What do we mean by “political opposition”: a theoretical perspective Nathalie Brack and Sharon Weinblum Introduction As Schapiro put it in one of his famous works, “it is perhaps too obvious to require stating that the process of government must be studied not only in the light of what those with power under their control try to do and actually achieve; but also with regard to those who oppose those aims, or whose interests and resistance have to be conciliated before those in power can act”1. Indeed, one of the fundamental bases for the development of democracy is the recognition of rights for political and social actors to publicly criticize and challenge the government, its actions and policies2. In this perspective, whoever is interested in studying democracy is compelled to tackle, in a way or another, the question of political opposition which one of the greatest political theorists of our times has defined as the first axis constituting polyarchies, alongside the inclusion/participation axis3. It is thus not surprising that the topic has drawn the attention of many scholars who have tackled the question from different perspectives. The first important branch of the literature to which Robert Dahl greatly contributed has concentrated on the function of opposition in democratic regimes and has been interested in the different forms opposition could take in democratic states4. Trying to understand the development of political opposition, comparatist politists have also dealt with the factors explaining the emergence, institutionalization and decline of opposition in both democratic and non-democratic regimes5. Relating to this literature, an important number of studies have also focused on opposition in non-democratic SCHAPIRO L., “Foreword” in Government and Opposition, vol.1, n°1, 1966, p.2. HELMS L., “Studying Parliamentary Opposition in Old and New Democracies: Issues and Perspectives”, The Journal of Legislative Studies, vol. 14, n°1, 2008, pp. 6-19. 3 DAHL, R.A. Polyarchies: Participation and Opposition, New Haven, Yale University Press, 1971. 4 Ibid. ; DAHL, R.A., (dir.), Political Oppositions in Western Democracies, New Haven, CT, Yale University Press, 1966 ; BLONDEL J., “Political Opposition in the Contemporary World”, Government and Opposition, vol. 32, n°4, 1997, pp. 462-486 ; HELMS L., op.cit., 2008. 5 See DAHL R.A. (dir.), op.cit., 1966; SARTORI G., “Opposition and Control Problems and Prospects”, Government and Opposition, vol.1, n°1, 1966, pp.149-154 ; HELMS L., “Five Ways of Institutionalizing Political Opposition: Lessons from the Advances Democracies”, Government and Opposition, vol., 39 n°1, 2004, pp.22-54; MUTALIB H., “Illiberal Democracy and the Future of Opposition in Singapore”, Third World Quarterly, vol.21, n°2, 2000, pp.313-342; CARBONE G., “Political Party in a ‘No-Party Democracy’ : Hegemony and Opposition Under Movement Democracy in Uganda”, Party Politics, vol. 9, n°4, 2003, pp. 485501; BARBER J., “Opposition in Russia”, Government and Opposition, vol. 32, n°4, 1997, pp.598-613. 1 2 1 and non-competitive regimes6 and on its role in the democratization process7. Besides, many scholars, amongst which Dahl himself, have been interested in the structural elements affecting the opposition’s modalities of action in the parliament and its relations with the majority in power8. Finally, and usually starting from a different theoretical perspective and interests, different scholars have concentrated on extra-parliamentary opposition and more specifically on social mobilization and the role of civil society9. However, despite the very wide range of studies that have dealt with the notion of opposition, it also appears very strikingly that, since the seminal works of Dahl, Ionescu and de Madariaga and Schapiro in the late sixties and early seventies 10, political opposition has generally “been studied within a larger framework: as a co-subject, usually included in the study of power, government, parliaments, parties, social movements”11. Thus, most surprisingly, 40 years later, the remark of Ionescu and de Madariaga still holds true: “very few works have ever dealt with [opposition] specifically and exclusively” 12. This lack of studies is even more blatant when it comes to theoretical contribution13. Except from the theoretical chapters of Blondel and Helms14, most of the works on opposition have indeed been case studies lacking theoretical inference and Dahl and Ionescu’s works remains the See SCHAPIRO L., “Putting the lid on Leninism. Opposition and dissent in the communist one-party states.” Government and Opposition vol.2, n°2, 1967 and SCHAPIRO L. (dir.), Political Opposition in one-party States, London, Macmillan, 1972; MUTALIB H., op.cit., 2000; CARBONE G., op.cit., 2003; FRANKLIN J., “Political Party Opposition to Noncompetitive Regimes: A Cross-National Analysis”, Political Research Quarterly, vol. 55, n°3, 2002, pp. 521-546; LECA J., “Opposition in the Middle East and North Africa”, Government and Opposition, vol. 32, n°4 , 1997, pp. 557-578 ; HLAVACEK P. and HOLZER J., “Opposition in Non-Democratic Regimes: Notes on Possibilities and Limits of Current Theory”, World Political Science Review, vol.5, n°1, 2009, pp. 1-16. 7 See STEPAN A., “Democratic Opposition and Democratization Theory”, Government and Opposition, vol.32, n°4, 1997, pp. 657-678; SPENCE J.E., “Opposition in South Africa”, Government and Opposition, vol.32, n°4, 2007, pp.522-540. 