Infinite Minds, A Philosophical Cosmology, John Leslie, Oxford University Press, 2001, ISBN 0-19-924892-3 Leslie’s new book supplies some bold answers to some big questions. The position he develops is an interesting one; although there is much that is speculative, the speculation is not groundless, but is invariably supported by argument, even if not all of the arguments are as polished or as precise as one might like. Leslie is well aware that his cosmology will strike many contemporary readers as bizarre, but this does not mean that it is wrong, or should be ignored. Even if it is wrong, it might well be wrong for interesting reasons, and in locating these reasons, we will be learning something about what the ultimate options might be. 1. Axiarchism For some, ‘Why is there anything rather than nothing?’ is the ultimate philosophical question, and they may be right. But there is a second question, scarcely less deep and difficult: ‘Why is reality the way it is?’ A completed physics might conceivably supply an answer to the ‘Why this?’ question, for it is not inconceivable that the laws of nature might be such as to necessitate the existence of the physical reality the laws themselves govern – if only in the sense that the laws cannot become actual independently of the reality to which they apply. But even if such laws did exist, the ‘Why anything?’ question would remain unanswered. Why has this possibility been actualized? Why has any possibility been actualized? Some say: ‘There is no answer; it is just a brute fact that a universe like this one exists.’ For those unwilling to swallow an unexplained datum of this magnitude, one option is to follow Lewis, and hold that all possible worlds have the same status, all are equally real. But although this manoeuvre neatly sidesteps the problem of explaining why only one of the infinitely numerous possible universes is actual, many feel the original ‘Why Anything?” problem remains unsolved; indeed, aren’t we now being asked to accept a far larger and more complex brute fact? Traditional theism provides another solution: God exists, and God chose to create this (rather than any other) universe. But as is well known, this option is also problematic, even if we assume God exists. Why did God create this universe (which, as is plain, is not without its flaws)? Why does God himself exist? Is the notion of a being that is responsible for its own existence, or which could not fail but to exist, really intelligible? There is at least one further option, vigorously championed by Leslie in his Value and Existence (1979), and now again in Infinite Minds, an option which can be traced back as far as Plato: perhaps the universe exists because it is ethically required to exist. On this view – ‘Extreme Axiarchism’ [EA] – of all the possible ways the universe could be, one is better than the rest; this possible universe actually exists, and it exists precisely because it is the best: truths about value are ‘creatively effective’. EA’s solution to the ‘Why Anything?’ problem can initially strike one as strange. If goodness is creatively effective, there is precious little evidence of this in day to day life; the good things that do happen (and we could do with there being more of them) usually seem to have more mundane explanations: the decisions people take, conjunctions of circumstance and physical laws. But even if the creative power of the good is never discernible in our surroundings (and some might question this), it does not mean that the universe as a whole might not owe its existence to this creative power. Moreover, as ultimate explanations go, and as Leslie takes pains to point out, EA has definite advantages. It is simpler than traditional theism, since a single creative principle explains both why there is something rather than nothing, and why this something takes the form it does. And if God does exists, the Axiarchist can explain why: it is simply because a universe which includes God has greater value than one which does not. Leslie does not claim that EA is true. He defends the weaker claim that EA might be true, that it is a conceptually coherent ultimate explanation. And he may well be right. Certainly – as Leslie (repeatedly) points out – there are influential philosophers, Mackie and Parfit amongst them, who think that he is. But for all its advantages, I cannot see that EA entirely avoids the problem of the unexplained brute fact, for one such is still being posited, namely the existence of creatively effective objective value. This brute fact may have the unusual property of being able to explain everything else, but it is a brute fact nonetheless. Indeed, it may well be that there are several ultimate and unexplained posits involved, not one. Leslie notes that the ‘concepts of ethically required existence and of existence required with causal or creative success truly are two concepts, not one. So far as mere concepts are concerned, absolutely any ethical requirement might fail to be fulfilled.’ (161) So on the one hand, certain possibilities have the property of being ethically required to exist, and on the other, certain possibilities possess the property of self-actualization (they are such that they come into being). It so happens that all the self-actualizing possibilities are ethically required. But why? Leslie argues that this is no coincidence. He maintains that it is a non-logical, non-analytic, but nonetheless necessary truth that ethical needs possess creative power. Even if we grant that such necessities exist, isn’t the existence of this particular necessity, as opposed to the conceivable alternatives, something which needs explaining? If so, then given that no explanation is forthcoming, we have yet another unexplained posit. Axiarchism may be a coherent doctrine, but it is not as simple and straightforward as it initially seems. 2. Cosmology If EA were true, what would the universe be like? Evidently, it would be better than any other possible universe. But can we go further? From the hypothesis that our universe is the best possible, can we deduce anything of interest about its nature? Leslie is of the opinion that we probably can, and Infinite Minds is largely devoted to the metaphysical implications of EA. While a good many of the ideas Leslie discusses were first introduced in Value and Existence, they did not feature prominently; in the newer work they are developed in considerably more detail. All the essentials of Leslie’s cosmology are determined by a few basic assumptions, none of which is absurd or implausible. Let us suppose, as many do, that only states of consciousness possesses intrinsic value. Are all forms of consciousness of equal intrinsic value? This seems unlikely. Leslie argues that only unified states of consciousness can possess intrinsic value, and that richer, more complex, forms of consciousness have greater value than simpler forms (given certain provisos about their contents). From this it follows that a maximally unified and maximally complex conscious mind will have greater intrinsic value than anything else. Are there any limits on how rich and complex a mind can be? Leslie thinks not: a maximally complex mind will be infinitely complex. Consequently, if EA is true, an infinite mind will not merely be possible, it will actually exist. Since this infinite mind is also maximally good, Leslie sees no objection to regarding it as God-like, or divine, and generally refers to it as ‘the divine mind’. For this conclusion to be believable, there are questions which require plausible answers. What is the relationship between the divine mind and the world we are familiar with from everyday life? If the actual universe is the best possible universe, why is it so easy to imagine universes which seem clearly to be better than the actual universe, universes which contain more beauty and less pointless suffering than our own? Leslie’s solution to the relationship question is a Spinoza-style pantheism. The divine mind does not contemplate anything external to it, everything it thinks about is realized (i.e. becomes actual) in it. Your consciousness and mine exist as tiny regions within the infinitely rich divine consciousness. As for non-conscious physical things, such as tables or bricks, Leslie suggests they exist merely as ‘structures’ within the divine mind, a position which is entirely compatible with what science tells us about the physical world, since the latter provides us only with causal-structural knowledge (it is silent about the intrinsic qualitative nature of material things). Quite what these structures are, however, is left unclear. Are they blue-print like images, or are they more akin to fully detailed conceptualizations? On occasion Leslie also displays sympathies with those panpsychists who hold that even the simplest material things possess a rudimentary form of consciousness. If this view is correct, material things would have the same status within the divine mind as ourselves (or at least, our streams of consciousness). While pantheism certainly provides the simplest answer to the relationship question, it promises to make the problem of evil harder to solve. If there are no limits to what the divine mind knows, and if a state of affairs becomes real simply by being entertained by the divine mind, won’t all possible states of affairs be actualized? Some of the resulting universes will be vastly superior to this one, but others will be vastly inferior. We are no longer faced merely with the problem of explaining why this universe is as bad as it is, we are faced with the likelihood of an infinite number of universes existing which are all far worse than this one. How can this depressing prospect be reconciled with EA? Leslie solves both problems with a single move. A divine mind does indeed, he suggests, contemplate an infinite number of possible universes, all of which are thereby actualized, but it does not contemplate all possible universes, it contemplates only those that are ‘worth thinking about’. The universes that are worth thinking about contain conscious lives that are generally (if not always or in every individual case) worth living, even if these lives contain a mixture of the good, bad and the indifferent – as is the case in our world. Those possible universes where most lives are not worth living are not worth contemplating, and