Introduction - Brown University

advertisement
Jermaine McCalpin
1
Race, Reparations and Rawls: Defending the
Morality of Black Reparations
And a Truth Commission
Jermaine McCalpin
Jermaine McCalpin
2
Introduction
The issue of reparations for blacks in America has been at times both a lively,
animated as well as myopic debate. Opponents and supporters alike have made the
reparations agenda too legalistic excluding or underemphasizing the morality of the
claims1; further, they have failed to challenge or support reparations on a philosophical
level. If political philosophy can develop complex hypothetical worlds premised on veils,
states of nature and man etc2, then why not use it to abstract an agreed upon principle
(and policy) of reparations from a position of ignorance of one's race and its position in
race relations. In other words it is moot to ask; would whites (who in general do not
support a program of black reparations), in an imagined world, support reparations if
they didn't know that they would be white or that whites would occupy a position of
dominance in America? Further, reparations has not been placed in a larger context I
argue to incorporate it within an overall project of a truth commission for the United
States. I believe that reparations seem more defensible if it is a part of a greater quest for
[official] acknowledgement, symbolic collective culpability, rectification and material
compensation.
My central proposition in the paper is in the form of a syllogism: if justice is
acting on the truth and the truth is that blacks had been seriously mistreated and
undermined, raped and robbed by a system of slavery and discrimination and we fail to
act on the truth, then that is injustice. The palliative (if even not the panacea) is a policy
of reparations. I will develop this first by using the Rawlsian original position and veil of
ignorance to abstract (reparations) its moral foundations and then to use this to model an
Jermaine McCalpin
3
actual truth commission for addressing reparations. In doing so I will also highlight the
weaknesses of a Rawlsian framework in addressing ‘silent but salient issues’ such as
reparations.
I am fully mindful of the difficulties encountered by reparations especially
directed entirely towards descendants rather than the wronged themselves. The clarion
call for reparations must not be viewed as an indictment of individual whites but rather of
a collective white supremacy manifested in the system of slavery, domination, and Jim
Crow etc3. There is something to be said however about whites that feel they had nothing
to do with slavery, the legacies of slavery continue to haunt America's present and
therefore it can only be extirpated by rectifying the past. Developing reparations present a
long neglected opportunity to do this. An invisible but potent collective guilt needs to be
expunged! 4
More fundamentally this paper seeks to argue that reparations are a moral right owed to
blacks (and Native Americans) by virtue of robbing them of their humanity, possessions
and potential. This injustice is contemporarily manifested in the recalcitrance and
tokenism on issues of rectifying the legacies of slavery and Native American
extermination.
I examine the possible philosophical support for reparations behind a Rawlsian
veil of ignorance, essentially attempting to see if in a hypothetical world there would be
opponents of reparations as a preemptive policy to rectify injustices founded on race
especially because the individuals behind the veil would not know their race. The
profound utility of the original position and the veil is to make a good case that there is
nothing intrinsically wrong with claims for reparations especially if no one knew to what
Jermaine McCalpin
4
race they would belong.5 I then move to make a case for reparations using the
framework of a truth commission abstracted from the veil of ignorance that evinces a
practical program of reparations for America. This context of reparations as a feature of
a truth commission is a better corrective measure to slavery and its effects than singular
reparation proposals. This may sound irrelevant because we all know that slavery
occurred. But the goal of a truth commission goes beyond this universal knowledge and
focuses on an official acknowledgement as well as policies of compensation (in monetary
and non-monetary forms).
I conclude this paper by examining some of the serious difficulties encountered
with reparations of any kind especially one where victims are not clearly identifiable.
This is not meant however to overthrow the power and imperative of reparations.
The Veil of Ignorance and Original Position
Rawls uses two analytic tools, the original position and the veil of ignorance, to
gain philosophical leverage for his theory of justice and they are at once both novel and
problematic. Nonetheless I intend to outline their basic features, assumptions and
weaknesses and then to rework them to make them amenable to an argument for
reparations. The basis of Rawls’ theory of justice is the original position, which is used to
account for, and “to be the condition under which to set up a fair procedure so that any
principle agreed to will be just”. 6 It essentially outlines how at some hypothetical time,
agreement is reached on the principles and procedure of justice from a starting point
where representatives meet (behind a veil of ignorance) to iron out what the well-ordered
society is to look like. The theory revolves around the overall assumption that we all have
an intuitive notion of justice.
Jermaine McCalpin
5
For Rawls:
The original position is a purely hypothetical situation. Nothing resembling it
need ever take place, although we can deliberately follow the constraints it expresses,
simulate the reflections of the parties…it tries to account for our moral judgment and
helps to explain our having a sense of justice.7
There are six central features of the original position that require some elucidation
before I move to the fulcrum of my argument.
The first is that of unconditionality – According to Rawls, it is incumbent and it is
“desirable to characterize the original position so that the parties are to choose principles
that hold unconditionally whatever the circumstances”. 8 In other words the principles are
therefore agreed upon but also agreed to apply to all circumstances. But this prompts a
fundamental question, if these principles hold for all circumstances, why then shouldn’t
they hold for all times? As we will see with the next feature of the original position, the
parties represent only the generation following them. This also brings into suspicion the
fact that the original position and its progeny (the veil of ignorance) can be resorted to
any time following the original abstraction. Why not make it, as I intend to, a one time
original situation where once the principles are ironed out, we never return to that
position (at least not for a few generations)?
