 50% and 50%. We can then make assumptions which permit us to estimate the extent of volume loss in hemispheric WhM (12.6.). We assume that the division between conduction velocities above and below 1 m/sec corresponds roughly to that between myelinated and unmyelinated axons; that the latter have a cross-section area approximately one fifth that of the former; and that axons comprise about 33% of the total volume of WhM (the rest being made up of glial cells, blood vessels, extracellular space etc). As a result the fractional reduction in WhM volume in schizophrenia would be about 7%. This figure is somewhat larger than observed empirically. The discrepancy may be accounted for if one assumes that part of the WhM volume is made up of large caliber axons (e.g. those descending to spinal cord and brain stem, and ascending from the thalamus), which are unaffected in schizophrenia. If these made up a significant volume fraction of WhM, the volume reduction in schizophrenia would be less than 7%, as found empirically. 2.13.5. Processes contributing to changes of volume of brain tissue in schizophrenia. In Sect. 12.2.5., the developmental origin to the volume changes in schizophrenia are discussed. It is suggested that the normal process of GM volume reduction occurs normally, but expansion of WhM, due to myelination is less than normal. Thus the expansion of WhM does not keep pace with GM volume reduction. This process is considered to be in operation throughout adolescence, and to a lesser extent in early adult years, and therefore in some cases even after onset of the manifest illness. However, additional processes are required to give a full account of the differences in volume of brain tissue between normal subjects and those with schizophrenia (12.7.). Reductions of brain volume (or alternatively, increases in fluid space volume) occur after onset of illness (12.7.2.). The most parsimonious explanation of most of this evidence is that tissue, perhaps in specific brain regions, may have increased blood flow, associated with increases in neural activity during active psychosis, and this produces a slight, but detectable volume increase. After treatment and remission of symptoms, blood flow decreases, and so does tissue volume (12.7.1., 12.7.3.). In the past, such volume changes have been attributed, by this author and others to a “lesion” (i.e. cell loss) occurring in relation to active psychosis. However, this suggestion is not necessary: The two processes just mentioned, acting together can account for evidence available on early stages of the manifest illness, and there is no cytological evidence for cell loss. In later Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia stages of the illness, reduction of tissue volume may occur to a greater-than-normal extent in schizophrenia (12.7.4.). This is unlikely to be the cause of the disorder, but may be a secondary consequence of the persistent disturbance in brain dynamics the disorder produces. 2.13.6. Correlations between morphological abnormality and symptom groups. Many studies explore possible correlations between brain morphology and symptoms groups in schizophrenia (12.8.). Non-significant findings are common and may have many explanations other than lack of causal relation between the variables. Focusing on significant correlations, it is an almost universal finding that negative symptoms are associated with expansion of ventricles or reduction of volume of brain tissue. This is to be expected from theory, if negative symptoms are the clinical expression of the stable underlying traits of schizophrenia, since these morphological abnormalities are also stable aspects of the brain. Positive symptoms have more complex correlations with morphological variables. Hallucinations, particularly auditory hallucinations which persist in stabilized patients, are consistently associated with reduction of brain tissue volume, especially in the left superior temporal gyrus. Correlations in a similar direction are also usually found for thought disorder or Schneiderian symptoms, although more diverse in the morphological measures involved. Volume reduction in STG is probably due in part to reduced neuronal size, a likely indicator of reduced axonal calibre or myelination in the axonal projections of these neurons. Given this, the correlation with auditory hallucinations supports the explanation of this symptom given in Sect. 7.3.4. (summary in 2.7.2.). Correlations between brain morphology and the symptom of delusions are more diverse, some reports indicating positive correlation, others negative correlation with reductions in tissue volume (or expansion of ventricles). The diversity of results may be an indication that two causal relations are implicated: On the one hand, the tendency to experience delusions, like the tendency to episodes of active psychosis, is an enduring trait, likely to be associated with the cytological changes discussed above, associated with volume reductions in GM and WhM. On the other hand, during the actual episodes of active psychosis, there may be detectable expansion of brain tissue, probably due to increased blood flow. 2.13.7. Genetic vs environmental determinants of brain morphology in schizophrenia. In normal subjects, twin studies have shown that some aspects of brain morphology, such as WBV, and the form of the deeper sulci, are under a high degree of genetic control (12.9.1.2.). Other aspects, such as ventricular size, or form of the superficial sulci are under lesser genetic control. Given these findings as a background, one can ask to what extent the deviations in morphology in schizophrenia are part of the genetic diathesis for the disorder, or have some other origin. Amongst the latter, there are significant non-genetic effects on morphology which predispose to the disorder, but are not seen in unaffected MZ co-twins (12.9.1.3.). Whether these differences arise from non-shared environmental influences or from essentially random processes during development is unresolved. Genetic effects, unconfounded by either of these would be seen in comparisons of unaffected MZ vs DZ cotwins of discordant pairs (12.9.1.4.). Only one study has used this design, and has found volume deficits in GM, related to the genetic predisposition for schizophrenia, in regions similar to but not identical with those for non-genetic effects. Another design which has shown unambiguous genetic effects involves comparison of unaffected obligate carriers of schizophrenia with non-carrier, non-affected relatives. Few studies examine the influence of pre- and peri-natal factors on brain morphology (12.9.2.), and it is not clear that the effects described distinguish schizophrenia births from births of unaffected subjects. However, recent studies have succeeded in defining interactions between such factors and genetic load (12.9.3.): Both fetal hypoxia and the genetic loading for schizophrenia were needed to produce brain morphological changes. A third influence - being born premature or small for their gestational age - increased the effect. Each of these, acting alone was not sufficient to produce morphological change. Human and animals studies have shown that the progenitors of oligodendrocytes, responsible for cerebral myelination, originate in the mid-trimester, well before myelination starts, and at this stage are vulnerable to fetal hypoxia (12.3.3.). Other studies in sheep (12.9.4.) show that placental insufficiency or prolonged hypoxemia can be followed by development of a cortex which is thinner than normal, with increased neuronal density, and, in reduced caliber and myelination of axons (at least in cranial nerves). Such evidence provides hints of the way in which pre-natal environmental problems may combine with genetic liability to produce the brain abnormalities predisposing to schizophrenia. It may be that the same developmental trajectory starting in the mid-trimester can be set in motion by either environmental or genetic influences, and especially a combination of the two. There is no research investigating whether psychosocial adversity predisposing to schizophrenic psychoses has an influence on brain morphology. 