so are not actualized. While there is no denying that this is an appealingly simple solution to the problem of evil, the notion that a divine mind might be selective in what it knows or contemplates may well seem dubious. How is it possible to decide not to think certain thoughts without first being aware of the content of these thoughts? How could a divine mind avoid actualizing those worlds it decides are not worth thinking about? But this objection draws its force from a conception of the divine mind as an intelligent agent whose cognitive processes are similar to our own. Leslie’s divine mind is more akin to a single timeless state of consciousness, one that is forced into existence by virtue of its supreme value. The idea that an experiential complex of this kind could include some, but not all, possible experiences is by no means absurd. Leslie extends his solution to the problem of evil to the problem of induction. He suggests that among the worlds that are not worth thinking about are those where the laws of nature suddenly vary (or vanish) after long periods of stability. I am not so sure. Can we be confident that worlds with variable laws are invariably not worth living in? If there were occasional (or even frequent) exceptions to the laws in our universe, would the consequences on conscious beings necessarily be catastrophic? Evidence has recently emerged that the ‘fine tuning constant’ may well have had a different value in the distant past; if it did, the speed of light or the charge on electrons must also have been different – our universe might in fact have variable laws of nature. Leslie also speculates that the divine mind might well find it worth considering how mental lives might continue to unfold after our bodily deaths: ‘cutting short a happy life is surely somewhat ugly at the very least’ (128). If so, an afterlife is something we can reasonably hope for, we may even have a right to one – the divine mind will be under something akin to a duty to sustain us in being. Our bodies will die, but our streams of consciousness will continue on in a dimension ‘orthogonal’ to that of ordinary spacetime, where we might join with other survivors, ‘sharing with them in an adventure of discovering even more about the marvels of divine knowledge’ (129). And the same might apply to other, more primitive animals, such as lions or frogs, provided they sometimes have lives worth living. The prospect of ‘continuing on’ in the fashion Leslie describes is not an unwelcome one, but again, I have my doubts. Does death always involve the cutting short of a life worth living? Is it not possible to live in such a way that death, when it comes, constitutes a not unwelcome completion to a life well-rounded and well-lived? In any event, there is something else that Leslie has not taken into account. In a manyuniverse model such as his own, an afterlife (of a kind) is inevitable, without the need for the sort of ‘extensions’ he hopes we may have. For do not forget, in a cosmos of this sort there is a very real sense in which each one of us is a multitude. For we each have counterparts in an infinite number of other universes; the lives of our counterparts are indistinguishable from our own for a while, and then diverge. So if you suffer the misfortune of being run over by a bus tomorrow, you have an infinite number of counterparts who will not take the fatal step, who will go on living their lives, in their increasingly different ways, for years to come. Some of these counterparts will live forever, for in their universes – where the laws of nature may be subtly different from our own – the secret of eternal life is discovered during their lifetimes. These counterparts of yours will lead every kind of life you could wish for; you may not live to visit the stars, but you have counterparts who do. ‘But these counterparts would not be me!’, you might object. But in the context of Leslie’s system, this objection has less than its usual force. You are not an individual substance, but merely a pattern of experience within a divine mind, a pattern whose many variants are exhaustively explored elsewhere in the same mind. The relationship between the experiences in your mental life and those in the lives of your counterparts is of a particularly intimate kind: they all belong to the same mental subject. Although Leslie generally writes of ‘the divine mind’, this is merely to keep things simple. He believes that if one divine mind exists solely because it should, it is likely that more than one exists; indeed he argues that it is more probable than not that an infinite number of divine minds exists. Of course, as every sweet-eating child learns, more of a good thing isn’t always better. But since minds do not compete for the same space, there is no limit to the number that can co-exist, even if each is infinitely rich and complex. It could even be that each of these minds is exactly similar. This would not be possible if indiscernibles were identical, but Leslie argues that there is no reason to suppose this need be the case. There is more to Leslie’s cosmology than I can usefully mention here. The Btheory of view of time is defended in chapter 3, and a version of compatibilism is explored in chapter 4, along with much else. I turn instead to examine, in some detail, an issue which is central to the system as a whole, and upon which all else hangs. 