Enlarging the Societal Pie – A Cognitive Perspective Max H. Bazerman Harvard Business School Harvard University Jonathan Baron Psychology Department University of Pennsylvania Katherine Shonk Harvard Business School Harvard University 11/13/02 2 Enlarging the Societal Pie – A Cognitive Perspective Abstract Based on contemporary research in decision making, negotiation, and cognitive psychology, we offer a cognitive perspective to explain the failure of governments to create what Stiglitz (1998) calls near-Pareto improvements. We examine the role of human judgment in the failure to find wise tradeoffs across diverse applications of government decision-making, including organ donation systems, endangered species protection, interstate competition, overfishing, and free trade. Our tools for analyzing these failures reflect the difficulty people have trading small losses for large gains, and include the omission bias, status-quo bias, the fixed-pie approach to negotiations, unwillingness to solve social dilemmas, ignoring secondary effects, and discounting the future. Collectively, we seek to offer a new approach for understanding suboptimality in government decision making. Key words: government decision making, biases, Pareto optimality 3 Between 1956 and 1980, as power providers began to turn from coal to cheaper and cleaner energy sources such as imported oil, employment in German coalmines plummeted. To restore reliance on a domestic industry and domestic labor, the German government persuaded the country’s electricity suppliers to cut off imports of oil and instead rely exclusively on German coal. To prop up the ailing industry, the government subsidized the mining of coal, and covered these costs with an electricity tax. By 1986, the mines were so heavily subsidized that German coal sold at three times the world market rate. By 1992, the average German miner earned the U.S. equivalent of $36,000 per year—yet if the subsidy had been funneled directly to workers, they would have been earning $92,000. The government could have saved money by switching to a cheaper energy source and paying the miners $36,000 to do nothing. The coal subsidies not only made poor economic sense; they were environmentally harmful. The process of burning coal releases carbon into the atmosphere; because artificially low prices reduced consumers’ incentive to conserve energy, carbon emissions increased. Carbon emissions contribute to the greenhouse effect and ultimately, most experts agree, to global warming (Ding and Houghton, 2001). During the early 1990s, facing pressure from other European countries to create a fairer energy policy, the German government began to explore means of reducing coal subsidies. If subsidies were eliminated completely, the government could expect coal production to fall by 75 percent (Radetzki, 1995); only 25 percent of production would compete efficiently with other energy sources. However, it was estimated that the number of coal workers would plummet from 250,000 to 31,000. Once the electricity tax was declared unconstitutional in 1994, the coal subsidy was supported primarily by the country’s general funds. At this point, Chancellor Helmut Kohl 4 proposed funding reductions that would cut mining jobs to 35,000 by the year 2005. In March 1997, the miners’ union, IG Bergbau, called on its members to demonstrate against Kohl's plan. The union was willing to reduce jobs, but refused to go lower than 45,000. For the three days that Chancellor Kohl negotiated with the head of the union, up to 15,000 miners protested in Bonn and about twice as many took part in demonstrations in the Saarland, the heart of the mining region. Miners took part in road blockades, then waited out the negotiations in a Cologne stadium. In the end, they returned home victorious. The government agreed to increase its original offer of a total federal mining subsidy through 2005 of 56.6 billion marks (about $34 billion) by 1.65 billion marks; the state government of North Rhine/Westphalia pledged an additional 1.75 billion marks (Deutsche Presse-Agentur, 1997). By 2005, annual subsidies would be fixed at 5.5 billion marks. The miners failed to achieve all of their goals, however: By 2005, the number of mining jobs was expected to range between 35,000 and 45,000. At first glance, it appears that each miner benefited from the actions of the group of miners as a whole. A conservative estimate is that the demonstrations cost each miner one lost day of wages. Although the miners sought to save about 11 percent of the 85,000 existing jobs, they only preserved an estimated six percent of the jobs over an eight-year period. Because some of the miners would have retired or quit working for other reasons during this time, the savings might have been closer to ten years saved for five percent of the currently employed miners. Thus, each miner saved about half-a-year of work, or as much as 200 days. Certainly 200 days was worth a day of lost wages to attend the demonstration (Bazerman, Baron, and Shonk, 2001). 5 This analysis considers the impact of the entire group of protestors on each miner. What effect did each individual miner have on the agreement? Did each miner reap significant benefits from his own participation in the protests, or would he have been better off staying at home and letting his comrades demonstrate on his behalf? If only 10,000 miners took part in the Bonn protest (the actual number was higher), then each protestor contributed one ten-thousandth of the group’s total gains. Thus, keeping in mind that each miner gained about 200 days of work, each contributed one ten-thousandth of this amount. Each miner therefore gained two percent of one day for himself, or about 10 minutes. How to explain the difference between 200 days versus 10 minutes gained? From the group’s perspective, each miner's contribution was worthwhile; their combined effort generated 200 days per miner. But each individual only contributed 10 minutes for each miner, including himself. If a miner were completely self-interested, then his day of protest was a personal loss. He could have let the 9,999 other miners fight for his 199+ days while sacrificing the ten minutes he would have earned for himself. A positive view of the situation is that the miners were cooperating in a social dilemma to help their group (Dawes, 1980; Messick and Brewer, 1983; Yamagishi, 1986). However, this view limits the extension of concern to the union, therefore overlooking the fact that the union is part of a broader society. Lobbying for the continuation of inefficient jobs that harm the environment is a defection on this broader interest group. While lobbying creates value to the union, it comes at cost to the union member and to the broader society. The case of German coal demonstrates that when members of a small special-interest group choose to look out only for the group, the group may achieve noteworthy short-term gains. But the larger group – in this case, society as a whole – will generally benefit only when 6 individuals choose to cooperate rather than defect in the more global social dilemma. This phenomenon illuminates a correlation between the narrow self-interest of the individual and the largest interest of society. All German citizens, and indeed all of humankind, would have been better off if every miner had chosen “selfishly” not to protest. Unmoved by demonstrations, the government might have reduced its coalmining subsidies even further, enabling it to spend more on projects that would benefit society, such as research into cleaner energy sources or investment in the former East Germany (Bazerman et al., 2001). When we consider the environmental and economic costs of a continued reliance on coal, it becomes clear that all Germans, and all citizens of the Earth, are hurt by the small group’s behavior. The scope of the problem extends beyond Germany: France, Spain, and Japan all subsidize coal in various ways (Light, 1999). Why do citizens allow their governments to continue to subsidize coalmining despite its known economic inefficiency and environmental hazards? More broadly, we might ask: Why do citizens tolerate inefficient government policies? This question has generated significant insights from economists and political scientists. We hope to bring a psychological perspective to this question, with the goal of understanding the inefficient behavior of politicians and the acceptance of these inefficiencies by their constituents. Most citizens would agree that a fundamental goal of any government should be enlarging the pie of resources that society has at its disposal. Yet few citizens judge their leaders according to this key attribute. Instead, voters too often focus on the narrow interests of a smaller group to which they belong (coalminers, lawyers, stockholders, soccer moms, anti-trade activists, etc.). But when government decisions are tailored to benefit small groups of constituents, valuable public resources – from tax dollars to national forests – are often misused, squandered, and ignored. 