2.13.8. Brain morphology in disorders related to schizophrenia. There is little evidence from brain morphology that the different disorders in the “schizophrenia spectrum” are categorically separate (12.10.). For schizoaffective disorder, the various forms of affective disorder, and personality disorders related to schizophrenia, various volumetric measures of the brain display changes from normal similar in kind, but usually less in degree compared to those found in schizophrenia. However, in the affective disorders, there is some evidence that depression with psychotic features shows greater morphological abnormality than that without such features. The only hint of categorical separation between affective disorder and schizophrenia is a small amount of evidence that GM volumes in some cortical areas are larger than normal in bipolar disorder, findings against the general trend to volume reduction. 2.13.9. Miscellaneous correlations of brain morphology. The degree of abnormality of brain morphology is related to various aspects of severity of schizophrenic disorder, 50 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia including measures of premorbid adjustment, longer-term outcome, and responsiveness to antipsychotic drugs. The reduced responsiveness to medication in those with more pronounced morphological abnormality probably reflects slower response rather than categorical non-response. Cognitive impairment, assessed by a wide variety of measures is generally correlated with greater morphological abnormality, but the complexity of this literature prevents its being used for testing the “central hypothesis” of this book in a precise way. Correlations with psychophysiological measures have also been documented, but again contribute little to theory development 51 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia . Chapter 13. The concept of schizophrenia: neurodynamic consequences of delayed and incomplete maturation of cerebral white matter. 13.1. “Psychosis” vs nearly-separate theories. “schizophrenia”: two A crucial premise for this book is that the theory needed to explain “psychotic” manifestations of schizophrenia is almost completely separate from that needed for schizophrenia as a whole. Psychosis does occur in schizophrenia, but is not specific to schizophrenia. Moreover, most features of psychosis are in principle parts of a transient state. Admittedly, this statement needs to be qualified in three ways: (i) Some psychotic symptoms, notably delusional beliefs, may persist long after the active phase of psychosis has abated. (ii) Schneiderian symptoms and auditory hallucinations are often not completely controlled by medication. (iii) In some patients, active psychotic states may persist because they are medication-resistant. Despite these qualifications, psychoses associated with schizophrenia are usually episodic in the days of modern drug treatment. Therefore psychotic symptoms should not be of predominant importance in defining schizophrenia, which is an on-going disorder when psychosis is under control. Schizophrenia includes many enduring non-psychotic trait abnormalities. These do not sharply differentiate normal subjects from those with schizophrenia. They are present before, during and after psychotic episodes, and are present also in relatives of schizophrenia probands most of whom never have psychotic episodes. Although they tend to be inherited, this inheritance is not of the single factor variety, but, as with schizophrenia itself, fits better a multi-factor type of inheritance. Nevertheless, some of them show stronger heritability than the diagnosis itself, presumably because environmental factors contribute significantly to the cause of the diagnosis, but less to individual traits. These traits may be more important for definition of schizophrenia than are the features of psychosis. This formulation is supported by the fact that, in chronic schizophrenia, the traits defined by experimental methods correlate with negative symptoms, thought disorder (or both), but rarely with positive symptoms. Thus, even when positive symptoms are present outside the times of active psychosis, they appear to have a basis different from that of negative symptoms and thought disorder. This is consistent with the idea that some positive symptoms endure as a memory or “cognitive habit”, first established during earlier periods of active psychosis, and are not true traits. 13.2. Explanation as the criterion scientifically-valid concept of disease. for a In Sect. 1.8., the guideline was suggested that “the criterion for a scientifically-valid definition is that it will support a comprehensive and rigorous explanatory argument”. According to this principle, the concept of “dopaminemediated psychosis” in schizophrenia is strongly validated: By extension to humans of psychobiological principles, wellestablished for the action of dopamine in animals, most of the important features of schizophrenic psychoses can be explained. With regard to trait aspects of schizophrenia, many measures show group differences from normal control groups. However, none of them distinguishes schizophrenia from either normal controls or a number of other disorders well enough to support a valid definition of a concept of mental disorder, if the argument is to be based just on statistics and correlations. However, if we bear in mind the above guideline (i.e., that definition depends on prior explanatory arguments), the theoretical arguments presented in this book give coherence to a concept of schizophrenia, although this concept is in several ways not congruent with those embodied in several widely-used diagnostic systems. The basic premise of these theoretical arguments is that there is a relative absence of rapidly-conducting cortico-cortical axons. This premise is used to explain much evidence in the areas of psychology, psychophysiology, clinical electrophysiology, and brain morphology examined with both classical neuropathological methods, and with modern methods of brain scanning. Brain volume, and the volumes of both GM and WhM in the hemispheres are reduced. However, there is no evidence of a degenerative process, and very little for a reduction in number of cortical neurons. Some studies of brain development during adolescence in schizophrenia are compatible with the idea that the normal process of myelination of cortico-cortical axons occurring between birth and adulthood is delayed and incomplete. The reduced expansion of WhM volume combined with normal loss of GM volume during adolescence accounts for the expansion of fluid spaces and deficit in volume of brain parenchyma in schizophrenia. Evidence from molecular genetics converges with these lines of evidence, pointing to abnormalities in myelination in schizophrenia. In normal subjects myelination of cortico-cortical axons is still continuing in early adulthood, and, in schizophrenia, the deficit in brain volume is still increasing at this stage. This can account for volume loss after the onset of psychotic illness, without postulating a psychosisrelated loss of tissue. Normal female subjects have brain volumes 12-15% less than in male subjects, a difference accounted for by lower numbers of neurons in females, and there may be different patterns of asymmetry in the two genders. In schizophrenia, the same gender differences are present. Schizophrenia in female subjects has a later age of onset than in males, and is generally more benign, but this difference probably does not have a basis in brain morphology. Probably it depends on the protective effect of estrogens in females, acting to limit psychotic decompensation. 