3. Unity Leslie’s second chapter, ‘Minds Human, Artificial and Divine’ is by far the longest in the book. The arguments here are complex, convoluted, at times exasperating, and range over topics as diverse as the nature and unity of consciousness (divine and human), machine mentality, Bradley on relations, quantum entanglement and quantum computation. I will focus on the main strand: the character of experiential unity, and the relationship between our minds and the divine mind of which they are a part. Like everything else in our universe, your consciousness and mine are constituent parts of a single divine mind. Despite its infinite complexity a divine mind is also unified: ‘divine thoughts form a whole supremely worth experiencing’ (43). As is obvious, there is tension here. If your experiences and mine are experienced together in a single conscious mind, why is it that our consciousnesses seem so completely separate? As William James put the point, ‘no thought ever comes into direct sight of a thought in another personal consciousness.’ To address this question at all we need to know more about the kind of unity to be found in an individual consciousness, and the kind of unity to be found in divine minds. Consider first the unity of our own consciousness at a given time. Our typical states of consciousness consist of a number of different experiences, but these experiences are not mere collections, they occur together in a distinctive way: they are experienced together, they are co-conscious, as one might say. It may be impossible to describe this mode of unity in an informative manner, but we nonetheless know what it is like for a visual experience to be co-conscious with an auditory experience, or for distinct visual experiences to be co-conscious with one another (e.g. seeing several points of light at once against a dark backdrop). Every part of a typical state of consciousness is, it seems, co-conscious with every other part. Or as Leslie puts it: ‘introspection indicates that conscious experiences can be wholes of a dramatically unified kind, wholes whose wholeness is grasped by the wholes themselves’ (79). Call this distinctive and dramatic experiential togetherness ‘phenomenal unity’. Leslie devotes a good deal of attention to the topic, and most of what he says is interesting and plausible. He notes that phenomenal unity extends a short way over time, which explains ‘why states of awareness seem to cover brief temporal intervals, as when musical notes played in swift succession appear to be experienced together’ (81). He even ventures the claim that phenomenal unity might ‘explain’ the qualitative character of experiences (72-6), which may be true, at least in the sense that there couldn’t be anything that it is like to have an experience of a certain expanse of colour (say), unless the constituent parts of the expanse are mutually co-conscious. But on one point Leslie does goes astray. We are told that phenomenally unified experiences are ‘not separate in their being’, they have ‘identities that are partially fused’. Although the latter notion is not clearly explained (or defended), it is not implausible to suppose that co-conscious experiences are holistically related, in such a way that the constituent parts of phenomenally unified wholes could not exist in different experiential configurations. For one could reasonably hold that when two experiences are co-conscious they are so intimately linked that a complete description of the phenomenal character of either would include a description of the phenomenal character of the other. If so, then given certain other plausible assumptions (e.g. that the identity of an experience depends upon its complete phenomenal character, its time of occurrence, and its subject), the conclusion swiftly follows that experiences in phenomenally unified wholes could not exist on their own, or in wholes of a different overall character. But note, this sort of inter-experiential interdependence, rooted as it is in inter-experiential relations, does not posit (or require) any interdependence or interpenetration at the level of intrinsic (or local) phenomenal character. This is just as well, for there is no reason to think that the intrinsic or local character of an experience is (typically) affected by the other experiences with which it is co-conscious. When I look at the tree outside my window, the purely visual aspects of this experience are generally the same irrespective of whether they are co-conscious with the sound of a birdcall, or the sound of a passing car, or no sound at all. If there is a sense in which the identity of the visual tree-experience depends upon the other experiences with which it is co-conscious, there is also a sense in which it is not. Now, on various occasions Leslie argues that even if a classical computer could reproduce the kind of information processing that goes on in our brains, such a computer would never be conscious, since its physical