8 See KERR H.H., “The Structure of Opposition in the Swiss Parliament”, Legislative Studies Quarterly, vol.3, n°1,1978, pp. 51-62; JOHNSON, N., “Opposition in the British Political System”, Government and Opposition, vol.32, n°4, 1997, pp.487-511.; MUJICA A. and SANCHEZ-CUENCA I., “Consensus and Parliamentary Opposition : the Case of Spain”, Government and Opposition, vol. 41, n° 4, 2006, pp. 86-108. 9 See WEIGLE M.A. and BUTTERFIELD J., “Civil Society in Reforming Communist Regimes: The Logic of Emergence”, Comparative Politics, vol. 25, n°1, 1992, pp. 1-23; KOLINKSY E. (dir.), Opposition in Western Europe, London, Croom Helm, 1987. 10 DAHL, R. A. (dir.), op.cit., 1966; IONESCU G. and DE MADARIAGA I., Opposition-Past and Present of a Political Institution, London, The New Thinker Library, 1968; SCHAPIRO L. (dir.), op.cit., 1972. 11 DE GIORIGI, E. “Parliamentary opposition in Western European Democracies today: systemic or issueoriented ? A comparative Study of two Parliamentary systems”, paper presented at the ECPR Joint sessions of worshops, Helsinki, 7-12 May 2007, p.2. 12 IONESCU G. and DE MADARIAGA I., op.cit.,1968, p. 2 13 Neunreither noted that indeed there have not been many recent attempts to theorize about political opposition. See NEUNREITHER K., “Governance without opposition: the case of the European Union”, Government and Opposition, vol. 33, n°4, 1998, p.423 14 BLONDEL J., op.cit., 1997; HELMS L., op.cit., 2008. 6 2 benchmark in comparative studies on the subject15. This observation already constitutes as such an incentive to reconsider the question from a theoretical perspective. Secondly, 40 years after these seminal works, the context, in which the opposition had originally been conceptualized -Western democracies based on strong political parties acting in a supposedly powerful political arena- has changed in some dramatic ways: the democratization of ex-authoritarian states; the regionalization of unitarian states; the development of a supranational structure at the European Union level and the changes that have occurred both in the relationships between the executive and the legislative (prezidentialisation of politics, change or decline of the parliament’s roles)16 and in terms of the roles performed by the parties17 (decline of party membership, decline of the traditional functions of the political parties, notably through the cartel-party thesis) are all important elements of change that should push us to new theoretical questioning on opposition. Finally, as will be seen, most of the studies on opposition have focused on very limited dimensions of opposition and have used a very specific approach, hence engendering a very narrow perspective (generally neo-institutionalist) on the question of opposition as well as very restrictive range of research questions Starting from these observations, the aim of this paper is to offer a new perspective on political opposition. In order to do so, the article is structured in two main parts. The first part of the analysis is a critical state of the art. It reviews the classical and contemporary literature on opposition in order to highlight their limits. We argue that the literature on opposition has neglected many dimensions, actors and types of relations due to three main biases: a normative definition of the opposition and its roles; a restricted definition of the actors seen as opposition actors; and finally, a narrow definition of the locus of opposition that is usually It has even led to some studies on the field after the works of Dalh such as PULZER P., “Is there life after Dahl?” in KOLINKY E. (dir.), op.cit, 1987. 16 See amongst others ANDEWEG R., “Executive-Legislative Relations in the Netherlands: Consecutive and Coexisting Patterns”, Legislative Studies Quarterly, vol.7, n°2,1992, pp.161-182; BLONDEL J., Comparative Legislatures, Englewood Cliff, Prentice Hall, 1973; COPELAND W.G., PATTERSON S.C., Parliaments in Modern World, Ann Arbor, The University of Michigan Press, 1994; COSTA O., KERROUCHE E. and MAGNETTE P., Vers un renouveau du parlementarisme en Europe ?, Bruxelles, Editions de l’Université de Bruxelles, 2002; LENMAN B.P., The Eclipse of Parliament, London & New York, Edward Arnold, 1992; LOEWENBERG G., Modern Parliament: Change or Decline, Chicago, Aldine Atherton, 1971; NORTON P., Parliaments in Western Europe, London, Frank Cass, 1990. 15 17 See amongst others MULLER-ROMMEL F. (dir.), New Politics in Western Europe: the Rise and Success of Green Parties and Alternative Lists, London, Westview, 1989; KATZ R. and MAIR P., “Changing Models of Party Organization and Party Democracy -The Emergence of the Cartel Party”, Party Politics, vol. 1, n°1, 1995, pp. 5-28; POGUNTKE T. and WEBB P., The Presidentialization of Politics: A Comparative Study of Modern Democracies, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2007. 