52 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia 13.3. The schizophrenia, laterality. “central hypothesis” for and that for normal cerebral The central hypothesis for schizophrenia - a relative absence of rapidly conducting cortico-cortical axons - is closely related to a previous hypothesis for normal cerebral asymmetry - that the left hemisphere has an abundance of slowly conducting axons, the right a predominance of more rapidly conducting ones. As a result the slogan “two left hemispheres” captures many of the trait abnormalities in schizophrenia, implying either a selective loss of right hemisphere functions, or an exaggeration of left hemisphere ones. However, the difference between normal and schizophrenia (in either hemisphere) is considerably larger than that between right and left hemisphere in normal subjects. This can be seen not only for morphological comparisons, but also in studies of visual and auditory perception, where, although the right hemisphere is most affected in schizophrenia, both hemispheres are impaired to some degree. Impairment of the left hemisphere in auditory threshold or vigilance tests is somewhat labile, depending on such things as time of day, long testing sessions, or a tendency to hallucinations. One possibility is that the more easily excitable right hemisphere normally “boosts” left hemisphere performance, but this boosting is prone to failure in schizophrenia. There are some facts which do not fit the “two left hemispheres” formulation. People with schizophrenia may have impairment in recognition of consonant speech sounds, a left hemisphere-preferred function in normal subjects. In dichotic listening studies, in accordance with the “two left hemisphere” slogan, there is loss of asymmetry in schizophrenia when the test is purely perceptual in nature. However, when the test includes a short-term memory component, asymmetry (left hemisphere superiority) is increased. Likewise in one study of visuo-manual control the right hand (left hemisphere) was found to be more impaired than the left hand (right hemisphere). Amongst electrophysiological findings, several measures reveal greater abnormality on the left than the right side: Thus the excess of power in the EEG beta frequency range is more prominent on the left than the right side. The reduction of amplitude of the P300 potential is more prominent on the left than the right side, especially for posterior temporal derivations. In morphological terms, volume reduction in the superior temporal gyrus is more pronounced on the left than the right side, a finding which correlates consistently with the predisposition to verbal auditory hallucinations. To account for some of these findings, a hypothesis, supplementary to the main theory, is proposed. This assumes that in the normal left hemisphere, projections from Broca’s to Wernicke’s areas are unusually fast-conducting, this morphological specialization mediating some of the normal left hemisphere’s facility with language. In schizophrenia, in accord with the “central hypothesis”, but not the simplifying slogan “two left hemispheres”, there is a relative loss of rapidly-conducting axons in this pathway, one of the consequences of which is a predisposition to auditory verbal hallucinations. At present, not all of the unexpected findings which contradict the 53 principle of “two left hemispheres” have been related to occurrence of this sort of hallucination. Further correlational studies are needed. There are suggestions that in active psychosis in schizophrenia, the pattern of abnormal asymmetry is different from that during stable remission. However, no consistent picture emerges. In some tests (e.g. tactile discrimination), during active psychosis the left hemisphere is more impaired than in remission, while in others the left hemisphere is less impaired (e.g. in some auditory and visual tests) and the left hemisphere advantage increases. 13.4. The “deepest question”: the relation between enduring traits and psychotic episodes in schizophrenia. The deepest question about schizophrenia is on the relation between the two bodies of theory, namely that for dopamine-mediated psychosis, and that for the enduring trait abnormalities. This question can be translated into neurodynamic terms: How can sustained over-activity of midbrain dopamine neurons arise when the hemispheres are connected by cortico-cortical connections with slower-thannormal conduction, allowing greater-than-normal temporal divergence of signals? From analysis of the neurodynamic basis of one area of psychological dysfunction (difficulty in shift of attention), supplemented by more direct electrographic evidence, it is possible to give an answer to this question: In schizophrenia, assuming a relative abundance of slowly-conducting axons, the hemispheres have greater “inertia” than normal - that is, they require more vigorous activation before transcortical signal propagation occurs reliably; but, once they reach this state, they have more “momentum” than normal, so the hemispheres are prone to prolonged periods of reverberatory activity. This state, likely to be related in real life to psychological traumata, in turn leads to sustained over-activity of the midbrain dopamine neurons, and therefore to onset of active psychosis. 13.5. Variability of schizophrenia: Fundamental heterogeneity or varied expression of a single process? The manifestations of schizophrenia are very varied. A hitherto unresolved controversy is whether this variability signifies one disorder with many manifestations, or many fundamentally different disorders, arbitrarily gathered together because of some surface similarity. The theory presented here is more compatible with the first than the second of these alternatives, since all the trait abnormalities, as well as the vulnerability to psychosis can be accounted for in terms of the same premise about properties of corticocortical axons. Moreover, the idea that the varied expression of schizophrenia reflects the action of a variety of separate genetic factors (genetic heterogeneity) does not fit data on inheritance as well as the polygene model. However, there are a number of relatively rare conditions, whose genetics is simpler than that of schizophrenia in which there is also a predisposition to psychosis and abnormality of cerebral white matter similar to that proposed for schizophrenia. These uncommon and discrete disorders may appear similar to the Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia broad run of schizophrenic disorders, which, in their varied form, make up most of the people who have this diagnosis. The idea that there is an underlying unity to schizophrenia which encompasses most cases need not imply that all trait abnormalities are found together in each patient with schizophrenia. It is not known how different trait measures associate or dissociate across patients. There is room for much further work here. Such work may give improved validation to subtype differentiation, in terms of explanatory arguments. Specifically, a combination of morphological and functional studies may be able to show how different trait manifestations of schizophrenia arise when there is loss of rapidly-conducting axons in different parts of cerebral white matter. A more detailed factorization of symptoms than has hitherto been established may then arise. 