The Origins of The Objection In this exercise in intellectual history I trace the development of the objection to utilitarianism (or consequentialism) that it would sometimes favor deliberately punishing an innocent person. I will call this The Objection, and I describe its origins. Utilitarianism is the theory that asserts that the morally right action is the one that produces the most happiness. Consequentialism is the generic theory that asserts that the morally right action is the one that produces the most good. Utilitarianism is thus a form of consequentialism, but there are others. The most well-known other forms of consequentialism were developed after most of our story is over, so we can work on the assumption that The Objection would have been directed specifically at utilitarianism. It is now a familiar criticism to argue that utilitarianism has the logical consequence that it would sometimes be morally right to deliberately punish an innocent person. In certain circumstances, the argument goes, the good results of punishment that utilitarianism seeks, especially the deterrence of intending criminals, might be achieved by deliberately punishing an innocent person. The possibility of such a case is commonly held to constitute a counterexample to this type of moral theory. In fact, it is commonly thought that this is the most serious counterexample it faces. It strikes many of us as outrageous to assert that legal officials could be doing the morally right thing in framing and then punishing an innocent person. In thinking about the cogency of this criticism I became interested in discovering the origin of it. It was described by John Rawls in 1955 as a “traditional” and 1 “longstanding” objection, suggesting that it dates back to, say, the nineteenth century.1 Some more recent historians have also suggested some such a dating for it. I here recount what I have been able to learn about this issue: The Objection was actually first clearly stated in 1929. I The Early Utilitarians In his magisterial work on Sidgwick’s moral philosophy and its intellectual antecedents, J. B. Schneewind writes: Utilitarianism first became widely known in England through the work of William Paley. Within a few years of the publication of his theological version of the doctrine in 1785, there appeared two secular versions, one by Jeremy Bentham in 1789, the other by William Godwin in 1793. Bentham’s book was almost completely ignored for decades.2 Let us begin by looking at these three writers. Since they were all concerned to defend some form of utilitarianism, we need to see if they exhibit any sense of needing to respond to The Objection. This would be some evidence for the conclusion that an opponent had offered it, or that they considered it a significant difficulty. A few scholars, who have also touched on the history of The Objection, have unearthed evidence suggesting that it was ‘in the air’ early on in the history of utilitarianism. I will try to show otherwise. John Rawls, “Two Concepts of Rules.” The Philosophical Review 64 (1955), pp. 3-32, at 3, 4, and 18. 2 J. B. Schneewind, Sidgwick’s Ethics and Victorian Moral Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), p. 122. 1 2 I can only mention, and not explore, the radically different substantive conclusions about the use of punishment that these three reach. Paley in effect defends the ‘bloody code’ of contemporary English law, which made many property crimes subject to the death penalty. (However, he also defends the use of the royal prerogative of mercy, which he thought meant that only 1 in 10 death sentences were actually carried out.)3 Godwin lies at the opposite extreme: while he admits that in theory state punishment could benefit society, he defends anarchism on the grounds that in fact it never does do this.4 Bentham lies somewhere in between, though it is clear that he is deeply critical of contemporary English practice, sometimes because of its leniency and sometimes because of its severity. So, let us focus on this question: were any of these early utilitarians concerned about the possibility that using punishment to increase human happiness might justify deliberately punishing an innocent person? Paley. At the end of the chapter on punishment in The Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy Paley does briefly consider an issue about the treatment of the innocent. He mentions and condemns two “popular maxims”. Use of these evidentiary maxims leads, he believes, to “injudicious acquittals”.5 The second maxim is of particular interest, since it explicitly mentions guilt and innocence. It is the principle “that it is 3 Paley, Principles, op. cit., p. 532. He grants that punishment by private individuals intended only to restrain individuals who pose a threat to society is permissible in emergencies. William Godwin, Enquiry Concerning Political Justice and Its Influence on Morals and Happiness, 3rd Edition, edited by F.E. L. Priestley (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1946), vol. II, pp. 379; 384; 393. (Originally published, 1798) 5 Ibid., p.551. 