constituents, scattered as they are through space, clearly do not possess the special kind of unity that our experiences possess. However, he suggests that quantum computers might be different, on the grounds that when particles enter certain quantum states (e.g. Bose-Einstein condensates) they almost entirely lose their individualities, they cease to be separate entities. As a consequence, it may well be that quantum states of this kind have the properties needed for a physical correlate of phenomenally unified states. But in the light of what has just been said, this seems quite wrong. While there is a sense in which experiences in phenomenal wholes are interdependent, such experiences clearly do not lose their individuality in the manner of the particles entering the Bose-Einstein condensates. In an audio-visual experience, the auditory and visual elements remain clearly distinct, rather than being submerged into some entirely new, non-auditory and non-visual, experience. But let us return to the main theme. What is the relationship between our states of consciousness and the divine mind? Are the experiences which compose the divine consciousness unified in the same way as our experiences? This is very hard to believe. Could my current state of consciousness have the character it actually has if all of its constituent experiences were fully co-conscious not only with your experiences, but with each and every other experience in the divine mind? Trying to argue that this is possible would be an intriguing exercise, but Leslie makes no such attempt, he willingly accepts that our states of consciousness have a higher degree of unity than the divine mind itself, taken as a whole: ‘Inside any greater unity possessed by our universe in its entirety there are complex systems whose elements are still more thoroughly unified: unified in ways fundamental to any intrinsically worthwhile experiences of ours. Knowledge of our own conscious states shows us that they are instances of such systems …’ (70) While this concession does seem plausible, it leaves us with a problem: in what way are the experiences in a divine mind unified? One possibility, which Leslie mentions but does not explore in detail, is overlapping chains of co-consciousness. It seems natural to think that synchronic coconsciousness is a transitive relation, that if a first experience is co-conscious with a second, and the second is co-conscious with a third, then the first and the third experiences will also be co-conscious. But perhaps – as Michael Lockwood has argued – co-consciousness is not transitive. If so, and as Leslie points out, then experiences A-BC-D could form a unified whole, as could experiences C-D-E-F, with these two wholes partially overlapping in the C-D region. However, even if experiential structures of this sort are possible, which is by no means clear, it is hard to see how this mechanism could unify all the experiences in a divine mind. What are the experiential intermediaries linking your current experiences to mine? No plausible candidates spring to mind. There is a further option, one which Leslie does not mention. If the co-consciousness relation were non-symmetrical, it would be possible for a collection of experiences A-B-C (e.g. your current state of consciousness) to be co-conscious with experiences D-E-F (e.g. other parts of the divine consciousness) without any of the latter being co-conscious with any of the former. But although this option meets Leslie’s needs, it is also highly implausible. Since experiences related by co-consciousness are experienced together – in effect, they are fused into a single state of consciousness – how could co-consciousness fail to be symmetrical? Co-consciousness, in this guise at least, is necessarily symmetrical. In fact, Leslie carefully avoids committing himself to the claim that a divine consciousness is a phenomenally unified whole. What he does claim is that divine minds are ‘unified in their existence’. The parts or properties of a thing are unified in their existence if (like the length and redness of a brick) they are incapable of existing on their own; parts of this sort are ‘merely abstract’, in the sense that they are merely aspects of a more fundamental reality, one which is capable of independent existence. If a divine consciousness is unified in its existence, it is undeniably a single entity. But a question remains to be answered: what is it, precisely, which binds the constituents of a divine consciousness together? Although Leslie supplies an answer, he spends little time developing it. The proposed solution is a form of telepathic linkage: ‘even a mind or mental region which had never been, say, fearful, could know what fear was like ‘as if telepathically’, its knowledge then coming very close to being knowledge of exactly what it’s like to feel fear … So I have little difficulty with the idea of a divine overview of our entire universe – a state of extraordinarily detailed knowledge appreciated as a single whole’ (105). Since we are told nothing more about this mode of ‘as-if telepathic’ awareness, it is difficult to evaluate Leslie’s proposal. Nonetheless, I foresee problems and complications. Leslie