1 Philosophy 352: Philosophy of Science Dr. Jackie Kegley Historical Background: Issues & Positions Logical Positivism to Logical Empiricism: 1918-1955 Forming the spirit of twentieth century philosophy of science were the grand syntheses and breakthroughs (or revolutions) in physics. 1901- Max Planck- black body law 1902- Lorentz proves Maxwell’s equations invariant under transformations. 1905- Albert Einstein- “Zur Eletrodynamik bewegter Koeper,” 1906- Albert Einstein –hv- indivisible unit of energy 1911- Einstein Theory of Light 1913- Niels Bohr- Model of the Atom 1916- Einstein Theory of Special Relativity 1918- Arthur Eddington- observes eclipse confirming general relativity 1925- Ernest Schrödinger- develops wave mechanics 1927- Werner Heisenberg formulates indeterminacy principle Project-epistemological one- If one takes physics as the paradigmatic science, and if science is the paradigmatic method by which one comes to obtain reliable knowledge of the world, then the project for philosophy of science is to describe the structure of science such that its epistemological underpinnings are clear. Logical Positivism (Vienna Circle, Berlin School, Poland, Prague) This school followed David Hume in affirming that all knowledge is based on experience. They also, like Comte, distrusted all metaphysics and affirmed scientific knowledge is paradigmatic. 2 Verifiability Theory of Meaning. They wanted to avoid the lack of clarity found in ordinary language. They changed the focus of meaning from ideas to linguistic entities such as sentences and words. The meaning of a sentence= the set of conditions that would show the sentence true. Focus was on basic or protocol statements, i.e. those describing what is directly observed through experience. “I am sensing a blue color patch now” “The sun is shining.” The attempt was to explicate the meaning of all scientific discourse in terms of observation conditions. 1927- Percy Bridgman, in The Logic of Modern Physics, presented the notion of operational definitions. In introducing scientific concepts, it is necessary to specify the operations through which one can confirm or disconfirm the statements using that term. E.g. Carnap- “reduction sentence”- define “solubility” “If x is placed in water, then x will dissolve if and only if it is soluble.” Criticisms Karl Popper argued that Basic statements that describe immediate experience are inherently more general than the experiences that call them forth. Immediate experience is unique and occurs only once but statements like “There is a big nucleus” or “Here is a glass of water” are associated with an indefinite number and variety of immediate experiences. Further basic statements are tested by other basic statements and the process can only come to an end by a decision to stop the testing. Norwood Hanson argued that it takes knowledge to “see” things. If scientific observation is not shaped by the scientists’ knowledge, then nothing observed would ever be relevant to what they know and what they know would never have significance for what they observe. Further, scientists have different training and “see” things differently. This claim became known as “theory-laden observation.” Role of advances in Logic 1899- David Hilbert, Die Grundlagen der Geometrie, introduced the concept of axiomatization 1910-1913- Russell & Whitehead, Principia Mathematica 3 1. Propositional and predicate logic became the models for clear thinking and explicit statement. Logic helps clarify the foundations of mathematics and it became the ideal language for modeling any cognitive enterprise. 2. Axiomatization- This was to ensure that there were no hidden assumptions and that everything in the system was made explicit. Scientific laws were conceived in idealized form and took on the following logical form: (x) (Fx Gx). Such a form could be used to clearly establish the implications of the law. Scientific explanation was conceived as deducing a particular statement (usually an observation or basic statement) from a universal law (given some particular initial conditions about the state of the world at a time). This came to be known as the Deductive Nomological Model of Explanation. Scientific theories were to be conceived as axiomatic systems, a structured set of statements from which one could derive laws. The model for scientific theory was Euclidian geometry. Scientific theory proved too complex to achieve this. There was a strong emphasis on confirmation. The more positive evidence that can be found for a hypothesis or a theory the more likely it is to be true. Problem: Hume’s problem of induction- can never establish definitely that a general statement is true. Raven paradox: “For all x, if x is F, then x is G. This is logically equivalent to “For all x, if x is not G, then x is not F.” “If X is a raven, the X is black.” = If x is not black, then x is not a raven.” - confirmed by every black object. Logical positivism evolved into Logical Empiricism which tried to deal with the problems of logical positivism. This school was led by people like Sir Karl Popper, Hans Reichenbach and American pragmatists, Ernest Nagel and W.V.O. Quine. 