The second feature is what I call the inter-generational proviso - Although this
proviso clearly outlines sympathy for posterity, it is limited in that it only explicitly
accounts for the next generation. In the original position, each person should “care about
the well-being of some of those in the next generation. Moreover…. the interests of all
are looked after and given the veil of ignorance, the whole strand is tied together”. 9 My
Jermaine McCalpin
6
problem with this idea of inter-generational well- being is that, if the principles of justice
laid down by parties in the original position are set, then I argue, why not make the well –
being consideration trans-generational rather than inter-generational? The parties in the
Rawlsian original position are not only veiled they have very limited clairvoyance. I think
that the agreement made should hold and transcend more than two generations! (I will
return to this point in a subsequent section of the paper).
Third, there is moral equality - Rightfully so Rawls contends “if the original
position is to yield agreements that are just then the parties must be fairly situated and
treated equally as moral persons”. 10 This is one of the simple but profound contentions
of Rawls’ theory of justice. Moral equality guarantees that all parties had a say in the
principles of justice to be negotiated and agreed upon. It also means that because they are
all equal in moral capacity (and ability) that they will be reasonable in their suggestions
as representatives of individuals in society.
The fourth feature is that of rationality - The parties to the original position are
rational to the extent that they take “effective means to ends with unified expectations
and objective interpretation of probability”. 11 This means that they are fully aware of
their lack of particular (specific) knowledge but come to the negotiation of justice with
the goal of maximizing their ends without fully knowing all of them; however they know
their primary goods.
Closely related to the above is the idea of mutual disinterestedness or limited
altruism - “The persons in the original position try to acknowledge principles which
advance their system of ends as far as possible”. 12 So everyone has ends that they want to
Jermaine McCalpin
7
advance but they know that this is limited to the extent that they do not fully know their
circumstances as well as are mindful of the fact that others have dissimilar ends (goods).
The final and most important feature of the original position is that of the veil of
ignorance - I would argue that this feature functions as the kind of axis for the theory of
justice. According to Bruce Ackerman the veil of ignorance “compels rational contractors
to adopt a strongly egalitarian conception of justice, concerned with maximizing the
interest of the worst off class (and as I will argue, race)”. 13 So from all indication the
original position is premised on equality as well as fairness.
More than that the veil is the hypothetical device that the parties to the original
position are behind, “they do not know how the various alternatives will affect their
particular case and they are obliged to evaluate principles solely on the basis of the
general considerations”. 14 The veil also helps to guarantee that the information is not
only relevant but always the same.15 The assumption of the veil of ignorance is really that
the parties are deprived of any knowledge of their place in society. 16 Furthermore Rawls
argues that the real utility of the veil is that it “makes possible a unanimous choice of a
particular conception of justice. Without these limitations on knowledge, the bargaining
problem of the original position would be hopelessly complicated”. 17 And although
parties are encumbered by limited knowledge there is still an availability of choice. The
critical assumption is that free and equal rational persons behind the veil choose to
develop heteronomous rather than autonomous principles of justice.18 To this is to be
added Sandel’s assertion that the “principles they (parties) choose are just in virtue of
their choosing them, the principle of justice are the products of choice.”19
Objections
Jermaine McCalpin
8
Although I intend to borrow Rawls’ ideas of the veil of ignorance and the original
position there are some serious objections to them. In the first place the contention is
made as to whether the original position achieves genuine detachment from existing
wants and desires.20 Sandel’s main issue with the Rawlsian original position is that he
thinks that it is biased in favor of particular conceptions of the good and therefore in
contradiction to others. But more adroitly, that it introduces assumptions that are not
universally shared (Western liberal bourgeois life plans he calls them). These products he
says are then the result of prevailing values after all.21 Contrariwise to the above objection
is that the original position achieves too much detachment from human circumstances
and that the initial situation it describes is too abstract.22 The real issue is that the
abstract world Rawls engineers has little or no contingency and can therefore not account
for motivations. As much as this seems like a justified point, in another sense that is the
unavoidable crucible of moral philosophy. So although I take Sandel’s point the problem
seems inevitable.
Third, there is the objection as to whether the veil of ignorance serves the analytic
purposes well or if it could be replaced with another tool. Ackerman has one in mind, he
argues that a veil imposes unnecessary burdens and that a rival device of representation
that substitutes neutrality for the veil is much better.23 Essentially the objection is that
more can be abstracted from a position of neutrality than from one of ignorance.
Finally and maybe more critically is the contention that, what is to be said about a
justice that is the outcome of negotiations made from a position behind a veil of
ignorance and not full knowledge. The issue I would argue is that the kind of justice
seems weak if it is developed with too much information excluded. I am prepared to
Jermaine McCalpin
9
concede however that even decisions made in actual societies agreeing upon principles of
justice are still not made from full knowledge (as this is untenable). But this situation is
less problematic than one with too much information unknown. I now turn my attention
to reworking the veil of ignorance with some important modifications to fit a proposal for
reparations.
Reparations behind the Veil of Ignorance
The veil of ignorance as an analytic tool or thought experiment for my purposes
starts with the original position that there are individuals who convene to decide on
preemptive policies of justice especially reparations, knowing at least that racial injustice
is very likely but not knowing who will be affected by it. My veil differs from Rawls’ on
some key dimensions.
First, my veil and original position is meant to be a one-time occurrence. The
assumption I make is that once the principles are laid down they are to remain
unchanging for at least a few generations. I would be bold enough to say at least 6
generations (180 years) because that seems to represent a reasonable enough timehorizon to get rid of a critical injustice like slavery, racism and their resultant effects. I
am also making my original position comprised of the individuals themselves and not
representatives, in other words I use the idea of the veil as a starting point to society that
has everyone deliberating on how justice is to be modeled. The next point will serve to
clarify possible confusion here.
