© J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê 22.954 words ‘ILLUMINATING WHAT IS THOUGHT’ A Platonist placitum on ‘Voice’, in Context BY JAAP MANSFELD ABSTRACT The Plato kefãlaion in Aëtius’ chapter On Voice is the result of the interpretation, modernization, and systematization of brief passages dealing with hearing, voice and speech to be found in several dialogues. This construction of Plato’s doctrine of ‘voice’ was mainly inspired by the systematic and innovative Stoic tÒpow On Voice. The ‘physical’ definition is based on passages in Theaetetus and other works, the ‘physiological’ on a passage in Timaeus. The distinction and relation between voiceless internal lÒgow (or thought) and spoken lÒgow in Theaetetus and Sophist was interpreted as being equivalent to that between internal and uttered f≈nh-cum-lÒgow which played an important part in the Stoic view of the relation between thinking and speaking. Because as a rule Plato uses fvnÆ of the human voice, the rigorous distinction between this voice and that of animals and lifeless things postulated by Diogenes of Seleucia and other Stoics could be attributed to him, and his unsystematic usage justified by claiming that he used fvnÆ both in the proper and in a loose (or improper) sense. Approaches such as these are characteristic of Middle Platonism. In the present case the neutralization of Theophrastus’ criticism of Plato in the De sensibus played a significant part. Plato’s statement that thought is mirrored in what is spoken was updated by 1 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê replacing it with a (fanciful) etymology of fvnÆ which must be dated to at least the Hellenistic period (it was known to e.g. Philo of Alexandria and used by the grammarian Philoxenus). Surprisingly full parallels for virtually the entire contents of the Aëtian kefãlaion are found in the Commentaria in Dionysium Thracem. The etymology of fvnÆ, and others like it, were quoted and used by grammarians and lexicographers from the later 1st cent. BCE up to late Byzantine times. The attempt to understand the doxographer’s lemma on Plato on voice thus becomes a case-study demonstrating both the openness and the tenacity of philosophical interpretation in antiquity. But note that the present inquiry is not concerned with the Aristotelian or (partly) Aristotelianizing tradition according to which language is conventional. One of the side-effects of the present inquiry was the unsurprising realization (again) that ‘parallel passages’, once quoted and interpreted out of context, may sort of drift from one book or paper to the next, while their interpretation hardens into received truth. In the present case the so-called parallels in Plato for the later distinction between the internal and the spoken voice proved to be not so parallel after all.*) 1. Doxographical Definitions The first kefãlaion of Aëtius, Placita 4.19, the chapter On Voice (per‹ fvn∞w, in both ps.Plutarch and Stobaeus) runs as follows: T 1 Plato defines ‘voice’ (fvnÆ) as (a) [on its physical side] breath (pneËma), impelled from the mind through the mouth, and (b) [as physiological stimulus of hearing] as a shock propagated by the air through the ears and brain and blood to the soul; * A considerable part of this study was prepared and written in the hospitable environment and thanks to the indispensable library of the Fondation Hardt, Vandoeuvres, August 2004. Gratitude for criticisms of earlier drafts is due to Tiziano Dorandi, Frans de Haas, Jan van Ophuijsen, David T. Runia, and Teun Tieleman. 2 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê (c) in a loose sense (or: improper sense, kataxrhstik«w)1) ‘voice’ is also said in the case of irrational animals and lifeless things, such as whinnyings 2) and mere noises, (d) but in the proper sense (kur€vw) it is articulate (¶naryrow) voice, considered as illuminating (fvt€zousa—i.e. revealing) what is being thought (tÚ nooÊmenon).3)4) The two definitions which come first, (a) plus (b), are based on passages in the dialogues.5) Diels ad loc. (1879, 408) however stated that the next two paragraphs, (c) 1) kataxrhstik«w (as opposed to kur€vw) may imply misuse either in a relatively strong sense, viz. when a term is used for something which has no name, or indicate extended or metaphorical use in a much less severe sense; see Runia (1988, 76, 83-7), also for references. I here prefer the less strong sense, because strictly speaking fvnÆ in the case of the animal example replaces something for which a name does exist, viz. xremetismo€, and this will also hold for numerous cases of cÒfoi produced by êcuxa. 2) Qosta ibn Luqa (ed. Daiber, 1980) has ‘dem Wiehern und dem Eselsgeschrei’ (my emphasis), which may or may not have been in the Greek text translated. Cf. further e.g. Diomedes, Gr.L. I p. 420.13-4 Keil, ‘confusa (sc., vox) est irrationalis vel inscriptilis [= égrãmmatow], simplici vocis sono animalium effecta, quae scribi non potest, ut est equi hinnitus (= xremetismÒw), tauri mugitus’ (quoted Ax 1986, 18). Also cf. Hsch. v. x 693: xremetismÒw: ≤ fvnØ t«n ·ppvn, and xremetistikÒw as epitheton ornans of ‘horse’. 3) Tr. Beare (1906, 107) inclusive of explanatory glosses; wording modified. Good brief overview of the ancient debate about speech (not: a certain kind of fvnÆ) as the distinguishing mark of humans, or as also attributable in some respect to animals, or to certain species of animals, at Sorabji (1993, 80-2). 4) Aët. Plac. 4.19.1 Diels, Plãtvn tØn fvnØn ır€zetai pneËma diå stÒmatow épÚ diano€aw ±gm°non, ka‹ plhgØn ÍpÚ é°row di' ka‹ a·matow m°xri kataxrhstik«w xremetismo‹ §p‹ ka‹ cux∞w t«n cÒfoi: diadidom°nhn: élÒgvn z–vn kur€vw d¢ fvnØ fvnØ tvn ka‹ §gkefãlou l°getai ka‹ ≤ t«n d¢ écÊxvn, ¶naryrÒw §stin ka‹ …w …w fvt€zousa tÚ nooÊmenon. Note that Stob. 1.57, the sorry remains of the chapter On voice and whether it is incorporeal and <***> what is its regent part, consists of only this single passage. Ps.Galen’s text stops after diadidom°nhn, which however need not entail that what follows was lacking in his copy of ps.Plutarch. 3 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê plus (d), “non iam ad Platonem pertinent”. In his index verborum s.v. fvnÆ he cited (c) and (d) not among the ‘placita’, but separately at the beginning, so perhaps as definitions; no further comments elsewhere in the Doxographi Graeci. Apparently this verdict has been influential. Little attention has been paid to the Aëtian lemma, and what has been said about its second half (to judge from what I have seen)6) is far from sufficient. In what follows I shall argue that paragraphs (c) plus (d), pace Diels, “ad Platonem pertinent”. We should observe that definitions (a) and (b) belong to the domain of physical philosophy (and the Placita explicitly transmit ‘the physical doctrine’),7) while paragraphs (c) and (d) are epistemological so belong to another part of philosophy. Moreover, only the definition of voice sub (d), as ‘articulate voice’, is a proper one per genus et differentiam; what is said at (c) helps to identify both the genus and its species ‘human voice’. The physical and physiological definitions sub (a) and (b) are descriptive. The mix of physical and epistemological approaches need cause no surprise: book four of 5) For (a) cf. Tht. 206d quoted below, n. 137, and Sph. 263e quoted below, n. 145, and the echo at [Pl.] Def. 414d, quoted below n. 95; for (b) cf. Ti. 67b quoted below, n. 91 (good discussion of how to translate this passage at Taylor (1928, 476-7)). See Ax (1986, 78-9), and further below, sections 5 and 6. 6) Ingenkamp (1966, 80) merely calls it an “anschliessende Erklärung”. Ax (1986, 78 n. 62) believes it is a “kritische Anmerkung”, or scholium, emphasizing fvnÆ as human voice in the Plato lemma “mit Hilfe der Etymologie”. For Tabarroni (1988, 107 n. 9) see below, n. 23. Lachenaud (1993, 293) refers to parallels such as the important passage Nemes. nat.hom. p. 4.165.1 Morani for a distinction between humans and animals as to speech (it has momentarily escaped him that “Plut., Mor. 909 A” is in fact the fourth lemma of ps.Plu. Plac. 5.20 [below, T 13], the tract he edits and comments upon). He has noticed a “jeu étymologique”, but also adduces the role of the sun in Stoic cosmology, and in cognition according to passages in Plutarch’s De facie—rather far-fetched. Baltussen (1993, 213) and (2000, 237) states that “the rest [i.e. from (c), l°getai d¢ ka‹ …] derives from other Platonic writings”, but see below, sections 5 and 6. On ancient etymologizing see e.g. Sluiter (1990, 12-3, 18-21, 27-33), Schenkeveld (1999, 181-2), also for references; and below, n. 13. 7) Aët. Plac. prooem. 1, the first words of the treatise: m°llontew tÚn fusikÚn parad≈sein logon. 4 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê the Placita contains more epistemological material, e.g. chapter 4.9, ‘Whether perceptions are true’. As we shall see, in the present case the epistemological ingredient came to be included because fvnÆ involves the multi-faceted notion, or rather notions, of lÒgow. That in the Plato lemma fvnÆ is more Stoico said to be pneuma, i.e. corporeal, entails that sides are taken in the well-known controversy about its being either corporeal or incorporeal.8) Actually, all the tenets (of [Plato], Epicurus, Democritus, the Stoics and Anaxagoras) described [Plu.] Plac. 4.19.1-5 take fvnÆ to be corporeal. Curiously enough, the diaphonia corporeal vs incorporeal is only at issue in the next (!) chapter, Plac. 4.20: long title in ps.Plutarch ‘Whether voice is incorporeal and how echo comes to be’, while the short and presumably original title ‘Whether voice is incorporeal’ may be abstracted from Stobaeus (where the text is no longer extant; ps.Plutarch’s is excerpted ps.Gal. Phil.Hist. 101). Here the first lemma lists ‘Pythagoras Plato Aristotle’ as arguing that voice is incorporeal, while the second presents the arguments of the Stoics in favour of its being corporeal. The postpoment of an exposition of the diaphonia is a further sign that Aëtius (a bit atypically) does not give equal weight to the two opposite sides. But I must postpone discussion of the surprising order in which these two Aëtian chapters have been excerpted and transmitted to another occasion. The etymological explanation ad finem of our passage is not, of course, an etymology in the modern sense, but an instance of the ancient way of unfolding the original and true meaning of a word. The function of this etymology is to demonstrate the role played by the ‘articulate human voice’ in relation to the thought it so to speak makes visible, and to do so more clearly than is the case at the beginning of this passage, where voice is already said to come from the mind. It is noteworthy that we are not told where in the body this mind is situated. 2. Grammarians and Lexicographers 8) For this ‘vetus atque perpetua quaestio’ (Gell. N.A. 5.15.1) see Baumgarten (1962, 148-9 n. 119) and Ax (1986, 33-4 and esp. 178-89), both with references to the evidence; also cf. below, n. 41. 5 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê The main ingredients of the Aëtian lemma can be paralleled from the rather laboured introductory paragraph of the Ars grammatica of Diomedes (ca. 370 CE, so about four centuries later), though their order is different (as are also the contents of the physical paragraph) and though, more importantly, the etymological explanation is lacking: T 2 [others begin elsewhere], but we are happy to begin with speech (oratio = lÒgow). For this, (d) revealing the secrets of the heart, (a)/(b) transfers itself to the tongue which steers it, being guided by a certain mobile breath (d) of the articulate voice (vox articulata = fvnØ ¶naryrow) (a)/(b) and by the rounded steering of its helm, and since the internal air which is near (it) is struck by the adroitness of the heart, and the palate slowly and gradually made to reverberate, (d) it [sc., speech] is impelled, as a sort of intermediary and betrayer of the human mind, to express the indications of the thinking mind in a rational way through the mouth and through spoken language. (c)/(d) By this its specific and great gift, reason expressed in spoken language, nature alone declares and proves that we are humans, separated from the other animals .9) 9) Gr.L. I p. 300.6-13 Keil, cf. FDS 517 (passage already cited by Schmidt (1839, 18 n. 31)) ‘[…] nos vero ab ipsa oratione auspicemur. (d) haec enim secreta pectoris arguens (a)/(b) ad linguam sui gubernatricem migrat, mobili quodam (d) vocis articulatae (a)/(b) spiritu rotundoque gubernaculi moderamine temperata, et interiore vicino aere pectoris argutia verberato palatoque sensim paulatimque pulsato (d) velut internuntius ac proditor humanae mentis ad indicia exprimenda cogitationis per os sermonemque rationabiliter agitatur. (c)/(d) hoc enim suo magnoque natura beneficio, expressa ratione sermonis, nos ceteris separatos animalibus sola homines fatetur atque demonstrat’. For the expression secreta pectoris cf. Sen. Ben. 6.38.5, Tac. Ger. 22.4; for the role of the physiological apparatus cf. also the references cited below, n. 15 ad finem. Note that Diomedes is so to speak old-fashioned and wholly unaware of the revisions argued by Galen, for which see Baumgarten (1962, 108-72). 6 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê Diomedes, otherwise a far from original author though his treatise differs from the general trend in grammar in treating the partes orationis or parts of speech first,10) has committed a rhetorical tour de force in the proem of book one, jumping back and forth from the physical to the cognitive aspect and indulging in choice expressions.11) Even so, we can hardly fail to notice that the crucial distinction between humans, endowed by nature with rational thought and spoken language on one side, and all other living beings on the other, which is implicit in paragraphs (c) plus (d) of the Aëtian lemma, is here spelled out explicitly. And whereas the doxographical passage simply states that the ‘articulate voice’ reveals what is thought, Diomedes uses more forceful language, stressing that unspoken thoughts are secret, and that when spoken they are in a way betrayed. We shall encounter further examples of this dramatic approach in section 3, below. Other parallels, which as to their lay-out are closer to the Aëtian lemma—that is to say especially for the combination of the contents of paragraphs (c) and (d) in the same sequence, and by the inclusion of versions of the etymological explicatio—are to be found in the so-called Commentaria on Dionysius Thrax, the remains of commentaries dating from late Antiquity and Byzantine times and separated from Aëtius by seven centuries or more. I adduce three passages containing variously phrased but as to contents very similar or even virtually identical information. As we shall see one cannot exclude that one of these passages depends on one of the others; what is implied is at the very least a shared tradition. The first to be quoted (T 3.1) is from the Scholia Vaticana. Hilgard in his edition attributes the paragraph from which I quote to the (otherwise unknown?) grammarian th Stephanus (early 7 cent.),12) but this attribution is not certain. The distinction between 10) See Ax (1986, 17-22) and HLL 5 (1989) § 524 (Schmidt (1989, 132-6)). 11) Dammer (2001, 68-9). 12) Hilgard (1901, 180); Gudeman (1929, 2399) says he is “nur als Erklärer der Grammatik des Dionysios Thrax [...] bekannt.” Wolska-Conus (1989) argues that Stephanus of Athens and Stephanus of Alexandria are the same person, to be situated in an environment indebted to Philoponus. She fails to mention the study of grammar, though Philoponus also taught grammar. It is anyhow unlikely that our grammarian is to be identified with the Athenian, because in a 7 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê kur€vw and kataxrhstik«w in (c) is explicit, just as in the Aëtian lemma; it is exemplified here by quotations from the (authoritative) Iliad. And in paragraph (d) two rather similar etymologies are spelled out at some length, while the ‘physical’ paragraph (e), here not at the beginning but ad finem, is somewhat different: T 3.1 (c) Note that phô-nê ‘(voice’) in the proper sense is said of humans, as in the poet: ‘not if I had ten tongues, and ten mouths, and a voice that cannot be broken’; in a loose (or: improper) sense ‘voice’ is also said of others, as Homer said of the trumpet: ‘just as when a voice is clear, when a trumpet calls’. (d1) phô-nê (‘voice’) is formed from phô, phainô (‘bring to light’), coming to be through addition of the syllable –nê [pho]13) phô-nê; for it brings the thoughts (§nyumÆmata) to light and brightly clarifies them; (d2) or because it is a sort of phôto-noê (‘light-thought’),14) for it brings forth the thoughts of the no-os (‘mind’) into the phô-s (‘light’). (e) voice is defined as follows: voice is a sort of breath brought up from a proper apparatus and blood as far as the tongue, being struck by which it is articulated and transmitted as intelligible to the ears of one’s fellow-men.15)16) passage in the Schol.Vat. dealing with questions and answers attributed to him by Hilgard his example of a po›ow-question is po›ow St°fanow; and the answer is ı fiatrÒw, S D.T. p.239.21-2 Hilgard; see Gudeman (1932, 403). He accordingly distinguished at least two different persons. But I cannot deal with the Stephanus-problem here. 13) Bracketed by Hilgard; see however below, n. 24. For the four main ways of explaining, or implementing, a change in a word or phrase see the list at Quint. 