3 studied. In a second part, we seek to provide with a broad definition of opposition and with new possible research questions. For different reasons, the article will not cover all the aspects of “opposition” but will rather focus on the notion of “political opposition”, hence including actors other than political parties but obviously excluding non-organized actors. Moreover, our aim is not to address the full question of checks and balances in democracy. Therefore, although some actors might play an important role as opposition, we will exclude them from the analysis if politics is not their primary concern or objective, such as the judiciary institutions. Limiting the research object is indeed a prerequisite if we want to provide with a potential new definition and reflections on opposition. Moreover, we need to put several limitations on the actors under scrutiny in order not to incorporate any kind of discontents against the power, be them privately or publicly expressed, in the category of political opposition. A. A critical state of the art: rethinking the notion of opposition The contribution of the classical literature A study of the classical literature on opposition provides us with a quite nebulous and extensive definition of opposition. Sometimes assimilated to checks and balances, to institutionalized conflicts or to minority parties, opposition is not easily defined. Most often, the notion is used as a relative term, referring to a relationship: “standing in some form of disagreement to another body”18. And indeed, Dahl defines it in a very simple way: there is opposition when B is opposed to the conduct of government A19, and Ionescu and de Madariaga sees it as “logically and morphologically […], the dialectic counterpart of power”20. However, besides the very broad and open definition of opposition offered by Dahl, Ionescu and de Madariaga, a large part of the classical literature has tended to comprehend opposition in a rather restrictive and normative way. On the one hand, when studying political opposition in a more empirical way or when typifying it, classical authors have usually attributed more emphasis to one specific kind of NORTON P., “Making Sense of Opposition”, The Journal of Legislative Studies, vol. 14, n°1, 2008, pp.236250. 19 DAHL R.A. (dir.), op.cit., 1966, p.18. 20 IONESCU G. and DE MADARIAGA I., op.cit, 1968, p.2. 18 4 political opposition, namely the parliamentary opposition, which was presented by Ionescu and de Madariaga themselves as the “most advanced and institutionalized form of political conflict”21. Thus, for Schapiro, opposition should be defined as “an organized political group, or groups, of which the aim is to oust the government in power and to replace it by one of its own choosing”22. In this perspective, political opposition has most often been limited to one specific arena in the classical literature: the parliament; to one specific actor: the minority parties with one supposed major goal: taking power. On the other hand, historically and culturally embedded in the specific post-second world war context and that of the cold war, the classical literature has entailed a very normative dimension when discussing the roles or “functions” of opposition. Besides the somehow evolutionist perspective of the authors, the normative aspect appears strikingly when we look at the typologies offered by some of the classical authors. More or less implicitly, it is indeed possible to distinguish a difference made between a ‘normal’ opposition on the one hand, and a ‘deviant form’ of it on the other hand, be it called disloyal or anti-system, that is supposed to be more disruptive and not very positive in democratic regimes. For instance, Kircheimer first distinguished three different types of opposition: “classic” or “loyal” opposition, offering alternative to the chosen policies while recognizing the government the right to govern and the constitutional system in place; principled opposition, opposing both the policies of the government and constitutional requirements of the political system; and finally, “political competition” where the minority group competes with the incumbent for power but cease to present alternative goals and objectives from that of the government 23 . During the same period, G. Sartori also differentiated the normal opposition from its deviant form. According to him, “a ‘real opposition’ presupposes consent on fundamental that is consent on the community and regime level”. It opposes “the government, not the political system as such”24 and acts quietly and constructively, by opposing but not obstructing. Alongside this “constitutional opposition”, he identified another type of opposition: the anti-system opposition, which challenges the very legitimacy of the regime as it is. This latter acts “irresponsibly” as it has no chance to be called to power and to respond. In this perspective, any “non-government” party would thus fall under the category of “irresponsible” parties. 21 Ibid., p.9 SCHAPIRO L., op.cit, 1967. 23 KIRCHEIMER O., Politik und Verfassung, Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp, 1964. 24 SARTORI G., op.cit., 1966, p.151. 22 5 This restrictive and normative perspectives, -which, as such, is not so problematic if we admit that the notion of opposition is part of the political theory sub-field-, has clearly left its mark on the contemporary studies on opposition. A first consequence has been to presume that the opposition actors have only very specific roles and objectives. Second, it has led most of the scholars to integrate a very limited range of actors studied under the label of “political opposition”. Third, it has narrowed the scope of studies, assuming that the first (and only) locus of opposition would be the parliament. These dimensions were further reinforced by the neo-institutionalist turn in political research after the 1980s. All these elements have engendered a very narrow questioning in terms of research, which we believe, should be overcome. A narrow perspective on the opposition’s roles and goals The rather normative and restricted definition of opposition by the classical literature has engendered three limits regarding the conception of the opposition’s roles and goals, which are often presented as intertwined in the literature. A first limit