Third, I want to make my veil and original position historical, to the extent I want
to use an actual historical starting point and to see what kind of society and principles
would be agreed upon behind a veil of ignorance. My starting point would be (no
Jermaine McCalpin 10
surprise) pre 1776 America. I will call this the original colony or Reparatia. So my
original position begins here and essentially is made up of all kinds of individuals that
have general knowledge, that is they know that there exists differences of race, class etc
beyond the veil but do not know which one specifically they shall be a part of. They are
therefore about to deliberate to found America, fully and universally knowledgeable that
racial injustice awaits some but not knowing whom it awaits. Therefore an inevitable
principle they must agree on is a corrective policy of reparations. It is also to be assumed
that none of the persons in the original colony (Reparatia) know when this racial injustice
will occur. This may seem to make the answer to whether actual present white
Americans (but not knowing there are whites in a raceless original position) would agree
to reparations if they didn’t know they would be white. However I insert a necessary
problematizer, would persons behind a racial veil of ignorance still support a policy of
reparations if also not knowing whether their (earned and inherited) wealth may be
subject to reparations claims? 24 I think this then makes my imagined world even more
problematic than when I first imagined it.
There is no simple solution to this thought experiment and it often becomes
difficult to abstract without being biased because of “full” knowledge about the actual
situation. So to add to the lack of knowledge about whether one would be black, white or
of other races, victim or offender we add whether reparation claims would benefit (give)
or disadvantage (take from) the individual. So the founding mothers and fathers of
America have these problems to deliberate on. My theory of the original position also
assumes that individuals are not risk averse and so may take calculated risks if the gains
Jermaine McCalpin 11
are high (even if the losses are great). However I am not sure whether one would risk
being the victim of racial injustice.
But once this pre-1776 meeting concludes the agreements made there will serve
to found America and its institutions, and there is no option of return to them. So
whatever they decide on will affect them (negatively or positively) and their progeny for
generations to come. The only opt out clause is if after 15 generations society decides to
renegotiate another agreement on justice. So to move from Reparatia there has to be
some agreement reached on the principles of justice and especially about what a policy of
reparations would look like beyond the veil.
Before I proceed to outline what society founded on reparations, as a feature of
justice will look like, I need to define these terms that have been floating around the
argument. Let me begin with reparations. This is one of the most problematic words to
have graced the mid to late 20th century’s landscape. It is often misunderstood, misused
and then ultimately dismissed frankly because it has been ill defined. Reparations can be
defined as “acts or processes of repairing or the condition of being repaired, the act or
process of making amends; expiation, something done or paid to compensate or make
amends”. 25 Fundamentally the contention with the word is that given the controversy of
reparations for blacks and the realization of reparations for Japanese American and Jews
is that it is just about money.
Reparations are a duty or obligation and therefore not an incidental idea,
following from the idea of developing an obligation-based theory, one can argue that
when harm has been committed, it is obligatory on the part of society or individuals to
compensate for the harm done. Some argue in a less absolute way that reparations is one
Jermaine McCalpin 12
of the prima facie duties. W. David Ross develops an argument outlining that there are
seven prima facie duties that we can examine.26 Moral rules conflict with one another but
the more stringent one should take place. In essence a prima facie duty is really a
conditional duty. The prima facie duty of reparations is the duty to make up for the
injuries one has done to others, but to this can be added that even if we were not the
original perpetrators it is still expected to hold true. This prima facie duty rests on a
previous wrongful act. The idea of duty in prima facie duty is confusing to say the least.
Ross is self-conscious of this. Rather than being understood as duties, they are really
guidelines, not unconditional obligations. For my purposes however I only am concerned
with the idea that reparations should be used when injury had been done. To this I add, in
ways beyond Ross’s claim, that reparations ought to be seen as duty in the strictest sense,
the committal of the previous wrongful act is the only justification necessary for the
obligation to correct it to be obligatory.
Reparations are about payment (in monetary and non-monetary terms) for
damages to persons injured by racial and other discrimination. The question that begs a
response then is who should pay for these damages caused by racial discrimination? The
preliminary answer I will offer is that if there are no clear or traceable individuals and
groups, it is the moral obligation of the state (one it shouldn’t renege on) to compensate
violated parties. It is also the case we cannot deny that monetary reparations is a
meaningful way to look at compensation for historical wrong but reparations can also be
collective and symbolic, in the forms of monuments, the renaming of buildings, proactive
social and economic programs geared towards restoring lost dignity.27 But before one
then runs to say, all these things have been done, there is one dimension that is missing, I
Jermaine McCalpin 13
will hint at it, there has not been an official (state-sanctioned and funded) commission
that has acknowledged and chronicled the atrocity and inhumanity of slavery as well as to
highlight culpability on the various levels of state, society and private individuals.
Let me also quickly move to define justice so I can return to the outline for
reparations made in Reparatia. I started off the paper with the idea that justice is acting on
or conformity to the truth, I won’t get into the schism of what is truth. I will speak of
truth with a small t. I will also remind the reader that we have an intuitive notion of
justice and though we may not agree on its provisions, we all seek to do what is just
(premised on equality and fairness). Added to this is that justice is to be defined by the
dimensions that it is comprised of. These dimensions are not necessarily mutually
exclusive or exhaustive but some are stressed more than others in differing contexts.