7 Decision research has identified judgment biases that underlie these failings. The most common of these cognitive errors concern the difficulties people have making and understanding tradeoffs. Indeed, we will argue that most failed government decisions can be traced to the widespread human failure to identify and make wise tradeoffs by accepting small losses in exchange for larger gains. While most people know tradeoffs to be exchanges that result in both a gain and a loss, the human mind often overlooks wise tradeoffs – those in which gains significantly exceed losses for all parties. Wise tradeoffs can be viewed in terms of a type of policy change that economists call “Pareto improvements.” A Pareto improvement is a policy shift that helps some people and harms no one. True Pareto improvements are rare; most changes will require sacrifices from some members of society. Thus, a more realistic goal for policy-makers are the types of tradeoffs that economist Joseph Stiglitz calls “near-Pareto improvements” (Stiglitz, 1998). These are policy changes that will greatly benefit some people while imposing comparatively trivial losses upon others, such as a special-interest group that may have already manipulated the political system to its advantage. According to Stiglitz, “if everyone except a narrowly defined special interest group could be shown to benefit, surely the change should be made” (Stiglitz, 1998). In this article, we examine a number of failed policy decisions and describe the cognitive biases that contribute to them. We argue that the pursuit of wise tradeoffs can be expected to lead to better government policy that expands the amount of societal resources available to us all. The U.S. Organ Shortage: A Harm of Omission Which would you prefer: 8 a. If you die in an auto accident, your heart will be used to save another person’s life. In addition, if you are ever in need of a heart transplant, there will be a 90 percent chance that you will get the heart. b. If you die in an auto accident, you will be buried with your heart in your body. In addition, if you are ever in need of a heart transplant, there will be a 45 percent chance that you will get the heart. If you are like most people, you chose Option A (Bazerman et al., 2001). Why, then, do the United States and most other countries maintain an organ donation policy that resembles Option B? In 2000, more than 60,000 Americans were waiting for an organ transplant (Gibbons, Meltzer and Duan, 2000). We can expect that at least one third of them will die waiting (Smirnoff, Arnold, Caplan, Virnig, and Seltzer, 1995). In the United States, consent for donation must be obtained from the potential donor or a close family member before an organ is harvested. This system favors deceased donors over still breathing recipients – despite the fact that the potential future pool of donors and recipients is nearly the same. After all, few of us can predict whether we will be put in either role someday. Within the U.S., discussion of organ donation has focused on how to divide a small pie, such as whether the available organs should be allocated on a regional or national basis. While experts debate who should receive available organs, little attention is paid to expanding the number of organs in the system. In countries such as Belgium, Austria, and Brazil, organ shortages have been alleviated and in some cases eliminated by a simple switch in policy from “required request” to “presumed consent.” Under presumed consent, organ donation, rather than burial with all of one’s organs intact, becomes the default. Instead of handing out donor cards to those who consent to 9 donation, the government gives objector cards to those who refuse. Citizens who do not object are automatically assumed to be potential donors. This simple change in mindset has saved thousands of lives. In Belgium, donations leaped by 140 percent after a presumed consent law was introduced. After a similar law was passed in Austria in 1983, the waiting list for organs fell to a small fraction of its previous size by 1990 (Gnant, Wamser, Goetzinger, Sautner, Steininger, and Muehlbacher, 1991). Such laws may be particularly effective because they presume the consent not only of donors, but of their families, who also must act to deny a donation. Presumed consent laws can be expected to save thousands of American lives each year. So, why hasn’t the United States enacted these reforms? Our faulty reactions to risk underlie the most popular objections to presumed consent. Most government policy changes carry some degree of risk. Ideally, reforms reduce one risk more than they increase another, resulting in overall benefit for each individual. Yet citizens often resist reforms, believing that they will suffer from the increased risk. Suppose you learn that you have a ten percent chance of catching a new strain of flu virus. The vaccine available for this virus will completely prevent it, but has a five percent chance of causing symptoms identical to those it is supposed to prevent, and with the same severity. Would you get the vaccine? Many people would refuse it (Ritov and Baron, 1990). They would worry more about the risk of harm from action – the five percent risk of an adverse reaction to the vaccine – than about the risk of harm from inaction, or the ten percent risk of catching the flu without the vaccine. This is the case despite the fact that the vaccine is a better bet, reducing the chance of flu symptoms by five percent. Although this example is hypothetical, it has been observed in people's real-life decisions about vaccination (Ritov and Baron, 1990). 10 The irrational preference for harms of omission over harms of action is known as the omission bias (Ritov and Baron, 1990). When contemplating risky choices, many people follow the popular rule of thumb, “Do no harm.” This principle embodies the notion that it is wrong to harm one person to benefit another, even if the benefit outweighs the harm. An admonition against harmful actions, “Do no harm” is silent on the question of harms of omission. In most cases, harmful omissions are not as blameworthy as harmful actions because actions involve greater cost, hence greater intention. Yet people apply the distinction between intended versus accidental harm even when it is unjustified (Baron, 1996). For example, when we are evaluating public policy options in which the costs are equal – such as required request versus presumed consent for organ donation – a bias toward harmful omissions cannot be excused away due to lack of intended harm. The omission bias is the cognitive error that most pervades our risk decisions in both the laboratory and the real world (Ritov and Baron, 1999), and helps to explain why many more people catch the flu than need to each year (Baron, 1998). Current U.S. law defines organ donation as an act and the withholding of donation as an omission. Thus, the relative lack of concern about failure to donate can result from the common intuition that harms arising from omissions are less blameworthy than those caused by acts. However, this distinction between acts and omissions is arbitrary, created entirely by the law. Presumed consent reverses this situation: By requiring an act to refuse donation, the do-no-harm rule works against refusal. In return