Proposed studies in evidential reasoning Evidence is crucial to many aspects of human cognition. We use it to update our mental models of the world, and to guide our inferences and decisions. Psychological studies of judgment and decision reveal a variety of cognitive biases in the gathering, assessment and use of evidence, but with no unifying framework. In part this is due to the lack of a comprehensive normative account. Bayesian networks provide such an account – a normative theory of belief revision and inference, dependency relations, evidence integration, and a natural link to causal models. The concept of an inference network formalizes the notion of a mental model, and the graphical representation suggests a compelling format to aid human inference, especially in complex situations. We plan to use Bayesian networks as a normative framework against which to explore how humans use evidence. This is a necessary step towards a more unified and systematic model of human reasoning. It will also facilitate the construction of appropriate inference aids where humans deviate from the normative standard. We do not presume that people’s actual inferential practices are based on mental ‘Bayesian network’ structures (although this has been proposed by some, e.g., Glymour, 2001; Gopnik et al. 2004). Current evidence suggests that when people represent and reason about uncertainty they adopt simplifying strategies and heuristics (Gilovich et al., 2002). These will sometimes approximate sound Bayesian reasoning, but can deviate in systematic ways. The discovery, integration and use of evidence depend crucially on the prior beliefs and assumptions of the agent. This interaction will provide an integrating theme for our psychological experiments. We will examine the various ways in which people’s prior conceptions (e.g., beliefs, causal models etc.) and processing mechanisms (e.g., belief revision and informationintegration) affect the assimilation of evidence. 1. Evidence gathering Cognitive biases in how people search for evidence have been well documented (but perhaps not well explained). Confirmation bias. Many studies suggest that people are prone to a confirmation bias (or positive test strategy), where they seek only confirmatory evidence for their favored hypotheses (Klayman & Ha, 1987; Wason, 1960, 1968). Some theorists argue that this is not sub-normative, but that people are engaged in rational Bayesian inference with certain prior assumptions about the distribution of events in the environment (McKenzie, 2003; Oaksford & Chater, 1994). We plan to test the plausibility of these claims (by manipulating people’s prior beliefs and seeing how this affects test strategies), and their applicability to singular hypothesis testing. Evidence seeking in decision making. Previous research suggests that people flout basic optimal rules (such as to gather new evidence only if the expected return is greater than the cost). They collect evidence when they shouldn’t and fail to collect it when they should (Harvey & Bolger, 1999). Further, studies in medical decision making (Harries, Evans, and Dennis, 1999) show that doctors often think that they use more types of evidence than they actually do. This implies that their evidence-seeking behaviour is likely to be unnecessarily expensive. We aim to generalize this work to other domains (law, intelligence analysis), and elaborate the reasons for such evidence-seeking behaviour. This work will benefit from a clearer picture of exactly what is normative in such cases (provided by other branches of the Evidence project). 2. Evidence integration This covers a wide range of cognitive activities: the weighting of individual items of evidence; the integration of multiple items; the affect of prior knowledge or opinion. Psychological research has revealed a variety of biases, although here again there is controversy. Base rates. Kahneman & Tversky (1982) demonstrated numerous cases of base rate neglect, where people under-weighted or ignored base rate information relevant to the solution of a judgment problem. These findings have since been questioned on both normative and empirical grounds (Koehler, 1996). Factors that encourage base rate usage include perceived causal relevance (Sloman, 2003), experiential exposure (Lagnado & Shanks, 2002), and frequency-based representations (Gigerenzer, 2000; Harries & Harvey, 2000). The use of base rate information is of particular relevance in a Bayesian model because these furnish the reasoner with priors. We will further investigate what promotes base rate usage, and incorporate these findings into the design of appropriate decision aids. Conservatism and anchoring. Another robust finding is conservatism: when confronted with new evidence people tend to adjust their prior beliefs less than is warranted (Edwards, 1968). A related tendency is for people to use an accessible anchor point, and under-adjust their beliefs in relation to this anchor (Tversky & Kahneman, 1974). Although often run together, these may