1.5.38-41, where also alternative views are discussed; of these four three were already known to Pl. Crt. 394b. See Ax (1987). Here we have addition (adiectio); see further below, nn. 32 (adiectio) and 40 (immutatio), and text thereto. 14) The word fvtonÒh is only paralleled in T 3.2 (d), see below n. 19, and in the additamentum from the Etymologicum Genuinum in the Etymologicum Gudianum quoted below, n. 40. 15) S D.T. p. 181.28-182.2 Hilgard, (c) fist°on d¢ ˜ti ≤ fvnØ kur€vw <m¢n> l°getai §p‹ t«n ényr≈pvn, …w parå t“ poihtª (B 489 f.) “oÈd' e‡ moi d°ka m¢n gl«ssai, d°ka d¢ stÒmat' e‰en, fvnÆ t' êrrhktow”: kataxrhstik«w d¢ ka‹ §f' •t°rvn l°getai fvnÆ, …w §p‹ sãlpiggow e‰pen ÜOmhrow (S 219) “…w d' ˜t' 8 érizÆlh fvnÆ, ˜te t' ‡axe © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê The second passage (T 3.2) is from the Scholia Londinensia. This is closely parallel to the passage from the Scholia Vaticana just quoted, paragraph T 3.2 (c) being virtually identical with T 3.1 (c), while paragraph T 3.2 (d), the only one I need translate, is shorter and a shade different. Hilgard in his edition attributes the paragraph from which I quote to the grammarian Heliodorus, who is believed to have excerpted Choeroboscus so sãlpigj”. (d1) sxhmat€zetai d¢ ≤ fvnØ parå tÚ f«, tÚ fa€nv, katå prÒslhcin sullab∞w t∞w <nh> ginom°nh [f«] fvnÆ: fa€nei går ka‹ lampr«w dhlo› tå §nyumÆmata (d2) µ ˜ti fvtonÒh t€w §stin: aÏth går tå toË noÚw §nyumÆmata efiw f«w §jãgei. (e) ır€zetai d¢ ≤ fvnØ oÏtvw: fvnÆ §sti pneËmã ti épÚ sustÆmatow fid€ou ka‹ a·matow énaferÒmenon ßvw t∞w gl≈tthw, Íf' ∏w tuptÒmenon diaryroËtai ka‹ nohtÚn ta›w plhs€on ékoa›w parad€dotai. This ‘physical’ definition (two parallels cited below, n. 19) is not so easy to place, see Schenkeveld (1990b, 300); it is also in some respects very old-fashioned, see above, n. 9 ad finem. The sÊsthma ‡dion remains unclear; could it represent the heart? The contribution of the tongue can of course often be paralleled, see X. Mem. 1.4.12, Ar. HA 4.9.535a27-b3, and then e.g. Diomedes (T 2 (a)(b) + (d), above, n. 9 and text thereto) and the Philonian texts (T 7.2 and 7.3) quoted in section 3 below, while the ears of one’s fellow men are referred to implicitly (and sometimes explicitly) in most of the texts about fvnÆ quoted in the present study. See also Porphyry’s exegesis of Pl. Ti. 67b (cf. below, text to n. 110), in Harm. p. 47.29 Düring, plÆssei ≤m«n tØn a‡syhsin ı éÆr, ‘the air strikes our sense organ’. So this definition has a bit of everything, just as Plutarch’s account at Gen.Socr. 589C and even Nemesius’ at nat.hom. p. 71.16-72.2 Morani. FDS 503A contains p. 181.18-32 Hilgard up to and including paragraph (c). 16) A very briefly phrased parallel for the etymologies is found in the Canones sive De orthographia of the grammarian Theognostus (9th cent.), § 538.1 Cramer, fvnØ parå tÚ f«w ka‹ noËw: ≤ tå §n t“ n“ fvt€zousa (‘phô-nê from phô-s and no-ûs; what illuminates what is in the mind’). 9 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê must be later than the first half of the 9th century.17) I do not think one can exclude that Heliodorus(?) excerpted Stephanus(?) here. Note however that the etymological explanation of fvnÆ through faonÆ is not found in T 3.1 (d2): T 3.2 (d1) phô-nê (‘voice’) is spoken of as in a way being phao-nê18) (‘light’-nê) which means splendidly clarifying the thoughs (noÆmata); (d2) or because it is a sort of phôto-noê (‘light-thought’), from its illuminating (i.e. revealing) the mind.19) 17) Hilgard (1901, 482). For the date of Choeroboscus see Montanari (1997); for the relation of Heliodorus to Choeroboscus the best account I have seen is still that of Hoerschelman (1874, 468). 18) The quasi-hapax faonÆ is only paralleled in the explanation of fvnÆ at EM p. 803.52-6 Kallierges: fvnÆ: parå tÚ f«w ka‹ tÚn noËn, ≤ tå §n t“ n“ fvt€zousa: µ tÚ toË noÚw f«w: parå tÚ fãow e‰nai toË noÒw: diå går t∞w fvn∞w tå t∞w cux∞w §nyumÆmata gin≈skomen, faonÆ tiw oÔsa, ka‹ fvnÆ. The etymology of fvnÆ from (noÚw) f«w is cited by Betz (1973, 272 n. 3) with reference to this passage; he calls it “erbaulich”; following Steinthal (see next n.) he sees the etymology of fvnÆ as f«w toË noË as Stoic (1973, 285 n. 6), but see next n., and below, section 4. 19) S D.T. p. 483.5-6 Hilgard, fvnØ d¢ l°getai oflone‹ faonÆ tiw oÔsa, tout°sti lampr«w dhloËsa tå noÆmata: µ fvtonÒh tiw oÔsa, parå tÚ fvt€zein tÚn noËn (for faonÆ see above, n. 18, for fvtonÒh nn. 14 and 15). This etymological account is followed by the same ‘physical’ definition as in paragraph (e) of the passage cited above, n. 15. Another passage that is entirely parallel, from (c) up to and including ‘physical’ definition (e), is found in a late tract, [Theodosius] Per‹ grammatik∞w p. 16.6-19 Göttling. Here (d) is formulated as follows, p. 16.11-5: e‡rhtai d¢ fvnØ diå tÚ e‰nai f«w noË, ≥goun ≤ tå §n t“ n“ fvt€zousa: tå går §ndiãyeta ka‹ kekrumm°na toË noË fanerå ≤m›n ≤ fvnØ §mpoie›, ka‹ tå noÆmata lampr«w de€knusin. The etymological part of this passage is quoted by Schmidt (1839, 18 n. 31) and Heinze (1872, 142). It is discussed by Steinthal (1891, 285), who writes: “Die Sprache aber, ı lÒgow, ist die Offenbarung dieser Vernunft [noËw], was die Stoiker auch in dem Namen fvnÆ ausgedrückt fanden; denn nach ihnen war die Etymologie dieses Wortes f«w noË”. There is however no evidence that the etymology is Stoic, see below, section 4. 10 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê The third of these passages (T 3.3), an explanation of tÒnow (‘pitch accent’), is from the Scholia Vaticana too, and again from a passage attributed to Stephanus by Hilgard in his edition (1901, 174). No explicit reference in (c) here to the distinction between kur€vw and kataxrhstik«w, but the distinction between the human voice issuing from the mind and that of animals (i.e. here those animals which can imitate human speech) is stated explicitly.20) The etymological explicatio uses other means to arrive at the same conclusion: T 3.3 (c) He says that pitch is a resonance of the enharmonic, or rather of the articulate, that is to say the human voice; for only the human voice is articulate. (d) This is why ‘man’ (ênyrvpow) is called phô-s, the voice (phô-nê) being in some way luminous (phôtonoeidê),21) because it illuminates (i.e. reveals) and makes clear what is inside the mind. (c)(d) Accordingly the [sc., voice] sent out from the mind and going back to the mind is also called enharmonic, i.e. articulate [...]. (c) Since there also other living beings, which imitate the enharmonic voice and speak in such a way that one believes to hear a human being, should we therefore say that their Steinthal’s claim is presumably based on the fact that the [Theodosian] passage is quoted by Schmidt in his book on Stoic grammar. 20) For another and differently worded parallel for the distinction between the human voice and that of animals and lifeless things see S D.T. p. 130.8-21 Hilgard; cf. also Tabarroni (1988, 106). For Stoic views of animals capable of imitating human speech see the passages cited below, n. 48. 21) The word fvteinoeid∞ is only paralleled at S E. Hipp. 740, p. 92.8 Schwartz. The etymology of fvnÆ from f«w/f≈w (= ênyrvpow) is paralleled Elias in Porph. p. 37.1-4 Busse, koinvnoËmen d¢ éllÆloiw diå fvn«n, ˜yen ka‹ fvnØ e‡rhtai …w efiw f«w êgousa tå toË noË gennÆmata, diÚ ka‹ f∆w mÒnow ı ênyrvpow l°getai …w polÁ tÚ fvtistikÚn ¶xvn ka‹ §jaggeltikÒn: o�tow går ka‹ tå gnvstikå •autoË pãyh §jagg°llei diå t∞w fvn∞w t∞w §nãryrou ktl. See also below, n. 31 and text thereto. 11 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê voice too is enharmonic? We say it is not, for it imitates the voice of man, but is not sent out from a mind.22) In paragraph T 3.3 (d) I have printed fvw in the footnote without accent, to highlight the etymological wordplay: f≈w, ‘man’ (synonym of ênyrvpow, ‘man’), is identified with f«w (contraction of fãow),‘light’,23) in order to provide an explanatory etymology for fv(-nÆ) as the exclusive property of humans. This wordplay is paralleled in T 4.2 below. ‘What is inside the mind’ are, obviously, thoughts. The derivation at T 3.2 (d1) of phô-nê from a monosyllabic verbal root phô, said to be equivalent to phai-nô, which is then supported by an explicatio, or explanatory comment, viz. ‘for it brings the thoughts to light and brightly clarifies them’, is attributed to the grammarian Philoxenus (late 1st cent. BCE) by the editor of his remains.24) The formula 22) S D.T. p. 175.5-9 Hilgard, (c) l°gei d¢ tÚn tÒnon e‰nai épÆxhsin t∞w §narmon€ou fvn∞w, ≥goun t∞w §nãryrou, tout°sti t∞w ényrvp€nhw: mÒnh går ≤ toË ényr≈pou fvnØ ¶naryrow: (d) ˜yen ka‹ fvw ı ênyrvpow, …w e‰nai aÈtØn fvteinoeid∞ tina, tØn fvt€zousan ka‹ safhn€zousan tå §ntÚw toË noË. (c)(d) ˜yen ka‹ §narmÒniÒw §sti, tout°sin ¶naryrow, ≤ épÚ diano€aw §kpempom°nh ka‹ efiw diãnoian énerxom°nh [...]. (c) §pe‹ d¢ ka‹ êlla §st‹ z“a tØn §narmÒnion fvnØn épomimoÊmena, ka‹ fy°ggetai …w doke›n ényr≈pou ékoÊein, îra kéke€nvn e‡poimen §narmÒnion e‰nai tØn fvnÆn; fam¢n oÎ: mime›tai går tØn toË ényr≈pou fvnÆn, oÈk épÚ diano€aw d¢ §kp°mpetai. 23) Cf. above, n. 18. Tabarroni (1988, 107 n. 9) is the only scholar I know of who has noticed the parallel between this D.T. scholium with Aët. 4.19.1, but he errs in stating that the scholium has “light (phôs)”, and has failed to notice the parallels in T 3.1 and 3.2. For the derivation from f≈w see below, n. 31 and thext thereto. 24) Fragment abstracted from the passage quoted above, n. 15: S D.T. p. 181.33-5 Hilgard = Philox.Gramm. fr. *195 Theodoridis (1976, 179), sxhmat€zetai d¢ ≤ fvnØ parå tÚ f«, tÚ fa€nv, katå prÒslhcin sullab∞w t∞w nh ginom°nh: f« fvnÆ: fa€nei går ka‹ lampr«w dhlo› tå §nyumÆmata. This is an “erschlossenes Fragment” (which is why it is preceded by an asterix); for Theodorides’ reasons see ibid., 76-7. 12 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê parå tÚ f« tÚ fa€nv vel. sim. is also found in a named Philoxenus fragment from the Etymologicum of Orion (5th cent. CE), and in four anonymous others which have been plausibly attributed.25) And the explicatio is paralleled ad sententiam in two fragments where the name Philoxenus has been preserved as well. In the lemma on frãzv we read ‘we accomplish the publication and demonstration of thoughts by speaking (frãzein)’, and in that on frÆn (phrên, in the sense ‘mind’)26) we hear that the frÆn is that ‘from which deliberations come forth’. In the anonymous but convincingly attributed fragment concerned with frÒnimow, ‘prudent’, this explicatio is stated more fully: the frÆn is that ‘from which deliberations and judgements come forth’.27) And the derivation of words from monosyllabic verbal roots is the shibboleth of Philoxenus. As is to be expected the corpus of so-called Etymologica contains further echoes, or versions, of the etymological explanations of fvnÆ. Critical editions are only available for parts, or sections, so often enough one does not know what the transmission and interrelations of the extant manuscript versions of this succession of treatises are. It will be clear that I cannot agree with his remark that this “Glosse” has not been “andersweitig überliefert”. Note that he reads fv fvnÆ:, so keeps fv, expunged by Hilgard (above, n. 13). 25) Philox.Gramm. fr. 26 Th. ap. Orion Et. p. 160.23-7 Sturz, FilÒjenow §n t“ Per‹ monosullãbvn =hmãtvn, and frs. *40, *55, *60 and *107 Th. But parå tÚ f« tÚ fa€nv is also found in passages that are perhaps less easily attributable, such as Et.Gud. v. f≈skv, p. 560.35-7 Sturz d¢ parå tÚ f« tÚ fa€nv, ka‹ pleonasm“ toË skv, or EM v. ¶rifow, p. 375.710 Kallierges, ¶rifow: ı mikrÚw a‡j, µ ≤ mikrå a‡j. parå tÚ ¶ar ka‹ tÚ f«, tÚ fa€nv, §ãrifow ka‹ ¶rifow katå sugkopØn, ı §n t“ ¶ari fainÒmenow, ≥goun pr≈Ûmow. ı goËn §n t“ xeim«ni texye‹w, x€marow. 26) frÆn is standardly identified with diãnoia in the lexica, e.g. Suda v. phi 709, and elsewhere, e.g. Gal. Hipp.Off.Med. XVIIIB p. 649.18-9 Kühn (SVF 2.135 1st text, cf. below, n. 48), tØn diãnoian, ¥n te ka‹ noËn ka‹ fr°na ka‹ lÒgon koin«w ofl ênyrvpoi kaloËsin. 27) Fr. 27a) Th., […] t«n går nohy°ntvn ¶kdosin ka‹ de›jin diå toË frãzein poioÊmeya. oÏtv FilÒjenow §n t“ Per‹ monosullãbvn; fr. 29a) Th., […] frÆn, éf' ∏w pro˝etai tå bouleÊmata. oÏtv FilÒjenow; fr. *194a) Th., […] frÆn, éf' ∏w pro˝etai tå bouleÊmata ka‹ afl gn«mai. 13 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê Accordingly the evidence is not as good as one would like it to be, but still, one supposes, sufficiently reliable to be used. For one of the sources of the Etymologica, the Epimerismi Homerici, the situation is good thanks to Dyck’s magisterial editions. Dyck moreover quotes or refers to parallel passages in the Etymologica in his second apparatus, using ms. evidence where no critical edition is available.28) Even so, I do not pretend to have found all the lemmas in the Etymologica containing parallels that may be relevant, nor shall I quote all those I have collected. Early instances are found in the Etymologicum of Orion (a work cited above in connection with the Philoxenus fragment). In the first of these brief entries we find the term lÒgow in the sense of ‘speech’, or ‘discourse’ (compare the proem to book one of Diomedes’ Ars quoted above (T 2) where the equivalent used is oratio): T 4.1 phô-nê (‘voice’): what illuminates the (contents) of the mind (noûs) through speech (lÒgow).29) This is immediately followed, ibid., by two etymologies of f≈w, ‘man’: T 4.2 phô-s: ‘man’ (ênyrvpow), the only one to illuminate the (contents) of the mind (diano€a) through speech (lÒgow); alternatively from ‘phô’ ‘speak’ (l°gv);30) for man is a rational (logikÒn) animal.31) 28) I have consulted Reizenstein (1897) and (1907), Alpers (1969), Serrano Aybar (1977, 102-5), Dyck (1983, 5-16, 22-33), Dyck (1995, 23-48, 848-64), and Tosi (1998); Schironi (2004, 16-25) was not yet available to me. 29) Orion Etym. p. 160.12 Sturz, fvnÆ: ≤ fvt€zousa t“ lÒgƒ tå toË noË. 30) The formula parå tÚ f« tÚ l°gv (cf. attributed frs. *55, *159 and *191 Th.) is not implausibly attributed to Philoxenus too by Theodoridis, whose fr. *196a)—abstracted from this very Orion passage—runs: f≈w: … µ parå tÚ f« tÚ l°gv: logikÚn går z“on ı ênyrvpow. Note that the part omitted by Theodorides is paralleled ad sententiam at Philox.Gramm. fr. *195 Th., see above nn. 24 and 27. But parå tÚ f« tÚ l°gv also occurs in passages which are less easily attributable (e.g. EM v. frãzv, p. 799.21 f. Kallierges). 14 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê The remark in T 4.1 that the contents of the mind are revealed by means of lÒgow entails that fvnÆ in this sense cannot be attributed to other living beings; T 4.2, where it is said that man is the only one to do this, states this even more clearly. We should note the wordplay which is the same as in T 3.3 (d) above: f≈w, ‘man’, is put on a par with f«w, ‘light’. The etymological point in T 4.1 and T 4.2 about the illumination of the contents of the mind is also paralleled in T 3.1 to T 3.3 above. Orion’s treatise is earlier than the paragraphs of the Commentaria in Dionysium Thracem from which I have quoted above, so one could argue that what is found there derives from (a fuller version of ?) this Etymologicum, though naturally one cannot be certain. A very similar explicatio is preserved in a lemma of Orion concerned with another verb meaning ‘to speak’: T 5.1 To speak clearly (phtheggesthai): is produced [viz., from pheggesthai] by the insertion of the y (‘th’). For to shine (pheggesthai) is derived from bright light (pheggos). Note that it [viz., phtheggesthai] is said from the bringing into light (phôs) of the operations (kinÆmata) of the mind (toË noË).32) 31) Orion Etym. p. 160.13-5 Sturz, f≈w: ı ênyrvpow, ı mÒnow tå t∞w diano€aw fvt€zvn t“ lÒgƒ, µ parå tÚ f« tÚ l°gv: logikÒn går z“on ˆ ënyrvpow. Cf. Ep.Hom. f 15, p. 724.1-2 Dyck, and the parallels cited ad loc. by Dyck (1995), among which a passage from the Et.Gen. Also cf. Apollon. Lex. p. 166.1-2 Bekker, f«tew: ofl ênyrvpoi, épÚ toË fvt€zein tå nooÊmena pãnta diå toË lÒgou. 32) Orion Etym. p. 162.12-4 Sturz, fy°ggesyai: pleonasm“ toË <y>. f°ggesyai går §st‹ parå tÚ f°ggow, ˜ §sti tÚ f«w. e‡rhtai oÔn parå tÚ efiw f«w êgein tå toË noË kinÆmata. Insertion (adiectio) is a standard explanation or effectuation of change, see above, n. 13. The expression noË (or diano€aw, or cux∞w) kinÆmata in the sense cogitata, ‘thoughts’, is quite common, see e.g. S.E. M. 7.221-2, 8.11-3 (LS 33B), 70, 137-9, D.L. 9.70, the Nemesius passage referred to above, n. 6 and partly quoted below, n. 48, and nat.hom. p. 71.9-10 (see below, n. 145), Cic. N.D. 3.71 mentis motus, Sen. Ep. 117.13 motus animorum enuntiativi corporum, Calc. p. 234.3 Waszink (SVF 2 p. 236.21 von Arnim, see quotation below, n. 86). —Perhaps Plutarch alludes to this etymology, see Gen.Socr. 15 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê The Byzantine Etymologica too preserve this sort of information. First, a passage from the Etymologicum Gudianum, v. êsyma (I do not quote the whole entry): T 5.2 phtheggesthai from phô, from the bringing to light (phôs) of the contents of the mind (tå toË noË).33) The compiler of this Etymologicum abstracted the entire lemma êsyma from the Epimerismi Homerici plausibly attributed to Choeroboscus.34) Lentz, who quoted from Cramer’s edition (1835) of the Epimerismi and from the Etymologicum Magnum, argued that it derives from the Per‹ pay«n of Herodianus (2nd cent. CE), an attribution provisionally accepted by Dyck (who ad loc. refers to the parallel in Orion) in his edition of the Epimerismi.35) Lentz also attributed other entries of similar content to this work.36) The most interesting passage is found in Hdn. Path. fr. 220 Lenz, again deriving from the Epimerismi for which now Dyck’s text is available:37) 589BC: humans get to know each others’ thoughts (noÆseiw) by means of voice, which is like groping in the dark (ÍpÚ skÒtƒ), whereas the thoughts of the demons, which possess bright light (f°ggow), shine upon (§llãmpousin) those able to <see> them (cf. also below, n. 89). 