for the small risk that an individual’s desire not to donate will be ignored – because of pressure to consent, for example – many lives are saved. When consent is presumed, potential donors are forced to view refusal as a harmful act. The omission bias is usually correlated with another bias, the bias toward the status quo (Samuelson and Zeckhauser, 1988; Ritov and Baron, 1992). Risky decisions, such as changes to 11 government policy, usually require action. Thus, when contemplating a change, people are more likely to be concerned about the risk of change than about the risk of failing to change, and will be motivated to preserve current systems and beliefs. Occurring independently of the omission bias (Schweitzer, 1994), the status-quo bias is a general source of opposition to reform even when people regard the consequences of reform as an improvement (Baron and Jurney, 1993). The status-quo bias makes us reluctant to change to an organ donation system that presumes donor consent – although, as discussed, the risks of change are much smaller than the potential benefits. Those who oppose presumed consent laws and other beneficial changes to government policy must accept that their irrational approach to risk causes real harm. Environmental Negotiations and the Fixed-Pie Pitfall For decades, forester Benjamin Cone, followed by his son, Ben Cone, Jr., managed their 7,200 acres in North Carolina’s Pender County for wildlife by planting fodder, conducting controlled burns, and keeping timber sales low. The land was a profitable forest where songbirds, wild turkey, quail and deer thrived. This all changed in 1991, when a wildlife biologist hired by Cone, Jr., determined that approximately 29 red-cockaded woodpeckers, members of an endangered species, were living on the property. Acting on the authority of the 1973 Endangered Species Act (ESA), the U.S. Fish and Wildlife Service seized control of the woodpecker’s habitat – 1,560 acres, or about fifteen percent of Cone’s land (Baden, 1995). In the aftermath of the seizure, Cone abandoned the moderate, sustainable practices he learned from his father. Instead of clearcutting fifty acres of land every five to ten years, he began clearcutting up to five hundred acres of forest each year. Why did Cone turn to such destructive practices? He explained: “I cannot afford to let those woodpeckers take over the rest of the property” (Stroup, 1995). By harvesting the oldest trees on the land still within his 12 control, Cone prevented the woodpeckers from expanding their habitat. In the process, he also destroyed vast swaths of his forest, perhaps forever. The Endangered Species Act (ESA) was designed to protect endangered or threatened species and restore them to a secure status in the wild. Clearly, Cone's actions were not what the authors of the ESA had in mind. Indeed, the ESA offers its own solution to dilemmas such as Cone’s: Habitat Conservation Plans (HCPs). In simple terms, HCPs allow private landowners "incidental take" of listed species in the course of lawful development activities, provided the landowner also takes certain steps to preserve the species. HCPs attempt to serve both the interests of the endangered species and the economic interests of landowners; they have resulted in many innovative agreements. The Fish and Wildlife Service repeatedly approached Cone with proposals for HCPs, but he rejected these offers, choosing to stick with his slash-and-burn strategy. Why? Cone apparently assumed that if a plan was desirable to environmentalists, it must be bad for his business. A common negotiation pitfall, the assumption that “anything good for them must be bad for us” eliminates the search for solutions that could bring benefits to both sides. The mythical fixed-pie mentality – the belief that the pie of resources is fixed in size – is antithetical to the cooperative discovery of the types of wise tradeoffs that can improve the overall quality of negotiated outcomes. Because the ESA appears to pit economic development against environmental protection, it has often led parties to approach negotiations with a win-lose attitude such as Cone’s. Negotiators influenced by the fixed-pie bias can be expected to “reactively devalue” – interpret as negative – any proposal offered by the opponent (Ross and Stillinger, 1991). 13 Agreements in diplomatic situations are frequently blocked by the assumption that the parties’ interests are diametrically opposed. Creative agreements occur when participants discover tradeoffs across issues – but individuals will not search for these trades if they assume the size of the pie is fixed (Neale and Bazerman, 1991). The assumption of a fixed pie is rooted in social norms that lead us to interpret most competitive situations as win–lose (Bazerman, 2002). Humans tend to generalize from these objective win–lose situations to situations that are not necessarily win–lose (Bazerman, Magliozzi, and Neale, 1985). Thompson (2001) has found that even when two sides want the exact same outcome – such as ending the Cold War – negotiators often settle on a different outcome, or reach an impasse. The fixed-pie assumption leads parties to assume their interests are incompatible. In fact, this is rarely the case, as parties will discover once they become willing to accept a small loss in return for a larger gain. If one side cares about X much more than Y, and the other side cares about Y more than X, the best outcome is for the first side to get X and the second side to get Y. For both sides to achieve maximum benefit, each should make a small tradeoff in exchange for something it values much more. Unfortunately, when inefficient regulations, laws, and policies are already in place, the omission and status quo biases combine to focus attention on losses rather than on the benefits of any change. Thus, unwillingness to accept small losses in return for larger gains prevents negotiators from achieving the best outcome for both sides. The integrative complexity of your thought processes – the degree to which you consider a problem from multiple perspectives – may be one factor that predicts whether you will move beyond the fixed-pie mentality (Chaiken, Gruenfeld, and Judd, in press). At the lowest levels of integrative complexity, people view negotiations in black and white: They recognize all of the advantages of the option they favor and none of its drawbacks. At higher levels, they begin to 14 identify the pros and cons of various options, and view the decision as a quest for the best overall balance. Negotiators who have adopted integratively complex thinking are likely to consider the advantages of the other side’s proposals; when these advantages are substantial, and the disadvantages to themselves are small, they are likely to accept the proposal. This mindset reflects the ability to identify and accept wise tradeoffs. In independent work, Gruenfeld and Tetlock have argued that the wisest government policies often result from “integratively complex” thinking rather than from the intransigent positions found in most political, economic, or environmental negotiations (Gruenfeld, 1995; Tetlock, Peterson, and Lerner, 1996). Flexibility and creativity are the keys to satisfying economic and environmental agreements. The Unocal Corporation and the Environmental Protection Agency demonstrated such ingenuity in reducing its costs for complying with the hydrocarbon and nitrogen oxide standards in the Los Angeles basin (Bazerman and Hoffman, 1999). In 1990, rather than undertaking costly and inefficient refinery renovations, Unocal launched a program aimed at clearing the air more cheaply: The company began buying up pre-1971 high-polluting vehicles from the L.A. area for $600 apiece and scrapping them. Estimating the number of miles the vehicle would have been driven had it not been scrapped, Unocal determined that it had prevented nearly 13 million pounds of air pollution per year from the L.A. basin. The same reductions would have cost ten times as much and taken ten times as long had they been made at the company's L.A. refinery (Stegemeier, 1995). A creative perspective could lead parties away from the fixed-pie mindset, toward a rational search for outcomes that maximize both environmental and economic gains. 