relates to the roles which are attributed to the opposition. In the narrowest perspective, the opposition’s role or “function” is defined as to provide alternative policies and to prepare an alternative government. It is then seen as highly institutionalized with a clear defined and recognized statute25. The classical example is the Westminster model where the loyal Opposition in the House of Commons takes its role as an alternative government, “complete with shadow ministers, a shadow cabinet and at least the shadow of a legislative program”26. In a less restrictive approach, authors have also conceived opposition as a force trying to influence the legislative agenda. Thus, most scholars have focused on the opposition’s room of maneuver and on its influence on the legislative process from a (neo)institutional perspective27. However, only within the parliament, an opposition can have more roles than offering alternative policies or preparing for an alternative government. For instance, in compound societies, it plays an important role of representation of the out-groups by voicing their 25 NORTON P., op.cit. 2008, p. 237. MILNOR A. J. and FRANKLIN M.N., “Patterns of Opposition Behavior in Modern Legislatures,” in KORNBERG A. (dir.), Legislatures in Comparative Perspective, New York, David McKay, 1973, p. 423, cited by KERR H.H., op.cit, 1978 ,p.52. 27 See amongt others most of the articles in The Journal of Legislative Studies, vol. 14, n°1/2, 2008, and MUJICA A. and SANCHEZ-CUENCA I., op.cit., 2006. 26 6 concerns even though they might not be taken into account28. Instead of offering alternative policies, a parliamentary opposition can also collaborate with the majority to reform the system, especially in consensual regimes29. Finally, an opposition can use formal rules to make sure that the majority and the government are responsive and justify their actions to the parliament. Besides, one should not forget the informal powers of opposition actors. Indeed, alongside the formal powers provided to the opposition in the parliament, the opposition can play many other roles; serve as a channel of communication by informing the public on specific political issues or serve as a “safety valve”30. It can also politicize a question, by turning a non-issue into a political issue, notably through public debate, and by so doing, conscientizing the public opinion on a specific question. Finally, through its input, the opposition can also improve the legitimacy of the government and that of the political system as a whole by making it more responsive to the needs of a broader part of the electorate31. Starting from the consciously or unconsciously admitted assumption that the opposition’s first function would be to offer alternative policies and to form an alternative government, contemporary scholars like most classical ones, have also deduced a very a narrow perspective on the opposition’s goals: seeking to take power and to influence the legislative process. Indeed, very commonly, political opposition has been seen as power-seeking and the idea is that, for the opposition parties, “the aim is not accommodation but conquest”32. However, as Pizzorno underlined, this assumption is quite restrictive for political opposition may have a multiplicity of goals besides or instead of preparing for another government, while sometimes, institutional structures simply impede it to do so. This is of course the case in non-democratic regimes but also in the hybrid European parliament: despite the absence of a majority and a minority (and so the impossibility to govern as such), moving oppositions on different dimensions exist and more particularly, an opposition on the pro/anti-EU dimension has been able to emerge33. This state of facts does not prevent these actors from playing an opposition role for it can be a non-power seeking force but nevertheless contributing to the politicization of certain issues and to the conscientizing of the public opinion; it can wish to PARRY G., “Opposition Questions”, Government and Opposition, vol.32, n°4 ,1997, pp.457-461. MUJICA A. and SANCHEZ-CUENCA I., op.cit., 2006. 30 SARTORI G., op.cit., 1966, p.150. 31 HOLZHACKER R., “The Power of Opposition Parliamentary Party Groups in European Scrutiny”, The Journal of Legislative Studies, vol.11, n°3, 2005, p.430. 32 KING A. cited by NORTON P., op.cit., 2008, p.238. 33 BRACK N., “Quelle opposition au sein du parlement européen?” in CRESPY A. and PETITHOMME M. (dirs.), L‘Europe sous tensions :appropriation et contestation de l”intégration européenne, to be published. 28 29 7 remain and act outside of the parliament and by so doing, contributing to the formation of a new form of polity frame etc. Impact on the actors under study: excluding anti-system parties from the analysis A second consequence engendered by the premises that the opposition’s major and specific function would be to form an alternative government and to offer alternative legislation is that the literature on opposition has quasi systematically differentiated the regular and legitimate opposition from the so-called anti-system parties regarded as a deviant form of opposition. This has progressively led to the establishment of two separate and very rarely connected fields of studies: the study of mainstream parties acting as opposition parties in the parliament on the one hand, and that analyzing the anti-system, anti-establishment, anti-incumbent parties on the other, which are usually considered as de facto protest actors using different modes of action