1. What is a power of appointment? A power of appointment is a type of equitable mechanism which facilitates the management and allocation of property. It is a personal mandate given to a person who may in his discretion create or dispose of beneficial interest or proprietary rights in property which that person does not himself own, and this mandate may be exercised or not. 2. Distinguish between general, special and intermediate (or hybrid) powers of appointment. General powers of appointment are powers which the donee may exercise in favour of such person or persons as he please, including himself, as well as in favour of any purpose of purposes as he pleases. (in Re Dilke [1921] 1 Ch 34, the omission of the words “and purposes” after “such person or persons” was considered unimportant) As long as such a power exists, it will generally not be subject to any restrictions or limitation as to the mode or manner of its exercise. A special power is a power which can only be exercised in favour of certain specified persons, although the donee of the power may be included in the class of specified persons. An intermediate or hybrid power is a power to appoint to all persons except a named or specified person, persons, or class of persons. Which class of power is created by an instrument is a question of construction. A power may partake of several of the characteristics of each class, and may change its status and category as circumstances change. 3. Distinguish between a special power of appointment and a discretionary trust. While the duty of a trustee to exercise his discretion under a discretionary trust is mandatory, the donee of a power of appointment may choose not to exercise the power at all: a donee asks “shall I exercise the power?” and “in whose favour?”, while a trustee’s only question is “in whose favour?”. While both trustees and fiduciary donees may owe duties to the objects, such as to consider periodically whether or not to exercise the power, to consider the range of objects of the power, and to consider the appropriateness of individual appointments, (Re Hay’s Settlement Trusts [1982] 1 WLR 202 (ChD) ), the extent of the duties owed by a fiduciary donee is much less than that of a discretionary trustee. This is illustrated in the judgment of Lord Wilberforce in McPhail v. Doulton [1971] AC 424 (HL), where he stated that the court would “not normally” compel the exercise of a power nor intervene except where the powers were exceeded or exercised capriciously, whereas in the case of a discretionary trust, the court would if called upon exercise the trustee’s discretion “in the manner best calculated to give effect to the settlor’s or testator’s intentions”. This was so, he explained, because “A wider and more comprehensive range of enquiry is called for in the case of [discretionary trusts] than in the case of powers.” Another, perhaps more nebulous difference is that, in the case of a discretionary trust, it is debatable whether the beneficiaries as a class have an equitable interest in the trust property, in the case of a power, until and unless the power is properly exercised, the beneficial interest will be suspended. 4. Consider the effect of the following dispositions, the gifts being limited to the perpetuity period. As well as the validity of the gifts consider (a) the duty of the trustees and (b) the ‘whereabouts’ of the beneficial interest. (a) “to distribute amongst B, C, D, E and such of my other business associates and old friends as T shall see fit” The gift is likely to be invalid for uncertainty of objects. In this case, the trustees have no discretion to refuse to distribute the property transferred on trust for them. Moreover, “old friends” and “business associates” are, barring the admission of further evidence, concepts which are incapable of definition to a degree sufficient to satisfy the requirements of legal certainty; it is impossible to define objectively, for example, the criteria which the possible beneficiary must satisfy in order to be considered a friend of the settlor. A similar situation occurred in Re Barlow’s Will Trusts [1979] 1 All ER 296 (ChD), where the testator in her will sought to allow 'any members of my family and any friends of mine who may wish to do so’ to purchase particular paintings in her collection at particular prices. In that case, the court held that the gift was valid by treating it as a series of ‘one or more individual’ gifts subject to a condition precedent, such that the test for validity was whether or not the claimant could prove that he satisfied the condition, given that the testator had had acquaintances of a kind so close that on a reasonable basis any person would have considered them friends. By holding that the test in McPhail v. Doulton did not apply, the court seems to implicitly have accepted that the gift would be void for uncertainty had it been construed as a discretionary trust. Therefore, since it cannot be said with the requisite degree of certainty that any person is or is not an “old friend” or “business associate”, the gift fails for uncertainty and reverts to the settlor’s estate on a resulting trust. In such a case, since the trustee is not given any discretion to refuse to distribute the trust property, the property would if the trust were valid belong to the beneficiaries as a class. The trustees