13.6. The broad concept of schizophrenia defined by traits vs schizophrenia defined in terms of psychotic symptoms. The present concept of schizophrenia differs from ones previously adopted in several ways: (i) The heart of the concept is the collection of trait abnormalities. Indeed, in genetic terms, some traits (pursuit eye movement abnormalities; impairment in tests of sustained attention) are inherited more strongly than the schizophrenia diagnosis itself (which has additional, non-genetic causal contributions). The psychotic manifestations of the disorder are then conceived as severe complications of the underlying diathesis. While psychosis may cause long-lasting damage to the psychosocial fabric of a young person’s life, and in practice may be the area of disorder requiring most urgent attention, psychosis is not the core of the disorder. (ii) The diathesis for schizophrenia occurs far more widely than schizophrenia as defined by the occurrence of psychotic symptoms. Many people with a variety of the trait abnormalities may escape the psychotic manifestations, due, perhaps to a benign early environmental factors which does not predispose to the transition to psychosis. (iii) In terms of currently used diagnoses, the broadened concept of schizophrenia developed here overlaps with several other current diagnoses. This is evident both in studies of inheritance of one disorder in relatives with another disorder, and also in the degree of functional or morphological abnormality seen in schizophrenia compared to other related disorders. A particular example of the relationship of schizophrenia to other disorders is the dichotomy (originating with Kraepelin) between schizophrenia (a.k.a. dementia praecox) and bipolar disorder (a.k.a. manic-depressive illness). This dichotomy is central for psychiatry, and merits more detailed discussion. 13.6.1. Are schizophrenia and manic-depressive illness separate and distinct disorders? In genetic terms, schizophrenia and manic-depressive illness, as diagnosed, are mainly, but not completely separate. The pattern of cross-prevalence for disorders in the broad schizophrenia spectrum is not well accounted for on the assumption that these disorders represent different degrees of a single disease process. Further differentiation between these two comes from the fact the schizophrenia has earlier onset and is more severe in males than females, but the opposite is true for bipolar disorder (see Sect. 3.5.1.). There appears to be more than one disease process involved in this broad spectrum, but the different processes do not correspond exactly to diagnostic labels. In terms of diagnostic stability, a patient may receive one diagnosis at one time, another in a later episode. Diagnostic stability across time is less than the reliability between raters at a single point in time. Change of diagnosis is therefore is not due solely to imperfect inter-rater reliability. Any symptom of schizophrenia may also occur in manic-depressive disorder, although there are quantitative group differences in incidence of specific symptoms in different diagnostic groups. Evidence on putative contributory environmental causes (for instance obstetric complications) sometimes appear to shift diagnosis from affective to schizophrenic disorder, again bringing into question their genetic distinctness. Functional traits associated with schizophrenia might give hints of qualitative differences from manic-depressive illness. One diagnostic group might show impairment in a particular test, while another group shows test performance above normal. If more than one test is considered, there may be some tests in which group A is significantly more impaired than group B, and other tests in which group B is the more impaired than group A. Such patterns of results would suggest the existence of separate disease processes in the two groups. Little of the evidence reviewed in this book shows either of these patterns. Usually patients with schizophrenia show impairment, while those with affective disorder show milder or no impairment. Quraishi and Frangou (2002) tabulate many studies where comparisons were made between the two diagnoses, with respect to general intelligence, attention, memory and learning, and executive function. Regardless of whether the affective subjects were ill or stabilized at the time of testing, there were no clear dissociations of trait abnormalities, suggestive of separate diatheses for schizophrenia and affective disorder, though generally the former were more impaired than the latter. A few studies of traits give hints of dissociations. In Chapter 6, it was mentioned that, in factor analyses of symptoms, patient groups with bipolar disorder do not give a clear Disorganization factor. High performance at age 20y in an arithmetic reasoning task is characteristic of subjects who later develop bipolar disorder, and differentiates them from those who develop schizophrenia, although both groups share impairment in visuo-spatial reasoning tasks (Tiihonen et al, 2005). Park and Holzman (1992) found, in a memory-guided oculomotor delayed response task, that patients with schizophrenia were less accurate than normal subjects, while medicated bipolar patients were more accurate. However, the bipolar subjects also had slower reaction times than controls, so they may have differed from controls merely in how they traded off speed against accuracy. Lohr and Caligiuri (1995b) measured hand force stability, and found that schizophrenia patients were impaired with both hands, but had greater rightthan left-hand instability, while bipolar patients had greater left-hand instability. Normal controls were symmetrical in this task. V.A.Curtis et al (2001) found that functional activation of frontal lobes in a verbal fluency task was above normal in stabilized bipolar patients, but below normal in 54 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia schizophrenia. Greater focus on results of this sort might help to clarify underlying differences between these two diagnoses. Different medications (e.g. lithium vs antipsychotic drugs) are effective in different illnesses, but the effectiveness does not correlate exactly with diagnosis: Lithium can be effective in schizophrenia (Alexander et al, 1979; Hirschowitz et al, 1980), and antipsychotic drugs can be effective in manic depressive disorder when lithium has failed (Garver et al, 1988). The conclusion again appears to be that there is more than one disease process within the broad schizophrenia spectrum, but they cannot be distinguished categorically on the basis of symptoms. What the disease processes may be other than those analyzed here is beyond the scope of this book. The dimension emphasized here - the repertoire of conduction times in cortico-cortical axons - allows many variants other than the “central hypothesis” for schizophrenia, which could form the basis for a theoretically-based definitions of a number of psychiatric conditions. For instance, evidence of greater-than-normal GM volumes in some cortical regions in bipolar disorder (Sect. 12.10.2.), could indicate that in these regions neurons are larger than normal, and give rise to abnormally rapidly-conducting axons. Another starting point would be to examine how lithium acts. Schizophrenia defined in terms of any of its associated traits is in complete continuity with the range of normal personality variants. Those most strongly linked to schizophrenia, in terms of traits held in common, are “schizotypy” as defined psychometrically, and schizotypal personality disorder as defined with clinical instruments. (There is little to chose between these two in strength of association to schizophrenia itself.) None of the trait abnormalities, nor schizophrenia itself, show a tendency to be inherited in a categorical fashion. However, by long usage we have become accustomed to thinking of schizophrenia as a sharply-defined category. Psychotic states can claim to be categorically separate from normality, but this does not apply at all to the concept of schizophrenia as a whole, as it emerges in the present theory. The view that schizophrenia is a sharply-defined category also has its cultural roots in the unfortunate tendency in most human societies to identify one or other group of marginalized people as “aliens”. For these reasons a new name is required for this disorder, in whatever way it is eventually conceived in coming years. This is currently a matter of discussion by the committee developing the forthcoming DSMV document (Kingdon et al, 2007), and one of the proposals is a “general psychosis syndrome”. The present author does not have the experience to propose a new name. However, while perhaps of some pragmatic value, this proposal misses the point that the enduring traits are a surer guide to the cause of what is now called “schizophrenia” than are psychotic episode. It is suggested that a new name should incorporate the concept of “delayed or incomplete maturation of cerebral white matter”. 