in the political arena, and outside of the parliament. This a priori distinction between both types of actors seems however to be inconsistent in many respects. First, from a purely theoretical perspective and if we admit that the opposition can play a wide range of roles, we should assume that anti-system parties can also carry on these roles, namely, influencing the legislative process, criticizing, politicizing issues, conscientizing the population etc. Moreover, still from a theoretical perspective, we need to admit both the normativeness and relativity of discriminating between “constitutional” and “unconstitutional” groups or between system and anti-system parties. Indeed, as Dahl himself highlighted in 1973, when writing on opposition’s vision in hegemonic regimes: “ […] if all opposition are treated as dangerous and subject to repression, opposition that would be loyal if it were tolerated becomes disloyal because it is not tolerated.”34. Pizzorno has also shown that a party may be seen as seeking to obstruct the government because of its anti-system stance, while the party defines itself as a party working within the system. The relativity of the “anti-system party” notion and more specifically the dynamic process engendering such labeling also leads us to challenge the static vision of the irresponsible antisystem parties incapable or not willing to “respond”. Thus, regarding the supposed “irresponsible” modalities of actions of so-called anti-constitutional opposition parties, there is no empirical justification for assuming a particularly protest-based or irresponsible pattern of behaviour. Indeed, as Ionescu and de Madariaga already pointed out in 1968, we observe 34 DAHL R.A. (dir.), Regimes and Oppositions, London, New Haven, 1973, p.13. 8 that such parties that have a very critical rhetorical appeal against the system as a whole in fact both tend to compete in elections and tend, when elected, “to accept the ‘rule of the game’”35, at least in the parliament where the same modalities of actions are used against the incumbents as that used by the other so-called “normal” opponents36. This was for instance the case of the Italian communist party, which despite its status of “anti-system” party, has in fact contributed after the 1970s to the passing of many laws amongst which constitutional reforms and the transformation of the economic structures37. This has also been the case of the Communist party in France before the 1980s as well as that of regionalist parties that play the democratic game in several countries, or of some eurosceptic parties in the European Parliament that use the same kind of modalities of action as the other opposition parties in the assembly38. Consequently, without denying the relevance of studying these actors per se, it seems however problematic when it leads to the creation of a conceptual barrier between these supposedly outsiders and the actors considered as the “real legitimate and institutionalized” opposition. In contrast to these interpretations and classifications, we believe that any study of the opposition in democracy should not exclude political actors that denounce the incumbents or even the system as a whole. If these actors accept to play the democratic game and enter the electoral competition, we would suggest carrying on an in-depth analysis with the same theoretical tools as the so-called “constitutional” opposition. Impact on the arena under study: sticking to the parliamentary opposition A third consequence of the normative stance vis-à-vis opposition, is the very obvious focus of the literature on one particular site of opposition: the parliament where the opposition would be constituted of the parties of the minority. In a recent period, several authors like Blondel have encouraged researchers to look at the extra-parliamentary dimension of political 35 IONESCU G. and DE MADARIAGA I., op.cit., 1968, p.83 See on this topic, DE GIORGI E., op.cit., 2007. 37 PIZZORNO A., “Opposition in Italy”, Government and Opposition, vol. 32, n°4 ,1997, p.649. 38 Lavau showed interestingly that the Communist party in France could be seen as playing a “tribunitian function” (fonction tribunitienne). See LAVAU G., A quoi sert le Parti Communiste Français?, Paris, Fayard, 1981 (in particular pp.342-356) ; LAVAU G. “A la recherche d’un cadre théorique pour l’étude du Parti communiste français”, Revue française de la science politique, vol.18, n°3 ,1968, pp. 445-466. 36 9 opposition, but nevertheless, except rare exceptions39 most of the studies have continued to focus, usually from a (neo)-institutionalist approach, on the minority-majority relation within the national legislative arena. This posture seems however very questionable. On the one hand, it seems insufficient to consider only the opposition as a minority-majority relation acting within the parliament. Firstly, because it is sometimes impossible to distinguish a majority and a minority in the classical view and it is thereby very difficult to study opposition in those narrow terms, e.g. in Nordic countries or in Swiss40. Secondly, because only inside of the parliament, we can envisage many more possibilities of political opposition actors and relations. In some cases, As Andeweg and Norton have shown drawing on King’s typologies, the relation of political opposition can indeed include a very broad number of relations 41 oppositions: the opposition mode, which is the one where the majority opposes to the minority; the inter-party mode which refers to an opposition from a party