would have the duty of conducting a survey of the range of objects ‘in a businesslike way’, the extent of which would depend on the size of the trust, so that an allocation cannot be made without first assessing the appropriateness of that allocation in light of the claims of other possible beneficiaries, and the duty not to make allocations outside of the class of potential objects. (b) “to distribute amongst such of the inhabitants of Toa Payoh as T in their absolute discretion think fit” This situation is analogous to the case of R v. District Auditor (1986) 26 RVR 24 (QBD), where a trust for the inhabitants of West Yorkshire was held to be invalid for administrative workability. In that case, although the class of beneficiaries was held to be conceptually certain, the definition of the beneficiaries was so wide as to be incapable of forming “anything like a class”, as suggested by Lord Wilberforce in Mcphail, as the inhabitants of West Yorkshire at the time number around 2.5 million. The justification behind the administrative workability doctrine is that the court will not uphold any trust it cannot enforce; to do so would be contrary to the nature of the trust relationship as an obligation, as the trustees would then be free to commit breaches of trust without fear of reprisal, rendering the trust relationship nugatory. While this reason is sound in principle, it entails many difficulties in application. For example, it is unclear at what point the definition of a class of beneficiaries becomes so wide as to not form ‘anything like a class’. Would the trust in District Auditor have been valid if expressed as a series of smaller trusts for smaller districts? At a cursory look, Toa Payoh has a population of anywhere between 116, 000 to 200, 000 inhabitants, a number far smaller than that in District Auditor. In Pearce & Stevens, it was surmised that “’administrative workability’ will only render discretionary trusts void which have a class ranging in the magnitude of millions”. By this reasoning, therefore, the trust would not be invalid for administrative workability. Furthermore, however large the class of beneficiaries, it would not be impossible to enforce the trust as long as the trust document defines with sufficient clarity the objectives of the trust; any member of the class would then have the right to compel the trustees to exercise their discretion ‘bona fide’, ‘fairly’, ‘reasonably’, or ‘properly’. (IRC v. Gartside [1968] AC 553 (HL)) However, it might nonetheless be held void on another ground, that of capriciousness. In Re Manisty’s Settlement [1974] Ch 17 (ChD), Templeman J stated that the court could be persuaded to intervene where a trustee of a discretionary trust exercised his power ‘capriciously’, in a manner which could be said to be “irrational, perverse or irrelevant to any sensible expectation of the settlor”. By parity of reasoning, he considered that the objections to the capricious exercise of a power might well be extended to the creation of a capricious power, for such a power would ‘negative any sensible intention on the part of the settlor’ and therefore negative any sensible consideration by the trustees of the exercise of the power; such was “a power to benefit ‘residents of Greater London’”. In Re Hay’s Settlement, Sir Robert Megarry V-C appears to have accepted this proposition implicitly when he gave as a negative example the case of a former chairman of the Greater London Council. However, he then went on to caution that the court should be slow to declare that a trust was void on ‘a peradventure’, for “[d]ispositions ought if possible to be upheld, and the court ought not to be astute to find grounds on which a power can be invalidated.” He considered that such grounds included cases where there was ‘some real vice’ in the power, or if there were ‘real problems of administration or execution’. It is doubtful whether trusts for the benefit of the inhabitants of an area could be considered trusts with ‘some real vice’, and Sir Robert’s example of a situation in which “a trust for the benefit of Greater London” could be considered not capricious demonstrates the sheer ridiculousness of the doctrine. The motive of the settlor in deciding what is ‘sensible’ when constituting a trust in favour of particular beneficiaries should be, unless contrary to public policy, a matter towards which the courts should be neutral. Why should it be that the former mayor of Greater London may make a valid gift to the residents of Greater London, but a quiet resident who has lived there all his life may not? It is submitted that the real justification behind the capriciousness doctrine is the desire to limit the number of public trusts. However, since Re Denley [1969] 7 Ch 373 (CA), it has been settled that though a trust may be expressed as a purpose trust, it may be enforced if it is directly or indirectly for the benefit of individuals. There is then really no reason why such a trust for the benefit of Greater London, if free of ‘some real vice’ or administratively workable, should be invalid; the act of the settlor in constituting the trust shoudl be sufficient evidence that he intended to benefit the inhabitants of Greater London, and it should not be for the court to decide whether such intention is sensible or not. Indeed, to do so might be to constitute undue