4 3 better that ten guilty persons escape than that one innocent man should suffer.”6 Paley disagrees. He concludes the chapter thus: The security of civil life…is protected chiefly by the dread of punishment. The misfortunes of an individual, for such may the sufferings, or even the death of an innocent person be called, when they are occasioned by no evil intention, cannot be placed in competition with this object. I do not contend that the life or safety of the meanest subject ought, in any case, to be knowingly sacrificed. No principle of judicature, no end of punishment can ever require that. But when certain rules of adjudication must be pursued, when certain degrees of credibility must be accepted, in order to reach the crimes with which the public are interested; courts of justice should not be deterred from the application of these rules, by every suspicion of danger, or by the mere possibility of confounding the innocent with the guilty. They ought rather to reflect, that he, who falls by a mistaken sentence, may be considered as falling for his country; whilst he suffers under the operation of these rules, by the general effect and tendency of which, the welfare of the community is maintained and upheld.7 This is a chilling and evasive passage.8 But it is clear that Paley is concerned with the burden of proof governing criminal trials. He accepts that the level of certainty required for conviction by utilitarianism will mean that innocent people are occasionally and unwittingly punished. But he dismisses as unworthy of discussion the idea that utilitarianism could favor knowingly punishing an innocent person. So it seems that he had no familiarity with The Objection. Bentham. Bentham presents special problems for me, because I have not examined all of his voluminous writings. What is more, it seems that a large number of his writings are, some 180 years after his death, still unpublished. The website of the Bentham Project at University College London states that 25 of a projected 70 volumes 6 Ibid., 552. Ibid., pp. 552-3. 8 The evasion occurs in Paley’s use of the phrase “falling for his country”, which suggests the honor accorded to military men. But innocent people who are unwittingly executed receive no honors. In Paley’s day their bodies could end up on gibbets. 7 4 of Bentham’s Collected Works have been published in this series as of December 2009.9 (However, some of the volumes will contain previously-published works.) So I will have to present a very tentative case for this conclusion: Bentham was not aware of The Objection, either. An Introduction to the Principle of Morals and Legislation (1789) is often—but, as we have seen, erroneously—thought of as containing the first systematic presentation of a utilitarian approach to punishment.10 I can state on my own authority that the three chapters (13-15) therein that are devoted specifically to the topic of punishment nowhere mention as a possible problem that the theory might favor punishing an innocent person. Does The Objection appear anywhere in the rest of his works? Given the vastness of this terrain we might despair of ever establishing the truth of the negative existential statement that it does not. I can, however, repeat what Frederick Rosen—who was editor of the Bentham Project from 1983-1994—concludes after investigating the matter: Bentham does not mention this difficulty anywhere else in his writings. Rosen writes: “…that the innocent should be punished is never seriously considered [by Bentham].”11 Godwin. The treatment of punishment in Book VII of The Enquiry Concerning Political Justice opens with some bold metaphysical assertions, which Godwin had defended earlier on. Human actions are the product of necessary causes; “the assassin 9 http://www.ucl.ac.uk/Bentham-Project/Publications/public.htm For a useful sketch of the background of Bentham’s views on punishment, and his debts in particular to Montesquieu and Beccaria see Frederick Rosen, “Utilitarianism and the Reform of the Criminal Law” in The Cambridge History of Eighteenth-Century Political Thought, ed. Mark Goldie and Robert Wokler (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), pp. 547-72, esp. 547-63. Frederick Rosen, “Utilitarianism and the Punishment of the Innocent: The Origins of a False Doctrine.” Utilitas 9 (1997), pp. 23-37, is devoted in part to tracing the origins of The Objection. I am indebted to him at many points, but we also differ in some important ways, as I will explain. 11 Rosen, “Punishment of the Innocent,” op. cit., p. 25. 10 5 cannot help the murder he commits, any more than the dagger [he uses].”12 Hence, “in the refined and absolute sense in which that term has frequently been employed, there is no such thing as desert.”13 Godwin believes that those, like him, who accept “the doctrine of necessity”, as well as those who have not even considered it, will agree “that the only measure of equity is utility, and whatever is not attended with any beneficial purpose, is not just.”14 It is in this preliminary material that Schneewind finds and quotes this startling passage: An innocent man is the proper subject of punishment, if it tend to good. A guilty man is the proper subject of it under no other point of view. To punish him, upon any hypothesis, for what is past and irrecoverable, and for the consideration of that only, must be ranked among the most pernicious exhibitions of an untutored barbarism.15 This sounds as if Godwin was not only aware of the suggestion that utilitarianism could favor deliberately punishing an innocent person, but that he is “biting the bullet” and accepting this consequence of his theory. If we read him carefully, though, we can see that this is not what he is saying. The passage quoted by Schneewind continues as follows: Every man upon whom [such] discipline is employed, is to be considered as to the purpose of this discipline as innocent. The only sense of the word punishment that can be supposed to be compatible with the principles of the present work, is that of pain inflicted on a person convicted of past injurious action, for the purpose of preventing future mischief.16 12 Godwin, Enquiry, op. cit., vol. II, p. 324. Ibid., p. 327. 