15 Dysfunctional Competition in the Sports Arena In recent decades, state and local officials across America have spent billions of tax dollars on new sports facilities in the hope of luring or retaining a professional sports franchise in their region. Team owners have fueled this building boom, pitting city against city in the scramble for new sports venues with profit-generating restaurants, luxury suites, and seat licenses. At least thirteen communities now provide or have proposed providing at least $250 million in subsidies for professional sports franchises: Baltimore (and Maryland), Cincinnati, Cleveland, Denver, Detroit (and Michigan), Hartford, Milwaukee, Nashville, Pittsburgh, San Diego, Seattle, Scottsdale, and St. Louis. These giveaways add up to one of the most extravagant corporate welfare systems in the United States today. Team owners faced with losses or low profits have a strong incentive to demand public assistance to build or improve their stadiums. New or renovated stadiums generally increase the profits of team owners, at least temporarily (Quirk and Fort, 1997); the team’s resale value soars when it moves into a new home. Because team owners band together in leagues to limit the number of teams available, more cities and states desire major league franchises than there are franchises to go around. Although teams move infrequently, the excess demand provides team owners with strong bargaining power. Their threats of relocation drive cities into expensive bidding wars that local politicians rarely can resist. This is true despite the fact that, according to a Media Research and Communications poll, 80 percent of Americans oppose having their tax dollars spent on sports stadiums and arenas (Rosentraub, 1997). In some cases, politicians have blocked or ignored referendum elections held to resolve these matters. Voters in Milwaukee overwhelmingly rejected a sports lottery to fund a new stadium, yet the Wisconsin state legislature went ahead and granted $160 16 million in subsidies for the facility. And it's not just locals who must foot the bill: A change to the Tax Reform Act of 1986 facilitated the use of federally tax-exempt bonds in arena construction, diffusing the costs of building a stadium throughout the country. When a team threatens to leave a city, some residents will pressure their local government to enter a bidding war with other communities. Public officials must ask themselves whether the public benefits of retaining the team justify the associated public costs. One study found that of fifteen new or renovated stadiums, only the Dodger stadium in Los Angeles generated enough tax revenue to pay for the original public assistance plus interest cost (Baim, 1990). New jobs generated by new sports facilities tend to be low-wage (janitors, concession workers, and parking lot attendants); meanwhile, the high salaries paid to players and managers typically flow out of the local economy (Rosentraub, 1997). As for non-monetary “public goods” such as civic pride, these should be factored alongside other intangibles such as traffic congestion and air pollution (Hartley and Hooper, 1992). At the very least, taxpayer financing of sports stadiums must be considered in relation to other potential civic investments. Because public resources are finite, stadium deals reduce the amount of funding available for far more critical community needs, such as education or community policing. Typically, the community that acquires the team savors a momentary victory, and the politicians behind the deal may secure their re-election, but all parties will generally lose far more than they gain. Bad stadium deals are the product of dysfunctional competition between governments. Private-sector competition generally improves the local or national economy, creating better and more affordable goods and services. Competition can become dysfunctional, however, when organizations invest resources simply to achieve the satisfaction of winning or to hurt a competitor. Government competition can be far more destructive than private-sector competition 17 because, unlike corporations, governments must provide public services such as highways to libraries. When competitive practices backfire, citizens suffer the consequences in the form of service cutbacks or tax increases. In private industry, competition fuels creativity and innovation; between governments, competition fuels the flow of taxpayer funds to selected private interests. Valuable, finite resources such as tax dollars and government land are squandered in destructive competition between cities, states and regions. Dysfunctional competition between communities and regions for professional sports teams, manufacturing plants, and corporate headquarters can be explained by a psychological mechanism known as the winner’s curse. When a bidder wins an auction in which parties have made varying estimates of the prize’s worth, the highest bidder is likely to have overvalued the prize commodity in comparison to other bidders (Capen, Clapp, and Campbell, 1971; Bazerman and Samuelson, 1983; Kagel and Levin, 1986). The winning bidder has failed to draw a key inference: The party who most overestimates the value of the prize often makes the winning bid. Similarly, when city leaders estimate the value of a baseball team, the “winning” city will be the one with the most overoptimistic estimate of the team’s value. If a bidder assumes that her organization, city, or state will win an auction, she should recognize that she may have overestimated the value of the commodity in comparison to other bidders. The other bidders may not value the prize for reasons the winning bidder has not considered. The creation of excess capacity in the context of sports arenas is consistent with Camerer and Lovallo’s (1999) observation that overconfidence may lead too many firms to enter a market and with Zajac and Bazerman’s (1991) discussion of cognitive blind spots in market-entry decisions. Even in domains where competition is generally beneficial, an excess of entrants can result from cognitive biases. In the case of competition for sports teams, the fact that market 18 entrance is subsidized by taxpayers exacerbates the harms created by excess capacity. It would be best if everyone supported some sort of regulation preventing such practices – even an agreement among the cities themselves. But pushing such regulation through would itself require time and money, losses that might loom larger than the gain. In fact, the long-term gains of regulation or mutual agreement would far outweigh short-term losses. Efforts to curb the stadium-building frenzy have failed at the national level, leaving cities to fend off owner threats one by one. In San Antonio, thanks to a Texas law that gives school districts a voice in proposed tax deals affecting land values, a local school board was able to block the Spurs’ bid for a $156 million arena. When the board of the North East School District voted against the deal, the Spurs were forced to abide by their decision. “If you have to choose between the National Basketball Association and children, it’s no choice,” explained school board president Bruce Bennett (Johnson, 1999). But most politicians, lacking both regulatory support and a clear understanding of the pitfalls ahead, are only too happy to hand over the keys to the city treasury. The Global Fishing Crisis and Future Generations Fishing has become an increasingly dangerous profession in recent years. Vietnamese have shot at Thai fishers, the Malaysian navy fired on a Thai trawler, Russians shot at Japanese fishers, Iceland used force to exclude Danish trawlers from its waters, and a Portuguese naval boat fired on a Spanish fishing boat, to name just a few cases (Zimmermann, 1996). Such violence is part of the mounting economic and social disruption that has occurred as the world overharvests the oceans (McGinn, 1998). The result of too many well-equipped boats chasing after too few fish, overharvesting has become a global epidemic. Once-plentiful species have disappeared, forcing consumers to adapt