33) Et.Gud. p. 211.12-3 di Stefani, tÚ fy°ggesyai parå tÚ f«, tÚ efiw f«w êgv tå toË noË. 34) Text at Dyck (1995, 105-6: a 143), where several parallel passages in the lexica are indicated in the apparatus ad loc. For the attribution to Choeroboscus see ibid., 23-4. 35) Lentz (1868, Hdn. Gr. III.2 p. 286) ad Hdn. Path. fr. *364, attribution accepted by Dyck (1995, 105; for the text see now Dyck (1995) quoted in the previous note). 36) See Lentz (1868, Hdn. Gr. III.2 p. 248) ad Hdn. Path. fr. 220, a cento composed by him from passages in Et.Gud. and Ep.Hom.; for these texts see now Dyck (1995, 376: i 13 and 390-1: i 56), who attributes the first passage to [Hdn.] Ep..Hom. and the first part of the second to Hdn. Path. and Cath.Pr. Finally Lentz (1868, Hdn. Gr. III.2 p. 371) ad Hdn. Path. fr. *627, quoted by him from EM. 37) Lentz (1868, Hdn. Gr. III.2 p. 248); better text at Dyck (1995, 376: i 13, p. 376), who attributes it to [Hdn.] Ep. Hom. 16 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê T 5.3 About ‘strong’ (iphthimos) Seleucus says [it is derived] by the insertion of the ‘th’;38) just as from bright light (pheggos) comes to shine (pheggesthai) and [from this again] to speak clearly (phtheggesthai), from bringing the lÒgow into the light (phô-s).39) With the grammarian Seleucus, a contemporary of Tiberius and a (later) rival of Philoxenus, we find ourselves in the early 1st cent. CE. Though the methods of derivation of these two men are different, Philoxenus starting from monosyllabic verbal stems, Seleucus adding supernumerary letters, in the present case both are agreed that words pertaining to speech and speaking are to be explained by having recourse to a semantic element, viz. the etymological explanation by means of words for ‘light’ and ‘shine’. One cannot, of course, exclude that Seleucus was inspired by Philoxenus, but as we shall see the idea itself was sufficiently common to make a derivation from a single source most unlikely. We should also cite the first explanation, in an additamentum to the Etymologicum Gudianum deriving from the Etymologicum Genuinum (2nd half of the 9th cent.), of a synonym of fvnÆ, viz. aÈdÆ (‘human voice’, ‘speech’, ‘sound’) via a synonym of f«w, viz. aÈgÆ: 38) This phrase is more intelligible in Dyck (1995, 390: i 56, p. 390.79-81), where anonymous ‘others’ (i.e. other than Herodianus mentioned at the beginning of the entry) derive ‡fyimow in this way via ‰fi. For insertion see above, n. 32. 39) Ep.Hom. i 13, p. 376.83-5 Dyck = Seleucus fr. 1 Müller, <§p‹> toË ‡fyimow ı S°leukow l°gei pleonasmÚn e‰nai toË y, Àsper parå tÚ f°ggow f°ggesyai ka‹ fy°ggesyai, parå tÚ efiw f«w proãgein tÚn logon. Dyck ad loc. says that it may come from Hdn. Path., as Lentz believed, but is very skeptical about Lentz’ claim that Herodianus said he agreed with Seleucus. We may add that the words ka‹ ≤me›w sugkatatiy°meya t“ SeleÊkƒ which Lentz apparently claims to have taken from the text at p. 208 of Cramer’s edition of the Ep.Hom. are not in fact to be found there, and I have been unable to establish their provenance. 17 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê T 6 aud-ê: voice (phô-nê); it is said from aug-ê (‘bright light’) through substitution of d for g; (audê/augê is that) through which the (contents) of the mind (noû) are shone upon and illuminated (phot-izetai). And voice (pho-nê) the same, because it is a sort of phôtonoê (‘light-thought’).40) An etymology of aÈdÆ is not found in texts T 1 and T 3 - T 5, but the link between light (in T 6 aÈgÆ as well as f«w) and the expression of thought contents by speaking is the same in all these passages, and the etymology of fvnÆ through fvtonoÆ at the end is only paralleled in T 3.2 (d2) and T 3.3 (d2) above. The evidence studied in this section demonstrates that the second part of the first lemma of the Aëtian chapter On Voice can be paralleled in various ways in what we may call a grammatical tradition. In one branch of this tradition, that of the Etymologica, the material is (unsurprisingly) limited to versions and varieties of the etymological ingredient. Two virtually identical passages in the Commentaria in Dionysium Thracem are closer to the Aëtian lemma because they not only contain etymological explanations but also a paragraph on the distinction between fvnÆ in the proper and in the loose, or improper, sense, and a (different) physical description. In the third parallel passage from the Commentaria (T 3.3) and in that in Diomedes (T 2) quoted above the etymology is lacking. 40) Et.Gud. add. p. 231.22-3 di Stefani, aÈdÆ: fvnÆ: e‡rhtai parå tÚ aÈgÆ §n tropª toË <g> efiw <d>: di' ∏w aÈgãzetai ka‹ fvt€zetai tå toË noË: ka‹ fvnØ tÚ aÈtÒ, fvtonoÆ tiw oÔsa (for fvtonoÆ cf. above, nn. 14 and 15). Di Stefani ad loc. notes that this derives from the Etymologicum Genuinum, information he received from Reitzenstein, see (ibid., iii). ‘Substitution’ (immutatio) too is an old etymological ploy, cf. above, n. 13. —I note in passing that Gal. Hipp.Epid., XVIIA p. 757.6-759.8 Kühn (first part at SVF 2.144 2nd text = FDS 478; partly in SVF 2.144 1st text = FDS 477, from the spurious commentary on Hum. so to be discounted), explaining the co-occurrence of ênaudow and êfvnow at [Hipp.] Epid. 3.17.(3), and also Def., XIX p. 79.16-80.3 Kühn, argues against the view (attested Erot. p. 44.3-6 Klein, cf. e.g. Hsch., Suid., and Phot. s.vv.) that ênaudow and êfvnow are synonyms; ênaudow, he posits, pertains to human speech only; see further Ax (1986, 207-9). 18 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê In the sections that follow we shall see that the evidence for the etymological explanation (and also that for the physiological account) is not limited to grammatical or lexicographical sources, so that we need not assume that whoever composed the Aëtian lemma depended on a grammarian’s account of ‘voice’. We should moreover keep in mind to what extent it ultimately derives from several dialogues of Plato, that is to say is linked with a philosophical tradition. The extant Commentaria presuambly derive to a large extent from the comments on Dionysius’ grammar by people who (like John Philoponus derive) also taught philosophy, and they also contain other philosophical items, such as definitions of definition, of technê, etc. 41) Accordingly, the passages from these commentaries quoted above may ultimately be indebted to a philosophical as well as a grammatical tradition. 3. Philo, Cicero, Heraclitus the Allegorist Two species of human speech are mentioned in a passage of Philo of Alexandria (early 1st cent. CE), which lacks the etymology but provides an explanation which comes quite close: T 7.1 […] and beside truth he set a kindred quality which he called ‘clarification’ (dÆlvsiw); these [i.e. truth and clarification] represent both (species of) speech we possess, viz. the internal and the uttered (§ndiay°tou te ka‹ proforikoË). For 41) For a related passage in a philosophical commentary see the quotation from Elias, above n. 21. I cannot enter here into a discussion of the treatment of question per‹ fvn∞w by the late Neoplatonist commentators in general; for some comments see Tabarroni (1988, passim), Chiesa (1992, 16, 29). For definitions of definition in the S in D.T. see e.g. ‘Aristotle’, p. 107.1-2 Hilgard, ‘Chrysippus’, ibid. p. 107.5 (SVF 2.226 ), and‘Antipater the Stoic’, ibid. p. 107.6-7 (SVF 3 Ant. 23); for versions of the standard Stoic definition of technê (cf. SVF 1.73, 2.94) see ibid. pp. 2.24-6, 6.20-1, 26.24-6, 108.31-3, 157.18-29, 161.27-9, 445.12-3; for an instance of the diaphonia referred to above, n. 8, see ibid. p. 482.9-14. 19 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê the uttered requires clarification, by which the hidden thoughts in each of us (tå éfan∞ t«n kay' ßkaston ≤m«n §nyÊmia) are made known to our fellow-men […].42) There are, as a matter of fact, quite a few passages dealing with ‘voice’, and ‘speech’, in Philo’s oeuvre which contain most of the ingredients studied in the previous sections of this study, though the majority lack the etymology. Look for instance at his account of ‘articulate voice’. Philo insists on the crucial difference between men and animals, describes the physical process of the production of voice as sound upon which articulation and reason are imprinted, and declares that speech is the herald and interpreter of the mind: T 7.2 As to articulate voice (§nãryrou fvn∞w), moreover, an advantage possessed by man alone of all living creatures, there are particulars of which we are aware; as, for example, that it is sent up from the mind (diano€aw), that it is in the mouth that it acquires articulation, that it is the stroke of the tongue that imparts articulation (tÚ ¶naryron) and speech to the (pneumatic) tension of the voice; it does not produce a mere idle sound and formless noise (cilØn … fvnØn érgØn ka‹ édiatÊpvton ∑xon), as it performs for the suggesting mind the function of its herald or interpreter (kÆrukow µ •rmhn°vw …tãjin).43) 42) Ph. Spec. 4.69; tr. here and in the following passages by Colson — Whittaker, modified. For other Philonic passages where ‘internal speech’ and ‘uttered speech’ occur (or are hinted at) see FDS 530-534 (none of these is in SVF). Add Congr. 33-4, Mut. 69; also Anim. 12 and 98, see the instructive comments of Terian (1981, 125-6, 203-4). Good brief overview at Betz (1973, 285); Otte (1968, 131-9) is to be used with caution. For the ‘hidden’ thoughts cf. below, T 7.3 and nn. 86 and 89 and text thereto. 43) Phil. Det. 40. Cf. Mos. 2.127 (FDS 531), Migr. 71 (FDS 530), Migr. 117, Congr. 33, Mut. 69. Hülser (1987, 564-7, i.e. FDS 515-8) has a paragraph “Der Verstand als Quelle der Rede”, a theme for which he also refers to passages elsewhere in his collection. But FDS 515 (SVF 2.840) does not provide independent evidence; this quasi-apophthegm is derived from Galen’s note toioÊtoiw d¢ ka‹ tØn diãnoian sumf≈nvw éforizÒmenoi l°gousin aÈtØn phgØn e‰nai lÒgou embedded in his excerpt from Chrysippus at PHP 2.5.18, or from the fragment itself (PHP 2.5.15-20; SVF 2.894, FDS 450). Tieleman (1996, 271 n. 38) 20 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê The mind (diãnoia), according to Philo, is the ‘source’ (phgÆ) of speech, a formula which is first found in a verbatim fragment of Chrysippus preserved by Galen.44) The best parallel passage, Deter. 125-9, demonstrates that Philo not only knew the etymology of fvnÆ as f«w noË vel. sim., but apparently also that of aÈdÆ from aÈgÆ.45) It is too long to translate and quote in its entirety, so I merely present the following abstract: T 7.3 The Creator says he knows that uttered speech (tÚn … proforikÚn lÒgon), the brother of the mind (diano€a), does speak […]. This speech speaks and talks and interprets the thoughts (§nyumÆmata) for both me and you and all humans, and goes out to meet the reasonings of the mind. For when the mind bestirs itself and receives an impulse towards some object belonging to its own sphere, either moved from within itself or experiencing various impressions from external objects, it becomes pregnant and is in labour as to its thoughts (noÆmata). It wishes to be delivered of them, but cannot, until the sound produced by the tongue and the other organs of speech takes the thoughts (noÆmata) into its hands like a midwife, and brings them forth into the light (f«w). This [viz., articulate sound produced by human adults] is the farthest-shining (thlaugestãth) voice (fvnÆ) of our thoughts. For just as things laid up in darkness are hidden, until a light (f«w) shines upon them and shows them, in the same way thoughts (§nyumÆmata) are stored in the mind—a hidden place—until the voice, illuminating (§naugãsasa) them like a light (oÂa f«w), uncovers them.46) suggests that Galen’s source for this interpolation is a Stoic lexicon. For the ‘interpreter’ cf. below, nn. 48 and 86. 44) For Stoic antecedents of the formula ‘source of speech’ see below, text after n. 69. 45) See above, n. 40 and text thereto; thlaugestãth and §naugãsasa in Philo’s text. 46) Phil. Det. 126-8. Cf. Bas. hex. 3.2.8-16 Amand de Mendieta – Rudberg, esp. for Basil’s formula §n t“ krupt“ nÒhma (it has escaped the editors that this passage is quoted in part at Melet. nat.hom. p. 22.8-3.6 Cramer, without the author’s name but after a quotation from another oration of Basil which is not anonymous). See further Gronau (1914, 69-71), also for parallel passages. Gronau believes that what is in Basil is Stoic, but the evidence does not 21 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê Most of the ingredients of this somewhat fulsome passage we have met before. It is hard to miss the Platonizing colouring: the well-known ‘Socratic’ simile of pregnancy and deliverance is here applied to the everyday act of speaking. The etymology of fvnÆ is not Stoic either, but a considerable part of its further contents seems to be of Stoic provenance. Philo himself, who is quite familiar with the discipline of grammar, ascribes its development to the influence of ‘philosophy’. 47) A similar concatenation of ideas is found in a Ciceronian passage (the epistemological setting here, however, lacks the Platonizing element): men are distinguished from the beasts by ratio, i.e. by what ‘enables us to draw inferences, to prove and disprove, to discuss and solve problems, and to come to conclusions’. This ratio, clearly, is what in other texts is called ‘internal speech’. The ‘rudimentary beginnings of intelligence’ are imprinted via the senses. ‘Speech’ is characterized as ‘the mind’s interpreter’.48) support this view, see section 4 below. For ‘hidden thoughts’ also cf. the Philo quotation above, T 7.1, and n. 42 ad finem. 47) For Philo’s familiarity with ‘grammar’ cf. Congr. 148-50 (SVF 2.99), on which see Schenkeveld (1990a, 105-6) and (1990b, 306). 48) Cic. Leg. 1.30 (for the formula cf. above, text to n. 43; below, n. 86). For Cicero on the production of speech and the distinction between men and animals cf. e.g. N.D. 2.149 (FDS 518), with Pease’s notes. For Cicero on exclusively human thought processes see e.g. N.D. 2.147, Off. 1.11, with Dyck’s notes, and the parallel at Gal. Hipp.Med.Off. XVIIIB p. 649.16-650.5 Kühn st (SVF 2.135, 1 text = FDS 528, cf. the first words quoted above, n. 26; Arnim omits the final words ˜sa t' êlla toiaËta, Hülser prints them), but note that Galen mentions neither Stoics (only ofl filÒsofoi in general) nor animals. Sext. M. 8.275-6 (~ SVF 2.223 and in part 2.135, 2nd text; FDS 529, LS 53 T) speaks of humans differing from animals (such as parrots, which may imitate them) because humans have internal speech (the translation of lÒgow §ndiãyetow as ‘disposition intérieure’ in the French tr. of LS 53T is peculiar) and presentation arising from inference and combination; cf. Chiesa (1991, 304-7), Labarrière (1993, 235-6), Long (1996a, 117-8). Chrysippus ap. Varr. L 56 (SVF 2.143; for the sequel, not in SVF, see below, n. 66) is reported to have argued that parrots and children only have ‘quasi-speech’ (ut loqui = …sane‹ l°gein, cf. Pohlenz (1970-2, 1.40, 2.23)). Nemes. nat.hom. p. 71.9-13 Morani compromizes by saying that humans are the ‘most rational’ (mãlista logiko€) of 22 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê We may conclude this section with passages from the Allegoriae, or Quaestiones Homericae, of Heraclitus (date uncertain; possibly 1st cent. CE), who like others identifies Hermes with lÒgow,49) manages to believe that internal and uttered speech are implied in the Homeric descriptions of the god, and rather forcefully stresses that internal speech is hidden: T 8.1 This is why Homer called the internal (speech) chthonic (Hermes), for invisible it lies, darkened, in the depths of the mind; but the uttered (speech) he located in the heavens, because it is clear from far away.50) Earlier in the same chapter Heraclitus explains Hermes’ epitheton ornans érgeifÒnthw, insisting here as well that it is speech which lays bare the operations of the mind: T 8.2 Homer calls the god argeï-pho-ntês […] because only the reality of logos as a whole clearly reveals what is thought.51)52) all living beings through the presence of internal speech. Long and Sedley (1987, 2.319) point out that Sext. M. 8.275-6 is certainly Stoic (see also Long 1972, 87), while Sorabji (1993, 80) speaks of “unnamed philosophers”. 49) Thus already Pl. Cra. 407e-408b. For parallels see van der Stockt (1990, 189), Ramelli (2003, 331-2). 50) Heraclit. All. 72.18, diå toËt' oÔn ÜOmhrow tÚn m¢n §ndiãyeton e‰pe xyÒnion, éfanØw går §n to›w t∞w diano€aw buyo›w épeskÒtvtai, tÚn d¢ proforikÒn, §peidØ pÒrrvy°n §sti d∞low, §n oÈran“ kat–kisen. Cf. Zeller, cited below, n. 59. 51) Heraclit. All. 72.10-1, êrgeifÒnthn te går Ùnomãzei tÚn yeÒn […] §peidØ m€a pantÚw lÒgou fÊsiw §kfa€nei §narg«w tÚ nooÊmenon. 