The development of geometry and its philosophical implications Geometry has its historical origins in empirical findings about the world, but was subsequently developed as a theory of theoretical and mathematical interest. The success of Euclid’s project to axiomatise geometry and thereby provide rigorous deductive proofs of its various theorems suggested that laws of geometry, unlike the empirical sciences, possess a universality akin to those of other mathematical fields. Given that the axiomatic bases that can be provided for Euclidean geometry were accepted as obviously true of ordinary space, the necessary truth of the theorems followed, so the study seemed to be expressing facts about the world that were both synthetic and a priori. In fact, Euclidean geometry and the further non-Euclidean geometries that have been discovered are consistent branches of pure mathematics and as such generate analytic truths which only on a given interpretation can be seen to express factual truths about the world. The first expressions of geometrical laws were undoubtedly arrived at through observation and inductive reasoning from measurements and calculations about physical objects. Euclid sought to formalise the study and express all its truths in universal form, concerned with what holds true of geometrical concepts in principle rather than in practise. Clearly, in order to arrive at conclusions through strictly logical deductive reasoning, we must start with some premises, so a number of unproved statements must be held without proof. Euclid selected as these a small number of postulates and axioms, the former being statements directly relating to geometrical concepts, the latter more general truths, but all considered to be so clearly true that no reasonable person could doubt them. He also saw it as necessary to begin with definitions of all terms employed, and while he did not explicitly recognise the need to accept without further explanation some ‘primitive’ terms by which the rest can be defined, refinements of his system by others makes this clear. The set of primitive terms and set of axioms (there is conventionally no longer a distinction drawn between axioms and postulates as in ‘The Elements’) adopted are not uniquely suitable, rather there are many equally fruitful choices. Since the truth of all theorems derived in the system depends simply on the truth of the axioms, the axioms need to be simple and evident as possible. That Euclid’s axioms are a priori truths was a widely accepted belief, as unlike empirically founded propositions they seem to have a necessary, universal quality. For example, that the sum of interior angles of a triangle is equal to 2 right angles is a fact that we would like to say could never be disconfirmed by experiential evidence, we think it is an undeniable truth. One of the postulates of Euclidean geometry, and its various logical equivalents, stands out as anomalous. Without it the system is incomplete, however it is of a more complex and less self-evident nature than the others adopted, requiring slightly more reflection on the concepts involved to accept it as true. The axioms states, roughly, that two non-parallel straight lines eventually meet at one unique point. Attempts to show it can be removed from the list of postulates, instead perhaps derived as a theorem, while unsuccessful in that specific aim, led to the shocking discovery of other mathematically interesting systems of geometry adopting postulates different to and incompatible with Euclid’s. Given the certainty with which we adopt Euclidean theorems as true, it seems natural to suppose these conflicting geometries necessarily false, hence inconsistent. In fact, closer inspection reveals some of Euclid’s original proofs are not as logically rigorous as intended, but rather appeal to diagrams and our intuition of geometrical forms. Conversely, our intuition regarding the falsity of nonEuclidean theorems may lead us to overlook their logical deducibility and consistency. In order to prove the consistency of any geometrical system, it must be reformulated in as abstract a form as possible, so that primitive terms become logical variables and all attention is on the logical interrelations between sentences rather than the meanings of the sentences themselves. This schematic form of geometry can be referred to as pure or uninterpreted geometry, whereas our ordinary interpretation is applied or interpreted geometry. Any postulates are clearly not ‘self-evident’ truths, but devoid of any assertion about specific objects, and all deduced propositions are analytic ones. An absolute proof of consistency may not be possible as it requires a model to be found under which all postulates of the system are true, and it is likely such a model must be an infinite one of which we can never have perfect knowledge. However, a relative proof can be given, which shows remarkably that non-Euclidean geometries are consistent if Euclidean geometry is. The consistency of the latter can be shown to be dependent on the consistency of the mathematical theory of real numbers. Now we are faced with several incompatible systems of geometry each as consistent as the others, the question as to which accurately represents the physical world seems to be a straightforwardly empirical matter. Of course, on a physical interpretation the postulates assert universal laws, so could never be proved beyond all doubt, merely corroborated by evidence. The first step in interpreting geometry is to assign meanings to the primitive terms. Taking as an example the term straight line, it can be seen that there are various ways of explaining its meaning. We could interpret it as the shortest distance between two points, or as the path of a ray of light through a medium of uniform refractive index, or as the path along which a stretched cord lies as its tension increases without limit. When all terms are described in a similar way the geometrical theorems become theorems about the universe in just the same way as those of empirical science, capable of being refuted by experimental results. The Newtonian laws of physics imply that it is Euclidean geometry that is true of the physical world; however today Einstein’s physics lead us to conclude that Euclidean geometry is false, Riemannian true. It would seem that the matter is settled, the geometry of space empirically decided. But is it just an empirical question whether or not the universe is Euclidean in nature? As previously mentioned, it does not seem possible that we could come across a triangle whose interior angles did not add up to equal two right angles, and if we did seem to do so we would assume some error in our measuring rather than take it as disconfirmation of the proposition. The previously illustrated way of describing terms does render geometrical theorems empirical in nature, but this is not the only way of interpreting them. Instead, we might simply say that it is an essential part of the meaning of ‘straight line’ that a triangle composed of straight sides has interior angles adding up to two right angles. Then evidence to the contrary would not lead us to conclude that this is a false statement, but that the figure we have observed is not a triangle in this sense, that the sides aren’t really straight lines. In testing any interpreted geometry, we are actually presupposing a physical theory. A result that conflicts with the geometrical hypotheses must lead us to correct our theory, but this correction could be made within the geometry or the underlying physics. If we wished, we could retain Euclidean geometry and adjust our theories regarding light rays for example. Under this interpretation, the truths of the geometry would not be empirical ones but analytic ones, true by virtue of the language employed. This approach may seem appealing when considering the relative simplicity of Euclidean geometry as compared to Riemannian, however it is the overall simplicity of our theories about the world that should be taken into account. Adjusting physics to accommodate Euclidean geometry may not result in a more simple theory of space, and is not preferred by practising physicists. Given that we can interpret geometrical terms in the first empirical sense detailed above, or the second analytic sense, the important question is which reflects a deeper tendency in our ordinary discussion of space. Certainly physically interpreted geometry can not imbue theorems with the necessity they were once considered to possess, but it is only if reduced to analytic truths that they can do so. Although geometry seems at first glance to be a branch of mathematics that is ‘about’ the physical world, it is now recognised that it can be studied in a pure or an interpreted way. Geometrical axioms on the ordinary physical interpretation are not known a priori, as is clear from the discovery of non-Euclidean systems. Alternatively, the necessity of the axioms can be preserved, but then the facts they express are no longer synthetic ones about the world. Without considering the truth or falsity of the axioms, geometrical theories are of great mathematical interest and significance. The various applications of different systems of geometry to the physical universe show the remarkable way in which pure mathematics is indispensable to the empirical sciences. That an abstract mathematical theory can be developed without consideration of its possible interpretations and then prove to be a model for physical reality, as in the case of Riemannian geometry, can be seen as support of a realist conception of mathematics.