to low-quality fish. Eleven of the world’s 15 major 19 fishing regions and nearly 70 percent of the most sought-after species of fish are in decline. Two hundred million jobs, a world resource, and peace between nations are all at risk. The pattern of devastation has been quite predictable. Improved technology and increased funding allow capacity to increase until fishers are catching unsustainable amounts of fish. When scientists note that populations are threatened, fishers dispute the evidence. In good years, fishers expand their capacity; in bad years, they lobby for, and receive, government support. As fish populations are destroyed, fishers move on to less attractive species and other locations. Half of the world’s fishing vessels could be taken out of commission without any reduction in potential harvest (McGinn, 1998). Too many boats are chasing too few fish. Government subsidies – in the form of tax incentives, low-interest loans, and direct subsidies – are arguably the leading threat to the world’s fish populations (Porter, 1996). Such aid encourages fishers to either remain in or enter an overextended fishery. Currently, fishers operate at huge losses; for each U.S. dollar earned worldwide from fishing in the late 1980s, governments, taxpayers, and fishers spent $1.77. By 1989, direct and indirect subsidies totaled $54 billion against estimated revenues of $70 billion (Zimmerman, 1996). These handouts distort markets, increase overcapacity, and speed up the destruction of the fishing basin. Common sense tells us that if fishers would harvest fewer fish, the fish remaining would have the chance to regenerate their species, providing sustainable catch for these and future fishers. Why do humans instead choose to behave so self-destructively? Flawed human decision-making lies at the root of the world fishery crisis. The global fishing crisis is a classic social dilemma. Each fisher has an incentive to harvest as much possible to maximize profits. Of course, when all fishers in the fishing basin act in this way, they harm themselves by depleting the fish supply. Similarly, each nation can justify 20 subsidizing its fishing fleet to remain competitive in the marketplace, but when all nations behave competitively, they all suffer. While regulations and treaties are logical solutions to such social dilemmas, special-interest groups have proven very effective at blocking them. A special aspect of the fishing dilemma is that society should be motivated to preserve fish populations beyond our own lives, so that future generations will benefit from thriving oceans and an adequate supply of nutritious fish. Fishers who defect in the present social dilemma are trading immediate benefits for long-term costs for themselves and others, including those who are not yet alive (Wade-Benzoni, 1996; Wade-Benzoni, Hoffman, Thompson, Moore, Gillespie, and Bazerman, in press). For this reason, the fishing problem can be viewed as a unique type of social dilemma: an intergenerational dilemma (Wade-Benzoni, 1996), or a social trap (Messick and McClelland, 1983). Why do fishers resist coordinated efforts to allow the oceans to recover? Because decision makers tend to deny the long-term effects of their behavior. When they focus on present concerns, people are likely to discount the future, even if they would personally benefit from taking future interests into account. The tendency to overweight the present at the expense of the future pervades human decisions. Homeowners often fail to adequately insulate their homes, even when they would save a great deal of money in the long run and help conserve natural resources (Gately, 1980; Ruderman, Levine and McMahon, 1986). According to Mannix and Loewenstein (1992), high discount rates help to explain why most businesses fail to invest in the long term, pay little attention to customer loyalty, and dedicate few funds for research and development. In the same manner, fishers concentrate on snaring as many fish as they can now – a relatively small amount compared to the much larger future catch they are sacrificing. Overweighting the present can be viewed not only as foolish, but immoral, robbing opportunities 21 and resources from future generations. Certainly we have a moral obligation to remember future inhabitants of the earth when making decisions that will impact them. Much of our tendency to overly discount the future can be attributed to wishful thinking in an uncertain environment. Psychologists have found that people view themselves, the world, and the future much more positively than reality can sustain (Allison, Messick, and Goethals, 1989; Kramer, 1994; Taylor, 1989). In one study, most subjects claimed they had a better-thanaverage chance of living past 80 (Weinstein, 1980). Similarly, subjects who bet on sporting events tend to bet on the team they hope will win, even if the odds are stacked against them (Babad and Katz, 1991). In such cases, people expect the future to better and brighter than they should reasonably assume it will be (Kramer, 1994; Tyler and Hastie, 1991). These positive illusions enhance self-esteem, increase personal satisfaction, and assist individuals in persisting at difficult tasks. But wishful thinking can also lead decision makers to deny that a problem exists, often until it is too late. Because estimates about the future will always contain some degree of uncertainty, intergenerational dilemmas leave room for decision makers to indulge in wishful thinking. Insisting that scientists who predict species depletion are “doomsayers” or flat-out wrong, fishers cling to the positive illusion that fish supplies will recover with no adjustment to their own behavior. They ignore the fact that small changes in their fishing practices could eliminate the eventual need for massive upheaval, such as the loss of their jobs. Unfortunately, reality is too often deaf to their wishes (Baron, 1998). Because of the insidious nature of psychological biases, we can hardly expect fishers to solve this intergenerational dilemma on their own. Governments, currently major contributors to the crisis, need to become part of the solution. The most obvious recommendation may be the 22 creation of an international agreement to bar countries from subsidizing their fishing fleets. Indeed, it would make more sense to tax the fishing industry for the resources they are removing from common ownership than to continue to subsidize them for doing so. Only through joint agreement will parties be able to reverse the current crisis and improve the long-term welfare of all nations. Common-sense restraints should be placed on the lobbying activities and campaign contributions of special-interest groups, which are bound to fight such an agreement. The other essential component of a long-term solution to overharvesting is restricting access to fish harvests. Once an appropriate harvesting level is identified for a fish species or fishing basin, strategies could be developed to encourage fishers to fish up to, but not beyond, a maximum sustainable yield – an equilibrium between a fish population’s ability to reproduce and the value of future harvests. Harvests could be reduced in one of two ways. First, regulations and taxation could be imposed on fishers to keep the ocean from being depleted; the political left typically prefers these measures. Alternatively, property rights could be granted to the ocean, giving owners a greater incentive to manage their portion of the scarce resource; the political right typically prefers this approach. Note, though, that because property rights must be enforced, governments will be involved either way. Early community-based management projects have been highly successful. When fishers in Alanya, Turkey faced a declining harvest, their local fishing cooperative began to rotate designated fishing sites among fishers, who enforced the system through informal and formal penalties (Ostrom, 1990). As a consequence, the best locations are not overharvested, and fish supplies and profits have recovered. In 1991, the Filipino government devolved management of near-shore fisheries to municipalities and local fishing communities. This change has