52) This etymology is paralleled in Cornutus’ Epitome of Greek Theology, from the middle of the st cent. CE, Corn. N.D. p. 21.11-3 Lang: ‘argeï-phon-tês is like argeï-phan-tês (‘white- 1 revealing’), from showing everything whitely [i.e. clearly] and making it clear; for the ancients called ‘white’ (leukos) argos’ (érgeifÒnthw d° §st‹n oÂon érgefãnthw épÚ toË leuk«w pãnta fa€nein ka‹ safhn€zein^tÚ går leukÚn érgÚn §kãloun 23 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê 4. Stoic Views The etymologizing explicatio of fvnÆ from f«w is also known to the learned Eustathius, who in a passage of his commentary on the Odyssey explaining the Sirens’ song (m 197-8) declares that T 9 the definitions of voice as ‘air that has been struck’ or ‘the proper sense-object of hearing’ are not to the point, for we clearly need here (the definition) ‘light of the mind’. For such is uttered speech, which illuminates for the hearers the internal speech which is practised in the heart.53) ofl palaio€.) The etymology by means of érgÒw = leukÒw is also found in the Etymologica, see Et.Gud. v. érgeifÒnthw, p. 186.3 de Stefani and three of the additamenta quoted ibid. p. 185.14-186.25. The first explanation of the epitheton (paralleled in the same additamenta), at p. 185.8-9, attributed to Alexion, Archias and Aristarchus, is similar to that given by Heraclitus and Cornutus, viz. ‘from making the presentations clear’ (parå tÚ §narge›w tåw fantas€aw poie›n). The inference that Heraclitus and Cornutus depend on a shared tradition is unavoidable, cf. Ramelli (2003, 334-5), also for further parallels. 53) Eust. in Od. 2.7.36-8 Stallbaum, thnikaËta går oÈ fam¢n ırismÚn fvn∞w toiaÊthw tÚ é°ra peplhgm°non aÈtØn e‰nai µ ‡dion afisyhtÚn éko∞w, éllå dhladØ f«w noË. toioËtow går ı proforikÚw lÒgow, diafvt€zvn to›w ékroata›w tÚn §ndiãyeton, ˘w §n kard€& meletçtai. The context, from p. 7.24 ff., where Eustathius discusses various terms for voice or speech, insists on the difference between humans and others, and of course demonstrates his knowledge of the Etymologica is interesting. The poet’s ‘daring expression is cured in a philosophical way through etymology’ (p. 7.35, yerapeÊetai … filosÒfvw ≤ tÒlma di' §tumolog€aw). At in Il. 4.237.6-7 van der Valk (SVF 1.74) he states disertis verbis that ‘air that has been struck’ is ‘Zeno’s definition of voice’ (tÚn katå ZÆnvna t∞w fvn∞w ˜ron), but Zeno in this late author (as so often) probably represents ‘the Stoics’. 24 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê Part of this terminology is Stoic, or had become Stoic. The etymological explanation of fvnÆ is not Stoic,54) but the standard definitions of ‘voice’ as ‘air that has been struck, or the proper sense-object of hearing’, which Eustathius here disprefers, are found in the abstracts from the influential handbook On Voice by Diogenes of Seleucia in the longer account of Stoic dialectic of Diogenes Laërtius book seven, and elsewhere.55) However our evidence for the terminological speciality ‘internal speech’ / ‘uttered speech’ as early Stoic is not good enough.56) Max Pohlenz, who rightly pointed this out, 54) See below. 55) D.L. 7.55 (SVF 3 Diog. 17, LS 33H). Later also found in a passage containing doxographical material, S D.T., Schol.Lond. p. 482.5-7 Hilgard (FDS 481, not in SVF; see Ax (1976, 166 n. 112)). At Simp. in Ph. p. 425.34-426.2 Diels the second of these definitions is anonymous and the first attributed to Diogenes (cf. SVF 3 Diog. 19). Parallels from or (perhaps) attributable to Apollonius Dyscolus are cited by Schneider (1910, 2); also see Dalimer (2001, 265) ad A.D. Conj. p. 220.3-4 Schneider. Stroh (1998, 442) also adduces [Plu.] Mus. 1131D, ır€zontai tØn fvnØn ofl êristoi grammatiko‹ é°ra peplhgm°non afisyhtÚn ékoª. Cf. in a doxographical passage Gell. 5.15.6 (SVF 2.141): ‘Stoici … ictum aëra’ (see also below, n. 110). See also Tabarroni (1988, 107), Ax (2002). 56) One may compare the technical term ≤gemonikÒn, already attested in verbatim fragments of Chrysippus ap. Gal. PHP 2.5.70 (SVF 2.898, §n tª kard€& m¢n toË ≤gemonikoË ˆntow) and 3.7.11-2 (SVF 2.885, m°row ... tÚ ≤gemonikÒn, and per‹ d¢ toË ≤gemonikoË m°rouw t∞w cux∞w, where the presence of m°row reveals that the use is not yet entirely technical). This formula seems to have been preceded by the somewhat less technically sounding tÚ m°row tÚ ≤goÊmenon aÈt∞w (sc., t∞w cux∞w), Cleanthes on Zeno at Ar. Did. fr. 39 Diels ap. Eus. PE 15.20.3 (SVF 1.141), expression paralleled [Gal.] Def. XIX p. 365.9 Kühn, tÚ ≤goÊmenon t∞w cux∞w m°row, and Dio Or. 36.51 (SVF 2.602), tÚ fronoËn ka‹ tÚ ≤goÊmenon aÈt∞w (sc., t∞w cux∞w). Galen knows it, see PHP 2.5.81. Chrysippus’ terminology is not fixed; to support the claim of the heart as seat of the regent part through etymology he calls it tÚ kurieËon ka‹ kratoËn t∞w cux∞w m°row, ap. Gal. PHP 3.5.28 (SVF 2.896). Arist. EN 3.5.1113a6 exceptionally has tÚ ≤goÊmenon for the ‘commanding part’ of ourselves (the mind according to Asp. in EN p. 74.32 Heylbut), though not explicitly as a part of the soul and certainly not as a technicality (he is already thinking of the Homeric commanders adduced 1113a7 ff.). 25 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê also argued that the doctrine behind the formula, pace the consensus among earlier scholars, cannot be attributed to the early Stoics.57) It would have been quite generally known in the Hellenistic period and cannot be linked with a specific school. Its provenance is stated to be the debate on animal intelligence between Stoics and Academics. According to Pohlenz “internal” and “uttered speech” are only explicitly attributed to “the Stoics” by as late an authority as Porphyry, while Sextus Empiricus in the parallel passages only speaks of the “Dogmatists”.58) But these arguments have failed to convince me. Pohlenz’—in itself correct—point that a variety of this idea is already found in Plato59) does not preclude that the Stoics subscribed to it; in fact, he writes: “Zweiffellos entspricht die Lehre [viz., die Scheidung der beiden Logoi] den Anschauungen der alten Stoa”. But on the next page he takes this back again: “Die Scheidung der beiden Logoi ist für die alte Stoa ausgeschlossen”.60) It is also odd that he fails to exploit the fact that the (as he knows) parallel accounts of the ‘internal speech’ and ‘uttered speech’ which animals are claimed to possess in Philo, Sextus Empiricus, and Porphyry must go back to a common source earlier than Philo.61) 57) Pohlenz (1970-2, 2.21-2) “[d]ie Termini wie die Lehre sind der alten Stoa fremd” (my emphasis). For details see his “Anhang: LÒgow §ndiãyetow und lÒgow proforikÒw”, Pohlenz (1939, 191-8 = 1965, 79-86), followed e.g. by Waszink (1962, 55: “hanc distinctionem non necessarie ad Stoicos referendam esse recte monet Pohlenz”), Babut (1973, 73 with nn. 9 and 10), van der Stockt (1991, 188-90), and Chiesa (1991, 312-4); Pohlenz’ argument is criticized unsuccessfully by Mühl (1962, 8-16). 58) Porph. Abst. 3.2, p. 187.20-4 Nauck (FDS 529A); cf. below, n. 61 and text thereto for the context from which it is quoted. 59) See already Zeller (1865, 61 n. 1), slightly revised Zeller (1888, 67 n. 1) and Zeller-Wellmann (1909, 68 n. 4); for the phrase in Aristotle adduced as a parallel by Zeller (and Pohlenz, and others) see below, n. 144. For the rather different Platonic view (which, unlike the Stoic, places speech on a lower level than thought and stipulates that thought is voiceless, while Chrysippus and Diogenes of Seleucia, as we shall see, speak of an inner voice) see below, section 6. 60) Pohlenz (1939, 195 = 1965, 83 and 196 = 84). 61) Phil. Anim. 12-70, S.E. P. 62-77, Porph. Abst. 3.2.1-82; argued by Tappe (1912), to whom Pohlenz refers. Cf. Dierauer (1977, 269-70); good survey and table with three facing columns at Bouffartigue – Patillon (1979, 138-43), informative account at Tabarrroni (1988, 108-11), further 26 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê And though it is true that Philo omits to mention the Stoics, Porphyry is not the only author to refer to them, for Sextus explicitly mentions them as well. Indeed, virtually the whole argument in Sextus (concluding his exposition of the first trope of Aenesidemus)62) is aimed at the Stoics.63) The fact that an idea, or formula, came to be in common circulation does not entail that it is not Stoic: numerous Stoic terms and ideas were, as we know, taken over by others. What is true is that one cannot conclude that a doctrine is Stoic and nothing but Stoic when it is found to contain Stoic terminology— but that is another matter. Zeller will moreover be right that the ne≈teroi, to whom the formula ‘uttered speech’ is attributed in a passage where they are contrasted by Theon of Smyrna with another school of thought, viz. the Peripatetics, can only be Stoics:64) T 10 lÒgow according to the Peripatetics has many meanings, (viz.) that accompanied by voice called ‘uttered’ by the younger (philosophers); and the internal (logos) that lies in the mind without sound and voice; and that of proportion, (etc.).65) discussion at Chiesa (1991, 308-12). Also see the mainly anti-Stoic arguments at Plu. Soll.An. 960A-62C and 972F-73A already adduced by Tappe; the treatise efi lÒgon ¶xei tå z–a (Lamprias 135) is lost. 62) Not paralled in the versions of the first trope Phil. Ebr. 171-5 and D.L. 9.79-80. 63) Pohlenz refers to S.E. P. 1.62 (cf. 1.64) and M. 8.175 for the dogmatiko€, but overlooks P. 1.65 on internal speech katå toÁw mãlista ≤m›n éntidojoËntaw nËn dogmatikoÊw, toÁw épÚ t∞w Stoçw. For the thrust of Sextus’ (or Aenesidemus’) argument see further Glidden (1994, 136-7). 64) See reference above, n. 59. It is either the context or the specific doctrine attributed to ne≈teroi which enables one to identify them when identification is possible. Here it is the context. 65) Theo Sm. p. 72.24-73.2 Hiller, lÒgow d¢ katå m¢n toÁw PeripathtikoÁw l°getai pollax«w, ˜ te metå fvn∞w, proforikÚw ÍpÚ t«n nevt°rvn legÒmenow, ka‹ ı §ndiãyetow [ka‹ uncis inclusi] ı §n diano€& ke€menow êneu fyÒggou ka‹ fvn∞w [‘without sound or voice’: very Platonic!], ka‹ ı t∞w énalog€aw ktl. This passage is not in SVF or FDS; it is cavalierly treated by Pohlenz (1939, 192 = 1965, 80). 27 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê Forms of the quite common verb prof°resyai may be behind a passage of Varro which however need not apply to the Stoics only, though Chrysippus has been mentioned a few lines earlier:66) ‘so he who knowingly puts each word in its own place does speak; and then, when he has expressed by speaking what he had in his mind, he is (someone) who has uttered’. Prolocutus is of course a Latin derivation, but it is analogous to a term one could derive from the Greek verb. But in the formula tÚ … §g∆ proferÒmeya, ‘we utter the word “I”’, in a verbatim fragment of Chrysippus67) the term proferÒmeya does not yet seem to be a technicality. On the other hand the distinction between l°gein and prof°resyai in the passage in Diogenes Laërtius which presumably derives from Diogenes’ On Voice (or from that of his pupil Archedemus of Tarsus) is certainly technical: ‘to speak is different from to utter, for what is uttered are voices [or: words, sentences], and what is spoken [or: said] are states of affairs, which naturally turn out to be speakables [or: sayables]’.68) Note that this statement lacks an explicit reference to the mind. I submit that the presence of l°gein, a term which (together with lÒgow) is described and clarified in a technical way in what comes before in Diogenes Laërtius’ account, is sufficient. Furthermore, two verbatim snippets from Chrysippus’ On the Soul, the second of which followed closely upon the first, provide an analysis of thinking-and-speaking. First we have the process of ‘rehearsing statements and the like’ and the ‘thinking and speaking’ which take place in the mind (diano€a). Then these are firmly linked with each other: ‘speaking must be from the mind, and also speaking within oneself and 66) Var. L 6.56 (passage included at FDS 512), ‘igitur is loquitur, qui suo loco quodque verbum sciens ponit, et is tum prolocutus, quom in animo quod habuit extulit [proen°gkhtai or prof°retai ?] loquendo’; comments at Stroux (1923, 309-15), Pohlenz (1970-2, 2.23), Sluiter (1990, 206), Barnes (1993, 57), Labarrière (1993, 237), Sorabji (1993, 81). For the reference to Chrysippus see above, n. 48. 67) Ap. Gal. PHP 2.2.11 (SVF 2.895). 68) D.L. 7.57 (SVF 3 Diog. 20), diaf°rei d¢ ka‹ tÚ l°gein toË prof°resyai: prof°rontai m¢n går afl fvna€, l°getai d¢ tå prãgmata, ì dØ ka‹ lektå tugxãnei. Cf. Long (1996a, 121, 122). 28 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê thinking, and going through voice in oneself, and sending it out’,69) §n •auto›w fvnØn dieji°nai ka‹ §ktÚw §kp°mpein. The ‘voice within ourselves’ which is ‘sent out’ and thus constitutes ‘speaking from the mind’ clearly represents what came to be called ‘internal’ plus ‘uttered’ speech. In a longer verbatim fragment from the same work, dealing with the regent part of the soul, Chrysippus argues that the ‘source of speech [viz., the regent part] is not different from the source of mind, and the source of voice is not different from the source of speech’. ‘It is plausible70) also for other reasons that what is spoken (tå legÒmena) should receive its meaning from the place to which it conveys meaning, and that spoken words (tåw fvnãw) should come from there in the manner described’.71) Following in Chrysippus’ footsteps but stating matters more precisely Diogenes of Seleucia defined lÒgow, ‘speech’, as a species of articulate fvnÆ, which in its turn is a species of fvnÆ in general.72) He argued that ‘from where voice is sent out, (from there) also the articulate voice (is sent out), so also meaningful articulate voice, which is speech’.73) ‘Some people’, he continues a bit further on, ‘define speech as voice sent out from a mind.74) It is also for other reasons plausible that speech is sent out imprinted and stamped, as it were, by the cogitations in the mind (ÍpÚ t«n §nnoi«n Gal. PHP 3.7.34 and 43 (SVF 2.903); translations here and in the following passages are De 69) Lacy’s, modified; my emphasis. See also Barnes (1993, 57). 70) On the role of the piyanÒn in Chrysippus’ argumentation see Tieleman (1996, index s.v.). 71) Gal. PHP 2.5.15-20 (SVF 2.894). See also Barnes (1993, 57-8). 72) Gal. PHP 2.5.9-13 (SVF 3 Diog. 29, LS 53U). See Ax (1986, 149). Against the idea that fvnÆ is the genus of lÒgow see e.g. Amm. in Int. p. 16.13-30 Busse, who argues that one should follow Aristotle’s view in the De generatione animalium (viz., GA 5.7.786b20-5—Aristotle in this passage inter alia also refers to the De anima, viz., to 2.8.419b3-421a6) that fvnÆ is only the Ïlh of lÒgow. 73) ˜yen §kp°mpetai ≤ fvnÆ, ka‹ ≤ ¶naryrow: oÈkoËn ka‹ ≤ shma€nousa ¶naryrow fvnØ §ke›yen: toËto d¢ lÒgow. See also Barnes (1993, 58). 74) ¶nioi goËn ka‹ ırizÒmenoi aÈtÒn [sc., lÒgon] fasin e‰nai “fvnØn shma€nousan épÚ diano€aw §kpempom°nhn”. Sluiter (2000) 379 translates diãnoia as ‘thought’ not ‘mind’, which I find unfortunate. 29 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê §nseshmasm°non t«n §n tª diano€& ka‹ oÂon §ktetupvm°non),75) and that it is temporally parallel qua completion of thought and activity of speaking’. The presence of the word oÂon shows that this imprinting-and-stamping is meant metaphorically, not literally. This presentation of the co-presence and co-duration of not only analogous but also coterminous cognitive and vocal activity once more shows in what way what came to be called internal and uttered speech are bound up with each other.76) Speech is invariably prompted and accompanied by thinking, whereas the converse is of course not true. The definition ‘meaningful articulate sound sent out from the mind’ quoted by Diogenes can easily be abstracted from Chrysippus’ arguments and may indeed be 75) Sedley (1993, 330-1) states that Diogenes amplified Zeno’s syllogism on the origin of speech and voice (ap. Gal. PHP 2.5.8, SVF 1.148) with the help of the Theaetetus passage quoted below, n. 137, where §ktupoÊmenon is said of the stamping of one’s opinion on the vocal stream. We may add that Diogenes’ ÍpÚ t«n §nnoi«n §nseshmasm°non is paralleled at the account of memory [not: soul, or voice] at Tht. 191c as a wax tablet (kÆrinon §kmage›on) in the soul ‘which we hold under the perceptions or conceptions and imprint them on it as we might stamp the impression of a signet-ring’ (Íp°xontaw aÈtÚ ta›w afisyÆsesi ka‹ §nno€aiw, épotupoËsyai, Àsper daktul€vn shme›a §nshmainom°nouw). However the metaphors of stamping or imprinting and wax are not restricted to Plato (for the possible impact of the Theaetetus on Zeno see Ioppolo (1990, esp. 438-9, 447)) but are also found in Denocritus’ explanation of visual perception according to the detailed report of Theophrastus (Sens. 50-3 = Dem. fr. 68A135 DK). For details see below, Appendix, p. 000 f. 76) Cf. Long (1972, 82): “thinking as internal discourse goes back to Plato” [cf. Sorabji (2004) 211-3, but see below, section 6]. “In Stoicism it seems to mean that the processes of thought and the processes of linguistic communication are essentially the same.” See further Baratin (1982), whose argument is concerned with the relation between signifier and signified in the “énoncé” (e.g. 1982, 13: “il n’y a pas de pensée sans parole, parole intérieure ou émise”), and Chiesa (1991, 319-21), who, quoting and translating SVF 3 Diog. 19, points out ibid. 320: “Diogène fixe le cadre théorique dans lequel la distinction (des) deux <<logoi>> [viz., the internal and the uttered] devait s’insérer”, but I believe one may ascribe this “cadre théorique” to Chrysippus already. 