13.7. Traits aspects of schizophrenia and normal functional development. Many of the traits of schizophrenia are similar to features 55 found in normal pre-adult development. Amongst psychological measures, this is the case for the abnormalities in smooth pursuit eye movement, sustained attention (as assessed with the CPT), span of apprehension, antisaccade errors, and (tentatively) the reaction time cross-over effect. Amongst electrophysiological measures it is the case for interhemispheric transfer time, P50 suppression, and amplitude of the mismatch negativity and P300 potentials. This is all in accordance with theory, since children and adolescents have relatively incomplete myelination of cerebral white matter, just as, according to the theory presented here, is the case for adult schizophrenia. It may then be asked why normal children and adolescents show active phases of psychosis very rarely10. Turned around, this question becomes: Why is the age of onset of schizophrenic disorder delayed to late adolescence or early adulthood? This may be because, as Weinberger (1987) has noted, dopamine levels in the brain reach their peak at about the time when schizophrenia makes itself manifest. However, there may be another contributing effect: The theory relating the trait abnormalities (and their supposed basis in axonal properties) to psychosis (and its basis in over-activity of dopamine mechanisms) was based on the fact that in schizophrenia, the activated cortex is capable of prolonged reverberatory activity. In other terms this amounts to a tendency to activation of long chains of neuronal firing (mediating “long chains of thought”). Such chains are likely to be progressively acquired (learned) during development by Hebbian strengthening of synapses at each of the links in the chain. In real-life terms, this process continues throughout the years from early childhood to adulthood. Thus, given the schizophrenia diathesis, the ability to produce the reverberatory activity leading to psychotic destabilization may also be conditional on a certain degree of “cognitive maturity”, associated, at least in people with the schizophrenia diathesis, with the capacity to sustain long chains of thought. 13.8. Correlations between traits assessed in the laboratory and symptoms assessed clinically. The analysis of functional trait abnormalities in schizophrenia included a review of the correlations of each measure with the three main symptom groups (psychomotor poverty [negative symptoms], disorganization [thought disorder], and reality distortion [positive symptoms]). As 10 Childhood schizophrenia is a controversial concept, partly because it cannot be assumed that the underlying disease process is expressed phenomenologically in the same way in children as in adults. However cases are known where psychotic symptoms occur in children between ages of 5 and 10 years, which progress to the recognizable adult form of schizophrenia (Annell, 1963; Eggers et al, 1989; Werry et al, 1991). These are responsive to antipsychotic drugs, although clozapine and other atypical drugs are more effective (Remschmidt, 1993; Frazier et al, 1994; Kumra et al, 1996; Turetz et al, 1997). They have increased incidence of schizophrenia-spectrum disorders in FDR (Kallman and Roth, 1956; Bender, 1975). Such cases are quite rare, ~50-fold less common than adult-onset schizophrenia (Burd and Kerbeshian, 1987; Thomsen, 1996) Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia mentioned above positive symptoms rarely show significant association with trait measures. However, on the basis of correlations with symptoms, it is possible to separate two classes of trait abnormality. The first, including lengthened critical stimulus duration, and impaired visual backward masking, impairment in smooth pursuit, vigilance tests, visuospatial WM and olfactory identification, correlate with negative symptoms but not with thought disorder or Disorganization factor scores. The second, including excessive semantic priming, impairment in pre-pulse inhibition of startle. Measures of persistence of set in attention-shifting paradigms are associated with thought disorder/disorganization. The so-called glutamate hypothesis of schizophrenia has drawn attention to the fact that NMDA antagonists such as ketamine can produce effects in normal subjects similar to negative symptoms. Ketamine can also mimic in normal subjects some of the trait abnormalities surveyed in Chapter 7-11. It is of interest to note that the trait abnormalities to which this applies (i.e. smooth pursuit eye and hand movements, sustained attention, rote learning, mismatch negativity) are ones which correlate mainly with negative symptoms, whereas for other traits (such as those in semantic priming, prepulse inhibition, WCST or P300 potentials) there are no reports of NMDA antagonists producing the same effect in normal subjects. The theory explaining the similarity between schizophrenia traits and the effects of NMDA antagonists would also involve just the traits similar to negative symptoms, not those produced in states of higher cerebral activation. 13.9. Psychosocial influences contributing to occurrence of schizophrenia. Most of this book is devoted to exploring the brain dynamics underlying the state and trait aspects of schizophrenia. However, in Chapter 4, evidence was reviewed showing that psychosocial factors in the environment could have a major impact on the incidence of diagnosed schizophrenia, notably in certain immigrant groups: The evidence on this is clear, but it is less obvious how psychosocial adversity during pre-adult years can interact with the supposed biological factor - a relative absence of rapidly-conducting axons - in determining the appearance of definite illness. There are three possibilities to consider: (i) Psychosocial adversity might affect gene expression, which in turn determines cellular development during childhood and adolescence. (ii) Such adversity might influence plastic processes in synapses, mediating cell assembly development. Without changing the actual morphological substrate in the brain, this could still affect the repertoire of cognitive abilities seen in the adult, and predispose a person to schizophrenia, including its underlying traits. (iii) Prolonged psychosocial adversity during upbringing, might have an influence at the level of “whole person” psychology, which interacts with the substrate of brain morphology to produce manifest illness. Specifically, when a person grows up in an environment dominated by all-prevailing disadvantage and discrimination, he or she may develop a personal style of “all-out striving” to succeed, which may nevertheless fail. Such an attitude to life may have the consequence that the activated “up-state” of the cortex may be generated more commonly than in more relaxed young people who do not grow