correspond to distinct cognitive operations (Harvey & Harries, in press). We aim to clarify the nature of these biases, and uncover the cognitive mechanisms that underlie them. Sequential belief adjustment and order effects. Evidence is often encountered in a sequential fashion. Hogarth & Einhorn (1992) have developed a general belief adjustment model that describes certain aspects of human inference very well. It distinguishes between the process of evaluation (which invokes an additive model) and estimation (which invokes an averaging model), and between adjustments that are made as each new item of evidence is received, and those made after all items are received. The model accounts for various order effects, in which people’s final judgments depend on the precise order that information is received and integrated. On most Bayesian models this is sub-normative. We will examine the possibility of order effects in some of the areas addressed in the Evidence project (e.g., in forensic and criminal investigations), and see what factors accentuate or alleviate these effects. 3. Cascaded inference Inferences are often made on the basis of uncertain evidence, or a previous uncertain inference. This involves multiple chains of probabilistic inference. Bayesian networks provide a normative model here but people appear to adopt short-cut strategies. Earlier research (e.g., Steiger, 1972; Gettys, Kelly & Peterson, 1973) suggests that people use ‘As-if’ or ‘Best-guess’ reasoning. That is, they infer the most probable outcome in the first step, and then condition on this outcome in the second step, neglecting alternative inferential paths. There is very little recent research on this, although Lagnado & Shanks (2003) show that people condition on an initial uncertain categorization in order to make a probabilistic inference about a related category, and that this can lead to anomalous judgments. We plan to re-formulate some of the earlier research questions (by Schum and colleagues, 1973), and develop a cognitive model of cascaded inference. We will see under what conditions people make inferential errors, and whether these can be attenuated by ‘inference’ aids. We will also link this work with questions about order effects. 4. Causal models Causal knowledge is often used to structure inference problems, and can influence how beliefs are revised in the light of new evidence. For example, in studies of jury decision making Pennington and Hastie (1991) found that jurors construct causal or narrative-based summaries of the presented evidence, and that these representations predicted their verdicts (and confidence in verdicts). Further, a story-based account was judged more plausible if the order of evidence receipt matched the real world unfolding of events. A more general example involves the discounting (or explaining away) of alternative hypotheses once a target hypothesis is confirmed (an issue much studied in social psychology, e.g., Morris & Larrick, 1995). Sloman & Lagnado (2004) show that the nature and extent of discounting depends on the assumed causal relations between hypotheses and evidence. Finally, Sloman (2003) has shown that people’s prior causal models predict whether they give Bayesian responses to the taxi-cab problem. We plan to investigate how people’s causal knowledge affects their structuring of inference problems, and their integration and use of evidence. This will be particularly relevant to how people use graphical inference aids, as the efficacy of these aids depends on appropriate problem representation. 5. Inference aids As well as providing a framework for normative computations, graphical representations provide a compelling visual presentation format. They have already been used in publicly available diagnosis software (e.g., Microsoft Bayesian Networks). Previous studies have shown that reasoning is facilitated with appropriate diagrammatic representations (Novick, 2001; Tversky et al., 2000, Sloman et al., 2003), although no work has been done with Bayesian networks. Can people use such visual ‘inference aids’ to improve their evidential reasoning? We will investigate this question, and compare a variety of software packages (including FLINTS and Maverick (Leary) and any prototypes developed within the Evidence program). Experimental paradigms Ongoing work by other members of the Evidence project will be used to generate experimental scenarios and task paradigms. For example, we plan to use simplified versions of paternity investigations (Dawid), in which participants make judgments about paternity on the basis of incomplete evidence from DNA markers, prior probabilities, etc. We also plan to use modified versions of real criminal investigation tasks (Leary). Such paradigms provide natural environments in which to explore various aspects of human inference (e.g., use of multiple sources of evidence; order effects in evidence receipt; evidence gathering strategies; cascaded inference etc.). They will also facilitate the comparison of different decision aids.