30 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 originally Chrysippean.77) Phonê Virtually the same formula is attributed to Diogenes himself at D.L. 7.55 (SVF 3 Diog, 17, 33H LS) in a definition of human voice, not speech, as distinguished from that of living beings in general: ‘the voice of animal is air that has been struck by impulse, and (that) of man is articulate and sent out from the mind, as Diogenes says’.78) This formula, by the way, does not necessarily entail that no animals (such as parrots) exist who may produce an articulate voice: the opposition is between impulse, i.e. nothing but impulse, on the one hand and mind on the other.79) Other Stoic texts may be cited in this context, for instance the strange argument cited by late authorities concerning the nominative case, which is called ‘straight’ because ‘it has fallen from the thought; for if we wish to show the thought “Socrates” which we have in ourselves, we utter the name “Socrates” ’.80) Or the suggestive phrase in Diogenes 77) 78) Barnes (1993, 59-60) only grants that the definition is Stoic. D.L. 7.55 (SVF 3 Diog. 17, LS 33H), z–ou m°n §sti fvnØ éØr ÍpÚ ırm∞w peplhgm°now, ényr≈pou d' ¶stin ¶naryrow ka‹ épÚ diano€aw §kpempom°nh, …w ı Diog°nhw fhs€n. See also Pohlenz (1970-2, 40), Tabarroni (1988, 107-8), Barnes (1993, 58), and below, text to n. 124. Note the absence of shma€nousa in Diogenes’ definition of ‘human voice’: a portion of articulate voice sent out from the mind need not be meaningful (standard example: bl€turi, e.g. D.L. 7.57, SVF 3 Diog. 20). So I cannot accept Long’s argument (1996, 123) that épÚ diano€aw and shma€nousa are equivalent, the former explaining the latter, though in general I agree with his account of the relation between thought and speech in Stoic philosophy in this paper (esp. 1996, 119-27). 79) Chiesa (1991, 306-7) argues that the account at D.L. 7.55-7, esp. the definition of Diogenes which says that the human voice is articulate, is at variance with that at S.E. M. 8.275-6 (above, n. 48). But the abstract in Diogenes Laërtius does not say animal voices are never articulate. 80) Amm. in Int. p. 43.11-6 Busse (SVF 2.164, LS 33K) épokr€nontai ofl épÚ t∞w Stoçw …w épÚ toË noÆmatow toË §n tª cuxª ka‹ aÏth [sc., ≤ eÈye›a or ÙryØ pt«siw] p°ptvken: ˘ går §n •auto›w ¶xomen tÚ Svkrãtouw nÒhma dhl«sai boulÒmenoi, tÚ Svkrãthw ˆnoma proferÒmeya. Cf. the parallels cited by Frede (1993, 18). Barnes (1993, 54) says “the contents of the last sentence [viz., from ˘ går §n •auto›w] is a commonplace”. Yes and no … 31 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê Laërtius brief account of Stoic logic: ‘the mind, being prone to expression, utters (§kf°rei) by speech what it experiences by the agency of the presentation’.81) In the account of fvnÆ, lÒgow and l°jiw provided by Diogenes Laërtius,82) where Diogenes’ name is often mentioned, the division is the same as in the verbatim Diogenes fragment about meaningful speech, articulate voice, and voice in general quoted by Galen, but expressed in a different way:83) the technical term l°jiw (‘articulate’ but not necessarily meaningful voice), here added to the formula ‘articulate voice’ paralleled in the other passage, is a species of fvnÆ (‘voice’); and lÒgow, speech (‘meaningful articulate voice’) is a species of l°jiw so a sub-species of fvnÆ. Consequently the Stoics, and Diogenes of Seleucia in particular, argue in favour of a rigorous distinction between voice and speech as issuing from the adult human mind on the one hand, and voice and quasi-language produced by irrational impulse, as is the case with other living beings, including parrots and children under the age of fourteen, on the other.84) And I have found no evidence implying that speech is in any way inferior to thought. The etymological explanation(s) of fvnÆ discussed in the previous sections of this study however are not found in Stoic reliquiae. Though a definition of ‘speaking’ in Sextus Empiricus comes quite close, the point about the illumination of thought is lacking: 81) D.L. 7.49 (SVF 2.52, LS 33D), ≤ diãnoia §klalhtikØ Ípãrxousa, ˘ pãsxei ÍpÚ t∞w fantas€aw, toËto §kf°rei lÒgƒ. Sluiter (2000) 376 translates diãnoia as ‘thought’ not ‘mind’, cf. above, n. 74. 82) D.L. 7.55-6 (SVF 3 Diog. 17 + 18 + 20). 83) See Ax (1986, 165), Barnes (1993, 58-9). 84) D.L. 7.55 (SVF 3 Diog. 17, LS 33H), cf. above, n. 48. Cf. Tabarroni (1988, 107), Sorabji (1993, 81), Glidden (1994, 136). 32 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê T 11 To speak, as the Stoics themselves say, is is to utter the meaningful voicing of the state of affairs that is being thought.85) The only evidence I have found pertaining to speech as giving away (not yet: illuminating) the secret thoughts of the mind according to the Stoics is late and dubious: T 12 They [sc., the Stoics] say that the voice is sent out from the innermost part of the breast, that is to say from the heart, the pneuma exerting itself in the depths of the heart, where an interposed boundary, covered with sinews, separates the heart from the lungs on both sides and the other vital organs. With this (pneuma) it [sc., the innermost part of the heart], battering the narrow passages of the windpipe, through the tongue and the other vocal organs which shape them produces articulate sounds, the elements of uttered speech, through which the secret operations of the mind are laid bare. This (innermost part of the heart) he [sc., Chrysippus] calls the regent part of the soul.86) This is the final paragraph of a chapter in Calcidius where views of Zeno and Chrysippus on the soul and its regent part (the spider in the web) are quoted at quite some ) S.E. M. 8.80 (SVF 2.167), l°gein gãr §sti, kay∆w aÈto€ fasin ofl épÚ t∞w 85 Stoçw, tÚ tØn toË nooum°nou prãgmatow shmantikØn prof°resyai fvnÆn. Cf. Barnes (1993, 60). 86) Calc. ch. 220 p. 233.23-34.3 Waszink (SVF 2.879, p. 236.17-23 von Arnim), ‘vocem quoque dicunt e penetrali pectoris, id est corde, mitti, gremio cordis nitente spiritu, qua nervis obsitus limes interiectus cor a pulmone secernit utroque et vitalibus ceteris, quo [i.e., spiritu] faucium angustias arietante formanteque lingua et ceteris vocalibus organis articulatos edit sonos, sermonis elementa, quo quidem interpretem [for this metaphor cf. above, text to n. 43, n. 48] mentis arcani motus aperiantur. id porro principale animae vocat’. For the change from Chrysippus to the Stoics in general and back see Waszink ad loc.; cf. the move from fhsi + proper name (Chrysippus twice, Posidonius once) to fasi at Ar.Did. frs. 23, 27, and 28 Diels, and the switch from ofl Stviko€ fasin and kaloËsin to Zeno to kaloËsin again at Aët. 4.21 (partly quoted in the text quoted to the next n.; the final sentence of this ch. reports a minority position, cf. tinåw d¢ t«n Stvik«n at Phld. Piet. col. 9.8-12 Gomperz, printed SVF 3 Diog. 33). 33 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê length, or at least paraphrased. This context is in favour of the authenticity of the information just quoted. The at first sight bizarre omission of the role of the lungs can be paralleled in the physical definition of the fvnçen ÍpÚ toË ZÆnvnow efirhm°non, ˘ ka‹ fvnh<tik>Ún kaloËsin (‘the ‘vocal’ [sc., part of the soul], thus expressed by Zeno, which they also call ‘phônêtikon’’).87) The idea is that a direct stream of psychic pneuma stretches from the regent part to the speech organs,88) which presumably is why the separation of the heart from the lungs is stressed in the Calcidius passage. However I believe that the emphasis on the secrecy which is broken derives from the Platonist tradition to which Calcidius is indebted, for such ‘secret operations’ 87) Aët. 4.21.4 (SVF 1.150), the translation of fvnçen in this passage as ‘power of speech’ in LSJ is wrong, but this is by the way. fvnh<tikÒ>n scripsi, for ps.Plutarch’s fvnÆn (kept by Diels, accepted by von Arnim, Mau, Lachenaud) does not make much sense, while the technical term for the vocal part of the soul is fvnhtikÒn: see SVF 1.143 (Nemes. nat.hom. p. 72.7-9 Morani, cf. below for Panaetius), 2.828 (D.L. 7.110, 157), 2.830 (Porph. de An. ap. Stob. 1.49.25a = fr. 253F Smith); Panaet. fr. 125 Alesse (Nemes. nat.hom. p. 72.9-11 Morani); add ps.Gal. Phil.Hist. 24, DG p. 615.3-10 Diels, where we are also told that the early 1st cent. BCE Stoic Mnesarchus (?—conjecture of Diels for ms. men°maxow and men°paxow) tÚ fvnhtikÚn <ka‹> tÚ spermatikÚn perie›len, ‘abolished the vocal and the seminal part’. The corruption in ps.Plutarch is old, for Qosta ibn Luqa translates Laut. Note that the excerpt of Aët. 4.21.4 at Thdt. CAG 5.20, quoted ad. loc. in the DG, has preserved tÚ fvnhtikÒn, and so has the excerpt at ps.Gal. Phil.Hist. 102, DG p. 638.27-39.1 Diels. 88) Aët. 4.21.4 (see previous n.), continued: pneËma diate›non épÚ toË ≤gemonikoË m°xri fãruggow ka‹ gl≈tthw ka‹ t«n ofike€vn Ùrgãnvn. Gal. PHP 5.3.7 (SVF 2.841), discussing the parts of the soul according to Chrysippus, mentions the pneËma ... fvnhtikÒn. I therefore believe that Gal. PHP 2.4.40, printed as a genuine Stoic fragment at SVF 2.893 and accepted by Sedley (1993, 330), was thought up by Galen to serve his polemics, for here the (psychic?) pneuma of the heart stamps the pneuma (i.e. breath) in the lungs, which then imprints in accordance with itself the pneuma (breath) in the windpipe. 34 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê (arcani motus) are paralleled several times by comparable expressions elsewhere in the in Timaeum. We have also encountered ‘hidden th in passages of Philo.89) 5. Theophrastus, Platonists, Aëtius again Theophrastus in the De sensibus famously criticizes Plato’s theory of sense-perception in Timaeus. We look at his remarks on hearing and voice. Plato, the Eresian tells us, T 12.1 defines hearing in terms of voice (ékoØn d¢ diå t∞w fvn∞w ır€zetai): for voice is a blow given by the air to the brain and blood through the ears till it reaches the soul; the motion caused by this blow and extending from the head to the liver is hearing.90) From ‘voice is a blow ...’ this is a quite accurate abridged rendering of Plato’s description in Timaeus.91) And ‘voice is a blow ... till it reaches the soul’ is repeated later 89) Calc. p. 153.23-5 Waszink, ‘sine voce et sono ratio est in intimis mentis penetralibus residens. haec autem differt ab oratione: est enim ratio interpres animo conceptae rationis’—cf. also above, text to n. 43, and esp. Calc. p. 178.21-79.1: God speaks ‘non illa sermone qui est positus in sono vocis ad declarandos motus intimos propter humanae mentis involucra’. Cf. the parallels for silent communication cited by Waszink ad loc. and cited and those discussed by Theiler (1954, 434-40 = 1966, 305-12); also see van der Stockt (1990, 183-4) for Plutarch (esp. Gen.Socr. 588C-89C), and Kirwan (1994, 208-11) for Augustine on this topic. 90) Sens. 6, ékoØn d¢ diå t∞w fvn∞w ır€zetai: fvnØn går e‰nai plhgØn Íp' é°row §gkefãlou ka‹ a·matow di' tvn m°xri cux∞w, tØn d' ÍpÚ taÊthw k€nhsin épÚ kefal∞w m°xri ¥patow ékoÆn. Translations of Sens. are Stratton’s, modified. Long (1996b, 352) points out that Theophrastus’ ‘report is impeccable and almost verbatim’. 91) Pl. Ti. 67b, ˜lvw m¢n oÔn fvnØn y«men tØn di' tvn Íp' é°row §gkefãlou te ka‹ a·matow m°xri cux∞w plhgØn diadidom°nhn, tØn d¢ Íp' aÈt∞w k€nhsin, épÚ t∞w kefal∞w m¢n érxom°nhn, teleut«san d¢ per‹ tØn toË ¥patow ßdran, ékoÆn. ‘In general, let us take it that voice is the 35 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê in the treatise, where it is made to function as a definition of voice.92) Finally, Theophrastus criticizes Plato’s definition (lÒgow) of voice as insufficient, for it T 12.2 is not equally applicable to all creatures (oÎte går koinÚw ëpasi to›w z– oiw); and he fails to state the cause of the perception though he wants to do so. Moreover he seems to be defining not sound or voice (tÚn cÒfon ka‹ tØn fvnÆn) but our sensory process.93) Theophrastus Sens. 6 and 91, when taken together, correspond in interesting ways to the Aëtian lemma quoted in the first section of this study. The etymological explicatio of fvnÆ is (unsurprisingly) absent, but several other ingredients are there. I quote Plac. 4.19.1 and Sens. 6 + 91 in facing columns, underlining expressions that are parallel either verbally or ad sententiam: ¶naryrÒw tØn pneËma diå …w fvt€zousa tÚ nooÊmenon. Aëtius Plãtvn §stin fvnØn ır€zetai stÒmatow épÚ diano€aw ±gm°non, ka‹ plhgØn ÍpÚ é°row §gkefãlou ka‹ tvn di' a·matow ka‹ m°xri Theophrastus cux∞w diadidom°nhn: ékoØn d¢ ır€zetai: plhgØn l°getai d¢ ka‹ kataxrhstik«w ka‹ §p‹ t«n élÒgvn z–vn fvnØ ka‹ cux∞w, t«n k€nhsin écÊxvn, …w xremetismo‹ ka‹ cÒfoi: kur€vw d¢ fvnØ ≤ diå t∞w fvn∞w fvnØn går e‰nai Íp' a·matow tØn é°row di' d' épÚ §gkefãlou tvn ÍpÚ kefal∞w m°xri taÊthw m°xri ¥patow ékoÆn. percussion of air by way of the ears upon the brain and the blood and transmitted to the soul, and that hearing is the motion caused by the percussion that begins in the head and ends in the place where the liver is situated’ (tr. Zeyl, modified). 92) Sens. 85. 93) Sens. 91. Good analysis of Theophrastus’ criticism at Ax (1986, 72-4). 36 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 §ndeest°rvw t∞w afisyÆsevw boulÒmenow. ¶ti d¢ fvn∞w e‡rhtai lÒgow: oÎte går oÈ tÚn cÒfon ka‹ tØn fvnÆn, koinÚw ëpasi to›w z–oiw §st‹n éllå oÎte ¶oiken éfor€zein. tØn <d¢> Phonê afit€an ka‹ ı l°gei t∞w tØn ≤met°ran a‡syhsin Wolfram Ax argues that in the first Aëtian definition ‘(voice is) pneËma, impelled from the mind through the mouth’ at Plac. 4.19.1 Plato’s accounts of voiceless, i.e. mental, and spoken lÒgow at Th. 206d (mental lÒgow also at Tht. 189e-190a) and Sph. 263e have been transformed into one of voice.94) He strikingly calls this transfer from lÒgow to fvnÆ “Umlemmatisierung des Originalbelegs”.95) One should add that the introduction of pneËma in this context (rhyming with and replacing =eËma) must be dependent on Stoic usage.96) Speaking of lÒgow in this context Plato uses other terms: at Tht. 206d =oÆ, at Sph. 263e =eËma (echoed [Pl.] Def. 414d). The ‘flow of lÒgoi streaming out’ is also mentioned Ti. 75e, lÒgvn nçma ¶jv =°on. The swap of pneËma for =eËma etc. may have also been stimulated by the fact that in the physical definition of hearing and voice at Ti. 67b (see further below) air is said to play a major role. Aristotle knows a doctrine (ultimately based on an interpretation and systematization of remarks on the senses in various paragraphs in Timaeus) according to which individual elements are coupled with individual senses. In this way ‘the capacity to 94) 95) Ax (1986, 78-9). See further below, section 6. See already Ingenkamp (1966, 80), who argues that the definition of fvnÆ as =eËma diå stÒmatow épÚ diano€aw at [Pl.] Def. 414d1 and the similar pneËma diå stÒmatow épÚ diano€aw ±gm°non in the Aëtian lemma (he speaks of the “Epitome” of “Plutarch”) suggest that “der Verfasser der Definition [viz., in Def. 414d] Platons lÒgow-Bestimmungen aus dem Theaitet und Sophistes vor Augen gehabt und absichtlich oder unabsichtlich die auch für fvnÆ sinnvolle ganze Definition des lÒgow zu fvnÆ gestellt hat.” 96) Baltussen (1993, 212 n. 6) and (2000, 235 n. 61). For the voice as a stream of pneËma from the mind to the speech organs see e.g. the verbatim fragment from Chrysippus’ On the Soul, ap. Gal. PHP 3.1.10-11 (SVF 2.885), and Aët. 4.21 (SVF 1.41, 2.835). Ti.Locr. 58, p. 200.4-6 Thesleff is different: here the pneËm (‘whose movement is hearing’) is not that of uttered speech but of perceived sound, which is situated in the ducts of the ears stretching to the liver. This is another attempt at modernization, see Baltes (1972, 1712). Note that Baltes (1972, 25) dates the tract to the 1st cent. BCE—1st cent. CE. 37 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê perceive sounds belongs to air’.97) This doctrine is famously adopted by Posidonius ‘explaining Timaeus’: ‘voice is grasped by airlike (éeroeidoËw) hearing’. It is also echoed in Aëtius, a lemma (in Stobaeus only) with the name-labels ‘Pythagoras Plato’: here it is the ‘breathlike’ element (tÚ pneumatikÒn) which gives rise to hearing.98) Air and breath (pneËma) are closely related;99) the Stoics held that pneËma is composed of air and fire. The use of pneËma in this context moreover gives Plato’s view a more actual scientific sense. It may also be relevant that the term =eËma is preserved in the next lemma, Aëtius 4.19.2, name-label Epicurus:100) a contrast between updated Plato (and his Stoic allies) and old-fashioned Epicurus may be intended. The second Aëtian definition at 4.19.1 is based on Ti. 67b, as we have seen.101) Because of the wording of this definition: ‘(voice is) a shock propagated by the air through the ears and brain and blood to the soul’, we should, I submit, in the first place think of the account of hearing at Ti. 67b as abridged by Theophrastus: Plato tØn di' tvn Íp' é°row §gkefãlou te ka‹ a·matow m°xri d¢ cux∞w k€nhsin, plhgØn diadidom°nhn, tØn Íp' kefal∞w aÈt∞w épÚ t∞w m¢n 97) Ar. Sens. 2.438b20. See further Baltes (1978, 187-9 = 1999, 38-40). 98) Posid. fr. 85 E.-K. (395a Theiler) ap. S.E. M. 7.93; Aët. 4.9.10 (in the chapter about the reliability of the senses), and Taurus fr. 26B Lakmann (33 Gioè) ap. Phlp. Aet.Mu. p. 520.15 Rabe, katå tÚn é°ra ≤ ékoÆ, Apul. de Plat. 1.209, Gal. PHP 7.5.49, Nemes. nat.hom. p. 56.9-10 Morani. See Baltes (1978, 195-6 = 1999, 49-50). Also cf. Plu. Gen.Socr. 589C, ı går éØr ... genÒmenow di' ˜lou lÒgow ka‹ fvnÆ. 99) Baltes (1978, 185 and 190 = 1999, 35 and 42). For the composition of the Stoic pneËma see SVF 2.310, 442, 796. 100) For this acoustic =eËma see Epicur. Ep.Hdt. (ap. D.L. 10) 52-3. 