1. Justice as retribution - this dimension is literally about repayment but in terms that
resemble the way in which the original act of violation was committed. In other
words, retributive justice is about desert, giving to someone what he or she is due
(this is however for ill). In other ways it may focus on punishment, which may fit
the crime, or if it can’t be modified to fit the crime it must fit the felt effects of the
original offense.
2. Justice as restoration - this dimension of justice is “concerned not so much with
punishment as with correcting imbalances…”28 It is therefore meant to focus both
on the victim and the violator but it is unclear as to who gets more attention from
justice. Justice as restoration is therefore more about the ideal of healing and
reconciliation.
Jermaine McCalpin 14
3. Justice as non-repetition – One of the key parts of justice is that at its heart it is
about securing against a recurrence of the original offense. Non-repetition is
important because it means that all will be done to avoid the wrong that slavery
and racial discrimination represented.
4. Justice as compensation – in a more concrete sense, justice has to be material.
Compensation does not have to (but often) take monetary forms. If the wrong can
be identified then restoration to the victims may include making up for the losses
(that are often economic) with like economic measures. It also includes policies of
(re) distribution if the offense meant the unfair acquisition of property or other
possessions.
5. Justice as Acknowledgement or Recognition- This dimension is critical to many
justice claims. It is important that if a wrong has been done that one of the first
(logical) steps is to acknowledge its occurrence and then to recognize that
something needs to be done to redress the imbalance caused by the wrong. This
acknowledgement may take the form of an official, chronicled report (such as a
truth commission, to which I turn later). To this one may add the accountability
dimension. Who is to be blamed, or made to stand culpability for the wrong done.
I hasten to say however that it does not mean that the person(s) or institutions that
take responsibility for the wrong mean by that extension they committed the
wrong (they may not have been around, but rather have inherited the wrong).
However it may mean that they have inherited the obligation to make amends of
the wrong, which is what the duty of reparations suggests.
Jermaine McCalpin 15
So in effect these are the critical dimensions of justice and because of my
introductory maxim (justice is acting on the truth), the second, fourth and fifth
dimensions serve my purposes best. I would argue that the claims of reparations have
to do with these three dimensions, [truth, compensation and acknowledgement) and
not mistakenly just about money. I return to outlining the agreement made in
Reparatia about what reparations would look like in the post-original colony. I will
focus narrowly on reparations behind the veil because I think in one way or another
all the dimensions highlighted speaks to the issue of reparations.
Agreement on Reparations as Corrective Policy
In the first place the justice modeled behind the veil of ignorance is imperfect;
however it is good enough to constitute the basis of society because rational and
reasonable persons develop it. As has been said before now, the policy of reparations
that could be agreed on is one that is inherently preemptive to the extent that it factors
in the inevitability of injustice and unjust practices. To this dimension of preemption I
would reiterate (using Rawls’s proviso) that the parties have an intuitive notion of
justice, it is the principles and procedures they need to come to some agreement on.
Second, reparations are the policy of choice to rectify racial injustice and should
consist of among other things official acknowledgement of the injustice, chronicling
the injustice for posterity, material compensation for the violated and their
generations (up to six generations).
Thirdly, reparations are a moral right that therefore has priority over respective
social goods, that is the self-interested wants and desires of each person (and their
Jermaine McCalpin 16
progeny) behind the veil. In other words the right is ethically prior and when the good
and the right come into competition, the right always triumphs.29 Sandel’s contrast
between the right and the good is helpful in understanding this point. He argues “the
good, whether individual or collective, includes as ingredients various contingencies
which are arbitrary from a moral point of view, while the right is free from
arbitrariness”. 30 So the real issue is that the right has been agreed upon behind the
veil while the good (according to Rawls, the satisfaction of rational desires) was prior
in terms of order and not in terms of importance because is preceded the trip behind
the veil. This does not mean however that the imperative of reparations may not
result in a sacrifice of other helpful policies in society, such as resources for health,
jobs etc.
Fourth, the expressed aim of all policies of reparations is not to ascribe blame but
rather responsibility with an end to reaching (if tenable) the ideal of reconciliation.
The idea here is that racial injustice divides us and therefore its resolution should not
widen the chasm but build a bridge across it.
Finally, once the truth of an (racial) injustice can be proven and established,
justice is acting on this knowledge. Action here is to be defined as taking all measures
to restore the actual or potential loss and securing against it recurring.
The basis for all decisions made behind the veil in Reparatia is consensus and not
necessarily unanimity. And even if person(s) do not agree with the provisions or
policy of reparations they should not be ostracized or neglected because they
disagreed with the policy. And once the veil is lifted that person is subject and liable
to both the claims and obligations for reparations. It is also incumbent to answer the
Jermaine McCalpin 17
question as to who is responsible for initiating, funding and enacting a policy of
reparations. The individuals behind the veil of ignorance should come to agreement
on this. The agreement could look something like this: if offenders or violators be
they individuals, groups or institutions perpetrate racial injustice and discrimination
then they should fund and support reparations.
If the spiral of responsibility and culpability makes it too difficult to identify
offenders then the state should see it as its moral obligation to fund and acknowledge
the need for reparations. Corporations and other groups must also be made to join this
effort. Because the basis for reparations would be well known (having been passed on
through generations until it is necessary to use it), not only the directly offended
should be in support of reparations.