in the coalition; the intra-party mode, which encompasses an opposition within a party against a policy; the non-party mode that involves different actors who unit independently from their party affiliation against a government policy; the cross-party mode, which refers to the processes or loci where political parties in opposition achieve consensus over specific policies. Moreover, and even more important, if the parliament is the privileged locus for the institutionalization of political action in our nowadays democracies, it seems very restraining to take the parliament as the sole place of political opposition action. First because the role and structure of the legislature are not equally the same across countries and the strategies of parliamentary opposition might vary according to the relative strength and functioning of the institution. In some cases, the codes and norms of conduct foreclose the expression of opposition within the chamber but these constraints set into motion various oppositions outside the parliament.42 This element is especially relevant, in a context of multilevel governance (regionalization and supranationalism), where we observe a multiplication of institutionalized sites of opposition and centres of decisions. This indeed affects the government and the opposition as well as their relations and dynamics. DUBROW J. and TOMESCU I., “Political Opposition to the USA Patriot Act of 2001” Paper presented at the Annual meeting of the American Sociological Association, 14 August 2004; KRAMM L., “Grundzüge einer Theorie der politische opposition”, Zeitschrift für Politik, vol. 3, n°1, 1986, pp. 33-43. 40 KERR H. H., op.cit., 1978, p. 52. 41 ANDEWEG R., “Executive-Legislative Relations in the Netherlands: Consecutive and Coexisting Patterns”, Legislative Studies Quarterly, vol.17, n°2, 1992, pp.161-182; NORTON P., op.cit, 2008, pp.244-246. 39 10 Secondly, political parties and political actors in general also act as opponents outside the assembly. On the one hand, opposition parties represented in the parliament can also act as an opposition force through extra-parliamentary tools, like the media, demonstrations or the call for a referendum or even the seizing of a constitutional court. In doing so, they can influence both the agenda setting and the legislative outcome and put into question government’s decisions. Thus as Kerr stressed, “an accurate portrayal of the patterns of conflicts and consensus within parliamentary arena must be sensitive to the patterns of political opposition generated by political activity outside Parliament”43. On the other hand, political forces that do not succeed in being elected in the national arena can nonetheless continue to play an opposition role as long as they are organized to assume one of these roles and have some chance to continue in the future. This is for instance the case for small political parties which fail in passing the electoral threshold or which compete only at one level of representation in multi-level systems. Third, with the evolving role of political parties and the crisis of representation and participation, we can assume that political actors do not have the monopoly on the perception of being the sole ‘legitimate representatives’ of those opposing the government. As Parry quickly mentioned, multiple oppositions can be found in lobbies and civil society. 44 If the latter has been much analyzed as an actor of opposition in democratization studies45, we should not overlook it in democratic regimes and should try to grasp the links established between extra-parliamentary and parliamentary opposition and stop studying public and parliamentary arenas as two separated spheres. Consequently, we believe that we should pay more attention to this extra-parliamentary dimension of opposition and encourage a decompartmentalization of the literature on these topics, which would allow for very interesting mutual contributions. B. Toward a broad framework for the study of opposition 42 Ibid,, p. 53 Ibid. 44 PARRY G., op.cit.,1997, pp. 457-461. 45 STEPAN A., op.cit, 1997; KOPECKY P. and SPIROVA M., “Parliamentary Opposition in post-Communist democracies: Power of the Powerless”, The Journal of Legislative Studies, vol. 14, n°1/2 ,2008, pp. 133-159. 43 11 Rethinking opposition: a tentative new definition In order to provide with a broader framework for the study of opposition, which would not confine itself to specific and normative perspectives of opposition, we need to go back to the fundamentals. More specifically, we need to start by offering a new definition of what we mean by political opposition. In order to overcome the flaws that were underlined in the existing literature on opposition, and especially the very restrictive approach on the topic, we believe, following the footsteps of Dahl and Ionescu and de Madariaga’s studies on opposition that we should define it by starting from the whole range of roles that the opposition entails, rather than from its locus or from its institutionalized and visible form, both of which may vary over time. This perspective would allow us to adopt a more neutral look –although influenced by Dahl’s definition of polycarchy and democracy- on the opposition but also to take into account a larger range of actors and types of relations. As mentioned above, the roles and targets of the opposition are numerous and go from criticizing to offering new options, shedding lights on a specific question, politicizing issues etc. All these activities can have different targets, amongst which influencing the government, or the legislative arena, but also the public opinion. From these premises, we thus offer the following definition of the political opposition or rather of the political oppositions: “ *any organized actor –the parliament; represented political parties; non-represented political forces; trade unions; social movements * expressing its stance in the public sphere –in the government; in the parliament; in the media; in the street etc.