101) Ax (1986, 78-9, 105 n. 144); cf. above, nn. 5 and 93. The Platonic definition of hearing at Aët. 4.16.4 is not an acceptable quotation or paraphrase of Ti. 67b, because this passage is “vage und mit fremder Begrifflichkeit angedeutet” (Ax 1986, 80-1; cf. Whittaker 1990, 124 n. 343, and Baltussen 1993, 210, and 2000, 233). A similar sloppy formula is found Gal. Plat.Tim. 15.23-6, see Kraus-Walzer ad loc. 31 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê érxom°nhn, d' teleut«san k€nhsin épÚ Theophrastus kefal∞w m°xri plhgØn Íp' é°row §gkefãlou a·matow m°xri d¢ ¥patow taÊthw ¥patow ékoÆn. tvn cux∞w, tØn tØn toË ßdran, plhgØn ÍpÚ é°row di' tvn ka‹ §gkefãlou ka‹ a·matow m°xri cux∞w ka‹ di' per‹ ÍpÚ Aëtius diadidom°nhn. toË ¥patow ßdran, ékoÆn. ékoÆn. d¢ per‹ tØn Han Baltussen has argued that this part of Aëtius’ text is closer to Plato’s original than to Theophrastus’ excerpt, so has been excerpted from the passage in the dialogue.102) But the tripartite comparison above shows how close the Aëtian sentence in fact is to the first half of the phrase in the De sensibus. There is, to be sure, a minor difference in word order: Plato has ears, air, brain, blood; Theophrastus air, brain, blood, ears; Aëtius air, ears, brain, blood. So the ears, first in Plato, come last in Theophrastus and second in Aëtius. Baltussen is of course right in pointing out that Aëtius’ diadidom°nhn (‘transmitted’) is lacking in Theophrastus and must have been imported from Timaeus.103) The question, however, is whether this has happened directly or via an intermediary tradition. I prefer to assume that retrograde contamination has taken place, viz. of (a text based on) the excerpt in Theophrastus’ De sensibus with the Platonic original, or possibly even with another source based on Timaeus, or an epitome of, or excerpt from, this dialogue. One may point out that diadidom°nhn is quite successful as an epitomists’ substitute for Theophrastus’ phrase tØn d' ÍpÚ taÊthw k€nhsin épÚ kefal∞w m°xri ¥patow ékoÆn (‘the motion caused by this blow and extending from the head to the liver is hearing’). 102) 103) Baltussen (1993, 210-3) and—a shade modified—(2000, 234-7). Baltussen (1993, 212) and (2000, 236-7). Teun Tieleman points out to me that diad€dosyai became a standard technical term for the transmission of impressions etc. in physiological theory, cf. e.g. Gal. PHP. 2.5.35. 2 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê The catalogue of Aristotle’s writings in Diogenes Laërtius lists a (lost) monograph containing abstracts (i.e. an epitome) from Timaeus and from the works of Archytas, tå §k toË Tima€ou ka‹ t«n ÉArxute€vn aÄ.104) We do not know for how long this may have been available; but an epitome of Timaeus may have been one of the sources of Timaeus Locrus.105) A (to some extent Stoicized) epitome of the first part of the cosmology of Timaeus also containing material deriving from other dialogues is part of Diogenes Laërtius presentation of Plato’s philosophy.106) The paragraph on hearing (Ti. 67b) moreover was quite well known. It was not only one of the starting-points of the theory concerned with the relation between the elements and the senses,107) but was also cited or paraphrased in texts dealing with Plato’s physical doctrine of hearing, such as that of Alcinous.108) The whole of Ti. 67a-c is quoted (following upon Aët. 16.1-4) at Stobaeus 1.53, the (remains of the) chapter On Hearing. And it has been generally overlooked that Porphyry quotes, and comments upon, Ti. 67b (and 67c, less relevant here), ı dØ Plãtvn §n t“ Tima€ƒ per€ te fvn∞w ka‹ éko∞w diaforçw te fvn∞w dialegÒmenow grãfei taËta ktl.109) He refers to what he claims to be the wrong view of ‘the Platonists without exception’ (ofl Platvniko‹ pãntew èpajapl«w) who understand Plato’s plhgÆ in a passive sense, viz. as a plhgØ é°row instead of (as Plato says disertis verbis) a plhgØ Íp' é°row, and insists that we should think of ‘the effect of this blow upon the listeners’ (katå … tÚ §nerge›n tØn plhgØn efiw toÁw ékoÊontaw). We have seen that (unlike Porphyry’s Platvniko€) both Theophrastus and the Aëtian lemma preserve Íp' é°row. 110) It is clear that our Timaeus passage on 104) D.L. 5.25. 105) Thus Baltes (1972, 24-5). 106) D.L. 3. 67-77. 107) Above, n. 98 and text thereto. 108) Cf. below, n. 119. 109) Porph. in Harm. p. 46.3-47.12 Düring. diaforçw fvn∞w pertains to the sequel about pitch accent, which is not relevant here. 110) Porphyry apparently did not know, or neglects, Plutarch’s paraphrase (esp. Plat.Qu. 1006B, ¶sti går ≤ fvnØ plhgØ toË afisyanom°nou di' 33 tvn Íp' é°row). We may © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê hearing was discussed, or used, by more Platonists then we know of. Furthermore, the participle diadidom°nh found in Aëtius is not only paralleled in Alcinous’ paraphrase, but also in Porphyry’s and Stobaeus’ excerpts. Timaeus Locrus paraphrases it with diiknoum°na.111) Baltussen claims that Aëtius’ xremetismo‹ ka‹ cÒfoi (which he calls “animalnoises”) derive from a passage in Plato’s Republic about imitating animals, and e.g. the sea, on stage.112) But the Aëtian lemma explicitly echoes what had become a standard distinction between sounds produced by humans, animals, and lifeless things respectively, the xremetismo€ representing animal ‘voices’, the cÒfoi (‘sounds’) those of things. What cannot be paralleled in Plato (as Baltussen correctly argues) is the terminological distinction between ‘voice’ in the ‘proper sense’, according to which it pertains to humans, and in the ‘loose (or: improper) sense’ in which it may also pertain to animals and things. Though it has been shown that most of the time Plato does use fvnÆ of humans,113) a rigorous distinction between them and the rest is never formulated in his oeuvre. But as we have noted it is presupposed in Theophrastus’ critique of Plato’s use of fvnÆ; no wonder, since Aristotle had done much to clarify the difference between observe that Porphyry’s criticism is to some erxtent captious, for the formula Íp' é°row is ambiguous. Other cases in Plutarch look more vulnerable but are in fact equivalent (Fort. 98B, plhg∞w é°row di' »tÚw ka‹ §gkefãlou prosferom°nhw, Def.Or. 436D, ékoÊein d¢ tª plhgª toË é°row). And plhgØ é°row is attributed to Plato in dialectico/doxographical passages (cf. above, n. 8) such as S D.T. p. 482.9 Hilgard (cf. ibid. p. 181.7, without Plato’s name); already Gell. N.A. 4.15.7, where Plato himself is made to reject the first part of the Stoic definition of voice (see above, n. 53), a phrase followed by a free paraphrase of Ti. 67b.: ‘Plato autem non esse corpus putat: “non enim percussus`’, inquit, “aer, sed plaga ipsa atque percussio, id vox est”. 111) Ti.Locr. 58, p. 220.4 Thesleff. 112) Pl. R. 396b; Baltussen (1993, 213) and (2000, 236-7). cÒfow in this sense (and without further qualifications) seems to be specifically Aristotelian, see Ax (1986, 122-6). 113) Ax (1986, 102-13). 34 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê articulate and significant sound on the one hand and other kinds of sound on the other.114) And because it is not exclusively Stoic, I cannot agree with Baltussen’s view that “the concept of ‘articulate phônê’ here is certainly Stoic”,115) though I accept that the specific technical formula looks like being originally Stoic.116) His conclusion that the gist of Theophrastus’ critical remark is only “remotely akin to the [second half of the] Aëtian passage”117) should be revised. The relationship is closer, for Theophrastus, as we have seen, severely criticizes Plato’s indiscriminate use of fvnÆ for all living beings. We may perhaps render Ax’s Umlemmatisierung into English as ‘translemmatization’, and may well ask what is the cause of this modification in the present case. I believe that someone at some time stood Theophrastus’ criticism on its head. Theophrastus in his critique says that Plato defines hearing through voice; in order to defend Plato we react by starting with voice straightaway. Theophrastus criticizes Plato (from a Peripatetic point of view rightly, one may say) for using fvnÆ in a broad sense, according to which it applies to both humans and other living beings. This we admit, but we stipulate that (of course!) he distinguished between the proper and the loose (or: improper) use of the word so knew what he was doing. This person must have been a Platonist. Confirmation is fortunately forthcoming. It has been noticed that the account of sense-perception and its objects in chapters 19 and 20 of Alcinous’ Didascalicus has been significantly influenced by Theophrastus’ 114) Ax (1986, 98 n. 119, 130-8) and (1993, 18-9) on Aristotle on diãlektow, diãryrvsiw, and lÒgow. Cf. also Dierauer (1977, 234-5), Sorabji (1993, 81), Schenkeveld (1999, 185). 115) Baltussen (1993, 212 n. 56) and (2000, 235 n. 31). 116) The formula is attested twice in the verbatim fragment SVF 3 Diog. 29 ap. Gal. PHP 2.5.9 cited above, n. 73; cf. further D.L. 7.55 (SVF 3 Diog. 17), S.E. M. 7.38 (SVF 2.132) and 8.275-6 (SVF 2.135/223), cf. above, n. 48. Already for Philo fvnåw §nãryrouw, ‘articulate utterances’, belong with the domain of ‘grammar’ (grammatikª), see Opif. 126 and above, n. 47. 117) Baltussen (1993, 211) and (2000, 235). 35 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê discussion of Plato’s views in the De sensibus.118) Little attention however has been paid to the first sentence of ch. 19, which states that ‘hearing has come into being for the cognizance of voice’.119) This is translemmatization with a vengeance: the whole purpose of hearing turns out to be knowledge of ‘voice’. Theophrastus’ criticism has been successfully neutralized. So Plato is updated, not only in Alcinous (or rather in the tradition upon which Alcinous depends), but also, and even much more so, in the Aëtian lemma. The Stoics had given the part of logic dealing with ‘voice’ a prominent position on the philosophical agenda. Earlier philosophers, esp. Aristotle, had dealt with various aspects of this theme in different works and contexts; the Stoics brought all this together, made it more systematic, and considerably revised and added to it. The majority of the Stoics, Diogenes Laërtius tells us, ‘are agreed that dialectical theory begins with the part (tÒpow) dealing with voice’.120) Porphyry tells us that the Early Academic Xenocrates too began dialectic with ‘voice’, but all that is further attributed to him is a distinction between scriptible and 118) Whittaker (1987, 104-5) and (1990, 124-5; and first apparatus ad loc.), followed by Dillon (1993, 143-5) and Baltussen (2002, 44). 119) Alc. p. 173.42 Hermann, ékoØ d¢ g°gone prÚw fvn∞w gn«sin. This is p. 173.42- 174.4 followed by érxom°nh m¢n épÚ t∞w per‹ tØn kefalØn kinÆsevw, teleut«sa d¢ per‹ ¥patow ßdran: ≤ d¢ fvnÆ §stin ≤ di' tvn §rxom°nh §gkefãlou te ka‹ a·matow, diadidom°nh d¢ m°xri cux∞w plhgÆ, ‘beginning from a movement situated in the head, and terminating in the seat of the liver. Sound is a blow transmitted through the ears, the brain, and the blood, and penetrating as far as the soul’ (tr. Dillon); ‘physical’ definition based on Ti. 67b (quoted above, n. 91) again. Whittaker (1990, 124 n. 342) submits that “Alcinoos a oublié de préciser que le son est transmis Íp'é°row”. But if the criticism voiced by Porphyry (above, text after n. 109) was already known to Alcinous (or his tradition), the words Íp' é°row may have been omitted on purpose. Tim.Locr. 58, p. 220.4 Thesleff has §n é°ri. 120) D.L. 7.55 (SVF 2.136), t∞w d¢ dialektik∞w yevr€aw sumf≈nvw doke› to›w ple€stoiw épÚ toË per‹ fvn∞w §nãrxesyai tÒpou. This is followed by Diogenes’ definition cited above, n. 78 and below, text to n. 124. For the Stoic revision of earlier efforts see Ax (1986, 152-62) and (1993, 12-5, 17); for the tÒpow in general see Schenkeveld (1999, 184-6). 36 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê musical and melodious voice.121) Melodious voice is mentioned in the Stoic tÒpow on voice,122) but as far as one can see it is quite unimportant in this context, while in Xenocrates it is the second subdivision. Even so, the position of Xenocrates may not only have influenced the Stoics to some extent, but will also have been a factor of some weight in so top speak preparing Platonic doctrine for its updating modo Stoico. One may add that in the group of grammatical and logical definitions in the pseudo-Platonic Definitiones,123) itself undoubtedly attesting a modernization of Platonic doctrine, diãlektow (‘phrase’) is two times said to be ‘without melody’, êneu m°louw— could this be an echo of Xenocrates’ main division? We have seen that the Stoic Diogenes of Seleucia is the first philosopher on record to have distinguished sharply between lÒgow, or the meaningful articulate voice of human adults sent out from the mind, and the (eventually but not necessarily also articulate and meaningful) voices, or utterances, of other living beings sent out from impulse.124) It is precisely this distinction which is at the basis of the statement at Aët. 4.19.1, ‘in a loose (or: improper) sense ‘voice’ is also used in the case of irrational animals and lifeless things, such as whinnyings and mere noises, but in the proper sense it is articulate voice’. At the end of another Aëtian lemma a comparable point of view is formulated, one book further down: T 13 Pythagoras Plato (hold) that also the souls of so-called irrational animals are rational, but not rationally active because of the bad composition of their bodies, and because they 121) Fr. 10 Heinze = fr. 88 Isnardi Parente ap. Porph. in Harm. P. 8.20-30 Düring, §st‹ t∞w fvn∞w tÚ m¢n toioËton, oÂon §k grammãtvn sugke›syai, tÚ d¢ toioËton, oÂon §k diasthmãtvn te ka‹ fyÒggvn. See Frede (1978, 50 = 1987, 319), Ax (1986, 160-1). 122) In the short account of dialectic, D.L. 7.44 (FDS 474), see Schenkeveld (1990b, 303). 123) [Pl.] Def. 414d-e. I cannot deal with this rather neglected passage here. No comment on the formula êneu m°louw in Ingenkamp (1966); parallels S D.T. p. 451.4 Hilgard, Dicaearch. fr. 89 Wehrli. Def. is generally believed to be Academic, see Ingenkamp (1966, 8-12, 110-4); the earliest and first attestation is in the lexigographer Ammonius (1st-2nd cent. CE ?), the second in Olympiodorus (Ingenkamp 1966, 104, 112). 124) Cf. above, n. 78 and text thereto. 37 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê lack the apparatus for speaking, as in the case of apes and dogs; for they prattle, but do not speak.125) This tenet distinguishes between between humans and other living beings as to their utterances. The animals’ inability to speak is attributed entirely to their bodily constitution.126) The view that they have rational souls can be paralleled in the so-called Pythagorean Hypomnêmata preserved in Diogenes Laërtius, and in the tradition upon which Philo, Aenesidemus in Sextus Empiricus, and Porphyry depend in the passages referred to above.127) Note that only the final colon of T 13, viz. ‘they prattle but do not speak’, provides a parallel to what is at Aët. 4.19.1. But as we have seen the refusal to allow ‘speech’ to animals is not consistent with Plato’s own attitude. Such attempts to attribute a more up-to-date view to Plato can be paralleled in the paragraph on fvnÆ in the so-called Divisiones Aristoteleae which purportedly report Plato’s doctrine: a short abstract at D.L. 3.107, a longer version in Marcianus gr. 257.128) 125) Aët. 5.20.4 (ps.Plutarch only), PuyagÒraw Plãtvn logikåw m¢n e‰nai ka‹ t«n élÒgvn z–vn kaloum°nvn tåw cuxãw, oÈ mØn logik«w §nergoÊsaw parå tØn duskras€an t«n svmãtvn ka‹ t“ mØ ¶xein tÚ frastikÒn, frãzousi d°. 126) Cf. e.g. Porph. Abst. 3.4.6, some animals ‘do not speak because they are thwarted by their vocal organs’, t“ ÍpÚ t«n Ùrgãnvn t«n t∞w fvn∞w §mpod€zesyai. This ultimately goes back to Ar. HA 4.9.535a27-b3. 127) For the Pyth.Hyp. see Burkert (1972, 75). He also compares what he calls ‘the Stoic’ doctrine of internal and uttered speech, but according to the Stoics the fundamental difference between humans and beasts is not a matter of uttered but one of internal speech (see above, n. 48 and text thereto). Gal. Protr. 1, p. 103.2-6 Marquardt, knows this doctrine too but does not attribute it to specific people; he says that though maybe ‘all (animals) do not possess speech (lÒgow) in respect of voice, which they call uttered (proforikÒn), they share in that in respect of soul, which they call internal (§ndiãyeton)—some more, some less’. See Sorabji (1993, 80 with n. 21). For Philo, Sextus, and Porphyry see above, n. 61 and text thereto. 128) Tabarroni (1988, 108 n. 12) compares D.L. 3.107 and Aët. 4.19.1. Baltussen (1993, 211 n. 55) and (2000, 235 n. 30) too refers to D.L. 3.107 only. I quote from the obsolete edition of 38 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê Though the version in Diogenes Laërtius is formulated as a bipartite division into ‘animate’ and ‘inanimate’, its first part, ‘animate’, is further subdivided into articulate (humans) and inarticulate (animals). The longer version presents a division into four. First, voice is divided into animate and inanimate, just as in Diogenes Laërtius; then into ‘in letters’/‘scriptible’ (§ggrãmmatow) and ‘not in letters’/‘unscriptible’ (égrãmmatow). Animate voice is that of living beings, inanimate voice is ‘e.g. sounds and noises and the voice of the lyre and the flutes’. ‘Scriptible’ is the ‘voice of men and of some animals, e.g. nightingales and swallows and sparrows and the like, unscriptible the unarranged (édiãyetow) voice, such as cluckings and sounds and noises and the like’. The word édiãyetow (not at D.L. 3.107) can only be paralleled in late authors. It would seem that whoever is responsible for this unhistoric scholastic exercise attempted to bring Plato in line with a more Peripatetic point of view.129) 6. Plato interpretatus To sum up. The ingredients of the first lemma of Aëtius’ chapter On Voice (4.19.1) can be shown to be Platonic, or ‘Platonic’. It has long been seen that the formula ‘breath (pneËma) impelled from the mind through the mouth’ is a Stoicized version (pneËma !) of the ‘stream’ or ‘flow’of speech described in Plato’s Theaetetus, Sophist, Philebus, and Timaeus (=eËma, or =oÆ, or nçma, of lÒgow, or lÒgvn, from the diãnoia, or cuxÆ, or frÒnhsiw through and from the mouth, diå toË stÒmatow, ¶jv =°on).130) The translemmatization, or transfer from lÒgow to Mutschmann (1906). Div.Arist. is now believed to be (Early) Academic, see e.g. Rossitto, 1984 (and 200-2 on the present passage), but the text of such manuals is unstable, as the various mss. versions show; see Dorandi (1996). 