Dividing Harm Draft Gerhard Øverland Those who argue against the permissibility of killing innocent aggressors take mere causal contribution to harm to be morally insignificant.1 In order to be a permissible target for defensive force, according to this view, a person must be morally responsible for a threat to others. In this paper I argue that mere causal connection to the threat of harm is morally significant, and explore the degree to which it is. The paper has two parts. In the first I look to demonstrate the intuitive plausibility of what I call “the asymmetrical fair share procedure”. According to this proposal, innocent contributors have a duty to take on a fair share of the harm if dividing it is possible, and a fair share of the risk of being harmed if redistribution of harm is impossible. In the second part, I develop a contractual account of why causal connection is morally significant. Preliminaries Contributing to harm is an elusive notion. My interest is in simple ‘paradigmatic’ cases. For instance, a person fires a gun and shoots someone, or flips a switch that empties water into a container, drowning the person trapped inside, and so forth.2 Mere contribution is contribution to harm without moral responsibility, and is what we find among innocent contributors. A person might, for instance, be an innocent contributor when the agent is excused for believing that harming another is permissible, perhaps because he or she has good grounds for believing so, has been manipulated into believing so, or has been drugged, 1 There is a growing literature on the topic and an increasing number of philosophers seem to support this view, see N. Zohar “Collective War and Individualistic Ethics: Against the Conscription of ‘Self-Defense’” Political Theory 21 (1993): 606–622; Michael Otsuka “Killing the Innocent in Self-Defence”, Philosophy and Public Affairs 23 (1994): 74–94; Jeff McMahan “Self-Defense and the Problem of the Innocent Attacker” Ethics 104 (1994); David Rodin War and Self-Defense (Oxford: Clarendon Press 2002), at pp. 70–99; Jeff McMahan “The Basis of Moral Liability to defensive Killing” Philosophical Issues 15 (2005), and; Kimberley Kessler Ferzan “Justifying Self-Defense” Law and Philosophy 24 (2005): 711–749. 2 One might be said to be the cause of someone’s death though there has been no significant causal connection. For instance, assume that Nice is very pretty and out walking. Stare drives past, and cannot resist turning head. As a consequence Stare drives off the road and eventually dies in a crash. In some sense it was her beauty that caused his death. We should not, however, say that Nice contributed to the death of Stare. 1 inducing her to harm the victim as an automaton. In my use of the term here, an innocent contributor is essentially someone who initiates or sustains a harmful causal sequence but is not morally at fault for having done so.3 When discussing the permissibility of defensive force against innocent contributors, it is common to envisage conflict situations involving a contributor and victim, one of whom will be killed. In such cases it is either permissible to kill innocent contributors in self-defence or it is not. I think we gain valuable insight into this issue by envisaging situations where the harm may be divided and shared between the two parties. Bill becomes a contributor to harm suffered by Alice when Bill initiated or sustained a causal sequence that led to Alice’s’ harm. Envisage that Bill through no fault of his own is in such a significant causal relation to harm suffered by Alice. We can imagine different levels of harm, from loss of a finger, through loss of limbs, to loss of life. Alice is not in a position to defend herself, but Cathy, who is close by, could intervene in the causal chain to prevent these harms. Since Cathy cannot save everyone from harm, we need to ascertain which rule she should act on to divide it. Now, there are various ways of distinguishing between innocent contributors. We may, for instance, distinguish between those intending harm because they have good reason to believe killing a particular person is a necessary corollary of a just cause (innocent aggressors); those causing harm accidentally by their actions (innocent agents); and those harming others through no actions of their own at all (innocent threats). Perhaps the most promising way to introduce a morally relevant distinction among these innocent contributors would be to distinguish between those who intend harm (innocent aggressors) and those who do not (innocent agents/threats). Yet, if the idea is to let intention be a morally decisive factor, the proposal leads to counterintuitive results as soon as we consider standard cases of self-defence. An innocent aggressor may have set out to harm someone, but hurt someone else by mistake. It seems irrelevant whether Bill intended to kill Alice or someone else and mistook Alice for this person. Whatever could permissibly be done to prevent (innocent) Bill from killing Alice when he intended to kill her, could also permissibly be done to prevent him from killing her even though he thought he was killing a 3 According to Philippa Foot, the relevant distinction between doing and allowing harm is primarily one between a) initiating or sustaining a harmful causal sequence, and b) allowing a harmful causal sequence to run its course. See