So after laying down the principles of reparations I now turn to the discussion of
the kind of institution that would best serve a policy of reparations beyond the veil of
ignorance. I would argue that the parties behind the veil would agree on and prefer an
institution that has a broader rather than a parochial platform. It must be an institution
that will address both the imperative of truth, justice and more optimistically
reconciliation, the latter being more of an ideal rather than a programmatic goal. I
implore the reader to therefore fully judge how close the idea of a truth commission
comes to the intuitive notion of justice that all parties to the reparations agreement
possess.
Given the multifaceted nature of reparations, the best institution that can model
dealing with the problem of racial injustice is a truth commission. It is to this idea and
model I now turn. Fully aware that its usage has been in actual societies making a
Jermaine McCalpin 18
transition from authoritarianism to a democratic society and of them none has seen a
truth commission developed voluntarily by those that are at fault or responsible for
the injustices. This makes my proposal for an American Truth and Reparations
Commission seems laughable. But I think given the context of a moral obligation,
such a commission would represent the moral reflections of a society that sees the
need to engage and expunge the evils of its past.
Beyond the Veil of Ignorance: The Case of a Truth Commission
To propose a truth commission for America has to be well thought out and even
then its existence and work may effect great chasms and divisions as to what is to be
presented as truth but more so what is to be done with or about the truth. My basic
argument is that apart from representing a possible actual social institution to help
address the effect of racial injustice, a truth commission is a potential moral break from
America’s racist and exclusivist past. And more than encapsulate the clarion call for
reparations it would establish a historical document one that acknowledges its wrongs, to
present to the world. More so contrary to what some may feel the “primary reason for
asking for reparations is not intrinsically about the money, the money is secondary”. 31
It is opportune for me then to give a definition and some context of what a truth
commission is. At its simplest a truth commission is “an official body that investigates
within a limited time frame, historical wrongs meted out to groups within (or without) a
society, wrongs such as slavery, that occurred over a specific period of time with an end
to establishing a comprehensive record of the past as well as to suggest measures of
rectification”. 32 This is a much-modified definition designed to fit the American context.
Let me state unequivocally however that a truth commission has never been used in the
Jermaine McCalpin 19
context in which I am proposing it. There are a few contextual differences that make the
proposal for the American Truth and Reparations Commission (which is the name I
propose) precedent setting. First, truth commissions have only been used in societies in
transition from authoritarianism to democracy of some sort. As much as America’s
historical treatment of its racial minorities has been bad this is not grounds to call it an
authoritarian regime. Second, an American Truth and Reparations Commission (hereafter
ATRC) even if it is a compromise solution between the federal government and others
constituents, it is not the same as the way the South African TRC was a compromise
between the new ANC regime and the apartheid regime. The division I argue can and
would not be as lucid. Third, the international community has not done much in way of
commenting on the evils of slavery and its long term effects. Rather treating the
American slavery experience as a national matter, due in no small part to America’s
global power position. In South Africa, as much as the National Party government tried to
make apartheid an internal policy of discrimination, it was felt to transcend such
limitations at least to the international community. Fourth, unlike the Chilean Truth
Commission and hopefully like the South African one, an ATRC would have to name
names. However unlike all previous commissions, institutions, federal governments and
other such groups rather than individuals would be the principal offenders. Further unlike
other societies that have used truth commissions the object and subject of an ATRC
would stretch farther back into history than any other before it and arguably after it. The
longest frame of reference for any previous commission is 34 years for the South African
TRC. An ATRC would stretch possibly as far back as 1619 or at least 1783. Finally some
would argue most societies (with the possible exception of South Africa) have used truth
Jermaine McCalpin 20
commission in contexts where the polity was not founded on these exclusivistic platforms
that now come up for mention in terms of rectifying them, exclusive platforms such as
slavery is what I have in mind.
These contextual differences beside I turn to develop my model of what an ATRC
would look like, its mandate, possible commissioners, committees, powers etc. Even the
very founding of the ATRC is critical to its role in helping to address racial injustice in
America.
Founding – I propose that this ATRC be founded by the passing of a Bill in Congress
entitled the National Truth and Reparation Bill. And should have as its expressed goal to
completely examine the institution of slavery, suggestions and commitments to rectify
this injustice and contemporary discrimination and in that regard to found an ATRC to
work on this task. After the passing and approval of such a Bill an ATRC would be
formed.
Commissioners – There should be at least 22 commissioners drawn from all sectors of
society but should have no explicit ties to the government or its agencies. The
composition would be as follows: 6 Native Americans, 5 African Americans, 4 Hispanic
Americans and 7 Caucasian Americans. The rationale is that the Native Americans have a
longer standing claim to reparations and white Americans and their founding institutions
would be the site of reparation claims, and African Americans who were explicitly
dehumanized and robbed of potential and wealth, and Hispanic Americans as a minority
(though not constituting a race) who have a formidable claim to discrimination. These 22
commissioners would be suggested by the public over a 6-month period and then would
be appointed by the President with approval from Congress. The assumption here is that
Jermaine McCalpin 21
there is political will to see this founding process move as quickly as possible. These
commissioners should come from all sectors of non-governmental organizations;
churches, professional and ethnic associations etc.
Mandate - The mandate to be given to the ATRC should be concerned with the
Commission collecting information over a period of four years, having access to
classified and rare documents that have pieces of the nation’s history enmeshed in them.
The Commission should have regulated but legal access to Congressional Papers. Their
frame of reference is from 1783 at the founding of the United States. This should go up
until 1991 when the latest civil rights act was passed. The report may need a further three
years to compile (for a total of 7 years). The central purpose of the ATRC would be to
exhume as complete as possible a picture of America’s past, recording the institutions
and policies of racial injustice as well as to make suggestions and recommendations on
appropriate corrective and reparative policies to redress these historical wrongs. One may
say that seven years is a long time, but that is not so in comparison to how long we have
already waited for anything resembling an official acknowledgement of America’s past
and its effects on the present and future. After the Report has been submitted to Congress
the ATRC would cease to be a standing body. The recommendations would then be
tabled and appropriate steps taken to implement them.