14 Ibid., p. 324. 15 Ibid., p. 327. Cp. Schneewind, op. cit., p. 138. 16 Godwin, Enquiry, op. cit., vol. II, p. 327. Cp. p. 329. 13 6 Godwin’s thinking here might be put as follows. Insofar as punishment is being inflicted on someone because she has done something wrong, it is barbaric and wrong. The person is innocent as far as such a ‘discipline’ is concerned. But, if punishing someone will prevent ‘future mischief’, it is morally acceptable. (It must be added: Godwin believes that state punishment never does prevent mischief effectively, so he is opposed altogether to its use.) However, Godwin’s phrase “convicted of past injurious action” indicates clearly that he is not thinking of imposing a utilitarian punishment on someone who has not performed an “injurious action”. Still, he wants to say, the punishment of such a person is being imposed on an ‘innocent’ because she does not deserve to be punished in “the refined and absolute sense” that believers in free will accept. Godwin’s provocative language is not a response to The Objection, but a pointed way to reject notions of free will and moral desert. II From Kant to Bradley I propose now to look at three later figures who are important in the history of moral and political philosophy over the succeeding century. Two are well-known critics of the utilitarian approach to punishment (or something close to it). One is a well-known utilitarian who is famous for his fair-minded treatment of its critics. These seem to me to be the best places to continue our search for the origin of The Objection. Kant. It is natural for us to suppose that Kant’s discussion of punishment in the first part of The Metaphysics of Morals (1797) is the source of The Objection to “the 7 serpent-windings of utilitarianism,” to quote an old translation of it.17 But closer examination of Kant’s text reveals our error. It is clear, incidentally, that the object of Kant’s criticism is Beccaria and his only partly utilitarian theory—and not Godwin, Paley or Bentham—because he later mentions Beccaria.18 Kant does indeed object to utilitarian thinking about the justification of punishment. In a famous passage he writes the following. (I have numbered the sentences.) (1) Punishment by a court…can never be inflicted merely as a means to promote some other good for the criminal himself or for civil society. (2) It must always be inflicted upon him only because he has committed a crime. (3) For a man can never be treated merely as a means to the purposes of another or be put among the objects of rights to things: His innate personality protects him from this, even though he can be condemned to lose his civil personality. (4) He must previously have been found punishable before any thought can be given to drawing from his punishment something of use for himself or his fellow citizens.19 This passage cannot be understood as presenting The Objection. It actually seems to be making two separate points, neither of which constitutes The Objection. Consider the first three statements: they concern the punishment of the guilty as well as the innocent. Here Kant is most naturally understood to be asserting precisely what Godwin called “untutored barbarism”, that is, that the only acceptable reason to 17 Immanuel Kant, The Philosophy of Law, trans. W. Hastie (Edinburgh: T and T Clark, 1887), p. 195. I think Mary Gregor wished to avoid the suggestion that Kant had Bentham’s theory in mind, so she rendered the phrase as “the windings of eudaemonism.” Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 141. For a recent general interpretation of Kant’s theory of punishment see Arthur Ripstein, Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal and Political Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2009), ch. 10. 18 Ibid., p. 143. Cesare Beccaria, On Crimes and Punishments, trans. David Young (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1986). Published 1764. 19 Kant, Metaphysics, op. cit., pp. 140-1. Some emphases removed. 