* that permanently or punctually checks, informs and criticizes the current state of affairs * through different non-violent modalities –legislative processes; parliamentary questions; press releases; mobilization of the media; public protests, demonstrations etc. * the targets of its critiques being the government and/or its policies and/or the political elite and/or the political regime as a whole.” New possible research questions on oppositions Starting from this broader definition and from the critiques presented in the first part, we would like to offer new possible research questions, which would in our sense overcome some of the limits previously mentioned: the limited view on the roles of opposition; the barrier between the studies of anti-system and “normal” oppositions; the focus on the 12 parliament and the compartmentalization between parliamentary and extra-parliamentary opposition -although most of the research questions offered can be used for studying parliamentary opposition only. More generally speaking, we would like to offer an alternative to the use of the neo-institutionalist approach for the study of opposition. First, in order to specifically go further than the study of parliamentary opposition, we believe that one should focus on the relations between parliamentary and extra-parliamentary oppositions. It would indeed be interesting to analyze how political parties can use extraparliamentary forces both as channel to create public debates and awareness, and as a tool to increase their legitimacy within the political arena. It would also be possible to ask this question the other around, by looking at the relationship the extra-parliamentary forces establish with the parliamentary opposition in order to politicize issue. Second, in order to overcome the restrictive (neo)-institutionalist perspective, it appears essential to think about the question of perceptions and legitimacy of both parliamentary and extra-parliamentary opposition actors46. More particularly, we could consider how the opposition actors perceive themselves, their objectives and the political arena within which they act as well as the way they are described and presented by the forces in power. Indeed, when an opposition actor whether or not against the system as a whole is presented as a “system-rejective”47 actor (e.g., Arab parties in Israel, extreme right parties in Europe, eurosceptic in the European parliament, some radical social movements etc.) by either the majority or the media, this type of labeling may produce at least two consequences: a process of delegitimization vis-à-vis the public and a process of self-redefinition by the actor. Both processes may affect their strategies, channels of communication and modalities of action. Moreover, the labeling of these opposition actors as anti-system may also influence the public’s perceptions of the opposition forces and it would be interesting to analyze further to what extent anti-system labeling can form structures influencing the roles of theses forces as their capacity to politicize issues. Third, and as a result of our previous point, we believe in the importance of language and rhetoric when studying opposition. Indeed, one of the main characteristics of democratic politics is its distinctive medium of communication, that is language and deliberation. See for instance on the question of perceptions and legitimacy the work of MUTZ D.C., “Effects of “In-Yourface” Television Discourse on Perceptions as a Legitimate Opposition”, American Political Science Review, vol. 101, n°4, 2007, pp. 621-635. 46 13 Deliberation as a means and principle for governing in democracy implies that decisions are taken through a process contradictory and conflicting discussions and debates 48. In that respect, language can be seen in democracy as the primary medium of political decisionmaking, as the way through which dissent is processed and as the opposite of violence 49. Whereas the literature on anti-politics and populist actors devotes attention to language and rhetoric, it is peculiar to note that it has been generally overlooked by studies on opposition. A more systematic and thorough analysis of the discourse and rhetoric and its use by the actors would lead to a better understanding of the style of opposition as well as of its strategies. Some research could for instance be developed on the content of the language used by the oppositions, the different frame of representation and meanings attached to the same concept (such as democracy or representation) by the governing actors and the opposition and inside the various opponents. One could also determine if the opposition accepts the deliberative process and simply assumes a declarative stance. It would allow us to assess the impact of opposition in a more relevant way as rhetoric can be used to shape perceptions, as an appeal or claim but also to politicize a non-issue into an issue. In this perspective, an actor could be seen as “efficient” in its role, even if it does not lead to changes in public policies or if it does not provide