Philippa Foot “Killing and Letting Die” in B. Steinbock and A. Norcross Killing and Letting Die (Fordham University Press: 1994): 280–289, at p. 281. Ultimately, of course, what it is to initiate and sustain a causal sequence needs to be made precise. I shall not do so here. 2 different person altogether.4 Hence, the fact that an aggressor intends to harm a particular individual does not imply that the implications of being an aggressor apply to him only when he is about to harm the intended target. At any rate, the implications of an intention to harm a particular individual carry over with equal force if the aggressor mistakes the identity of his victim. We therefore need to consider whether the mere fact of innocently acting on an intention to harm, though one is about to harm wrong person, would distinguish implication-wise this aggressor from one who innocently acts in such a way as to cause harm unintentionally (innocent agent). Both are completely innocent. One person is unlucky in believing that he needs to harm another; the other is unlucky for causing harm by his actions. While only the first intends harm, it is not clear why that should matter as long as he does the right thing given what he knows and forms intentions that we think he ought be disposed to form. He could, for instance, have good reason to believe that by harming Alice he would save others from her impermissible actions.5 That intentions are essential in moral appraisals should not lead us to conclude that they are significant when the agent is not at fault for forming them. At this point, we need to ask if there are grounds for distinguishing morally between people whose actions cause harm (innocent agents) and people whose actions do not, but who still represent a causal threat (innocent threats). The latter could, for instance, be a person who is blown by the wind or thrown against another by a villain. Again, it seems difficult to understand the rationale behind the distinction. After all, we are assuming that there is nothing risky or otherwise peculiar about the actions of the first agent, but that unexpectedly, and due to bad luck, his behaviour is about to cause harm. Perhaps the power circuits at his house were rewired, making the flip of a switch result in harm to his neighbour. It is hard to see why a different level of force should be permissible against such an agent as compared to against a person who was blown by the wind in such a way that he harms another. A different line would be to distinguish between innocents that have engaged in risky activity and those that have not. According to Jeff McMahan, the driver of a car that goes out of control through no fault of her own is innocent but not non-responsible. There might accordingly be reasons for distinguishing morally between two types of innocent threats: those brought about by responsible actions, such as taking up driving and risking brake 4 This, of course, applies to culpable aggressors as well, but then much more force may be levelled against them if necessary. 5 In fact, it might on some occasions be grounds for giving more protection to an innocent aggressor than just any unlucky agent, as only the former has demonstrated a willingness to incur risk to help protect others. 3 failure, and those where the agent has done nothing to become a threat to others. 6 McMahan’s contention that there are distinctions to be made here seems plausible.7 Against McMahan, however, I would suggest that responsible agents who have become innocent threats by choosing to participate in risky activities have to bear more of the cost than ordinary innocent contributors, and not simply more than innocent bystanders. Being responsible for engaging in risky activities widens the range of actions we can take against those engaging in them, though the baseline is not what can be done towards innocent bystanders, but towards innocent contributors.8 I now turn to determine the latter baseline. The asymmetrical fair share procedure Suppose again that Bill through no fault of his own is about to harm Alice. Basically, there are three positions to take regarding whether we should give priority to the innocent contributor, Bill, or his innocent victim, Alice. First, reasoning that people have a right to defend themselves against any unjustified aggression or threat, we might elect to help Alice. When becoming an unjust threat to another person, Bill might be thought to lose his right not to be significantly harmed. If someone is unlucky and contributed to harm, this unlucky person has to carry the cost, including the costs of helping to defend the prospective victim from harm. We need to take proportionality into account, but the fact that Bill is morally innocent is understood to be insignificant with regard to the question of defensive force, as he is causally responsible for being a threat to another person. For situations in which killing Bill would be necessary to thwart the threat, and the harm or risk to Alice was sufficiently grave, killing Bill would be permissible.9 Alternatively, we could instead give priority to Bill. The central intuition supporting this position is that Bill has not done anything to lose his right not to be harmed or killed, and should be treated accordingly. To become a permissible target, one might argue, one must be See McMahan “The Ethics of Killing in War” (2004): 693–733 and “The Basis of Moral Liability to defensive Killing” Philosophical Issues 15 (2005): 386–405. 