Committees - The ATRC would divide its work among four major committees:
1). Historical Clarification and Rectification Committee (HCRC) would be charged with
as best as possible ensuring that the Final Document is as close to the real history of the
US as possible. It is not charged with however finding an unchallengeable truth but one
Jermaine McCalpin 22
that is more than functional, fully knowledgeable that the truth is often uncomfortable to
rehearse especially given America’s past. This committee is to ensure and oversee their
work of the other committees like an Oversight Committee to ensure that all their claims
and suggestion are plausible and actual. The HCRC must also hear the testimonies and
hold hearings for persons who may serve as resources for the committee’s work as well
as those of individuals representing culpable institutions.
2). Symbolic Reparations Committee – they would be charged with making suggestions
as to the possible ways in which the US can make symbolic moves to not only preserve
the reality of the evils of slavery and discrimination for posterity but to also elevate the
struggle against this institution and the persons and institutions that opposed it. They
should be responsible for not only suggesting monuments, days of commemoration for
slavery and other such timelines but also the naming or renaming of places, etc that
would acknowledged the persons who struggled against slavery and racial discrimination.
3). Economic Reparations Committee – Inevitably this committee would have the most
difficult job that of making recommendations for if and how material compensation
should be allotted to historically marginalized groups and their progeny. They would
have to propose how to finance such effort: who is to pay and who is to be paid, how
much and for how long etc. I would however argue that economic reparations are not that
problematic if one justifies it on moral rather than just legalistic grounds. Even that
however may be difficult to do.
4. Finally an Institutional Liability Committee – This may have overlapping functions
with the previous committees, but is explicitly responsible for naming names. That is
identifying largely institutions still extant or traceable that supported (indirectly or
Jermaine McCalpin 23
otherwise) slavery. The real difficulty is whether governmental organizations should be a
part of this inquest and I would argue yes they should be subject to it. Other societal
organizations, schools, churches etc should also be subject to its liability claims.
Universities long argued to have been funded by the slave trade should prepare for a
possible suggestion of creating avenues or reserved places for qualified but
underprivileged members of minority racial groups. The expressed aim of the ILC is to
create some spiral of responsibility. As much as the ethic of the ATRC and any other
such body is creating responsibility for past injustices, it should not abrogate the liability
dimension.
With these organs and committees it is hoped that the ATRC would accomplish
its role to make a complete as possible a record of the past. The implementation of these
suggestions will most certainly depend on the political will of the government and other
institutions. The first place to start is to look at some of the applicable lessons from
especially the South African Commission.
Lessons
1. Truth will be highly contested and the final product won’t satisfy everyone’s idea
of truth, so the ATRC and America would have to settle for an official truth. This
is what the documented report would represent.
2. If the long-term goal is reconciliation and a united state, then restorative and less
if any retributive idea of justice is best.
3. Accountability and Culpability should go beyond the legalistic definition of guilt,
which necessitates punishment and focus rather on the collective responsibility
and to make amends of the wrong done in whatever ways necessary and possible.
Jermaine McCalpin 24
4. That justice can’t focus too narrowly on just desert of both offender and offended.
5. The real worth of the truth and reparations process is that it creates distance or
even a beak with the ignoble past. When we look to South Africa that is essentially
what the TRC represented.33
Limitations
The inherent limitation is that given the fact that truth commissions are rarely by
imposition, it means that they are creatures of compromise and therefore function as that.
Second, truth commissions normally have such short reporting times to document such
large tomes of history; they may and will exclude justifiably important information.
Third, they normally only have the power of report and recommendation but never that of
implementation. Finally the political constraints, lack of resources and restricted access to
information may also thwart its efforts.34 However amidst all this I persist in my defense
of a truth commission as the actual social institution to address the policy of reparations
agreed on behind the veil. In actual terms however it is useful in that it will both serve the
purposes of establishing the truth as well as recommending reparations and
acknowledgement in such a way that goes beyond the parochial proposals for economic
reparations. To this I would add it is moral choice with high premium on it.
Having given an outline of a theory of reparations agreed on behind a veil of
ignorance and then to sketch a model of what it may look like in real terms, I move to
discuss some of the unresolved issues surrounding reparations that couldn’t be ironed out
behind the veil but that need sorting out beyond the veil. And arguably my proposal for a
Jermaine McCalpin 25
truth commission may have simplified or ignored them. Most of the contention as my
readers should imagine centers on the economic aspect of reparations.