up having to deal with such adversity. This could precipitate the transition to psychosis in vulnerable people who would otherwise escape psychotic aspects of the schizophrenia diathesis. The studies of immigration in relation to schizophrenia show increased incidence of schizophrenic psychosis, but there is no evidence that it increases the incidence of the underlying traits (a topic which has never been explored). Thus, from evidence available at present, one does not need to postulate a psychosocial environmental effect which alters the morphological substrate during development (the first alternative). The second alternative carries the implication that psychosocial adversity would, by processes of synaptic plasticity, lead (without actual morphological change) to unusual functional predominance of slowly-conducting components of the repertoire of axons, with relative neglect of the rapidly-conducting ones. This is not inconceivable: A social environment dominated by negative reinforcement and punishment may produce a general suppression of spontaneous voluntary acts, and an encouragement of mental “rumination” when action is suppressed. These may correspond to plastic synaptic changes which suppress the influence of the rapidly-conducting axons and strengthen that of slowly-conducting components of the axonal repertoire. However, if this environmental influence on the cortical network could “mould” the potentialities of the morphological substrate, it is expected that it would enhance both trait and state aspects of schizophrenia beyond that specified genetically. Schizophrenic illness in which psychosocial adversity was an important contributory cause would then be predicted to have a lower genetic loading than that arising without this influence. This appears not to be the case: In studies of Afro-Caribbean immigrants in Britain, the best studied example of the contributory psychosocial cause of schizophrenia, relatives of the immigrant probands living in the Caribbean islands from which the immigrant families came have an incidence of schizophrenia which is elevated above the baseline rate by an amount similar to that in control FDR in the UK-born white population. By exclusion therefore, of the three possibilities listed in the previous paragraph, the third, where environmental pressures shapes people’s attitude to life, leading to a predisposition to psychosis rather than to the underlying traits, appears most likely. This conclusion can plausibly apply not only to the impact of immigrant status, but also to that of urban birth and upbringing. In support of this, some trait abnormalities are inherited more strongly than the diagnosis itself (which derives mainly from psychotic manifestations). The latter but not the former may combine both genetic and psychosocial determinants. 13.10. Schizophrenia and the “self”. Bleuler’s term “schizophrenia” means, literally, “a fragmentation of the mind or the ‘self’”. This “whole person” aspect of the psychology of schizophrenia can be considered in relation to both trait and state aspects of the disorder. The symptoms which are most conspicuously captured by this definition, which appear to be traits, but exacerbated in psychotic states, are those emphasized by Kurt Schneider 56 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia (otherwise known as “passivity symptoms”): A person may have the experience that his thoughts, actions or words are “not his own”, but the product of some other agency. This sounds like a contradiction in terms, since thoughts and voluntary actions or emitted speech, are by definition, “of the person”. The description of these symptoms make sense only if one realizes that the very processes which work together to produce a unified person are compromised in schizophrenia. Other traits also imply a “weakened sense of self”, though less dramatically so. For instance, the slowing of reactions in motor control tasks mediated moment-by-moment by sensory guidance can be extended as a personality trait so that a person cannot “pull himself together” to give a quick and accurate response in a testing moment. Such an impairment may be particularly limiting in social interactions, involving defense against social threats, or in initiating friendships. Amongst the strictly psychotic symptoms, delusional beliefs undermine a person’s “sense of self” in a different way: For a person to have to accept that firmly held beliefs are (or were) the symptom of a mental illness, shakes his or her confidence in any of his beliefs, and undermines his capacity to believe anything. Overall we see a pattern evident in study of many of the traits covered in Chapter 7-10: Definite trait impairments are present in well stabilized patients, but they become more severe when studied in actively psychotic ones. There is however another side to “sense of self” in schizophrenia: In some respects the trait aspects of “sense of self” are advantageous, rather than detrimental. Thus, in some circumstances, the ability to follow through “long trains of thought” may confer an advantage, compared with a person who can give a quick spontaneous response in a testing moment. Whereas the latter may have great confidence in their ability to react immediately in challenging and rapidlychanging situations, the former may have superior confidence in their ability to think through and plan strategies of response in advance of their actual use. In these two faces of the “sense of self”, one sees, writ large, the same characteristics evident in many of the more specific traits. Indeed “the self”, in the sense of being able to respond quickly in an emergency situation, can be regarded as a very complex Gestalt, bringing together, in a moment of time, all the habits, idiosyncrasies, implicit learning and explicit memories of a person’s life. 13.11. Schizophrenia: condition. a uniquely human One of the enduring puzzles about schizophrenia is that it appears to be quite unique to humans. No schizophrenia-like disorder is known in any animal species. Of course it is difficult to know how such a disorder would be expressed in animals. Nevertheless, we do have plausible animal models of dopamine-mediated psychosis, but not of schizophrenia itself. In a general way, this conundrum might be answered by pointing out that schizophrenia does not correspond to any of the broad classes of disease found in all animal species (infective, degenerative, autoimmune etc), but rather to a distinctively human class - neurodynamic disorders - as discussed in Chapter 1. However, a more detailed answer is needed. In this context, T.J.Crow (Crow, 1997, 2000; Berlim et al, 57 2003), has suggested that the origin of schizophrenia is closely related to the evolutionary origin of language. Indeed, he sees the vulnerability to schizophrenia and the origin of language as critical events in the origin of the human species. These ideas are based on several subsidiary propositions: that the symptoms of schizophrenia are fundamentally related to language dysfunction; that human language is related to the development of cerebral asymmetry; that cerebral asymmetry is unique to humans; that human language capacity is based on mutation at a single gene, variants of which lead to schizophrenia; and that there must be some heterozygote advantage to compensate for the reproductive disadvantage associated with schizophrenia. This thesis has one important point in common with the theory in the present book: Schizophrenia is seen as a disorder of cerebral asymmetry. Apart from this, each of the subsidiary propositions is questionable. It is a biased view of schizophrenia to link it so specifically to language problems. This is possibly related to one interpretation of the concept of schizophrenia arising from the British psychopathological system - the Present State Examination. However, from survey of all the traits associated with the diagnosis of schizophrenia, it is clear that the abnormalities cover many areas other than language functions. Human language functions derive from specializations in addition to cerebral asymmetry: Such asymmetry influences many psychological functions, not just language. Cerebral asymmetry is not unique to humans: Lateral specialization bearing some similarity to that in humans has been documented in rodents (Ehret, 1987; Bianki, 1988; Fitch et al, 1993; O’Connor et al, 1993; Güven et al, 2003), sheep (Peirce et al, 2000) and monkeys (Hamilton and Vermeire, 1988; Vermeire et al, 1998), and, if properly examined, may be quite widespread amongst mammalian species. In Chapter 4, it was argued that the genetics of schizophrenia could not be based on genes of such major influence that there was strong selection pressure to eliminate such genes. This being so, the concept of compensatory heterozygote advantage is irrelevant to schizophrenia. There is no paradox in the survival of schizophrenia despite fertility disadvantage, if one accepts that the inheritance is multifactorial, with phenotype dependent epistatically on genotype. More generally, although Crow refers to biological evidence (gross morphology; genetic factors), there is no attempt at “crosslevel” explanations of symptoms in terms neurobiology. Notably the account of Schneiderian nuclear symptoms fails to link neurodynamic parameters with the psychological symptoms. Furthermore, Crow tends to equate schizophrenia with psychosis; but it is clear from the evidence surveyed in the present book that the abnormalities in schizophrenia cover areas of function with little relation to psychosis. In terms of the present theory, the idea that there is no equivalent of schizophrenia in animals (even allowing for the difficulty in knowing how it would be expressed in animals) may be related to the much larger brain size of humans compared to any animal species (except cetaceans and elephants). As a result, the disparity between the spread of conduction times in a population of axons and the neuronal integration time is comparably much greater in humans. This disparity underlies much of the theoretical reasoning in the Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia present theory. 13.12 Neuropathology vs psychopathology. Pathology is the science of disease processes. In what sense is schizophrenia a disease? In what sense is there a pathology in this condition? Since the time of Virchow, cellular pathology has had a central place in the science of disease processes, although more recently, chemical and molecular pathology have become important, and, in psychiatry, psychopathology is a major focus. In almost every example of cellular pathology, the cells seen in the microscope are in themselves pathological: They are not normally present, are necessary for the disease to appear, and often are sufficient to make a diagnosis. However, these characteristics do not apply to the cellular changes postulated here for schizophrenia: There is nothing abnormal about fine calibre or unmyelinated cortico-cortical axons, or small cortical pyramidal cells. At the level of gross morphology, slight reductions in volume of the hemispheres or of grey or white matter within them are also not in themselves abnormal, or necessary or sufficient for schizophrenic illness to occur. They may prove to be necessary for the broadened concept of schizophrenia defined here in terms of traits. However that broad concept of schizophrenia is not necessarily a pathology or a disease. The real pathology arises partly as a result of changes in neurodynamics made possible by the altered repertoire of axonal conduction times, with causal contributions from psychosocial adverse experiences. The pathology is then primarily psychopathology rather than neuropathology. 13.13. Implications for treatment, and prevention of disability. What are the implications of the theory presented here for treatment of schizophrenic disorders, and for prevention (at least) of the disability they produce, if not of the disorders themselves? Clearly the most damaging aspect of schizophrenia is active psychosis. In itself, the mental turmoil of florid psychosis may do severe damage to the social fabric of a person’s life, occurring, as it often does, at an age when higher education, establishment of work and employment patterns, and development of close relationships are normally all taking place. Episodes of psychosis, especially if repeated, undermine development in all these areas. Even assuming that further psychotic episodes can be prevented, it may take years to rebuild and to recover the lost ground, after such assaults on expected development of adult roles; and sometimes such development is forever forestalled, or adult roles are never regained. Quite apart from the damage at the psychosocial level, it is also possible that florid psychotic episodes are “neurotoxic”, in the sense of causing neuronal loss. This possibility is discussed in Chapter 12. In the author’s view the neurotoxic effect of psychosis is not proven. Regardless of this, it is clear that psychosis is very damaging. An important focus therefore is not only to treat psychotic episodes when they occur, but also to prevent them occurring in the first place. This is easier said than done. Effective strategies for prevention require that persons who are highly likely to develop psychotic disorders, whether the diagnosis is schizophrenia or some other condition, can be identified, with a minimum of false negative and (especially) false positive identification. In principle this might be possible by screening for trait abnormalities. However, for mass screening, this would require development of methods of assessment much simpler and less expensive than most of the methods used in a research laboratory. This may become possible. However, there are further complications. Traits merge imperceptibly into the normal range of personality variations, and the transition from definite trait abnormalities to manifest psychosis appears to be highly conditional upon stressors in the psychosocial environment. It is therefore probably beyond what is practical to identify the very individuals who will become psychotic in advance of their doing so. Thus true “pre-emptive” early intervention is probably too ambitious a goal. Nevertheless, preventive strategies can be realized in other ways. Many young people who eventually suffer psychotic breakdowns, are, in the early prodromal stages, well aware that they are becoming unwell, and engage in help-seeking behavior. This “window of opportunity” is probably the time when early intervention measures can be instituted in a manner which is administratively and financially practical, and ethically acceptable. If left until later, when florid active psychosis is present, coercive treatment may be needed, and for this and other reasons, lasting damage may be done, not only to the social fabric of the person’s life, but also to the possibility of a good therapeutic relationship being established with mental health services. However, to make full use of this “window of opportunity” is a complex pragmatic matter, only partly dependent on scientific issues about the underlying disorders. As in many areas of preventive medicine, ideas that sound good in principle, need to be developed in a cautious manner, since their deployment involves complex financial, political and ethical considerations, differing from one society to another. A pre-requisite for such an approach to prevention of psychosis, or forestalling its adverse impact by treatment as early as possible, is public education. It is important that young people (and others) who might become ill have