Political rationality – what else are we fighting for? by Henrik Zinkernagel We live in a world where problems such as wars, pollution, poverty and violations of human rights are embarrassingly prominent. And even though most of us feel it ought to be different, we seem incapable of changing the situation. Not just because good intentions often get buried in economical interests that appear to be far stronger than ourselves. But also because it has turned out to be remarkably difficult, e.g. for the anti-globalisation movements, to formulate an overall rational political vision for what the world ought to be like. The question of how it ought to be is a classic philosophical question of fundamental political interest. Unfortunately, the general accepted philosophical answer is that one cannot get from ‘is’ to ‘ought’ – that is, one cannot deduce logically from how the world actually is, to how it ought to be. We can observe that millions of people are starving, that pollution destroys our living conditions, and that violations of human rights take place daily in all parts of the world. But according to standard philosophy, we cannot deduce from this that it is rationally and logically wrong. Of course, to a certain extent we can choose values – like the desire for a cleaner environment or increased solidarity – and then conclude that what is going on today cannot be right. But it helps too little as long as one might as well choose other values – such as the desire for increased wealth or power – higher. The West condemned China after the violent acts against humanity on the Tiananmen Square in 1989. But today the critique has practically disappeared while the West has re-established it's economic relationship with China, one of the world largest markets. This is done in spite of the fact that although China has made minor improvements, there are no doubts whatsoever that the country continues with large-scale violations of human rights. This is but one example among many which illustrates that politicians in the West do care about human rights – as long as they are not in conflict with economical interests. However, the philosopher Peter Zinkernagel has discovered that standard philosophy, and thereby the very foundation of our thinking, is wrong (see e.g. his book The Power of Customary Views, Copenhagen: Gerd Preisler Publishing 2001). The discovery consists in the realization that logic is not identical to formal logic (which essentially says that we should not contradict ourselves). Rather formal logic is only one among other examples of necessary logical relations between different concepts – and there are thus no a priori reasons to assume that we cannot get logically from how the world is, to how it ought to be. The main characteristic of such logical relations is that they cannot be denied without rendering meaningless the concepts appearing in them. For politics the discovery means that person’s rights are not a value we can choose if we like but rather a basic undeniable political norm. The argument is that we cannot deny that politics ought to respect person’s rights without doing away with politics as a rational activity (that politics also contain irrational elements is irrelevant in this connection). The point can be summarized through the following four premises: *Politics deals with persons and person’s forms of organization, and politics is about what political decisions ought to be made. *By ‘person’ we understand something which, in normal circumstances, can participate in social relationships (politics deals with some of these social relationships). *That persons can participate in social relationships means that persons can assume obligations and have rights. *That persons can assume obligations and have rights means that these persons know an objective condition for using the word ‘ought’ – namely that persons ought to be treated as persons having rights. None of these premises can be denied without rendering meaningless what we talk about, e.g. we cannot say ‘here we have a person who, in normal circumstances, can participate in social relationships but who cannot assume obligations and does not have rights’. We therefore cannot deny that politics ought to respect persons rights without rendering meaningless the word ‘ought’, thereby ‘rights’, thereby ‘persons’, and thereby ‘politics’. That politics ought to respect person’s rights thus constitutes a necessary logical relation between the words ‘politics’, ‘ought’, and ‘person’s rights’ in the sense that we would no longer know what a rational discussion in politics is, if we deny the relation. Try yourself, while pretending to discuss politics rationally, to pronounce the sentence “politics need not to respect person’s rights”. It may of course be discussed, for instance, what the precise definition of person’s rights is, but in fact the necessary logical relation between ‘politics’, ‘ought’, and ‘person’s rights’ holds independently of the precise definitions of these concepts. Unless we want to say that we do not at all know what the concepts mean. That we, for instance, might equally well say ‘Wolfgang does not have the right to expect that I will not hit him without provocation’ as opposed to ‘Wolfgang does have the right to expect that I will not hit him without provocation’. Thus, the logical relation between these concepts holds for any definition of the concepts one might come up with, provided that the suggested definition is not arbitrary, and that it can be justified relative to how these words are actually employed in logical or practical use of language (we are therefore not talking of other uses of language such as poetry or humour). This last clause is not a weakness, for if somebody claims that we know nothing about how words are used logically or practically, he is not only at odds with the actual state of affairs – but we (and him/herself) would not understand what he/she is saying. The clause of non-arbitrariness of definitions follows since rational discussions are incompatible with arbitrary use of words. This means, for instance, that persons cannot be defined exclusively as, say, ‘Christians’, because one might then equally well define persons as ‘Buddists’, ‘Eskimos’ or ‘red-hairs’ – illustrating that any such limiting definition would be arbitrary and therefore irrational. The discovery of the basic political norm makes it embarrassingly clear that the current political situation is not only deplorable but also grotesque: Political discussions have, at least in principle, the purpose of convincing the opponents that some actions are more correct than others. At the same time, since basic political norms are (so far) unknown, we assume that no political action can be rationally better than any other – at most there can be discussions between subjective values and interests. The current political situation is hardly made less grotesque by the fact that the closest we have to a basic norm in politics today is not the respect for person’s