7 I argue along these lines, though for a different purpose, in ‘Contractual Killing’ Ethics 115 (2005): 692–720. 8 It may at this point be worth observing that the tendency to let intentions play a role may be derived from the idea of being engaged in risky activity. After all, taking up arms and intending to kill someone is a risky activity in the sense that there might be some chance that the person is not a justified target after all. 9 One position that appears to take this form is Judith Jarvis Thomson’s right-based account of self-defence. It seems to put innocent aggressors and culpable aggressors in the same boat, as the right to self-defence is based on right violations which, according to Thomson, can be committed by innocent as well culpable aggressors. According to her, culpability has nothing to do with the right to self-defence, since an agent who exercises this right is not an agent of justice. See J. J. Thomson “Self-Defence”, Philosophy and Public Affairs 20 (1991): 283–310. For a good discussion of Thomson’s position see Yitzhak Benbaji “Culpable Bystanders, Innocent Threats and the Ethics of Self-Defense” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 35 (2005): 585–622 6 4 morally responsible for putting someone in danger. Innocent contributors would accordingly be morally indistinguishable from innocent bystanders. And, since there are strict constraints on what we can do to innocent bystanders to save ourselves and others from harm, there will be strict limits on what we permissibly can do to Bill as well. Call this view the “on-parwith-a-bystander view”.10 The on-par-with-a-bystander view assumes that an innocent contributor has no additional duty to shoulder the costs of neutralising the threatening consequences of his or her behaviour. Harming Bill to protect Alice in a situation in which the former is about to harm the latter through no fault of his own would be regarded on par with harming an innocent bystander, David, for the same purpose. Most maintain that not much could permissibly be done to David to save Alice from harm. It could perhaps be contested whether the on-parwith-a-bystander view gives priority to the innocent aggressor. But notice that in typical cases the decision to mount defensive force is in the hands of the victim. By holding a prospective victim’s use of force against the innocent aggressor to be on par with force directed at an innocent bystander, the upshot would be that the aggressor would be morally permitted to use defensive force against almost any forceful action taken by the victim, just as bystanders would. An attractive feature of the on-par-with-a-bystander view is that it points to something about which it is easy to agree has moral significance, namely moral responsibility. However, there are good reasons to distinguish between an innocent contributor and an innocent bystander and let mere causality have moral significance, though not for the purpose of blame or judging character. The view I shall propose – the third position – might be seen as occupying the middle ground between the positions just sketched. A fair share In the on-par-with-a-bystander view, the assumption is that mere causal connection is morally insignificant. There is some plausibility to this. If a person is unlucky and causes harm to another, the second person is unlucky too, as she ends up as the victim. It seems to make little sense to single out any particular person as being the unlucky one to determine who should be given priority. Yet although the direction of the causal link does not tell us where our priorities should lie, it would be a mistake not to recognize that the causal connection joining them also distinguishes them from others. An initial proposal would The most explicit supporter of the on-par-with-a-bystander view is Michael Otsuka, see his “Killing the Innocent in Self-Defence”. 10 5 therefore be that both have been unlucky, and that we therefore should divide the harm between them, keeping everyone else out. In the example at hand, harm would be divided between Bill and Alice, and not imposed on David. Normally, when we claim that fairness requires that something should be divided between particular individuals, we take it to imply that it should be divided equally, unless there is reason to the contrary. When two people are involved and dividing the cost is possible, I shall accordingly divide the cost equally between them. Hence, if Alice was in danger of losing both arms due to Bill’s innocent behaviour, and Cathy was in a position to intervene and divide the cost between Bill and Alice equally, each losing one arm, then she should do so. To take on a fair share in such cases means roughly that the harm is divided in equal parts amongst the people in the causal chain. We can indicate why Bill, as an innocent contributor, should bear a larger share than innocent bystanders by appealing to Bill’s duty to compensate Alice for damages sustained. If a person’s property is damaged, the person who did so is generally required to compensate the victim for his loss. And though one could argue that the innocent contributor has no duty to shoulder the whole cost and make full recompense, the contributor does, we may plausibly assume, have a duty to shoulder (at least) a