allowed 23 fishing cooperatives to provide its members with supplemental income projects and with credit, lending, and marketing services. Any solution to the fishing problem requires resolution of a social dilemma. Parties must become willing to invest time and effort on behalf of a regulatory or privatization scheme that can be expected to benefit the vast majority of people over time. Of course, short-term thinking prevents most parties from even considering such advocacy. We hope early, small-scale efforts will inspire governments and fishers elsewhere to cooperate on long-term solutions to the crisis. Free Trade and the Nationalist Impulse In December 1999, the World Trade Organization (WTO) held its annual meeting in Seattle with its upcoming series of “Millenial Round” talks high on the agenda. Formerly a sedate, low-key affair, the 1999 meeting received front-page press across the globe, thanks to the thousands who turned out to voice their opposition to free trade. The two-day demonstrations included a 25,000-strong march, a traffic-blocking sit-in, and the vandalism of businesses in downtown Seattle by self-described “anarchists.” With visiting dignitaries trapped in their hotel rooms, the WTO meetings came to a temporary standstill. When the delegates were finally able to congregate, their frustration led to dissension and inaction; they returned home having achieved none of their goals (Lacayo, 1999). A patchwork of special-interest groups known as non-governmental organizations (NGOs), the protestors included environmentalists who believe the elimination of trade barriers will destroy nature, nationalists who fear the homogenization of world culture, and labor union activists who think open trade eliminates jobs in developed countries and exploits workers in emerging nations. The NGOs succeeded in promoting the previously murky issue of free trade into a hot-button issue. Most of the activists are well meaning, and their causes certainly deserve 24 our concern and attention. But by focusing on blocking all new trade agreements, rather than focusing specifically on changing worldwide environmental and labor standards, they destroyed larger opportunities for gain. NGOs typically disregard what is arguably the most important benefit of open trade: its proven ability, in combination with other factors, to alleviate poverty worldwide (Bannister and Thugge, 2001). While loosened trade restrictions will cause short-term upheaval, including the loss of some jobs and possible environmental costs, free trade can be expected to bring about greater long-term benefits to all. The most important of these include the creation of productive jobs for workers around the world and the eventual promise of a cleaner environment through improved technology. Historical trends support the view that free trade is directly related to economic prosperity. The Smoot-Hawley Tariff Act of 1930, which inflated U.S. tariffs up to 59 percent of imported goods, has been blamed for contributing to the Great Depression. In Europe, protectionist policies during this era are believed to have turned a worldwide recession into an economic meltdown and to have played a part in the outbreak of World War II. Conversely, loosened trade restrictions in the second half of the century are credited with the phenomenal postwar recoveries of Germany and Japan and, according to the WTO, with lifting an estimated three billion people out of poverty. In recent decades, the standard of living in Asian countries such as South Korea, Singapore, and Malaysia improved dramatically following their entrance into the world marketplace. One study determined that open economies have grown an average of 2.5 percent faster than closed economies, with even more dramatic discrepancies among developing countries (Sachs and Warner, 1995). The anti-trade goals of protecting U.S. jobs and creating new environmental restrictions typically clash with the desire of poor countries to become active participants in the world 25 market. Poor nations have begun to demand a voice in global trade negotiations, but they will not achieve their goals without the help of the wealthy. As we have argued, some policy changes benefit everyone, while others will hurt some while helping others. Such is the case with the easing of trade barriers, which can be expected to cause short-term harms to rich nations and untold benefits for the poor. Effective governments will recognize the wisdom of these “nearPareto improvements.” When solutions to these complex problems are efficient, the loss to the rich will be much smaller than the gain to the poor; small amounts of money and other goods have greater value to those who have so little. Of course, the losers will protest such changes loudly, and politicians will be reluctant to impose losses on vocal constituents. Although accepting losses is never easy, maintaining artificial trade barriers would impose greater losses upon us all. Even when they understand that the benefits of increased trade outweigh its harms, many citizens of wealthy nations continue to oppose new agreements that would relax trade barriers, such as the North American Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA). As we discussed in the context of organ donation, the omission bias causes people to worry more about harms caused by action than about those caused by inaction (Baron, 1996). In an experiment designed to assess people’s opinions about free trade, most subjects opposed to NAFTA said that trade agreements should not result in the loss of jobs, even if the agreements prevent many more job losses then they cause. When asked if they would approve an agreement that would “cause 10,000 job losses in the U.S. but prevent 11,000 job losses in the U.S. over the same time period,” NAFTA opponents, more than others, tended to oppose the agreement (Baron, 1996). This opposition illustrates the irrational desire to avoid harmful actions even when they produce overall gains. 26 The omission bias is particularly common when inaction harms people of other nations, whom it is easy to consider outside our zone of responsibility. This introduces a second bias into the equation: nationalism. In psychological terms, nationalism can be viewed as a type of parochialism, or narrow loyalty to one's group. Because it reflects a preference for one group over others, nationalism can be considered a kind of prejudice. Now that racism and sexism are widely condemned, nationalism may be the last type of prejudice to be widely tolerated. This bias often takes subtle forms. A later question in the study described above asked subjects whether they would favor a trade agreement that would cause job gains in Mexico and job losses in the United States, such that the gains in Mexico would be 10 times the losses in the United States. Three-quarters of the American student subjects did not support such an agreement (Baron, 1996); they were willing to sacrifice ten Mexican jobs for every American job. Baron (1996) also asked subjects if they would favor the hypothetical agreement if they were citizens of a third country. Three-quarters of them said they would support it. They were also asked whether they would support an agreement involving Pennsylvania (where the study was done) and another U.S. state, in which Pennsylvanians would lose a certain amount of jobs but those in the other state would gain ten times as many. Most supported this agreement. “This agreement would hurt Pennsylvania, but it would greatly help the economy of the whole country, so I would support it,” said one. “I realize the implications of this last question, and it makes a valid point: If different countries could work together and look out for the benefits of the whole world, as the states of America are united, then everyone would benefit.” This is our point exactly. Most of us consider the effects of our behavior, including the effects of political action such as voting, on others. Why should this concern for others stop at the border? It is just as arbitrary to limit our concern to co-nationals as it is to limit it to people 27 of the same race or sex. If voters considered the best interests of