rights but rather the respect for money and power. From theory to practice How should such a political rationality be carried out practically? At first, it demands a revolt from inside ourselves. If it becomes clear to everybody, or at least to sufficiently many, that power – whether economical, political or religious – cannot logically and rationally be put above persons (something most of us already feel), the ground is prepared for substantial changes. In practice, we will have to evaluate all political proposals by attempting to judge if they are likely to contribute to the political goal that is a direct consequence of the basic norm – namely the respect for person’s rights and the, as far as possible, equal rights of all persons (equal rights to everybody being the only reasonable way to share rights). By the same standard, we must – as voters – attempt to judge who among our politicians are acting rationally. Of course, few politicians would disagree that politics ought to respect person’s rights. But since the norm constitutes the rational foundation for politics, the question is if the politicians also agree that nothing can have higher priority than person’s rights. Political situations are extremely hard to survey, and it will therefore often be complicated to evaluate whether a political proposal is rational or not. First, the norm will be insufficient in many cases, as different rights can be in conflict with one another. But while it may be difficult to compare rights, there can be no doubt that, for instance, the right to property is less important than the right not to die of starvation. Otherwise we would indeed be using the concept of rights arbitrarily. Second, we will often make wrong judgements, as things may turn out differently than expected. But although the political norm is not a crystal ball to predict the future, it is nevertheless our only available objective standard to evaluate political proposals. We know that power concentrations imply that certain persons get more power and more rights than others. Furthermore, we know that wars and ecological catastrophes are consequences of the growth and collision of power concentrations. The growth of power concentrations thus works against the political norm of equal rights to everybody, and, in general, we should therefore try to diminish power concentrations. This holds in spite of the fact that some power concentrations are most likely needed to secure our rights, and in spite of our uncertainty of what form and size such necessary power concentrations ought to have. Since we have no rational reasons to identify persons with citizens of a particular country, conviction, or colour, the overall political goal must be the global respect of person’s rights. Naturally, the goal requires collaboration between nations but such collaboration should, as far as possible, be made without building up new power concentrations. We do not know how this difficult task should be accomplished. Nevertheless, if all parties are conscious of the basic political norm, there are reasons to be optimistic. Economically, the task is first and foremost to realize that the political norm must rationally have priority over any other issue. There is a widespread tendency in the West to think that we by necessity must first have a strong (growing) economy and then attend the social needs of the people. The political norm tells us that the order of factors ought to be reversed, i.e. that we must first work for assuring person’s rights. To this end it might be wise to employ the already existing market economy – but in a modified form in which growth is not primary. One way to achieve this would be to promote a harmonization between the objective of companies and the objective for political actions (which is, first of all, the respect for person’s right). For instance we could aim for an ethical and rational policy for companies in which large parts of the profit is used for charity and to assure healthier production methods to the benefit of the environment, the employees and the customers. Since this model still assumes that growth is unconditionally beneficial, such a rational policy for companies needs to contain factors restricting growth – in accordance with the objective of not building new power concentrations. One could for instance implement the criterion that companies should be small enough for the distance between top and bottom to be sufficiently short to assure employee participation in company decisions. Of course, this is not an unambiguous constraint, and it is probably impossible to specify the maximum size of a company. But the mere focus on such strategies would most likely emphasize that growth and increased profit are not primary goals for rational companies – and, additionally, this focus would make it very hard to justify new company fusions. That such a rational policy for companies might also make employees’ work more meaningful can hardly count as negative. Of course, there will be those who think that humans naturally think in accordance with the contemporary company policy, that – in the spirit of self-interestedness – it is all about earning as much as possible to achieve the maximum number of material advantages. But in spite of the fact that the ideology behind current market economy is based on the idea of the “rational” egoistic consumer, there are no good scientific reasons to assume that it would be against our nature to put person’s rights above personal benefits. Being conscious of the political norm will also be crucial in the struggle against poverty. In accordance with the goal of equal rights to everybody, it will for instance be obvious to cancel the enormous debts of developing countries – something which in the present political situation seems impossible due to the preoccupation with our own economical interests. Of course, the debt is not the only problem for developing countries, and obviously such a debt cancellation cannot be unconditional (for instance, one cannot allow that the cancellation is used to buy weapons). But in so far as the difference in person’s rights increases with the distance between rich and poor, it is clear that we must attempt to make the distance between rich and poor as small as possible. And in so far as the planet cannot sustain 6 billion people with the same quantitative living standard as ours, it is clear that we ought, rationally, to accept a decrease in our quantitative living standards. It may appear utopical and unrealistic to fight for political rationality. But it is hard to be realistic about the present political situation without admitting the need for substantial changes. Indeed, the biggest utopia is the belief that we can continue to live as we do now. Furthermore, it is hard to disagree with Peter Zinkernagel that if we can change what people believe in – if we can convince ourselves that person’s rights are rationally and logically more important than power and money – then we can change everything.