THE ROLE OF PATIENT NARRATIVE IN BEST INTERESTS DECISION-MAKING Patient Narrative in healthcare decision making The process of healthcare decision-making has important consequences, not just for patients but for those who love and care for them. Respect for patient autonomy is at the core of healthcare decision-making and the concepts of ‘patient centred care’ and ‘shared decisionmaking’ resulting in increased patient involvement in treatment decisions have been associated with improved health outcomes.1 Patient narrative is recognised as underpinning the dialogue between the doctor and patient to facilitate informed decision-making which is consonant with the patient’s story. It provides “meaning, context and perspective for the patient’s predicament”.2 A narrative approach considers the unfolding of a person’s life according to the values and beliefs which make him who he is – the story of his life. Kuczewski considers that when an adult is unable to make healthcare decisions due to lack of capacity, the patient’s story, has a prima facie moral claim to being finished in a way consistent with what has come before and with the values and self-conception with which the person has tried to shape it. The surviving interests of a person are interests in seeing the story carried out in a way that is meaningfully related to how it has proceeded up to the loss of decision-making capacity.3 Of course there will be multiple narratives in the decision making process; family, carers, clinicians and perhaps the judiciary and each will bring their own perspectives and values. The weight given to these narratives depends on the authority of decision-maker, the R. Say and R. Thomson ‘The importance of patient preferences in treatment decisions: challenges for doctors’ (2003) BMJ 327: 542-545 2 T. Greenhalgh and B. Hurwitz ‘Why Study narrative?’ (1999) BMJ 318, 48 -50 at page 48 3 M. Kuczewski ‘Commentary: Narrative Views of personal identity and Substituted Judgment in Surrogate Decision Making’ (1999) Journal of Law, Medicine &Ethics 27 (1):32- 36,33 1 1 authenticity and perceived accuracy of his views and how far they move away from promoting the basic interests of the patient, such as dignity, freedom from pain and suffering, and life itself. At the heart of the decision-making process is the patient who lacks the capacity to make the decision. Thus, to give effect to the culmination of his ‘story’, sufficient weight should be attached to his narrative. Blustein considers that decisions should be made in accordance with the patient’s narrative because this is what it means to treat him as a person,4 thus affirming the value of autonomy. Best interests test for those who lack capacity to make healthcare decisions The best interests’ standard for decision-making on behalf of adults who lack capacity established at common law recognises the importance of both the medical and wider holistic factors. In Re A (Medical Treatment: Male Sterilisation) the Court of Appeal identified that best interests encompasses “medical, emotional and all other welfare issues.”5 The statutory provisions set out in the Mental Capacity Act 2005 (MCA) build upon common law. The MCA does not define ‘best interests’ but sets out a checklist of factors which the decisionmaker must take into account, including the patient’s past and present wishes and feelings, the beliefs and values that would be likely to influence his decision if he had capacity, and other factors that he would be likely to consider if he were able to do so (s4 (6) MCA). The MCA best interests checklist thus “involves an element of substituted judgment being taken into account”6 because it requires the decision-maker to consider the patient’s hypothetical choice. However, despite this subjective element, the best interests test is an objective test, balancing the overall benefits and burdens of the proposed treatment options. Tonelli states that “an objective standard, usually represented by best interests standard differs from J. Blustein “Choosing for others as Continuing a Life Story: The problem of personal Identity Revisited” (1999) Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 27: 20 -31, 28 5 Re A (Medical Treatment: Male Sterilisation) [2000] 1 F.L.R. 549 page 5 per Butler-Sloss L.J. 6 In the Matter of G (TJ) [2010] EWHC 3005 (COP) para 55 per Morgan J. 4 2 substituted judgement in that decisions will be independent of the personal desires of the patient and therefore, generalizable across a group of patients in similar circumstances”.7 This ‘theoretical tension’8 can be reconciled through recognition that patient well- being is shaped by the personal standards of the patient about acceptable living circumstances, and best interests are equated with patient well-being. But this account requires sufficient consideration of the patient’s narrative – his values, wishes and perception of wellbeing. If the patient’s narrative is marginalised, or at worse ignored, the focus of best interests shifts to the medical harms and benefits and renders respect for patient autonomy nugatory. This dilemma was illustrated in the High Court decision of W v. M. W v. M Aged 43, M (the patient), experienced a sudden collapse as a result of viral encephalitis which left her with extensive and irreparable brain damage. She has since been totally dependent on others for care and has been fed artificially through a gastrostomy tube. She is in a minimally conscious state (MCS), thus aware of herself and her environment but not fully conscious. Medical evidence shows that she experiences regular pain, discomfort and