humanity when they voted, and if they were willing to tolerate small losses for some in return for large gains for others, all would benefit. In the long run, we will achieve greater prosperity worldwide by taking opportunities to expand trade. To enlarge the pie of resources for all, citizens of prosperous countries must become willing to accept small and temporary costs at home. Discussion The collective outcome of rational individual behaviors can lead to suboptimal communal outcomes (Schelling, 1978). Political scientists have explained such suboptimality as the natural evolution of a web of political action (Brennan and Buchanan, 1985). We accept these analyses, but also argue that another means of understanding suboptimal government decisions should be explored. When applied to the behaviors of politicians and citizens, the findings of decisionmaking research yield new explanations for failed government policy. This research also suggests possibilities for improving government decisions. In this paper, we have highlighted a variety of psychological mechanisms to explain a number of suboptimal government policies. While featuring a variety of specific policy domains, our main goal is to begin to construct a roadmap of psychological tools that will be useful across policy arenas. Below, we quickly review some the psychological mechanism that can serve as tools to diagnose flawed government decision-making. What we present below is not a comprehensive list of known biases, but a selection of those that best account for current practices in social decision-making. They all arise from the widespread human failure to make wise tradeoffs by accepting small losses in exchange for larger gains. Omission bias. As citizens strive to lead just, moral lives, the admonition “Do no harm” is often – but not always – a useful guideline. In our discussions of organ donation and free 28 trade, we described opportunities for great gains that would require society to inflict some small, temporary harm. People can be predicted to oppose such programs, despite the fact that failure to act can be regarded as a harm (Ritov and Baron, 1990, 1999; Spranca, Minsk, and Baron, 1991). Status-quo bias. People are often unwilling to give up what they already have – their “endowment” – for a better set of options. In such instances, losses loom larger than expected gains (Thaler, 1980; Samuelson and Zeckhauser, 1988). When a person receives an offer for a new job that is much better than her old job on some dimensions and marginally worse on others, she can be expected to turn down the offer (Samuelson and Zeckhauser, 1988). Most changes to government policy will require certain losses in exchange for greater gain. For many decision makers, losses will be more salient than any gain. The status quo bias is an irrational barrier to legislative change. The fixed-pie approach to negotiations. People tend to over-simplify negotiations, viewing them as “fixed pies” (Neale and Bazerman, 1991). In other words, parties tend to assume they are fighting over a limited amount of resources whose size cannot be increased. Environmentalists and industry leaders frequently adopt such polarized view in disputes over land and conservation. In fact, most negotiation situations are made up of a number of issues, each of which has multiple dimensions. When parties have differing assessments about the importance of these various dimensions, they can make tradeoffs to improve the overall quality of the agreement. Because our intuition leads us to focus on losses rather than gains, we tend to ignore such opportunities (Bazerman, Curhan, Moore, and Valley, 2000). Unwillingness to help solve social dilemmas. A central role of good government is to resolve conflicts in which individuals must decide whether to pursue the short-term goals of a 29 small group to which they belong or the broader interest of society. As evident in the case of the German coal miners, when individuals fight on behalf of a narrowly defined group, society often suffers (Bazerman et al., 2001). Solutions to such social dilemmas exist, but coordinated action is required. Inevitably, a new social dilemma arises: It is in each citizen's narrow self-interest to let others do the work of persuading public officials to take action. However, such small sacrifices can bring about great benefits. Ignoring secondary effects. In the United States, our current election system gives too much power to wealthy special-interest groups, thereby decreases the amount of resources available to society as a whole. In exchange for small losses to those who have already benefited unfairly from the current system, cooperation on campaign-finance reform would benefit us all in the long term. Nevertheless, the public and the media consistently allow Congress to quietly defeat or weaken campaign-finance reform legislation year after year. Why does the public pay scant attention to this crucial issue? We argue that most people do not think about the secondary effects of boring issues on vivid issues such as education or welfare reform, even when these secondary effects have enormous collective importance (Bazerman et al., 2001). Discounting the future. Most people agree with the assertion that “we should leave the earth in as good a condition as we received it.” But, as shown by the worldwide failure to address the current fishing crisis, government policies often belie this view. Human beings have a general tendency to discount the future pain that our actions cause. Specifically, we overweight the present at the expense of the future, a phenomenon that only increases in severity when the future includes future generations (Wade-Benzoni, 1996). Global warming, the destruction of the rainforests, and the unsustainable use of water debt all reflect the tendency to discount the long-term effects of our decisions. We need to learn to recognize that by absorbing 30 small losses in the present, we may be able to protect future generations from the negative effects of our short-sighted policies. Diplomatic training includes significant doses of lessons on the benefits of democracy, the role of advocacy groups, the political process, and the logic of key actors in the system. Most citizens and students of diplomacy, however, do not have access to the type of the insights from decision-making research that are highlighted in this paper. Whenever citizens and politicians fall victim to the decision mistakes discussed, resources that might be available for healthcare, education, defense, tax reduction – or whatever issue concerns us most – are squandered. Thinking more rationally about politics is a worthwhile goal for everyone. We hope the ideas in this paper open up new directions for research on government decision making. 31 References Allison, S. T., Messick, D. M., & Goethals, G. R. (1989). On being better but not smarter than others: The Mohammad Ali effect. Social Cognition, 7, 275-296. Babad, E., & Katz, Y. (1991). Wishful thinking—against all odds. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 21, 1921-1938. Baden, J. (1995, October 25). The adverse consequences of the EPA. The Seattle Times, B5. Baim, D. V. (1990, November 26). Sports stadiums as “wise investments”: An evaluation (p. 6). Heartland Policy Study #32, The Heartland Institute. Bannister, G. J, & Thugge, K. (2001). International Trade and Poverty Alleviation. IMF Working Paper No. 01/54. Washington: International Monetary Fund. Available at: http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=270440. Baron, J. (1996). Do no harm. In D. Messick & A. Tenbrunsel (Eds.), Codes of Conduct: Behavioral research into business ethics (pp. 197-213). New York: Russell Sage. Baron, J. (1998). Judgment misguided: Intuition and error in public decision making. New York: Oxford University Press. Baron, J. & Jurney, J. (1993). Norms against voting for coerced reform. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 64, 347-355. Bazerman, M. H. (2002). Judgment in managerial decision making (5th ed.). New York: Wiley. Bazerman, M. H., Baron, J., & Shonk, K. (2001). You can’t enlarge the pie. New York: Basic Books. Bazerman, M. H., Curhan, J. R., Moore, D. A., & Valley, K. L. (2000). Negotiations. Annual Review of Psychology. Palo Alto, CA: Annual Reviews. 