interference with the settlor’s property rights. The law allows persons to leave money to their dogs or for the purpose of proving that Shakespeare did not write Shakespeare’s plays, why should it not allow persons to leave money to their own fellow citizens? Therefore, the trust should be valid. (c) “to distribute income and capital to such members or former members of the Faculty of Law, and in such proportions as they in their absolute discretion think fit, and if no distribution is made, then to the Dean absolutely” Such a disposition creates a power of appointment, because it allows the trustees to withhold distributing the trust property to the class of beneficiaries. It will therefore be valid if “members or former members” satisfies the test laid down by the House of Lords in Re Gulbenkian’s Settlement Trusts [1970] AC 508 (HL), where the test for validity of a power of appointment was held to be the requirement of conceptual certainty: ie. the ability to say with certainty whether or not a person is or is not a member of the class. Since the term is capable of objective definition, the trust should not be held void on this basis. In the case of a power of appointment, the beneficial interest in the subject-matter of the power is suspended until any disposition is made properly, or until the period for the exercise of the power has come to an end. The duties of a fiduciary donee of a power would be, as stated below in Re Hay’s Settlement, similar to those of the trustee of a discretionary trust except less comprehensive and wide, as stated by Lord Wilberforce in McPhail. (d) “to hold on a trust to distribute capital and income to such residents of Singapore as they think fit” The population of Singapore numbers over 4 million at least, which is far larger than the 2.5 million in R v. District Auditor. It is therefore clear that the trust will be held invalid for administrative workability. (e) “on trust with power to appoint amongst such persons as they in their absolute discretion think fit and in default of appointment to the Dean” Such a disposition grants T a general power to appoint such persons as they see fit. In Re Hay’s Settlements, Sir Robert considered that, whichever the nature of a power of appointment, there was nothing in the number of persons to whom an appointment might be made which would invalidate it. While addressing this remark in relation to ‘mere powers’, he went on to consider that in the case of fiduciary donees, there was imposed the additional duties of making a survey of the range of objects or possible beneficiaries, of finding out the permissible area of selection and considering responsibly in individual cases whether a contemplated beneficiary was within the power, and of considering whether, in relation to the possible claimants, a grant was appropriate. The power to appoint to anyone in the world was not contrary to these duties, as Sir Robert later took some pains to specify that the remarks on administrative workability made by Lord Wilberforce in Mcphail were not meant to apply to powers. (f) “on trust with power to appoint amongst such persons as they in their absolute discretion think fit, provided always that no distribution be made to anyone who, in the opinion of the Dean, has an unsavoury reputation, and in default of appointment to the Dean” This disposition is similar to (e), except for the specification that grants may not be made to persons whom the Dean considers tainted by an unsavoury reputation. This new class is not conceptually uncertain, merely imposing a duty on the trustees to confer with the Dean whenever they wish to make a grant. Therefore it is unlikely to be held void for uncertainty. 5. Discuss the validity and effect of S’s gift to his employees and ex-employees. The mandatory language of the document, which does not leave the trustees the discretion to refuse to make a grant, attempts to create a discretionary trust. The issue then becomes one of whether the class of beneficiaries is conceptually certain, capable of satisfying the ‘is or is not’ test of whether a particular individual may be said to be within or without the class. Here it is likely that ‘exceptional service’ by itself is an uncertain definition, as it would be impossible to provide an objective definition of what exactly makes service rendered ‘exceptional’. In Re Tuck’s Settlement [1978] 1 All ER 1047 (CA), however, a trust containing a similarly conceptually uncertain definition was held to be validated by the addition of a clause specifying that in the case of dispute the decision of the Chief Rabbi in London should be conclusive. Following this reasoning, therefore, the inclusion of the clause allowing Wilma to adjudicate should validate the gift as long as Wilma remains alive and capable of making a proper decision. However, the reasoning in Re Tuck failed to consider a situation where a decision was taken by the third party arbitrarily. In such a case it is submitted that the result in Tuck remains sound; the real intention of the testator being that the class should consist of such persons as considered within the class by the specified third party. 6. “The requirement of administrative workability in discretionary and purpose trusts serves no useful purpose. The same is true of the doctrine of capriciousness applied to powers.” Discuss. (see 4(b))