129) Mutschmann ad loc., followed by Rossitto (1984, 202), aptly quotes Ar. de An. 2.8.420b5- 10. 130) Tht. 206d quoted below n. 137, Sph. 263e quoted below n. 145, Ti. 75e quoted below n. 141 (for nçma cf. Phdr. 235d), Phlb. 17b (only fvnØ … diå toË stÒmatow fioËsa). 39 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê fvnÆ of the descriptive formula, is paralleled in the spurious Definitiones, where the original term =eËma has been preserved.131) The fact that the location of the mind in the body (according to Plato this was the head, according to the Stoics the heart) 132) is left undecided in this Aëtian chapter helps the re-formulation of the Platonic =eËma etc. as pneËma. The formula ‘shock propagated by the air through the ears and brain and blood to the soul’ is an abridged version of a passage in Timaeus.133) This descriptive formula too has been transferred to fvnÆ—but from Plato’s account of hearing, ékoÆ, a translemmatization paralleled in the Middle Platonist author Alcinous. Xenocrates is said to have begun dialectic with a treatment of voice. More important, however, is the fact that the Stoics did so too and, as far as we can see, in a much more systematic and influential fashion. The updating of Plato in the first part of the lemma is indeed indebted to the Stoic example.134) The added comment, viz.: ‘in a loose (or: improper) sense ‘voice’ is also used in the case of irrational animals and lifeless things, such as whinnyings <und Eselsgeschrei ?> and mere noises, but in the proper sense it is articulate voice’ is more difficult to determine. I have argued that someone who knew his Plato well (and had seen Theophrastus’ critique) was aware of the fact that the master mostly, though not exclusively, uses fvnÆ of the human voice. Updating Plato in this case meant applying to him the rigorous Stoic distinction between humans and animals, and rewriting his doctrine in a more up-to-date terminology: ‘articulate voice’, and ‘in a loose (or: improper) sense / in the proper sense’.135) We are left with the etymological definition of fvnÆ ad finem, articulate human voice ‘considered as illuminating what is thought’, which describes the function of voice as making what is thought accessible. This etymology cannot be paralleled in such evidence 131) Def. 414d. For this translemmatization see above, nn. 94 and 95, and text thereto. 132) I have discussed part of the evidence at Mansfeld (1990, 3092-3107), starting from another Aëtian chapter, viz. 4.5, t€ tÚ t∞w cux∞w ≤gemonikÚn ka‹ §n t€ni §st€n. 133) Ti. 67b, quoted above n. 91. 134) Above, sections 4 and 5. 135) Above, section 4. 40 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê for Stoic philosophy as is still available. That it is at least Hellenistic, and must have been quite familiar, is proved by the fact that in some form or other it was known e.g. to the grammarian Philoxenus (late 1st cent. BCE), the Platonizing exegete Philo of Alexandria (early 1st cent. CE), and Heraclitus the Allegorist (perhaps 1st cent. CE). A similar etymology was used by the grammarian Seleucus (early 1st cent. CE).136) I believe that this formula, too, should be interpreted as a modernization of something in Plato. We should look again at the passage in Theaetetus, where Socrates says: T 14.1 The first [sc., meaning of lÒgow] would be making one’s thought visible through voice by means of names and verbs—when a man impresses his opinion upon the stream through the mouth, as if upon water or in a mirror. Don’t you think this kind of thing is speech (lÒgow)?137) The crucial bit is tÚ tØn aÍtoË diãnoian §mfan∞ poie›n diå fvn∞w, ‘to make one’s thought visible through voice’ (my emphasis). The locution §mfan∞ poie›n is surprisingly rare.138) That thought, or mental speech, is so to speak made visible is further emphasized by the illuminating image added by Plato: thought is reflected in voice as in a mirror, or as upon the surface of water. This however could entail that spoken language is inferior to mental speech, for according to a well-known passage in the Republic images in water and other mirroring surfaces represent the lowest mode of cognition. Furthermore, a few pages down in Theaetetus lÒgow in the sense described in T 14.1 is said to be ‘so to speak the image (e‡dvlon, my emphasis) of 136) Above, sections 2 and 3. 137) Tht. 206d, tÚ m¢n pr«ton e‡h ín tÚ tØn aÍtoË diãnoian §mfan∞ poie›n diå fvn∞w metå =hmãtvn te ka‹ Ùnomãtvn, Àsper efiw kãtoptron µ Ïdvr tØn dÒjan §ktupoÊmenon efiw tØn diå toË stÒmatow =oÆn. µ oÈ doke› soi tÚ toioËton lÒgow e‰nai; A definition of lÒgow meaning ‘account’ is provided by giving a far too wide definition of lÒgow meaning ‘speech’. Cf. Chiesa (1991, 303). Sedley believes this passsage influenced Diogenes’ physicalistic description of significant speech, but see above, n. 75, and below, p. 000 f., Appendix. 138) Mostly found in later authors; in Plato only paralleled Lg. 634c. 41 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê mind [i.e., thinking mind] in voice’, and we know that in Plato an image of something is on a lower level than what it is an image of. 139) We should also acknowledge that earlier in the dialogue Plato presents the part of this tenet concerned with what is going on inside because he wishes to define (silent) opinion (Socrates again): T 14.1a to opine I call ‘speak’ and opinion ‘speech that has been said’—not to someone else and not with voice, but silently to oneself.140) 139) Tht. 208c—Chiesa’s view (1992, 26) that e‡dvlon here is “neutre” is arbitrary, but note that he also discusses its “connotations négatives” “même dans le corpus platonicien”; for examples in Tht. cf. 150b-51c, 191d (the quality of the impression varies because it depends on that of the receiving material). Further Platonic passages on speech at Derbolav (1972, 187-94), who however fails to mention Tht. 206d in this context. Plutarch states that ‘verbs and names’ are mere ‘images and likenesses of what is thought’ see van der Stockt (1990, 181-2), but links this up with the Aristotelian notion of ‘symbols’ (Gen. Socr. 589C, =hmãtvn oÈd' Ùnomãtvn, oÂw xr≈menoi prÚw éllÆlouw ofl ênyrvpoi sumbÒloiw e‡dvla t«n nooum°nvn ka‹ efikÒnaw ır«sin). Context is decisive; as Teun Tieleman points out to me, Phd. 99d-100a is more positive than Rep. 510a, 510e about looking at reflections in water. But note that Socrates is ironic and even a bit reluctant (100a, oÈ går pãnu sugxvr« tÚn §n to›w lÒgoiw skopoÊmenon tå ˆnta §n efikÒsi mçllon skope›n µ tÚn §n to›w ¶rgoiw). Tht. 208c is echoed Plot. 5.1 [10] 3.7-8 and paraphrased 1.2 [19] 3.27-8; here the hierarchy is very clear. 140) Tht. 189e-90a, tÚ dojãzein l°gein kal« ka‹ tØn dÒjan lÒgon efirhm°non, oÈ m°ntoi prÚw êllon oÈd¢ fvnª, éllå sigª prÚw aÍtÒn. Sedley (1993, 331 with n. 70) believes that the ‘internal speech’ (i.e. the lÒgow §ndiãyetow) at S.E. M. 275-6 (cf. above, n. 48) derives from this Theaetetus passage, but at the very least it does not do so directly (cf. above, n. 75); we have moreover seen in section 4 above that the pair ‘internal’/’uttered speech’ was very widely used. Also note the emphasis on opinion in the full Platonic sense both in this passage and in T 14.2a below; for this aspect of Tht. 189a-90e (and Sph. 263d-64b) see Chiesa (1992, 18), and Trabattoni (2002, 176-7): “il passo platonico ... non ha come suo scopo quello di dire che cos’è il pensiero, ma piuttosto di dire appunto che cos’è la dÒja”. 42 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê That ‘the flow of lÒgoi streaming out [i.e., uttered speech] which is subservient to thought’ is praised as ‘the most beautiful and best of all flows’ at Ti. 75e141) is presumably due to a difference of context rather than a change of mind, for in Timaeus this outgoing stream is set off against that of food and drink which goes in. But the point that uttered speech ministers to thought entails that it is thought which is in command and so is superior, and therefore is consistent with the hierarchy implied in Theaetetus. The metaphor of speech as the ‘servant’ of the mind is close to that of speech as its ‘interpreter’, which we have encountered in philo-Platonic later authors such as Cicero, Philo of Alexandria, and Calcidius.142) We have seen that the connection between mental and spoken language argued by Chrysippus, Diogenes of Seleucia and other Stoics appears to have led to the widely occurring technicality ‘internal speech’ / ‘uttered speech’.143) It has long been seen (but as a rule the all-important differences have been ignored) that this combination plus distinction is to some extent anticipated by Plato, not only in the Theaetetus passage just quoted, but also elsewhere; such passages have already been referred to above, in various contexts.144) Another well-known passage we may look at again is in Sophist—the visitor from Elea (V.) is addressing Theaetetus (Th.): T 14.2 V.: Aren’t thought and speech the same, except that what we call thought is a dialogue with itself [sc. of the soul with the soul] that occurs without the voice inside the 141) tÚ d¢ lÒgvn nçma ¶jv =°on ka‹ ÍphretoËn fronÆsei kãlliston ka‹ êriston. Cf. the paraphrase Apul. de Plat. 1.212, ‘quae prudentia corde conceperit, ea sensa promat oratio’. 142) Above, text to n. 44, and n. 86. 143) Above, section 4. 144) E.g. above, nn. 5, 91, text to nn. 59, 101, 103, and text to n. 130. The Aristotelian parallel already cited by Zeller (above, n. 59), and then by Pohlenz (above, n. 57 and text to n. 59) who is followed by others, viz. Ar. APo. 1.10.76b24 oÈ går prÚw tÚn ¶jv lÒgon ≤ épÒdeijiw, éllå prÚw tÚn §n tª cuxª, is not so significant, because lÒgow here means ‘argument’; the parallel with Plato only obtains when the phrase is quoted out of context. For lÒgow as ‘speech’ in Aristotle see Pol. 1.2.1253a7-18 with Schütrumpf ad loc. (1991, 2125), and Sens. 1.437a9-17 where the doctrine of Int. chs. 1 and 4 is presupposed. 43 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê soul? Th.: Of course. V.: And the stream from the soul that goes through the mouth accompanied by sound is called speech?145) But this time too the tenet is presented in order to determine opinion: T 14.2a When this [viz., affirmation of denial] takes place silently in the mind in the soul, can you call it anything but opinion?146) Sph. 263e-64b is the first of the three abstracts from Plato which (now) constitute Stobaeus’ chapter On Opinion (1.53, per‹ dojhw). Quotations or paraphrases of Sph. 263e in other sources147) as a rule do not take the doxastic aspect into account. An important difference between Plato’s view of the relation between thought and speech and that of the Stoics discussed above (in section 4) is that the hierarchical 145 ) Sph. 263e, JE. oÈkoËn diãnoia m¢n ka‹ lÒgow taÈtÒn: plØn ı m¢n §ntÚw t∞w cux∞w prÚw aÍtØn diãlogow êneu fvn∞w gignÒmenow toËt' aÈtÚ ≤m›n §pvnomãsyh, diãnoia; YEAI. pãnu m¢n oÔn. tÚ d° g' ép' §ke€nhw (sc., t∞w cux∞w) =eËma diå toË stÒmatow fiÚn metå fyÒggou k°klhtai lÒgow; Cf. Chiesa (1991, 302-3); but there is no need to distinguish with Chiesa (1992, 18) the “structure profonde”, viz. the “identité du langage et de la pensée”, from the “structure superficielle” indicated by the “clause restrictive” beginning with plÆn. Note however that Chiesa’s discussion of the ambiguities of the Platonic passages (ibid., 19-22, 24) sometimes comes close to the view argued in the present paper. As to the tradition concerned with the Sophist passage, see the version in the handbook of Alcinous, who omits êneu fvn∞w (possibly a case of Stoic influence), p. 155.17-20 Hermann: tØn d¢ diãnoiãn fhsi tÚn aÈt∞w t∞w cux∞w prÚw aÍtØn diãlogon, lÒgon d¢ tÚ ép' §ke€nhw =eËma diå toË stÒmatow xvroËn metå fyÒggou, that of Calc. p. 153.23-5 Waszink quoted above, n. 89, and that of Nemes. nat.hom. p. 71.9-10 Morani, ¶sti d¢ §ndiãyetow m¢n lÒgow tÚ k€nhma t∞w cux∞w tÚ §n t“ dialogistik“ ginÒmenon êneu tinÚw §kfvnÆsevw (note the intrusion of §ndiãyetow … lÒgow). 146) Sph. 264a, ˜tan oÔn toËto §n cuxª katå diãnoian §gg€gnhtai metå sig∞w, plØn dÒjhw ¶xeiw ˜ti prose€p˙w aÈtÒ; 147) See above, n. 145. 44 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê ordering which is part of Plato’s descriptions is lacking in the verbatim or quasi-verbatim Stoic evidence.148) The etymological explicatio concluding the Aëtian lemma on Plato on voice too does not show any trace of a such a distinction. So this is the extent to which Plato’s view has been Stoicized: no hierarchy involved. I do not know who first thought of the etymologies of fvnÆ as fvt€zousa tÚ nooÊmenon, or as fvtonÒh, or as faonÆ, or as derived from f≈w or f«w, or from f«/fa€nv. Several of these derivations could be quite early, just as the related etymology of fantas€a from fãow or f«w, which is not only found in Stoic texts but already in Aristotle.149) However this may be, what I think happened is that someone modernized the striking formula found in Theaetetus by replacing it with an equivalent (and apparently quite popular) etymological explanation. Thus Plato’s incidental remarks concerned with speech, voice, and hearing in Theaetetus, Sophist and Timaeus were abstracted from their context, and coalesced to form a single account dedicated to voice, just as the Stoics had assembled and then worked out much further the suggestions of their predecessors in order to create a single tÒpow per‹ fvn∞w. And these remarks were modernized by borrowings from other philosophical traditions, esp. from Peripatetic (think e.g. of Theophrastus’ De sensibus) and Stoic philosophy. This is typical of so-called Middle Platonism.150) We may suppose this Platonist Per‹ fvn∞w to have contained more than is now to be found in the 148) See Chiesa (1992, 24-5) on the lÒgow §ndiãyetow and proforikÒw; cf. also above, n. 59. 149) Chrysippus ap. Aët. 4.12.2 (SVF 2.54) on which see Long and Sedley (1987 Vol, 1, 239), Long (1999, 572); cf. S.E. M. 7.162 (SVF 2.63); Arist. de An. 3.2.429a1-4. Tabarroni (1988, 107 n. 9) correctly points out that the etymology of fvnÆ from f«w “is highly reminiscent of the Chrysippean derivation of representation (phantasia) from light (phôs)” but has missed the passage in Aristotle. 150) Excellent surveys in Runia (1986, 49-52, 495-9). See further Whittaker (1987, 110-4) on “The Aristotelian component in Middle Platonism” and (ibid., 114-7) on “The Stoic component in Middle Platonism”. 45 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê abstract in the Placita, which does not give us much more than the first section of a treatment of Voice. Perhaps a bit more is extant in the pseudo-Platonic Definitiones.151) The Didascalicus of Alcinous may be the best known example of this approach to Plato; think for instance of the results of a scan of the Platonic dialogues for anticipations of Aristotle’s syllogistic in ch. 6.152) The revised and abridged Timaeus which constitutes the De naturae mundi et animae of pseudo-Timaeus Locrus is another example. This author (or rather the tradition to which he belongs) too is capable of appropriating Stoic and Peripatetic material as Platonic.153) Several of the ancient sources referred to above also modernize Plato’s doctrine in other respects, e,g, as to the function of the liver.154) Accordingly, I believe that we should position the immediate source for Aët. 4.19.1, ‘Plato On Voice’, in a Middle Platonist context.155) Appendix: Imprinted Wax According to Democritus the air between the visual organ and the thing seen is ‘imprinted’, cf. Thphr. Sens. 50, tupoËsyai, ibid. to›w épotupoum°noiw; 51, épotÊpvsiw, tÚ tupoÊmenon, épotÊpvsin; 53, tÊpvsiw, §napotupoËsyai; esp. Sens. 51, quasiverbatim: Àsper ka‹ aÈtÚw l°gei parabãllvn toiaÊthn e‰nai tØn §ntÊpvsin, oÂon efi §kmãjeiaw efiw khrÒn, ‘even as Democritus himself, in illustrating the character of the “impression”, says that “it is as if one were to take a mould in wax” ‘(tr. Stratton; taken up 52, efi d¢ dØ toËto sumba€nei ka‹ ı éØr épomãttetai kayãper khrÒw, ‘if such an imprint occurs and the air is moulded like wax’). Note that Friedländer (1960, 456-7 n. 60) refuses to accept khrÒn, (unsuccessfully) 151) Cf. above, n. 123 and text thereto. 152) See e.g. Whittaker (1990, xxi-ix) on vocabulary, modernization, quotation out of context, and his commentary (passim) on doctrine, and Dillon (1993, xxx-xl) on doctrine. 153) Baltes (1972, 25) argues that the tract is partly based on classes where the teacher used “das Material der Stoa und des Peripatos als letzlich platonisches Eigentum”. 154 See Tieleman (1996, xxix, and esp. xxxi). 155) For other Middle Platonist elements in the Placita see Tarrant (2000, 75-6). 