an alternative government. A fourth element that could be taken more into account is the nature and the saliency of the issues debated in the political arena. Indeed, some authors demonstrated the relevance of the issue as a key variable in studying opposition in the parliament. Firstly because some issues on the agenda are more important for some actors than for others (saliency) and second, because issues can mobilize certain types of opposition. Kerr for instance used the issues to categorize oppositions, showing in the Swiss case how issues can lead to different types of opposition. De Giorgi, Mujica and Sanchez-Cuenca also revealed empirically how parliamentary opposition can behave and react differently in its votes and collaboration with the government/parliamentary majority depending on the nature of the issues debated. It would be relevant to further develop this perspective to question the impact on the role, type and modalities of action of oppositions depending on the issues, in a way that would include the relations between parliamentary and extra-parliamentary forces. The questions could be 47 SHTROMAS A., Political change and social development. the case of the Soviet Union, Frankfurt am Mein, P.Lang, 1981. 48 ROUSSELLIER N., Le Parlement de l’éloquence, Paris, Presses de Sciences Po, 1997, pp. 17-19. 49 SCHEDLER A., “Anti-Political-Establishment Parties”, Party Politics, vol. 2, n°3, 1996, pp.291–312. 14 framed as for instance: can we observe different coalitions of opponents on key issues? Are other strategies and channels of influence used in an out the parliament depending on the issues? How will the relationship between parliamentary and extra-parliamentary oppositions be affected depending on the issues under scrutiny? What mobilization capacity will the opposition have depending on the issues debated? Finally, we believe that the study of oppositions nowadays has not only to look outside of the parliament as previously mentioned but should also consider the change in model of governance and be better connected with other types of literatures, e.g. literature on federalism and multi-level governance. Even if we are only interested in political parties as opposition force, a broad spectrum of questions arises from the different levels of power and opposition. For instance in the case of asymmetric coalitions where a party is governing at one level and opposing at another, it would be interesting to focus on how this configuration impacts its modalities of action, its rhetoric and language and how it influences its selfperception. One could also consider how this asymmetry affects the way the electorate perceives the situation and the strategy of the party and supports it or not. Finally, one could also analyze the various tools and strategies put in place at the different levels to see if differentiated tactics and types of relations with other actors are used depending on the level of power. Conclusion Despite the very common use of the “opposition” notion, few recent articles have concentrated on this topic specifically and even less articles have provided with a theoretical reflection on the notion, since the 1970s. Moreover, most of the recent articles dealing with opposition have analyzed it in a very restrictive perspective, usually with an institutional focus. Starting from this notable observation, the objective of this article was to offer a critical state of the literature on opposition in order to rethink the way we commonly study this subject. A first step was to look at the classical studies on opposition and to see the impact it has had on the way contemporary scholars have analyzed this topic. We have thus highlighted three frequent biases both in he classical and contemporary literature: a normative and restrictive view of the opposition’s roles and goals; a limited view on actors and a restrained a priori on the locus of mobilization. We have also underlined the very frequent use of a (neo)institutionalist approach to study the subject. 15 Without denying the relevance and importance of studying the opposition acting in the parliament and its relations with the majority in power, we believe that this focus is too restrained on the one hand, due amongst other things to the developments that have taken place in the last decades and, on the other hand, that it too often implies a normative stance on the supposed “normal” function that an opposition should fulfill. Therefore, we have suggested a tentative broader definition of opposition in order to better grasp its different components and dimensions in terms of actors, sites of action and roles. In this perspective, opposition(s) could be understood as any organized actor that permanently or punctually checks, informs and criticizes the current state of affairs through different nonviolent modalities, the targets of its critiques being the government and/or its policies and/or the political elite and/or the political regime as a whole. Finally, new possible research questions have been offered which would take into account parliamentary and extra-parliamentary relations, perceptions and self-perceptions; the rhetoric and discourse of the oppositions; the issues which are opposed to and the impact of the multiplicity of “levels of oppositions” on the opposition actors. We assume that these new questions and perspectives on opposition would overcome the underlined flawed of the literature and widen its scope to better grasp the complexity of the roles of opposition in contemporary democracies. 16