does not say as much, but it seems fair to assume that the telepathically linked experiences are existentially unified in virtue of the fact that they are so linked. It is not implausible to suppose this would be the case. After all, we can make sense of the distinction between genuine and hallucinatory telepathic experiences; the former, but not the latter, provide the telepath with direct knowledge of another subject’s experience, and so could not exist in the absence of the ‘target’ experience. So far so good. But a problem remains. Even if we assume that telepathic links of the required sort do exist, it is by no means clear that collections of experiences linked in this way have the sort of unity that is required for them to belong to the same mind. Telepathy, as usually construed, is a relationship between distinct minds. Consequently, since it seems the divine overview is a complex experience in its own right, wouldn’t it constitute a distinct conscious mind in its own right? This problem may not be insoluble. Perhaps it would suffice to construe the telepathic link along the lines of a direct realist view of ordinary perception (though Leslie elsewhere rejects the pure structureless apprehending that this view seems to require, cf. 13-14); perhaps other options are available. In any event, let us suppose that a divine overview of all our individual consciousnesses does exist, as Leslie supposes. Why stop here? Might there not be less encompassing overviews, taking in rather less than the complete picture? Surely there would be, since these lesser overviews would still be experiences worth having, and so – given EA – experiences that would exist. There may well be an infinite number of these less encompassing overviews. By the same reasoning, perhaps too there would be overviews of the overviews – why not? – and these too might be infinite in number. But it does not end here. Leslie, it will be recalled, believes it likely that there would be an infinite number of divine minds, not just one. If so, then surely – given his own assumptions about the intrinsic value of unified experiences – there would be an overview of this multiplicity: an overview of an infinite number of infinitely complex minds. Perhaps it doesn’t end here. Just as there could be lesser overviews of a single divine mind, there could be less encompassing overviews of the multiplicity of minds. And, as before, there might also be overviews of these overviews – the process might be iterated indefinitely. Nor need it end here. What is to prevent entire complexes, of the sort just outlined, being instantiated more than once? But if multiple complexes exist, won’t there also exist overviews of these complexes? I will not go further, for the point is already clear: Leslie’s cosmos may be somewhat more complex than he himself appreciates. One last point. As already noted, although Leslie does not hold that the experiences within a divine mind must be phenomenally unified, he does maintain that they must be unified in their existence. He also claims that any state of mind that is intrinsically worth experiencing must be unified in its existence. The latter claim is, I suspect, problematic; so much so that I doubt whether his cosmology can survive the blow, at least in its original form. Our states of consciousness are unified in their existence – or so Leslie alleges, and he may well be right. But in addition, our states of consciousness also possess a distinctive form of unity – phenomenal unity – a form of unity that is not possessed by other types of existentially unified whole. The colour and length of a brick may be existentially unified, but they are not phenomenally unified. Given this, we can ask: which mode of unity is relevant to the intrinsic value that our states of consciousness possess? The answer, surely, is phenomenal unity. As Leslie himself argues, it is phenomenal unity which is responsible for experiences having the character they do. The fact that the constituent parts of an experiential whole could not exist in isolation is, in itself, irrelevant to the value of that experience. Experiential parts are existentially unified because they are phenomenally unified, and it is the latter mode of unity which, along with their intrinsic qualitative character, provides them with any value they might have. If so, and if a divine mind forms a whole that is ‘supremely worth experiencing’, then it is hard to see how the experiences which jointly constitute a divine mind could fail to be phenomenally unified. Mere unity in existence would not suffice, for this mode of unity, in itself, is irrelevant to the value of an experience. And since it is difficult to see how distinct ‘personal consciousnesses’, such as yours and mine, can be phenomenally unified with one another, it may well be that divine minds, in the form Leslie envisages, simply could not exist in the framework of EA. Perhaps the cosmos consists of multitudes of phenomenally unified consciousnesses of the sort we possess, some simpler, some far more complex. Axiarchism may lead us back to Leibniz, rather than Spinoza. Barry Dainton Department of Philosophy The University of Liverpool