Problems with Reparations
In a fundamental way all of the issues surrounding reparations at their core are
preoccupied with the problem of indeterminacy. I plan to itemize these issues and my
responses in return.
a. Who is to pay? The opponents of economic reparations often focus on the starting
problem as to how we are to identify the debtors (offenders). They often argue
that both those that enslaved and were enslaved have long died and therefore
claims for reparations are too anachronistic. My response to this is, even if both
the original offender and the offended are dead, the legacy and institution
continue to frame and influence American society and therefore something needs
to be done in order to rectify this past. More concretely if we create a hierarchy of
responsibility, as I have been suggesting, the founding institutions, organizations,
banks, trust companies etc are to fund the reparation payments. If the problem
however centers on the reality that all these offenders are not clearly identifiable
and traceable then the moral obligation falls on the federal government to provide
most of the money for repayments. The main quasi-legal problem with this above
issue is that only individuals or collectives should be entitled to reparations only if
they were the ones to whom the injustice was done. Likewise only perpetrators
should be made to pay. This is called the Exclusion Principle. (See fn 36)
b. Who is to be paid? (Offended). This is a real and difficult problem to address and
our abstraction behind the veil did not and I argue could not model for this issue
Jermaine McCalpin 26
in actual society. The problem is one of eligibility, which functions on two levels:
1). Are all African American blacks to be the recipients of reparations and if so,
what about persons of mixed (African and other) ancestry, are they also eligible
and on what grounds would they be so? Some authors have suggested
genealogical research to trace ones slave ancestry. 35 However the realistic
concession is that it would be extremely difficult to trace such ancestries because
often times not every good record were kept of slaves and their descendants. One
possible but problematic way out of this would be to base these claims on selfidentification first with the condition of traceable African American genealogy
(even with mixed ancestry). 2). The second level of eligibility is whether or not
wealthy and successful blacks should receive reparations. This is a formidable
issue but one that need not cumber us for the reason that yes we are fully aware
that if every black (African American) person receives reparations, it may do
some more good than others especially those who already are successful.
The issue is that of balancing over inclusion with under inclusion, ensuring that
everyone receives something. But I would hasten to make the argument that
reparations are fundamentally a moral obligation and therefore intrinsically has
nothing to do with the wealth of some of the recipients if all the recipients are not
wealthy. However like the first eligibility problem, this may also be solved through
self-identification, if persons do not feel the need to claim such reparations then that
is fine. However, because it is a moral obligation (agreed on from behind the veil) it
is less about just desert and meritocracy and more about an entitlement of all blacks
based on the reality of the historical harm.36 Reparations therefore is to raise the level
Jermaine McCalpin 27
of blacks who have been unrecognized to a position of parity within the general
(American) as well as their specific communities. The social and economic power
that whites have is not based on some moral desert but on historical circumstances
etc.
c. What is the wrong done (Offense)? On many levels this should be the most
uncontroversial dimension. However many opponents in the contemporary argue
that although slavery happened they didn’t make it happen and therefore why
should they pay for a wrong they didn’t commit. They could not have been more
in error! Something has to be said about what I would call transgenerational
accountability. And if I may use a biblical truth, the “wrongs of the fathers (and
mothers) impact upon the children for three and four generations”. 37
Fundamentally the passage means stand more than just to acknowledge the
wrongs that our ancestors' commit we are sometimes made to stand their
consequences; it is I would argue also about taking responsibility. The idea of
transgenerational justice is to represent the reality that each generation has a
responsibility to the present but also to future but especially to past generations.
Neither the past nor future generations have claims to rights (as only living things
can) but there is nonetheless an obligation to respond to historical injustice and to
secure the future against it. Inheritance therefore isn’t just about wealth it is also
about responsibility. If institutions founded, profited and were inherited with slave
wealth then they should be subject to reparation claims (remember the veil!).
Moreover responsibility should not only fall on perpetrators but also beneficiaries
of the violation.
Jermaine McCalpin 28
d. What is the amount? Some facetiously ask how much is to be paid in order to
atone for the sins of slavery and racial discrimination. I am aware that to put a
cost on the loss of humanity and recognition and not just economic potential is
inevitably weak, however I think that some matrix can be developed to calculate
the actual and potential loss of blacks because of slavery, and it was done for the
Japanese Americans and the Jews. Randall Robinson’s “The Debt: What America
Owes to Blacks”, represents a formidable project at arriving at a calculated figure
as well as the debt in non-monetary terms.38
e. When is enough payment made? How many generations before the balance are
secured? It is hard to tell but I would be quick to say that the effects of slavery
abolished in 1865 is still felt today and so if a policy of reparations were to begin
now (2002 or not long thereafter) it should be expected to equally take the over 4
generations (as from abolition until now). I would say depending on the program
for reparations they should take say at least until 2075 before a balance in
economic and terms are near possible. For as long as blacks and others have been
made to suffer they should be recompensed with like time. (I speak not of
retribution but reparations).
Towards a Repaired America?
There is never going to be a day and time when all our opinions of the right and
good agree. And therefore contentions about rectifying longstanding wrongs must be
fought on moral grounds and then on all other relevant battlegrounds. The aim of this
paper was to wage a crusade in defense of reparations using moral abstractions to reason
from a position of lack of knowledge to see if reparations are really inherently wrong as it
Jermaine McCalpin 29
is often made out to be, especially when applied to the black case. The program of
reparations may be less offensive to whites especially who think someone is out to take
what they rightfully earned. The thought experiment using Rawls and then Reparatia was
to argue that if we did not know how injustices would affect us our moral intuition would
lead us to choose the position of the worst off so that we may choose policies that would
make us in principle, all better off (limited altruism).
After leaving the realm of philosophy and thought experiments, a truth
commissions identifies most closely with the goal of addressing the inevitable injustice
the parties behind the veil preempted. It is not without its weaknesses but it is a
comprehensive apparatus in that it addresses truth, reparations and more ideally,
reconciliation. The latter is however possible if reparations are given and there is enough
political will to generate national healing. No united America is likely if a significant part
(blacks) of the nation continues to feel cheated, subordinated as if their claims are
unjustified. Nonetheless I also understand that not every black person cares about or
supports reparations and neither does every white person oppose reparations. My model
of the ATRC is meant to reflect some of the agreements extracted from Reparatia. I hope
this experiment can offer motivation for a truth commission in America someday. The
only way that America can progress is to confront the ghosts of its past and to prevent
them from haunting its present and future.