fair share, i.e., fifty per cent if the cost can be divided. At this point one might wonder why we should restrict our attention to those involved in the causal chain and no one else. Given the alleged moral insignificance of contribution, harm to innocent people should be divided equally between all kinds of innocents, including contributors, victims, and bystanders alike. A fair share procedure should consequently include bystanders in addition to innocent contributors and their respective victims. That would have serious counter-intuitive upshots, however. For instance, it would be permissible first to impose harm on an innocent bystander if the harm inflicted was reduced from three limbs to two or less, and second to kill one innocent bystander to save two innocent people. This proposal would obviate reasons for thinking innocent bystanders have claims on some special kind of protection, and few are ready to accept this conclusion. Luck reconsidered We have been considering the proposal that the innocent contributor and the innocent victim have both been unlucky, and that they ought to divide the burden between them. But though the equal-bad-luck view might be plausible on the face of it, there is an important difference between the two parties. It seems wrong to say that the victim has been unlucky if he or she 6 is able to escape the threat even though it leads to the death of the innocent contributor. The prospective victim’s bad luck is essentially connected to a prospect of being harmed. By contrast, it makes perfect sense to say that the innocent contributor has been unlucky in causing the death of the defendant, even though he should be able to survive himself – and lucky in that respect. Clearly, being lucky means different things here. In one situation bad luck refers to being a victim, in another it refers to being a contributor to harm. One might perhaps want to say that Alice is unlucky as well in that she needs to allow an innocent person to be harmed in order to save herself. But although the latter is true, I do not think we look upon this kind of bad luck in any way close to being a victim or a contributor. The bad luck on the part of Alice in not being able to save Bill is just the same bad luck that David would be subject to as an innocent bystander in case he were unable to save Bill. Anyway, I shall at this point propose that the innocent contributor has been exposed to the initial bad luck and has a duty to shoulder his or her part of the harm. The victim is still to be regarded as an innocent bystander with no additional duty to shoulder any particular cost to alleviate the burden on the innocent contributor. To capture this, I propose an asymmetrical fair share procedure, which requires the innocent contributor to take on a fair share of the burden at stake. Since the duty to take on a fair share is asymmetrical, it only applies to innocent contributors. A rationale behind this duty may be stated as follows. If a person has innocently initiated or sustained a causal sequence the effect of which is to put someone else under threat of being harmed, then, other things being equal, he has a duty as a matter of fairness to shoulder his share of the cost. There are situations that seem to support this proposal. Envisage innocent Bill again. He is falling at speed towards Alice, endangering both her legs. Alice has three options. She can remain where she is, lose her limbs but save Bill’s; she can roll to the left, save one of her own legs and one of Bill’s; or she can roll to the right, saving both of her own legs but causing Bill to lose his. If we think the fair share procedure should be symmetrical, the defendant would have a duty to turn to the left, saving one of her own and one of Bill’s legs. But it sounds rather implausible. It would seem perfectly permissible, on the other hand, if Alice flipped over to the right, and saved her own legs, but at the cost of those of the threatener. Consider next a situation that gives Alice no possibility of escape. This time, innocent Bill has three options. He can continue the direction of his fall and save his own legs by using Alice’s as cushion; he can flip towards the left, which would cost them one leg each; 7 or he could flip over to the right, this time sacrificing both of his legs and saving those of the victim. It seems plausible to assume the innocent contributor would have to accept half of the burden, and his appeal to innocence would at most justify his reluctance to bear the whole load. Hence, the innocent contributor would have a duty to turn, and turning left could be enough to discharge this duty. One might think the difference between the two cases has to do with Alice simply having to flip to one side, saving herself at the cost of Bill’s legs in the first example, while Bill needs to use Alice’s legs to cushion his fall, and thereby save his legs in the second. But that is not obvious. It seems permissible for Alice to shield herself even if it costs the innocent aggressor two limbs, or shoot him in the leg if that saves one of hers. By contrast, if Bill sees Alice’s attempt to roll over, in which case he will lose both of his legs, he may not alter his trajectory so that he manages to save one of his at the expense of hers, nor may he stop Alice from escaping to ensure that she cushions his fall.11 Observe that the duty to compensate