distress (about 30% of the time). She is totally dependent on others for care and is immobile, doubly incontinent and is moved by a hoist. There is no realistic prospect of recovery. Clearly M lacks capacity to make decisions about her treatment. Her sister in giving evidence in the High Court hearing contrasted M’s previous life with her current circumstances – “it’s not a life, it’s an existence and I know she wouldn’t want it”.9 To them M is a different person in comparison to her previous independent existence. M. Tonelli ‘Substituted Judgment in Medical Practice: Evidentiary Standards on a Sliding Scale,’ (1997) Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 25:22–29, 23 8 N. Cantor, Conroy, Best Interest, and the Handling of Dying Patients, (1985) Rutgers L. Rev. 37:543 – 577, 564 9 W v. M (2011) EWHC 2443 (Fam) at para 112 7 3 The perspectives of the different stakeholders in the decision making process, the patient as expressed by her family, clinicians and carers were considered at length by the court. Of course the judiciary has a role in interpreting and giving weight to these narratives. As Holm notes, “many of the disputes under the MCA are likely to be between persons and their health care team and many of these are not going to turn on differing interpretations of medical facts, or resolvable vagueness in moral or ethical values. The dispute will simply be about what set of values that should prevail in a particular case, the patient’s or the health care team’s.”10 If the different narratives promote conflicting values, which are prioritised – preservation of life or the patient’s values and wishes expressed at an earlier time? M’s narrative articulated by her family An evaluation of the patient’s best interests requires consideration of medical, emotional and all other welfare issues. Such considerations “go well beyond the expertise of a single doctor”11 and those close to the patient, his family and carers, may provide valuable insight in the assessment of the more holistic, non-medical aspects of best interests. Indeed the MCA requires the decision-maker, where practicable and appropriate, to consult anyone engaged in caring for the patient or interested in his welfare and to take into account their views as to what would be in the person's best interests (s4(7)). In W v. M12 M’s family considered that M would not want to continue her burdensome life with such a lack of dignity. It was their view that withdrawal of artificial nutrition and hydration (ANH) was in her best interests. On witnessing the decline of her grandmother in a nursing home M had said on more than one occasion words to the effect that she would not 10 S. HØlm, Best Interests: What Problems in Family Law Should Health Care Law Avoid? (2008) Health Care Anal 16:252–254, 254 11 Mentally Incapacitated Adults and Decision-Making: Medical Treatment and Research, Consultation Paper No. 129 (H.M.S.O. 1993) para 3.59 12 [2011] EWHC 2443 (Fam) 4 wish to live like that, that she would not wish to be dependent on others, and that she “wanted to go quickly”13. The court also heard from M’s sister that, when reports about Tony Bland appeared on television, M expressed views to the effect that it would be better to allow him to die. The court accepted the veracity of the evidence of M’s sister and partner but did it have sufficient probative value? In the US, where substitute decision-making is the basis for the decision-making for incompetent patients, the courts have articulated the need for ‘clear and convincing’ evidence as to what the patient would have wanted to justify withdrawal of life sustaining treatment.14 However, studies of surrogate decision-making demonstrate a lack consistency and accuracy between the choices made by the surrogate and those of their loved ones. A study by Vig et al has shown that surrogates describe five bases for decision-making: conversations; documents; shared experiences, the surrogates own values and a network of contacts such as religious leader. “Approximately 2/3rds of the surrogates planned to make future decisions based on knowledge of their loved ones’ care preferences that they had gained from conversations”.15 Thus, it may be very difficult for family members to provide ‘clear and convincing’ evidence that the patient would have wanted a certain outcome in a particular situation (substituted judgment). They can nevertheless provide insight into which treatment options seem to fit best with the patient’s wishes, beliefs and feelings. According to Ho, the input of laypeople relies on “various intuitions or visceral reaction rather than appeal to well-reasoned arguments”.16 In W v. M, M’s sister said that “I know that’s what she wanted 13 W v. M (2011) EWHC 2443 (Fam) para 230 Re Martin 538 NW 2d 399 (1995 Mich Sup Ct) 15 E. Vig et al, ‘Beyond Substituted Judgment: How Surrogates Navigate End of Life Decision-Making’ ( 2006) JAGS 54: 1688 – 1693, 1691 16 A. Ho ‘“They just don’t get it!’’ When family disagrees with expert opinion’ (2009) J Med Ethics 35:497–501 at page 498 14 5 in her heart of hearts”17 and M’s partner said “I think she would be horrified that she was carrying on in this undignified manner”.18 He said that knowing her views and opinions they were M’s ‘voice’. In the process of best interests decision-making the family input the patient’s ‘views and beliefs’ in contrast to medical ‘knowledge’ and ‘decisions’. One way of appreciating the role of the family is that they provide input on “how well a particular decision hangs together with elements of the formerly competent patient’s identityconstituting narrative”.19 Carers’ narrative In W v. M the court heard evidence from a number of professional care staff at the residential nursing home where M was cared for. They portrayed her life in much more positive terms than by members of her family. They described situations when M seemed happy or distressed and her responses to particular experiences; M’s eyes clearly moving and tracking, noises she made, M crying in response to records played and how M became tense and pulled her arms up under her chin when her wheelchair was being pushed across a rough path. In contrast to the evidence given by M’s sister and partner about the value M had attached to her independence before her collapse the professional carers’ input describes M’s current behaviours - akin to what Dworkin describes as experiential interests - what gives her pleasure. Dworkin considers that our perception of what makes a ‘good life’ involves critical and experiential interests. It is a person’s critical interests such as commitments, relationships and work, which are central to a meaningful life. The evidence of M’s family focusses on her critical interests, what makes M who she is. Dworkin argues that critical interests survive 17 [2011] EWHC 2443 (Fam) para 112 Ibid. para 119 19 J. Blustein “Choosing for others as Continuing a Life Story: The problem of personal Identity Revisited” (1999) Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 27: 20 -31at 23 18 6 incompetence and therefore should take precedence over a person’s experiential interests – experiences that give rise to a pleasurable life.20 Clinical Narrative The person responsible for making the determination about best interests, usually the clinician with care of the patient, will bring medical expertise in assessing the patient’s best interests. As Ho puts it, Physicians are experts with a superior ability to accurately diagnose patients and come up with a range of possible solutions for various clinical problems, such that they are in a better position than their lay patients to decide what medical options would be in the patients’ best interests.21 They can draw upon statistical data and their previous experience to predict the probability of outcomes. Thus the medical perspective of best interests could be seen to provide an ‘objective’ perspective based on knowledge and facts and is seen as dependable and evidence based. Even so, the clinical experts in the W v. M case had different views about the value of M’s life. Dr Badwan, a clinician in rehabilitation medicine instructed by the Official Solicitor, assessed Ms’ quality of life as ‘reasonable.’ He took the view that “ANH should never be withdrawn from a patient in MCS”.22 In contrast, Professor Turner- Stokes said she was “unable to identify any aspect of her [M’s] life that gives her positive pleasure or R Dworkin Life’s Dominion: An Argument About Abortion and Euthanasia, 1993 Harper Collins, London A. Ho’ “They just don’t get it!’’ When family disagrees with expert opinion’ (2009) J Med Ethics 35:497–501 at page 497 22 [2011] EWHC 2443 (Fam) para 198 20 21 7 satisfaction”.23 She thought that because M’s negative experiences outweighed the positive ones it would be appropriate to withdraw ANH and allow her to die in dignity. Of course the contribution of both the medical and wider welfare perspectives is essential to evaluate the best treatment option for the incompetent patient and indeed the involvement of family members may corroborate the proposed treatment as the ‘best’ option. But difficulties arise where there is a difference perception about the patient’s best interests. All stakeholders in the best interests’ decision making process will bring their own values in evaluating the patient’s best interests. Savulsecu acknowledges that “medicine as a practice is founded on commitment to certain values: pain is bad, longer life is usually better than shorter life, and so on. A part of learning to practise medicine is learning to take on these values”.24 Best interests will always have a normative imperative. As Dresser remarks, It is conceptually impossible to keep the best interests evaluation completely focussed on the individual patient. The only way to decide what is best for the patient is by reference to broader definitions of what is good and bad for human beings.25 The medical values of prolongation of life, avoidance of pain etc. can be perceived as objectively good. Tonelli takes the view that when families communicate decisions to the 23 Ibid. para 199 J. Savulescu ‘Rational non-interventional paternalism: why doctors ought to make judgments of what is best for their patients’ (1995) Journal of Medical Ethics, 21: 327-331, 329 25 R. Dresser, ‘Missing Persons: Legal Perceptions of Incompetent Patient’ (1994) Rutgers L Rev 46 (2) 636-47 at page 662 24 8 doctor he starts not with basis of evaluating the evidence to support it but with a comparison to the objective best interests of the patient.26 Which narrative is prioritised? Munby J. has stated that “the statute lays down no hierarchy as between the various factors which have to be borne in mind, beyond the overarching principle that what is determinative is the judicial evaluation of what is in P's “best interests”.27 Nevertheless, Ho considers that “clinicians’ ‘expert’ opinions are consistently considered superior”28 to the family’s beliefs regarding their loved one’s wishes or interests. Her proposal to equalise the ranking of the different perspectives, is a commitment to ‘epistemic humility.’ This involves, the recognition of the boundary of one’s expert domain as well as appreciation of the limitation of one’s knowledge in making appropriate decisions. It acknowledges the importance of considering diverse perspectives, including non-clinical ones held by the families.29 Counsel for M acknowledged that although it was not known exactly what M would have thought of her actual condition, M’s views should be given substantial weight. Baker J. recognised that many people would find the quality of life of MCS “impossible to accept were they able to consistently express themselves with full competence”.30 However, he thought it would be wrong to attach significant weight to the statements made by M before her collapse because there was no possibility of knowing how she now feels about her current life. Surely it is precisely because it is not known how M feels about her current life, that M. Tonelli ‘Substituted Judgment in Medical Practice: Evidentiary Standards on a Sliding Scale,’ (1997) Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 25:22–29 27 Re M (Statutory Will) [2009] EWHC 2525 (Fam) para 32 per Munby J 28 A. Ho ‘“They just don’t get it!’’ When family disagrees with expert opinion’ (2009) J Med Ethics 35:497–501 at page 4998 29 Ibid. at page 500 30 [2011] EWHC 2443 (Fam) para 34 26 9 respect is accorded to her prior wishes, feelings beliefs and values as a way of continuing her story in a way that is consistent with what has come before. It seems that in order to be accorded significant weight the prior views of M must be specifically directed at the issue in hand, that is withdrawal of ANH in the condition of minimally conscious state. “There is no evidence that M ever specifically considered the question of withdrawal of ANH, or ever considered the question whether she would wish such treatment to be withdrawn if in a minimally conscious state”. 31 The requirement for such a high specificity of evidence in effect “brushes aside the most compelling testimony of the family members based on years of experience and personal knowledge of the patient’s values.” 32 Conclusion Advances in medicine increasingly allow doctors to preserve the lives of patients. But just because they can does not mean that they should. Whether they should depends on an evaluation of best interests, where the patient lacks capacity. The goal of best interests’ decision making is not to decide what the patient would have wanted but rather to ascertain the overall benefits and burdens of the treatment options. The best interests’ assessment is clearly patient focussed because it requires consideration of the interests of the incompetent individual. Thus Buchanan and Brock argue that whether life-sustaining treatment is in a patient’s best interests depends upon whether life is worth living for the patient33. As Nicholas and Gillett note, 31 Ibid. para 230 Ho Mun Chan, ‘Sharing death and Dying: Advance Directives, Autonomy and the Family’ (2004) Bioethics 18 (2):87–103, 92 33 A. Buchanan and D. Brock Deciding for others: The Ethics of Surrogate Decision making (Cambridge: CUP, 1989) at page 123 32 10 Clinical choices are not isolated from all else that happens in people's lives but are part of an on-going narrative. Moral choices made, like all decisions, are part of an effort to live a life that has coherence and meaning34. Some may consider that avoiding the harm of cessation of basic interests (life itself) takes priority over giving effect to the patient’s narrative. Although not an absolute rule, society considers the preservation of life to be a fundamental good35 and therefore the law supports a very strong presumption in favour of preserving life. In W v. M Baker J. considered that preservation of life had the greatest weight in the best interests’ balance sheet. If the principle of preservation of life is such a weighty factor in the balance sheet appraisal only significant harms of being kept alive act as an effective counter- balance. Are the prior views of the patient, that he would consider prolongation of life in such circumstances a significant harm, an effective counter-balance? If the individual is to override the public interest in preserving life he must do so in clear terms36 and the law places a “‘heavy burden’ on those who are advocating a course which would lead inevitably to the cessation of a human life”.37 Following the High Court judgment in W v. M the prior views of the patient, articulated by those close to the patient, seem to require a high level of specificity in order to be accorded significant weight. Not only the circumstances but also the treatment to be refused should be identified by the patient. Whilst of course not wishing to undermine the need for sufficient certainty of the patient’s views in difficult decisions involving withdrawal of ANH it is proposed that the narrative of the patient should not be marginalised in the best interests’ decision making process. 34 B. Nicholas and G. Gillett, Doctors' stories, patients' stories: a narrative approach to teaching medical ethics (1997)J. Med Ethics 23: 295-299, 296 35 Re T: Adult Refusal of Treatment [1993] Fam 95, page 112 E per Lord Donaldson MR 36 Ibid. 37 W Healthcare NHS Trust v. KH [2004] EWCA Civ 1324 para 30 per Brooke LJ 11 Currently, the application of the best interests test in cases involving withdrawal of ANH overemphasises preservation of life at the expense of human dignity and the continuation/cessation of the patient’s story. Some rethinking of the weight given to the patient’s values, prior wishes and feelings and the practical way of evidencing them is required to ensure that the patient’s narrative is effectively heard. 12