46 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê defends ms. sklhrÒn, and of course argues that kayãper khrÒw is Theophrastean not Democritean; he flatly denies that Democritus is quoted at Sens. 51 and clearly holds Democritean influence to be infra dignitatem Platonis. The tÊpvsiw, naturally, cannot be denied, see e.g. Baldes (1975). One should add that the verbal forms §kmãjeiaw and épomãttetai are paralleled by §napomemagm°nhn in Zeno’s definition of the cognitive presentation (SVF 1.18, cf. 2.53 (D.L. 7.46, LS 40C), 2.60 (D.L. 7.50, which adds §napotetupvm°nh), 2.65 (S.E. M. 7.250-1 cf. LS 40E, where note daktul€vn sfrag›dew ... §napomãttontai t“ khr“, ‘markings from signet-rings are stamped on the wax’). épomãttein is found elsewhere in Plato, viz. Ti. 55e (describing imprints in the Receptacle), while several forms of the verb §kmãttein occur in the passage about memory (Tht. 191d-e). Forms of the substantive §kmage›on (one instance quoted above, n. 75) are found ibid., 191c-96c. Also compare Aët. 4.20.2 (SVF 2.387; ps.Plutarch only) on the corporeality of voice according to the Stoics: ‘we hear and percieve it (sc., voice) when it strikes against the sense of hearing [which is a part of the soul, JM] and stamps it like (the stamp) of a signet-ring in wax’ (ékoÊomen går aÈt∞w ka‹ afisyanÒmeya prospiptoÊshw tª ékoª ka‹ §ktupoÊshw kayãper daktul€ou efiw khrÒn). This metaphor (cf. D.L. 7.46 = SVF 2.53, toË ÙnÒmatow ofike€vw metenhnegm°nou épÚ t«n tÊpvn §n t“ khr“ ÍpÚ toË daktul€ou ginom°nvn, ‘the metaphorical designation being derived correctly from the imprints from the signet-ring which are produced in the wax’) is Zenonian and Cleanthean, not Chrysippean, see Ar.Did. fr. 39 Diels ap. Eus. PE 15.20.2 (SVF 1.141, 1.519), D.L. 7.50 = SVF 2.55 (LS 39A) with reference to Book 2 of Chrysippus Per‹ cux∞w, and the distinction between Zeno, Cleanthes and Chrysippus e.g. at S.E. M. 7.227-31 = SVF 1.58, 1.484, 2.56. Hoffmann (1921) convincingly argued that Plato depends on Democritus here, but as we have seen this is rejected out of hand by Friedländer (loc. cit.), who believes the “Prägemasse” is an idea of Plato himself, and by Pohlenz (1938, 175-6 with n. 2 = 1965, 3-4 with n. 2), who argues (a bit out of the blue) that the theory is originally pre-Democritean. On the other hand Pohlenz makes the important point that Chrysippus’ criticism of Zeno’s and Cleanthes’ view of tÊpvsiw (taken literally this would preclude the simultaneous or successive presence of many ‘voices’ in the same air-space) is anticipated by Theophrastus’ criticism (see Baldes 1975, 102-5) of Democritus, Sens. 53: ‘when several things are looked at in the same place, how will all these stampings get on the same piece of air?’ “Chrysipp kennt also die ältere Debatten” (Pohlenz ibid., 177 = 5). One cannot therefore exclude that Zeno (and then, indirectly or directly, some of his followers) were influenced not only by Plato (and perhaps by Aristotle, see below), but also by Democritus, presumably even by Theophrastus’ critical report as well. 47 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê The views of Democritus and Aristotle (possibly influenced by both Democritus and Plato), esp. de An. 2.12.424a17-20 on sense-perception as ‘the reception of sensible forms without matter, just as wax recieves the sign of the signet-ring’ (tÚ dektikÚn t«n afisyht«n efid«n êneu t∞w Ïlhw, oÂon ı khrÚw toË daktul€ou ... tÚ shme›on, cf. Mem. 1. 450a30-b3 on memory), part of a theory of perception, are qua type of theory even closer to Stoic epistemology. Burkert (1977, 99 with n. 6), referring to passages in Tht., Aristotle, and SVF, follows Hoffman and implicitly rejects Friedländer’s apodictic pronouncement (but he has missed Pohlenz’ contribution). He tersely and accurately points out that Democritus, using “the picture of seal-imprints on wax”, created “a comparison which has loomed large in ancient and modern epistemology”. Bibliography Algra, K. — Barnes, J. — Mansfeld, J. — Schofield, M. (eds.) 1999, The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy (Cambridge) Algra, K. A. — van der Horst, P. W. — Runia, D. T. (eds.) 1996, Polyhistor: Studies in the History and Historiography of Ancient Philosophy (Leiden — New York — Köln) Alpers, K. 1969, Bericht über Stand und Methode der Ausgabe des Etymologicum Genuinum (Mit einer Ausgabe des Buchstaben L) (Copenhagen) Ax, W. 1986, Laut Stimme Sprache. Studien zu drei Grundbegriffen der antiken Sprachtheorie (Göttingen) Ax, W. 1987, ‘Quadripertita ratio: Bemerkungen zur Geschichte eines aktuellen Kategoriensystems (adiectio – detractio – transmutatio – immutatio)’, in: Taylor, D. J. (ed.), The History of Linguistics in the Classical Period (Amsterdam — Philadelphia) 17-40 Ax, W. 1993, ‘Der Einfluss des Peripatos auf die Sprachtheorie der Stoa’, in: Döring — Ebert, 11-32 Ax, W. 2002, ‘Zum de voce-Kapitel der römischen Grammatik. Eine Antwort auf Dirk M. Schenkeveld und Wilfried Stroh’, in: Swiggers, P. — Wouters, A. (eds.), Grammatical Theory and Philosophy of Language in Antiquity (Leuven etc.) 121-41 Babut, D. 1969, Plutarque et le Stoïcisme (Paris) Baldes, R. W. 1975, ‘Democritus on visual perception: two theories or one?’, Phronesis 20, 93105 48 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê Baltes, M. 1972, Timaios Lokros Über die Natur des Kosmos und der Seele (Leiden) Baltes, M. 1978, ‘Die Zuordnung der Elemente zu den Sinnen bei Poseidonios und ihre Herkunft aus der alten Akademie’, Philologus 122, 183-96, repr. in: Baltes, M. 1999, DIANOHMATA. Kleine Schriften zu Platon und Platonismus (Stuttgart – Leipzig) 33-50 Baltussen, H. 1993, Theophrastus on Theories of Perception. Argument and Purpose in the De sensibus (diss. Utrecht; revised ed. Theophrastus against the Presocratics and Plato. Peripatetic Dialectic in the De sensibus, Leiden — New York — Köln 2000) Baltussen, H. 2000, ‘Plato in the Placita (Aëtius IV.8-23): A Dielsian blind spot?’, Philologus 144, 227-38 Baltussen, H. 2002, ‘Theophrastean echoes? The De sensibus in the Platonic and Aristotelian tradition’, in: Fortenbaugh, W. W. — Wöhrle, G. (eds.), On the Opuscula of Theophrastus (Stuttgart) 39-58 Baratin, M. 1982, ‘L’identité de la pensée et de la parole dans l’ancien stoïcisme’, Langages 65, 9-21 Barnes, J. 1993, ‘Meaning, saying and thinking’, in: Döring — Ebert, 47-61 Baumgarten, H. 1962 (ed.), Galen Über die Stimme. Testimonien der verlorenen Schrift Peri phones, Pseudo-Galen De voce et anhelitu (diss. Göttingen) Beare, J. I. 1906, Greek Theories of Elementary Cognition from Alcmaeon to Aristotle (Oxford, repr. Dubuque, Iowa 1970) Betz, O. 1973, ‘f≈nh ktl’, ThWNT Bd. IX (Stuttgart etc., repr. 1990) 272-94 Bouffartigue, J. – Patillon, M. (eds.) 1979, Porphyre: De l’abstinence T II: Livres II et III (Paris, repr. 2003) Brunschwig, J. — Nussbaum, M. (eds.) 1993, Passions and Perceptions. Studies in Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind (Cambridge) Burkert, W. 1972, Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism (Cambridge, MA) Burkert, W. 1977, ‘Air-imprints or eidola: Democritus’ aetiology of vision’, ICS (2) 97-109 Chiesa, M. C. 1991, ‘Le problème du langage intérieur chez les Stoïciens’, in: Voelke, J.-A. (ed.), Les Stoïciens, RIPh 45, 301-21 Chiesa, C. 'Le problème du langage intérieur dans la philosophie antique de Platon à Porphyre', Histoire Épistémologie Langage 14 (1992) 15-30 Daiber, H., ed. (1980) Aetius Arabus. Die Vorsokratiker in arabischer Überlieferung (Wiesbaden) Dalimer, C. (ed.) 2001, Apollonius Dyscole: Traité des conjonctions (Paris) Dammer, R. 2001, Diomedes grammaticus (Trier) 49 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê Derbolav, J. 1972, Platons sprachphilosophie im Kratylos und in den späteren Schriften (Darmstadt) De Stefani, A. (ed.) 1909-20, Etymologicum Gudianum quod vocatur fasc. 1-2 (Leipzig, repr. Amsterdam 1965) Diels, H. 1879, Doxographi graeci (Berlin, and later repr.). Abridged DG Dierauer, U. 1977, Tier und Mensch im Denken der Antike. Studien zur Tierpsychologie, Anthropologie und Ethik (Amsterdam) Dillon, J. 1993, Alcinous: The Handbook of Platonism Translated with an Introduction and Commentary (Oxford, repr. 1995) Dörrie, H. (ed.) 1965, Pohlenz, M., Kleine Schriften Bd. 1 (Hildesheim) Dorandi, T. 1996, ‘Ricerche sulla trasmissione delle Divisione Aristoteliche’, in: Algra & al. 1996, 145-65 Döring, K. — Ebert, T. (eds.) 1993, Dialektiker und Stoiker. Zur Logik der Stoa und ihrer Vorläufer (Stuttgart) Dyck, A. R. (ed.) 1983, Epimerismi Homerici. Pars prior Epimerismos continens qui ad Iliadis librum A pertinent (Berlin — New York) Dyck, A. R. (ed.) 1995, Epimerismi Homerici. Pars altera Epimerismos continens qui ordine alphabetico tradita sunt. Lexicon AIMVDEIN (Berlin — New York) Dyck, A. R. (ed.) 1996, A Commenbtary on Cicero, De Officiis (Ann Arbor) Everson, S. (ed.) 1994, Language (Cambridge) FDS see Hülser Frede, M. 1978, ‘Principles of Stoic grammar’, in: Rist, J. (ed.), The Stoics (Berkeley and Los Angeles — London) 27-75, repr. in: Frede, M., Essays in Ancient Philosophy (Oxford 1987) 301-37 Frede, M. 1993, ‘The Stoic notion of a grammatical case’, BICS 39, 13-24 Friedländer, P. 21960, Platon Bd. 3: Die platonischen Schriften. Zweite und dritte Periode (Berlin) Glidden, D. K. 1994, ‘Parrots, Pyrrhonists and native speakers’, in: Everson, 129-48 Gronau, K. 1914, Poseidonios und die jüdisch-christliche Genesis-Exegese (Leipzig — Berlin) Gudeman, A. 1929, ‘Stephanos 13) (Grammatiker)’, RE Bd. IIIA (Stuttgart) 2399-2401 Gudeman, A. 1932, ‘Melampus 8)’, RE Bd. XV (Stuttgart) 399-404 Heinze, M. 1872, Die Lehre vom Logos in der griechischen Philosophie (Oldenburg, repr. Aalen 1962) 50 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê Hilgard, A. (ed.) 1901, Grammatici Graeci I.3: Commentaria in Dionysii Thracis artem grammaticam (Leipzig, repr. Hildesheim — New York 1965) Hoerschelman, G. 1874, De Dionysii Thracis interpretibus veteribus commentationis particula I (Lipsiae) Hoffmann, E. 1921, ‘Zwei quellenkritische Beobachtungen. I. Die Herkunft des Wachstafelbildes im Theätet’, Jahresberichte des philologischen Vereins zu Berlin 47, 56-8 Hülser, K. (ed.) 1987-8, Die Fragmente zur Dialektik der Stoiker Bd. 1-4 (Stuttgart — Bad Cannstatt), abbreviated FDS Ingenkamp, H. G. 1966, Untersuchungen zu den pseudoplatonischen Definitionen (Wiesbaden) Ioppolo A. M. 1990, ‘Presentation and assent: a physical and cognitive problem in early Stoicism’, CQ 40, 433-49 Isnardi Parente, M. (ed.) 1981, Senocrate – Ermodoro: Frammenti (Naples) Kirwan, C. 1994, ‘Augustine on the nature of speech’, in: Everson, 188-211 Kraus, P. — Walzer, R. (eds.) 1951, Galeni Compendium Timaei Platonis aliorumque dialogorum synopsis quae extant fragmenta (London) Labarrière, J.-L. 1993, ‘De la ‘nature phantastique’ des animaux chez les Stoïciens’, in: Brunschwig — Nussbaum, 225-49 2 Lachenaud, G. (ed.) 1993, Plutarque: Oeuvres Morales XII , Opinions des philosophes (Paris) Lentz, A. (ed.) 1867-8, Herodiani technici Reliquiae. Grammatici Graeci III.1: Praefationem et Herodiani prosodiam catholicam continens, III.2.1 Reliqua scripta prosodiaca pathologiam orthographica continens (Leipzig, repr. Hildesheim — New York 1979) Long, A. A. 1971, ‘Language and thought in Stoicism’, in: Long, A. A. (ed.), Problems in Stoicism (London, repr. 1996) 75-113 Long, A. A. 1996a, ‘Stoic psychology and the elucidation of language’, in: Manetti, G. (ed.), Knowledge through Signs. Ancient Semiotic Theories and Practices (Turnhout) 109-131 Long, A. A. 1996b, ‘Theophrastus’ De sensibus on Plato’, in: Algra & al. 1996, 345-62 Long, A. A. 1999, ‘Stoic Psychology’, in: Algra & al. 1999, 560-84 Long, A. A. — Sedley, D. N. (eds.) 1987, The Hellenistic philosophers. Vol. I, Translations of thePrincipal Sources with Philosophical Commentary. Vol. II, Greek and Latin texts with Notes and Bibliography (Cambridge; and later repr.). German tr. of Vol. I: Hülser, K. 2000, Die hellenistischen Philosophen (Weimar — Stuttgart). Revised French tr. of Vol. I: Brunschwig, J. — Pellegrin P., 2001, Les philosophies hellénistiques. T 1, Pyrrhon l'épicurisme, T 2, Les Stoïciens, T 3, Les Académiciens, la renaissance du pyrrhonisme (Paris, repr. 2004). Abbreviated LS 51 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê Mansfeld, J. 1990, ‘Doxography and dialectic. The Sitz im Leben of the ‘Placita’’, ANRW II 36.4 (Berlin — New York) 3056-3229 Montanari, F. 1997, ‘Choiroboskos’, NP Bd. 2 (Stuttgart — Weimar) 1139-40 Mühl, M. 1962, ‘Der Logos endiathetos und prophorikos in der älteren Stoa bis zur Synode von Sirmium 351’, Archiv für Begriffsgeschichte 7, 7-56 Müller, M. 1891, De Seleuco homerico (Göttingen) Mutschmann, H. (ed.) 1906, Divisiones quae vulgo dicuntur Aristoteleae (Leipzig) Otte, K. 1968, Das Sprachverständnis bei Philon von Alexandrien: Sprache als Mittel der Hermeneutik (Tübingen) Pease, A. S. (ed.) 1958, M. Tulli Ciceronis De natura deorum libri secundus et tertius (Cambridge MA, and later repr.) Pohlenz, M. 1938, ‘Zenon und Chrysipp’, Nachr.Ak.Göttingen N.F. II.9, repr. in: Dörrie 1965, 138 Pohlenz, M. 1939, ‘Die Begründung der abendländischen Sprachlehre durch die Stoa’, Nachr.Ak.Göttingen N.F. III.6, repr. in: Dörrie 1965, 39-86 4 Pohlenz, M. 1970-2, Die Stoa. Geschichte einer geistigen Bewegung Bd. 1-2 (Göttingen) Ramelli, I. (ed.) 2003, Anneo Cornuto: Compendio di teologia greca (Milano) Reitzenstein, R. 1897, Geschichte der griechischen Etymologika. Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte der Philologie (Leipzig, repr. Amsterdam 1964) Reitzenstein, R. 1907, ‘Etymologika’, RE Bd. VI (Stuttgart) 807-17 Rossitto, C. 1984, Aristotele ed altri: Divisioni (Padova) Runia, D. T. 1986, Philo of Alexandria and the Timaeus of Plato (Leiden — New York — Koln) Runia, D. T. 1988, ‘Naming and knowing: themes in Philonic theology with special reference to the De mutatione nominum’, in: van den Broek, T. — Baarda, T. — Mansfeld, J. (eds.), Knowledge of God in the Graeco-Roman World (Leiden) 69-91, repr. in: Runia, D. T. 1990, Exegesis and Philosophy. Studies on Philo of Alexandria (Aldershot) Study XI Schenkeveld, D. M. 1990a, ‘Studies in the history of ancient linguistics, III. The Stoic t°xnh per‹ fvn∞w’, Mnemosyne 43, 86-108 Schenkeveld, D. M. 1990b, ‘Studies in the history of ancient linguistics, IV’, Mnemosyne 43, 289-306 Schenkeveld, D. M. 1999, ‘Linguistics’, in: Algra & al. 1999, 177-93 Schironi, F. 2004, I frammenti di Aristarco di Samotracia negli etimologici bizantini (Göttingen) Schmidt, P. L. 1989, ‘’Grammatik und Rhetorik’, in: Herzog, R. (ed.), Handbuch der Altertumswissenschaft Bd. 8.5 = Handbuch der lateinischen Literatur der Antike Bd. 5: 52 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê Restauration und Erneuerung. Die lateinische Literatur von 284 bis 374 n. Chr. (München) 101-58 Schmidt, R. 1839, Stoicorum grammatica (Halle, repr. Amsterdam 1967) Schneider, R. (ed.) 1910, Apollonii Dyscoli quae supersunt. Grammatici Graeci II.3: Librorum Apollonii deperditorum fragmenta (Leipzig, repr. Hildesheim — New York 1979) Schütrumpf, E. 1991 (ed.), Aristoteles: Politik Buch I (Berlin) Sedley, D. 1993, ‘Chrysippus on psychophysical causality’, in: Brunschwig — Nussbaum, 31331 Serrano Aybar, C. 1977, ‘Historia de la lexicografia antigua y medieval’, in: Gangutia Elicegui, E. (ed.), Introduccion a la lexicografia greca (Madrid) 60-106 Sluiter, I. 1990, Ancient Grammar in Context. Contributions to the Study of Ancient Linguistic Thought (diss. VU Amsterdam) Sluiter, I. 2000, ‘Language and thought in Stoic philosophy’, in: Auroux, S. — Koerner, E. F. K. — Niederehe, H.-J. — Versteegh, K. (eds.), History of the Language Sciences. An International Handbook on the Evolution of the Study of Language from the Beginnings to the Present Vol. 1/1 (Berlin — New York) 375-84 Sorabji, R. 1993, Animal Minds and Human Morals. The Origins of the Western Debate (London) Sorabji, R. 2004, The Philosophy of the Commentators 200-600 AD, Vol. 3: Logic & Metyaphysics (London) Steinthal, H. 21891-2, Geschichte der Sprachwissenschaft bei den Griechen und Römern, mit besonderer Rücksicht auf die Logik (Berlin, repr. Hildesheim 1961) Stockt, L. van der 1990, ‘Plutarch on language’, in: Swiggers, P. — Wouters, A. (eds.), Le langage dans l’antiquité (Leuven — Paris) 180-96 Stratton, G. M. 1917, Theophrastus and the Greek Physiological Psychology before Aristotle (London, repr. Amsterdam 1964) Stroh, V. 1998, ‘De vocis definitione quadam Stoica’, in: Baumbach, M. & al. (eds.), Mousopolos Aner. FS Görgemanns (Heidelberg) 443-52 Tabarroni, A. 1988, ‘On articulation and animal language in ancient linguistic theory’, Versus: quaderni di studi semiotici 50-51, 103-21 Tappe, G. 1912, De Philonis libro qui inscribitur ÉAlejãndrow µ per‹ toË lÒgon ¶xein tå êloga z“a quaestiones selectae (diss. Göttingen) Tarrant, H. 2000, Plato’s First Interpreters (London) Taylor, A. E. 1928, A Commentary on Plato’s Timaeus (Oxford, repr. 1962) 53 © J. Mansfeld February 12, 2016 Phonê Terian, A. (ed.) 1981, Philonis Alexandrini De animalibus: The Armenian Text with an Introduction, Translation and Commentary (Chico CA) Theiler, W. 1954, ‘Die Sprache des Geistes in der Antike’, in: Sprachgeschichte und Wortbedeutung, FS Debrunner (Bern) 431-40, repr. in: Theiler, W. 1966, Forschungen zum Neuplatonismus (Berlin) 302-12 Theodorides, C. (ed.) 1976, Die Fragmente des Grammatikers Philoxenos (Berlin — New York) Tieleman, T. 1996, Galen and Chrysippus On the Soul. Argument and Refutation in the De placitis Books II-III (Leiden — New York — Köln) Tosi, R. 1998, ‘Etymologica’, NP Bd. 4 (Stuttgart — Weimar) 198-200 Trabattoni, F. 2002, ‘Il pensiero come dialogo interiore (Theaet. 189e4-190a6)’, in: Casertano, G. (ed.), Il Teeteto di Platone: struttura e problematiche (Naples) 175-87 Waszink, J. H. (ed.) 1962, Timaeus a Calcidio translatus commentarioque instructus (LondonLeiden; 2nd ed. 1976) Whittaker, J. (ed.) 1990, Alcinoos: Enseignement des doctrines de Platon (Paris, repr. 2002) Whittaker, J. 1987, ‘Platonic philosophy in the first centuries of the Empire’,’ ANRW II 36.1 (Berlin — New York) 81-123 Wolska-Conus, W. 1989, ‘Stéphanos d’Athènes et Stéphanos d’Alexandrie. Essai d’identification et de biographie’, REB 47, 5-89 Zeller, E. 21865, Die Philosophie der Griechen in ihrer geschichtlichen Entwicklung Bd III.1, Die nacharistotelische Philosophie, 1. Hälfte (Leipzig, 3rd ed. 1880; 4th ed. Zeller, E. — Wellmann, E. 1909, repr. Hildesheim 1963) 54