8 punish anyone is “because he has committed a crime”. Even the punishment of a guilty person cannot be imposed in order to achieve any “other” good for him or society. This means that the objection Kant is making in these statements applies even when someone guilty is punished for utilitarian reasons.20 So this is not The Objection. Kant’s fourth statement that a person must “have been found punishable” before any thought of producing good can be entertained seems to be making a separate point. On a weak reading of this statement, it only requires that a court carry out the requisite procedures before a sentence is handed down. But officials could do this and still deliberately punish someone who they know had not committed the offenses he is to be punished for. So on this reading of statement 4 Kant is still not making The Objection. A stronger reading of statement 4 would treat the phrase ‘found punishable’ as a sort of success term. This reading takes Kant to be in effect asserting that really being guilty of the offense charged against a person is a necessary condition of his being rightfully punished. But this means, yet again, that he is not presenting The Objection, since this claim means that any punishment of someone who is not guilty of the offense charged is wrongful, whether the action by the official is unwitting or deliberate. There is no objection being made specifically about deliberately punishing the innocent. Furthermore, the passages in Kant that present the clearest counterexamples to specific official actions sanctioned by consequentialism—as opposed to its reasons for 20 It is true, however, that construing Kant in this way creates some tension with his claim in the Groundwork that it is possible to act in accordance with duty but not from duty. If Kant’s claim is that utilitarian reasons are, as it were, the wrong reasons for punishing people—even guilty people—then the most he is entitled to conclude is that punishing the guilty for utilitarian reasons is acting in accordance with duty but not from duty. But that doesn’t seem to be quite what he is saying. See Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. H. J. Paton (New York: Harper and Row, 1964), p. 65. 9 carrying them out—tend to portray a very different sort of problem from the one that The Objection does. Kant asserts that a consequentialist theory sometimes favors not punishing the guilty, or at least not punishing them to the full extent that they deserve.21 What…should one think of the proposal to preserve the life of a criminal sentenced to death if he agrees to let dangerous experiments be made on him and is lucky enough to survive them, so that in this way physicians learn something new of benefit to the commonwealth? A court would reject with contempt such a proposal from a medical college, for justice ceases to be justice if it can be bought for any price whatsoever.22 And there is the more famous passage of the ‘desert island’: Even if a civil society were to be dissolved by the consent of all its members (e.g., if a people inhabiting an island decided to separate and disperse throughout the world), the last murderer remaining in prison would first have to be executed, so that each has done to him what his deeds deserve and blood guilt does not cling to the people for not having insisted on this punishment; for otherwise the people can be regarded as collaborators in this public violation of justice.23 The problem that Kant sees in utilitarianism is that it will sometimes favor deliberately not punishing the guilty; it is not that it will sometimes favor deliberately punishing the innocent. And the inviolability of justice that later writers invoke in condemning punishment of the innocent, Kant himself invokes in condemning “overly compassionate feelings” towards the guilty.24 Mill. The logical next place to look for The Objection is in the fifth chapter of Mill’s Utilitarianism. By the time of its publication in 1861 the term ‘utilitarianism’ had As Rosen notes, “Punishment of the Innocent,” op. cit., p. 25, n. 7. Kant, Metaphysics, op. cit., p. 141. The last, ringing phrase was likely a source for the comparably powerful opening of John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 3-4. 23 Kant, Metaphysics, op. cit., p. 142. 24 Ibid., p. 143. 21 22 10 come into use, and Mill was expounding and defending a doctrine which had been a subject of controversy for many years. Chapter 5, “On the Connection between Justice and Utility”, responds to what Mill describes as “the only real difficulty in the utilitarian theory of morals.”25 The difficulty is the fact that justice seems to be a distinct part of morality, separate from and more stringently binding on us than any consideration related to what is useful for society. (Something like this assertion is already apparent in Kant.) Mill approaches the issue in an abstract way, construing the problem as being partly conceptual and epistemic. In developing his reply he does discuss various kinds of justice, including the justice of punishment.26 If we examine this passage carefully we can see that Mill is not responding to The Objection. It is very plausible, given Mill’s fair-mindedness, to think that he would have responded to it, if someone had made it. The closest we come to The Objection, I think, is this: …there are some who say that it is unjust to punish anyone for the sake of example to others, that punishment is just only when intended for the good of the sufferer himself.27 But the claim reported by Mill does not articulate The Objection, since it applies to the punishment of the guilty, as well as to the innocent. And Mill treats it as simply one of a number of familiar, and plausible, but also conflicting, principles of justice that require an appeal to the principle of utility in order to be given their proper interpretation and weight. Thus, immediately after the quoted passage Mill mentions a competing principle: 25 John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism, ed. George Sher (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1979), p. 62. See also Schneewind, Sidgwick, op. cit., ch. 5, for a discussion of the criticisms of utilitarianism that Mill was responding to in this work. He does not mention The Objection. 