32 Bazerman, M. H., & Hoffman, A. (1999). Sources of environmentally destructive behavior: Individual, organizational and institutional perspectives. Research in Organizational Behavior, 21, 39-79. Bazerman, M. H., Magliozzi, T., & Neale, M. A. (1985). The acquisition of an integrative response in a competitive market. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, 34, 294-313. Bazerman, M. H., & Samuelson, W. F. (1983). I won the auction but don’t want the prize. Journal of Conflict Resolution, 27, 618-634. Brennan, G. & Buchanan, J. M. (1985). The reason of rules: Constitutional political economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Camerer C., & Lovallo, D. (1999). Overconfidence and excess entry: An experimental approach. American Economic Review, 89 (1), 306-318. Capen, E. C., Clapp, R. V., & Campbell, W. M. (1971). Competitive bidding in high-risk situations. Journal of Petroleum Technology, 23, 641-654. Chaiken, S., Gruenfeld, D. H., & Judd, C. M. (in press). Persuasion in negotiation. In M. Deutsch & P. Coleman (Ed.), Handbook of constructive conflict resolution: Theory and practice. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Dawes, R. (1980). Social dilemmas. Annual Review of Psychology, 31, 161-191. Ding, Y., & Houghton, J. T., Eds. (2001). Climate change 2001: The scientific basis: Contribution of Working Group I to the Third Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gately, D. (1980). Individual discount rates and the purchase and utilization of energy-using durables. Bell Journal of Economics, 11, 373-374. 33 Gibbons, R. D., Meltzer, D., & Duan, N. (2000). Waiting for organ transplantation. Science, 287, 237-238. Gnant, M. F. X., Wamser, P., Goetzinger, P., Sautner, T., Steininger, R., & Muehlbacher, F. (1991). The impact of the presumed consent law and a decentralized organ procurement system on organ donation: Quadruplication in the number of organ donors. Transplantation Proceedings, 23, 2685-2686. Gruenfeld, D. H. (1995). Status, ideology, and integrative complexity on the U.S. Supreme Court: Rethinking the politics of political decision making. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 68, 5-20. Hartley, K., & Hooper, N. (1992). Tourism policy: Market failure and public choice. In P. Johnson & T. Barry (Eds.), Perspectives on tourism policy. New York: Casell Mansell. Johnson, R. C. (1999). Texas school district blocks NBA team’s arena deal. Education Week, 18(21), 6. Kagel, J. H., & Levin, D. (1986). The winner’s curse and public information in common value auctions. American Economic Review, 76, 894-920. Kohl boosts subsidy offer—69 billion marks coal aid through 2005 (1997, March 13). Deutsche Presse-Agentur. Kramer, R. M. (1994). Self-enhancing cognitions and organizational conflict. Working paper. Lacayo, R. (1999, December 13). Rage against the machine. Time,16. Light, M. K. (1999). Coal subsidies and global carbon emissions. The Energy Journal, 20 (4), 117-148. 34 Mannix, E. A., & Loewenstein, G. L. (1992). The effects of interfirm mobility and individual versus group decision making on managerial time horizons. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 59, 371-390. McGinn, A. P. (1998). Promoting sustainable fisheries. In L. Brown, C. Flavin, & H. French (Eds.), State of the world (pp. 59-78). New York: Norton. Messick, D. M., & Brewer, M. (1983). Solving social dilemmas: A review. In L. Wheeler & P. Shaver (Eds.), Review of personality and social psychology (pp. 11-44). Beverly Hills: Sage. Messick, D. M., & McClelland, C. L. (1983). Social traps and temporal traps. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 9, 105-110. Neale, M. A., & Bazerman, M. H. (1991). Cognition and rationality in negotiation. New York: Free Press. Ostrom, E. (1990). Governing the Commons. New York: Cambridge University Press. Porter, G. (1996, May). Fishing subsidies, overfishing, and trade. United Nations Environmental Program draft paper. http://www.unep.org. Quirk, J., & Fort, R. D. (1997). Pay dirt: The business of professional team sports. Princeton University Press. Radetzki, M. (1995). A scrutiny of the motives for hard coal subsidies in Western Europe. Resources Policy, 21, 99-106. Ritov, I., & Baron, J. (1990). Reluctance to vaccinate: Omission bias and ambiguity. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 3, 263-277. Ritov, I., & Baron, J. (1992). Status-quo and omission bias. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 49-61. 35 Ritov, I., & Baron, J. (1999). Protected values and omission bias. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 79, 79-94. Rosentraub, M. S. (1997). Major league losers: The real cost of sports and who’s paying for it. New York: Harper Collins. Ross, L., & Stillinger, C. (1991). Barriers to conflict resolution. Negotiation Journal, 8, 389404. Ruderman, H., Levine, M., & McMahon, J. (1986). Energy-efficiency choice in the purchase of residential appliances. In W. Kempton & M. Neiman (Eds.), Energy efficiency: Perspectives on individual behavior. Washington, D.C.: American Council for an Energy Efficient Economy. Sachs, J. D., & Warner, A. (1995). Economic reform and process of global integration. Brooking Papers on Economic Activity, 1-117. Samuelson, W., & Zeckhauser, R. (1988). Status-quo bias in decision making. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 1, 7-59. Schelling, T. C. (1978). Micromotives and macrobehavior. New York: Norton. Schweitzer, M. (1994). Disentangling status quo and omission effects: Experimental evidence. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 58, 457-476. Smirnoff, L. A., Arnold, R. M., Caplan, A. L., Virnig, B. A., & Seltzer, D. L. (1995). Public policy governing organ and tissue procurement in the United States. Annals of Internal Medicine, 123, 10-17. Spranca, M., Minsk, E., & Baron, J. (1991). Omission and commission in judgment and choice. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 27, 76-105. 36 Stegemeier, R. (1995). Straight talk: The future of energy in the global economy. Los Angeles: Unocal. Stiglitz, J. (1998). The private uses of public interests: Incentives and institutions. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 12(2), 3-22. Stroup, R. L. (1995, April). Endangered Species Act: Making innocent species the enemy. Political Economy Research Center Policy Series, Issue PS-3. http://www.perc.org/ps3.htm Taylor, S. E. (1989). Positive illusions. NY: Basic Books. Tetlock, P. E., Peterson, R., & Lerner, J. (1996). Revising the value pluralism model: Incorporating social content and context postulates. In C. Seligman, J. Olson, & M. Zanna (Eds.), Values: Eighth Annual Ontario Symposium on Personality and Social Psychology. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Thaler, R. H. (1980). Toward a positive theory of consumer choice. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 1, 39-60. Thompson, L. (2001). The mind and heart of the negotiator. Upper Saddle River, NJ: PrenticeHall. Tyler, T., & Hastie, R. (1991). The social consequences of cognitive illusions. In M. H. Bazerman, R. J. Lewicki, & B. H. Sheppard (Eds.), Research in negotiation in organizations (Vol. 3). Greenwich, Conn.: JAI Press. Wade-Benzoni, K. A. (1996). Intergenerational discounting. Northwestern University dissertation. 37 Wade-Benzoni, K. A., Hoffman, A. J., Thompson, L. L., Moore, D., Gillespie, J. & Bazerman, M. H. (In press). Contextualizing environmental negotiations: Uncovering barriers to efficient agreements. Academy of Management Review. Weinstein, N. (1980). Unrealistic optimism about future life events. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 39, 806-820. Yamagishi, T. (1986). The provision of a sanctioning system as a public good. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 51 (1), 110-116. Zajac, E. J., & Bazerman, M. H. (1991). Blind Spots in Strategic Decision Making: The Case of Competitor Analysis. Academy of Management Review, 16, 37-56. Zimmermann, T. (1996, October 21). If World War III comes, blame fish. U.S. News and World Report, 59-60.