In the end the truism rings profound, only those that have felt know what it means
to feel. The rest of us can simulate the experience but rarely is the effect duplicable. In
the reparations camp opponents and supporters alike would learn well to focus on the
morality of the claims and not on the side order of the economy of the claims. Billions of
Jermaine McCalpin 30
blacks have died with their dreams and potential intestate; it is a moral disservice to not
recount and reclaim their humanity by giving to their descendants whatever that will help
to ameliorate the memory of non-recognition and discrimination. Reparations in all its
forms are justified and are an impatient imperative.
End Notes
1. Few scholars have critically emphasized the moral claims of reparations among then
Bernard Boxill, “Morality of Reparations”, Social Theory and Practice 2(1972): 113-201
and Boris Bittker, The Case for Black Reparations (New York: Random House, 1973).
2. Within political theory especially the liberal tradition has been the frequent use of
complex imagined worlds. For my paper I will use John Rawls’ idea of the veil of
ignorance from an original position to be found in his A Theory of Justice (Cambridge,
Mass: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1971).
3. Cornel West argues that “blacks encounter with the modern world has been shaped
first and foremost by the doctrine of white supremacy which is embodied (not only in
slavery) but in institutional practices enacted in everyday folkways under varying
circumstances and evolving conditions” in Prophesy Deliverance! An Afro-American
Revolutionary Christianity (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1982), p.48.
4. As I see it, talks of reparations are not to ascribe guilt rather it is to let them (whites
especially) see the historical wrongs and to do something about it.
5. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, (1971) represents the resurrection of American
political theory. Using the analytic tools of the original position and the veil of ignorance
Jermaine McCalpin 31
he develops an argument for the principles of justice and how they are negotiated. I use
these tools especially the veil of ignorance to make a case for an agreed upon principle of
reparations as the preeminent feature of justice.
6. John Rawls, 1971, p.136
7. Rawls, p.120
8. Ibidem, p.124
9. Ibid, p.128
10. Ibid, p.141
11. Rawls, p.146
12. Rawls, pp.144-6
13. Bruce Ackerman, Political Liberalisms, Journal of Political Philosophy 91 (1994):
370-387, p.371.
14. Rawls, 1971, p.136
15. Ibid, p.139
16. Michael Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1982), p.24.
17. Rawls 1971, p.140.
18. Ibid, p.252
19. Sandel, 1982, p.122
20. Ibid, p.27
21. Ibid, pp.27-8
22. Ibid, pp.29
23. Ackerman, 1994, p.370
Jermaine McCalpin 32
24. Janna Thompson, Historical Injustice and Reparation: Justifying Claims of
Descendants, Ethics 112 (October 2001), pp.114-35. The critical point is made as to the
problem of the rival claims of descendants of the wronged and those that did the wrongs.
Both have different views on the nature of historical injustices and policies of reparations.
25. The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language, 4th Edition (New York:
Houghton Mifflin Company, 2000).
26. W. David Ross develops the claim that there are some conditional duties to perform,
based either on promises we made, injury we (or someone else) committed, prevention of
injury, or improvement on self. It is meant to challenge the consequentialist doctrine of
performing duties for because of the pleasure they result in. It is a moral intuitionist
argument that aims at deontological postulations different from Kantian obligationist
theory, where duty is an actual duty and not a conditional one. See David Ross, The Right
and Good (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1930), pp.18- 45.
27. Elizabeth Kiss makes this point in an article entitled “Moral Ambition within and
beyond Political Constraints: Reflection on Restorative Justice” in Robert Rotberg and
Dennis Thompson (eds) Truth vs. Justice: The Morality of Truth Commission (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 2000), pp.82-3.
28. Kiss, 2000, p.69.
29. Brian Barry, “John Rawls and the Search for Stability”, Ethics 105 (Issue 4, 1996),
p.883.
30. Sandel, 1982, p.155
31. This definition is the result of my own crafting but the influence of the South African
Truth and Reconciliation Commission is very much the context. Furthermore, most of the
Jermaine McCalpin 33
work that informs this section borrows heartily from my unpublished Master's thesis
entitled Truth, Justice and Reconciliation: Dilemmas of Transitional Societies
(University of the West Indies, Mona, Jamaica, September 2000).
32. Manning Marable, Director of the Institute for Research in African American Studies
make this perspicacious point quoted in Ronald Roach, “Moving towards Reparations”,
Black Issues in Higher Education 18, 19 (2001), p.21
33 These lessons are adapted from my unpublished thesis on the South African Truth
Commission.
34. The Report of the South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission (London:
Macmillan Press, 1999) Vols. I-V.
35. Kevin Hopkins, “Forgive U.S our Debts? Righting the wrongs of slavery”, The
Georgetown Law Journal 89, 8 (2001), p.2532
36. Watson Branch, “Reparation for Slavery: A Dream Deferred”, San Diego
International Law Journal, 3 (2002), pp.117-206
37. This is paraphrase of the Old Testament passage from the Holy Bible, Exodus 34:7.
The excerpt seems to speak to intergenerational responsibility for the actions of our
ancestors.
38. Randall Robinson, The Debt: What America Owes to Blacks (New York: Penguin
Press 2000). This book serves as a veritable anchor on which to secure a justified claim
for calculating a monetary compensation figure.
Jermaine McCalpin 34
Download