26 Ibid., pp. 54-6. 27 Ibid., p. 54. 11 Others maintain the extreme reverse, contending that to punish persons who have attained years of discretion, for their own benefit is despotism and injustice, since, if the matter at issue is solely their own good, no one has a right to control their own judgment of it; but that they may be justly punished to prevent evil to others, this being the exercise of the legitimate right of self-defense.28 Thus, it is evident that Mill does not treat the claim in the first passage as presenting a specific counterexample to his whole theory. Bradley. We would think to search next within the most important philosophical tradition opposed to utilitarianism in the late 19th century, British Idealism. And Rosen, who was searching for the origin of The Objection, thinks that he finds it there, in F. H. Bradley’s Ethical Studies (1876).29 (On the other hand, Rosen remarks that Bradley’s criticism is not developed by the other British Idealists.30) I think that Rosen is mistaken in finding the objection in Bradley, as I will now try to show. This will take a little work, given the obscurities of his work. Bradley’s discussion of punishment, like Godwin’s, occurs in a treatment of a metaphysical issue, the one we would now call the compatibility of determinism and moral responsibility—or, as he puts it in the title of Essay 1, “The Vulgar Notion of 28 Ibid. There is a certain irony, given Bradley’s later paper on punishment, in supposing that he objected to utilitarianism because it might favor punishing the innocent. “Some Remarks on Punishment” (1894) looks with favor on some sort of Darwinian “social surgery” to rid the “social organism” of the “unfit”. F. H. Bradley, Collected Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1935), pp. 149-164, at 152-3. While he grants that people will always be likely to “confine the name of punishment to that surgery which is retributive” Bradley thinks “the absolute restriction of punishment to crime…is the very center of the position threatened by Darwin.” Darwinism, in other words, “tends…to break the connection between punishment and guilt”. Ibid., p. 153. So Bradley is prepared to assert that the “surgery” he vaguely describes, and tentatively endorses, will be a sort of punishment visited on masses of innocent people. 30 Rosen, “Punishing the Innocent,” op. cit., p. 26. 29 12 Responsibility in Connection with the Theories of Free-Will and Necessity.” So the kind of responsibility that Bradley is interested in is moral, and not specifically legal.31 Given that this is his topic, we would expect him to investigate ‘blame’ rather than ‘punishment’. However, Bradley is almost prepared to accept Mill’s statement that “[Moral] responsibility means punishment”: Bradley’s only modification is to say that moral responsibility means liability to punishment.32 So it is clear that both Mill and Bradley, despite their many differences, are using ‘punishment’ to include the sentences of the “moral tribunal” or the “court of conscience”, as well as the sentences of legallyconstituted courts.33 The first half of Bradley’s essay deals with the question of whether the common sense (or ‘vulgar’) notion of moral responsibility is compatible with certain metaphysical theories of freedom and necessity. He concludes that the vulgar notion of moral responsibility, especially as regards character, is not completely compatible with determinism (or ‘Necessity’). Then, as a sort of test of his conclusions, he returns to the issue of punishment in the legal sense. “Let us see, then, what punishment means first for the vulgar, and, next, for the believer in Necessity.”34 Three pages afterwards there occurs the first passage that Rosen highlights: 31 F. H. Bradley, Ethical Studies, second edition, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1962), pp. 1-3. 32 Ibid., p. 4; 26. Bradley does not give the source for Mill’s statement. It is Mill, Examination, op. cit., p. 454. In fact, most of Bradley’s criticisms of Mill are directed at the compatibilism Mill defends in this work, not at Mill’s claims in Utilitarianism. 33 Bradley, Ethical, op. cit., p. 3. Cp. How Mill speaks of the “reproaches” of a person’s conscience as being a sort of punishment. Utilitarianism, op. cit., p. 47. 34 Bradley, Ethical, op. cit., p. 26. 