the knowledge to recognize those aspects of their own mental processes which might be a sign of developing psychotic illness. It is also important that the population as a whole has an accurate and non-stigmatizing view of mental illness, so that the prevailing social environment of people with developing problems does not deter them from seeking psychiatric help. Also these young people should have a reasonably accurate view of what modern mental health services can offer, and know that if they present themselves to the services their problems will be dealt with effectively and safely. If public education can achieve these goals, the outlook for psychosis prevention may be favorable. The trait abnormalities discussed in the present work are often inherently less disruptive to everyday life than the episodes of psychosis, and by themselves need not inevitably prevent a person from leading an independent and fulfilled life. However, since, at the present stage of development of mental health care, assessment of trait impairments is often compounded by the effects of present or past psychotic 58 Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia episodes, it is difficult to say how disabling and severe these impairments can be, when considered in isolation. The Schneiderian symptoms, often regarded as the most severe psychopathology, emerge, in the present work, as partly traits and partly aspects of the psychotic state. Even if prevention of active (dopamine-mediated) psychosis was completely effective, it is likely that many patients would still experience such symptoms, resistant to drug treatment, because they are only partly dopamine-mediated. The full benefits of early intervention will emerge from future developments in research and service delivery. The degree of disability the enduring traits produce is partly a function of the prevailing psychological stressors in the family, the employment environment, and other aspects of day-to-day life. Of course one could ask that societies in general become less stressful, but this is perhaps not a very feasible public health goal. More realistically, there are a number of situations in which awareness of the trait abnormalities, and the limits they impose on social functioning, can play a part in helping young people with their choice of employment or careers. For instance, people with a problem in continual switching of attention would be ill-advised to seek employment in front-line situations where they deal, face-to-face, with very widely varying demands of the general public, and have to make continual quick decisions. A better working environment would be one where the person’s facility for forward planning, imagination and creativity can be fully utilized. Just how far all this can go in alleviating distress and disablement due to schizophrenia is uncertain. Since these strategies depend on public education and effective antistigma campaigns, which are in the present time only just beginning to have significant impact, we cannot say how far early detection and prevention strategies can become effective in future years. However, indications that schizophrenic illness is generally less disabling in developing countries than in the developed world11 gives one hope that substantial improvement in the lives of persons with this disorder can be achieved. Some of the more ambitious biologically-based researchers might ask whether it is possible to intervene directly to change the morphological substrate proposed here as the basis of schizophrenia, or to mitigate its effects. To change the morphological substrate, that is the repertoire of axons with their particular range of calibers, types and conduction velocities, seems to imply that the developmental processes by which the adult repertoire is acquired could be modified. However, such a repertoire appears to be one of the core structural substrates of human personality. Making the big assumption that it is possible to interfere with such processes implies that permanent changes to personality would be produced. This seems to the present author to be at least very expensive, and probably in the realm of science fiction. To attempt such a drastic change seems hit-and-miss. It is not warranted, given that the psychological traits underlying schizophrenia are often not severely incapacitating, and in some measures reflect better-thannormal abilities. However, given that several of the abnormal 11 but see Patel et al (2006). 59 traits can be mimicked by NMDA antagonists, it is conceivable that pharmacological agents might be developed which could act in the opposite direction to mitigate these traits, as well as associated negative symptoms. An example of this is to use glycine or related amino acids in treatment of negative symptoms. This is based on the fact that the NMDA receptor has a glycine-modulatory site. Several clinical trials have shown glycine or related agents to be effective against negative symptoms (Coyle et al, 2002; Coyle and Tsai, 2004; review by Javitt, 2006). Nevertheless, it should be borne in mind that glutamate antagonists cannot totally reproduce the effects of a relative absence of rapidly-conducting corticocortical axons. For instance, in the literature on smoothpursuit eye movements, ketamine reproduces in normal subjects the reduced closed-loop gain, but not the prolonged latency in initiating eye movement responses. Much progress has already been achieved in the years in which this author has been studying the disorder; further improvement is to be expected. However, it is also clear that this progress can be attributed only in part to improved scientific understanding of the fundamental basis of the disorder. Changes in overall societal attitudes, including legal changes outlawing discrimination, and more optimistic views of what are considered realistic goals for human fulfilment have played a major part in progress so far. Nevertheless, the most important practical implication of the theory presented here may be that it offers a way of understanding schizophrenia. The great fear with which this illness is associated in the public mind arises not mainly from any objective reason, but because, subjectively, it is so difficult to understand. Indeed “incomprehensibility” has even been suggested as one of its defining features. Certainly some of its manifestations undermine fundamental assumptions most of us make about what a person is or can be. Only time will tell whether and to what extent the theory presented here is correct. It is virtually certain that future research will lead to substantial modifications of it. Nevertheless the author hopes that its central features will survive critical tests. If so, the theory may, over time, help to dispel the fear - borne of incomprehension - surrounding the subject of schizophrenia. Bitter polemics still continue about biological vs psychosocial causation of schizophrenia, and this hinders the development of effective modern services. The theory presented here, is mainly about brain mechanisms, understandably so since its author is a brain scientist. However, it should be clear that the author also accepts that psychosocial factors are important contributory causes. It is much easier to present simplistic formulations of schizophrenia leaning heavily to one or other side of this great divide, than to develop an even-handed perspective which shows in detail how the two sorts of contributory cause interact. If the main tenets of the theory presented here become accepted by those on both sides of this age-old divide, it may help to defuse the more strident and acrimonious manifestations of this debate, and allow mental health services to develop with more unity of purpose than has often been the case in the past. Conclusions: The Concept of Schizophrenia 60