4 New Paradigms and Scientific Change: Late 1950’s through the 1970’s Modern academic discipline of history of science began to develop. The goal of much of history of science was to examine historically significant intellectual episodes in science and to articulate these analytically in a way that exhibited the character of science at that particular historical moment and also showed how that moment fit into the development and progress of science. For example, a major question was “Was Galileo the last of the medieval scientists or the first of the moderns? Was his methodology, his use of experiment and of mathematics really revolutionary? Philosophers of science also began to pay more attention to actual episodes in science and began to use actual historical and contemporary case studies as date for their philosophizing. They often used these to criticize the idealized, positivistic models which they argued did not express the real nature of science in its ever changing complexity. In 1960’s the big philosophical question became: “Were there revolutions in science or was science a continuum of progress? In 1962, Thomas Kuhn published The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Kuhn argued that science in one period is characterized by a set of ideas and practices that constitute a “paradigm,” and when problems or anomalies begin to accumulate in a given paradigm, a new paradigm is often introduced which, in fact and in logic, repudiates the old and supplants it. Kuhn argued that the paradigms were incommensurate. This concept of revolutionary paradigm shift implied that scientific change was discontinuous, and that the meaning of terms, e.g. “mass, changed from their use in one paradigm (Newtonian) to their use in the new paradigm (Einsteinian). This was called “meaning variance.” Others did not adopt such a radical notion of scientific change. Lakatos talked about “research programmes,” and Laudan discussed changed in terms of “research traditions.” Both stressed more continuity than did Kuhn. 5 In addition, more attention was paid to the social and political settings of science. This was influenced by Wittgenstein and his “language games.” Quine began to talk about naturalized epistemology and Chomsky introduced new ways of looking at syntax, semantics and meaning. Feyerabend took a radical approach and argued that science has no identifiable structure. Anything should be allowed and theories should proliferate. Foucault introduced the idea of power and of evidence and proof as rhetoric. Philosophers of science began to work within science as actually practiced and discoursed with practicing scientists. Contemporary Foci and Future Directions Philosophers began to think about science in much more intricate detail and Philosophies of space-time, quantum physics, chemistry, biology and psychology developed. The science studies movement focused on the social dimensions of science and science as a human social activity. There developed a relativism of different or competing claims while at the same time there is now a strong scientific realism movement. Values and science and feminism and science are new topic areas. Key Publications in History of Philosophy of Science Ernst Mach- 1905- Erkenntnis and Irrtuum Moritz Schlick-1922- to Vienna as professor of inductive sciences Rudolf Carnap to Vienna- 1926- in philosophy 1928- Der logische Aufbau der Welt 1927- P.W. Bridgman- The Logic of Modern PhysicsOperationalism 1928-Ernst Mach Society founded 1934- Carnap to Chicago o- The Logical Syntax of Speech 1934- Ernst Nagel and M.R. Cohen, Introduction to Logic and Scientific Method 1936- Alfred Tarki, “Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den Formalisiterten Sprachen“ 1938- B.F. Skinner, The Behavior of Organisms Hans Reichenbach, Experience and Prediction 1940- Carl G. Hempel, “Studies in the Logic of Confirmation.” 1948- Hempel and Paul Oppenheim, “Studies in the Logic of Explanation,” Philosophy of Science 6 Norbert Weiner, Cybernetics 1952- Carnap, Logical Foundations of Probability 1953- Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations W.V.O. Quine, From a Logical Point of View Stephen Toulmin, Philosophy of Science R.B. Braithwaite, Scientific Explanation 1956- Ernest Nagel, Logic without Metaphysics Hebert Feigl and Michael Scriven, Minnesota Studies in The Philosophy of Science, Vol. 1 1958 Norwood Russell Hanson, Patterns of Discovery 1959 Morton Becker, The Biological Way of Thought Karl Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery 1960 W.V.O. Quine, Word and Object 1961 Ernest Nagel, The Structure of Science 1962 Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Mary Hesse, Models and Analogies in Science Israel Scheffler, The Anatomy of Scientific Inquiry 1963 Karl Popper, Conjectures and Refutations 1965 Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanation Michael Foucault, Les Mots et les Choses 1968 Imre Lakatos, Criticism and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes W.V.O. Quine, “Epistemology Naturalized.” 1969- Foucault, L’Archeologie du Savior 1975- Paul Feyerabend, Against Method 1980- Van Frassen, Bas C. The Scientific Image 1983- M. Friedman, Foundations of Space-Time Theories 1984 - Larry Laudan, Science and Values 1986- Richard Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker Sandra Harding, The Science Question in Feminism 1989 R. Healey, The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics 1990- Helen Logino, Science as Social Knowledge 1990- Richard Giere, Understanding Scientific Reasoning 1991- Sandra Harding, Whose Science, Whose Knowledge? 1994- Cushing, J.T., Quantum Mechanics, Historical Contingency and the Copenhagen Hegemony 1995- E.F. Keller, Refiguring Life: Metaphors of Twentieth Century Biology Daniel Dennett, Darwin’s Dangerous Idea 2003- Susan Haack, Defending Science within Reason 7