13 We must be careful here not to suffer ourselves to be led astray…we must not wander to a discussion of the right to punish. We need not ask how it is that, if 99 men are of opinion that it is more convenient, both for the 99 and the 100th, or for the 100th without the 99, or for the 99 without the 100th, that he, the 100th, should cease to exist—that therefore it is right for their opinion to be conveyed to him by the hanging of him, whatever may be his opinion on the subject. The discussion of this question we leave to utilitarian philosophers.35 Bradley’s antipathy to utilitarianism is clear in this passage, but I think it is also clear that he is not making The Objection. There is no claim (as we would expect) that the utilitarian will favor the opinion of the majority to the detriment of the 100th person. It seems, rather, that Bradley is disparaging its inclination to settle moral questions by a sort of counting, however exactly that comes out in a given case. (It is an incidental oddity that Bradley constructs the example using the opinions of the parties, rather than their happiness and unhappiness.) And, crucially, there is no mention (as we again would expect) that the 100th person is innocent. I think we can see that the second passage in Bradley that Rosen claims presents The Objection does not do so either.36 It is surprising that Rosen does not mention a third passage in Bradley, one that has historical importance. This passage immediately follows Bradley’s proposal to consider “what punishment means…for the vulgar.” Ibid., p. 29. Rosen does not quote the first two sentences. Rosen, “Punishing the Innocent,” op. cit., p. 26. 36 Bradley, Ethical, op. cit., p. 31, n. 2. The portion of this passage that Rosen quotes concerns the ‘correction’ of animals. Bradley claims that a utilitarian has no way to distinguish this from punishment, properly so-called. At this point he has returned to the definitional problem he is mainly concerned with, and is no longer addressing the substantive right to punish, which we saw he treats as a digression in the passage quoted above. So it is hard to see how this second passage could constitute a substantive counterexample to utilitarianism. And, in fact, it seems that given Bradley’s usage he should have objected to ‘necessitarian punishment’, rather than “utilitarian punishment”. 35 14 If there is any opinion to which the man of uncultivated morals is attached, it is the belief in the necessary connection of punishment and guilt. Punishment is punishment only where it is deserved. We pay the penalty, because we owe it, and for no other reason; and if punishment is inflicted for any other reason whatever than because it is merited by wrong, it is a gross immorality, a crying injustice, an abominable crime, and not what it pretends to be. We may have regard for whatever considerations we please—our own convenience, the good of society, the benefit of the offender; we are fools and worse, if we fail to do so. Having once the right to punish, we may modify the punishment according to the useful and the pleasant; but these are external to the matter, they can not give us a right to punish, and nothing can do that but criminal desert.37 Part of the historical importance of the passage rests on the fact that when, as we will see, W. D. Ross in 1929 does criticize utilitarianism on the grounds that it might favor deliberately punishing an innocent person he immediately goes on to say this: Plain men, and even perhaps most people who have reflected on moral questions, are likely to revolt against a theory which involves such consequences, and to exclaim that there is all the difference in the world between such action and the punishment of offenders against the law. They feel the injustice of such action by the state and are ready to say, in the words imputed to them by Mr. Bradley: “Punishment is punishment…”38 Etc. Ross seems to be suggesting that Bradley, or at least the plain man whose opinion Bradley is trying to articulate, revolts against the specific logical consequence of utilitarianism that Ross has just noted, viz., that it would sometimes favor deliberately punishing an innocent man. Another part of the historical importance of the passage from Bradley is backward-looking. It is a way for him to bring Kant and Hegel’s views on punishment to the attention of English-speaking philosophers. After describing the views of “the vulgar” 37 38 Ibid., pp. 26-7. The Right, op. cit., pp. 57. 15 in the quoted passage he goes on39 to translate into English, for the first time, it seems, a part of Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals, including his version of the four numbered sentences above. Bradley then asserts that the views on punishment of “unthinking people” are—unbeknownst to them and to English philosophers—the same as those of Kant and Hegel. So the similarities between Bradley’s assertions and Kant’s are not coincidental. This means that we can again see, if we look closely, that the second passage from Bradley that I have quoted at length does not present The Objection, as Ross suggested that it did. Just as Kant does, Bradley is making two different claims. First of all, he is asserting that punishment must be imposed for no other reason than “because it is merited by wrong”. This claim concerns the reasons for punishing both the guilty and the innocent. No special notice is being given to the punishment of the innocent. Second, Bradley asserts that only “criminal desert” gives society the right to punish someone. But this point condemns both unwitting and deliberate punishment of the innocent. To conclude: Bradley’s work does not present The Objection. And it seems that no one else had done so by 1876. 39 Bradley, Ethical, op. cit., p. 28. 16 III The Real Origins of the Objection The Objection seems to have been developed by philosophers working at Oxford in the 1920’s and 30’s. We can almost watch it taking shape. In a 1927 article A. C. Ewing merely poses a question: If the justification of punishment lies solely in its future consequences…why is it wrong to punish an innocent man?40 In 1928 E. F. Carritt offers an answer in the form of a brief counterexample. …if prevention of crime be the whole justification and nature of punishment, then the hanging of an innocent man who is universally believed guilty is as ideal an instance of punishment as can be conceived.41 In 1929 Ewing is likewise brief: It would indeed be difficult on purely deterrent principles to condemn the punishment of an innocent man if he were only popularly supposed to be guilty, for it would deter others as much as if he were really guilty.42 It is possible, given the brevity of their examples, to suppose that Ewing and Carritt still have in mind unwitting punishments of innocent people, as Paley in 1785 did. After all, even if legal authorities unwittingly punish an innocent person, this person might be A. C. Ewing, “Punishment as a Moral Agency: An Attempt to Reconcile the Retributive and Utilitarian View,” Mind 36 (1927), p. 295. 41 The Theory of Morals (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1928), p. 109. 42 The Morality of Punishment (London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner, 1929), p. 54. 40 17 widely thought to be guilty, and their punitive action might convince some people that ‘crime doesn’t pay’. But by the time we encounter this passage in Ross, also published in 1929, there can be no doubt that we have a description of the deliberate punishment of an innocent person: …a government which found some offense against the law prevalent, and in its inability to find the offenders punished innocent people on the strength of manufactured evidence, would still be able to justify its action on the same general principle [viz. utilitarianism]….43 H. W. B. Joseph repeats The Objection in 193144, and J. D. Mabbott in 1939 seems to.45 In a later book (1947) Carritt elaborates slightly on Ross’ scenario, in effect acknowledging a certain difficulty: …if some kind of very cruel crime becomes common, and none of the criminals can be caught, it might be highly expedient, as an example, to hang an innocent man, if a charge against him could be so framed that he were universally thought guilty; indeed this would only fail to be an ideal instance of utilitarian ‘punishment’ because the victim himself would not have been so likely as a real felon to commit such a crime in the future; in all other respects it would be perfectly deterrent and therefore felicific.46 W. D. Ross, “The Ethics of Punishment.” The Journal of Philosophical Studies (later, Philosophy) 4 (1929), p. 205. Philosophers are more likely to have encountered the passage in The Right and the Good (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1930), pp. 56-7. 44 Some Problems in Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1931), p. 93. 45 “Punishment.” Mind 48 (1939), pp.152-67, at 152. Mabbott refers only to Ewing’s Morality, op. cit., so it is not completely clear whether he has in mind the deliberate punishment of an innocent person. Mabbott states that the relevant difficulty is “wellknown.” 46 Ethical and Political Thinking (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1947), p. 65. It is this passage that Rawls quotes in “Two Concepts”, op. cit., before he begins to present a utilitarian reply to it. 43 18 These early versions of The Objection have largely been forgotten. Many philosophers recall the more vivid example modeled on American experience presented by H. J. McCloskey (an Australian) in 1957. Suppose that a sheriff were faced with the choice either of framing a Negro for a rape that had aroused hostility to the Negroes (a particular Negro generally being believed to be guilty but whom the sheriff knows not to be guilty)—and thus preventing serious anti-Negro riots which would probably lead to some loss of life and increased hatred of each other by whites and Negroes—or of hunting for the guilty person and thereby allowing the anti-Negro riots to occur, while doing the best he can to combat them. In such a case the sheriff, if he were an extreme [i.e., ‘act’] utilitarian, would appear to be committed to framing the Negro.47 McCloskey slightly modified the example in a 1965 article, in order to eliminate some of the sheriff’s uncertainty in the original version, and, I think, to remove worries about how the sheriff’s behavior could discredit the legal system. So he describes a utilitarian “visiting an area in which there was racial strife.” This utilitarian knows that some black man has raped a white woman, and that his false testimony about a particular black man will prevent riots and lynchings. McCloskey asserts that “he has, on utilitarian theory, an evident duty to bring about the punishment of an innocent man.”48 Of course, in this way of describing the case it is possible to suppose that the legal officials involved sincerely believe that the man whom the utilitarian accuses is guilty. Rawls’ description of The Objection in 1955 as a “traditional” problem for utilitarianism is incorrect. In fact, his attempt to formulate a utilitarian response to it was, I believe, the first of its kind. H. J. McCloskey, “An Examination of Restricted Utilitarianism.” The Philosophical Review 66 (1957), pp. 468-9. 48 H. J. McCloskey, “A Non-Utilitarian Approach to Punishment.” Inquiry 8 (1965), pp. 255-6. 47 19