is asymmetrical as well. Although innocent contributors have a duty to compensate costs imposed on a victim, the victim has no corresponding duty to compensate losses incurred by the innocent contributor. If Bill, for instance, is unlucky enough to damage a particularly fragile item of his against Alice’s belongings, he alone has to carry the cost of repairing it, provided, of course, that Alice’s belongings were clearly not in the way. In accordance with these observations, third parties could permissibly intervene in a manner that inflicted a fair share on the contributor. If it is impossible to divide the cost third parties might nevertheless have reason to impose the whole cost on the innocent contributor rather than letting it fall on the victim. Although a contributor only has a duty to take on a fair share, the asymmetry in duty between contributors and victims seem to tip the scale towards the former when the cost cannot be divided. This being so, it would be permissible to kill an innocent contributor to save a victim. Against the on-par-with-a-bystander view Let me indicate other reasons for granting moral significance to mere contribution. If the onpar-with-a-bystander view were true, we would have to allow an innocent aggressor to kill 11 Well, why not one might ask? After all, when Bill was falling towards Alice he would have a duty to take on fifty percent, but Alice was at liberty to escape. This leaves fifty percent unaccounted for. One option would be to say that Bill has to take on fifty percent, and then they are at liberty to fight over the rest. I shall have to leave that open here. In the last section I indicate contractual reasons why it would be wrong to force Alice to accept more cost than what is required from innocent bystanders. 8 more than one person, as we ought not to kill one innocent bystander to defend a small number of people. Hence, if a person was on a killing spree because he had been drugged or manipulated we could not kill this person unless the number of his potential victims hit a threshold number allowing us to kill a bystander for the same end. That seems implausible. According to the asymmetrical fair share procedure, we would be permitted to kill the lesser number, that is, the innocent aggressor. For the imposition of harm, on the on-par-with-abystander view, we would have to allow an innocent contributor to inflict quite serious harm on a victim – removing two limbs for instance – and we could still not sever one of the contributors’ limbs to prevent it, because it is impermissible to subject innocent bystanders to such treatment. According to the view proposed here, we could require the innocent contributor to bear a fair share of the cost, preventing him or her even at the cost of a limb. Friends of the on-par-with-a-bystander view could retort that the proposal is only meant to cover situations involving killing, and that situations involving harming should be dealt with according to the asymmetrical fair share procedure. While this would save the view from some counterintuitive upshots, it would leave some and create others. For instance, while we permissibly could prevent an innocent contributor severing both of a third party’s arms by removing one of his, we would have no right to inflict more harm on him than on innocent bystanders if he were about to kill the victim. To this proponents of the on-parwith-a-bystander view could reply that it covers situations only of killing on both sides. True, but then it seems odd to say that we might prevent a few people suffering serious harm by inflicting serious harm on the innocent contributor, but not to prevent the killing of a few by killing the innocent contributor. Moreover, it seems difficult to explain why we should treat killing and inflicting (serious) harm differently. Supporters of this view would have to explain why causal connection makes a difference in situations of harm yet lacks it in conflict between lives. Proponents of the on-par-with-a-bystander view seem to believe that a slight increase in moral responsibility transforms the contributor into a permissible target for lethal defensive force – as they seem to find it permissible to kill negligent contributors while denying the permissibility of killing innocent contributors.12 It seems puzzling that such a slight increase 12 One might question whether the difference between innocence and negligence is slight. But observe that we do not tend to blame negligence very much, perhaps because most of us are guilty of it from time to time. It is important not to confuse it with recklessness. As George Fletcher points out, according to the Model Penal Code “the difference between reckless and negligent risk-taking arises at the level of the actor’s awareness of the impermissible risk. In cases of recklessness, the actor disregards the risk; in cases of negligence, he fails to perceive it.” George Fletcher Rethinking Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2000), p. 261). In line 9 in moral fault can have such a huge impact. If one denies the significance of mere contribution it is difficult to explain why contributing to harm with only a very minor degree in culpability (negligence) is so much more significant than innocent contribution to harm. After all, the innocent contributor remains on par with an innocent bystander while the negligent contributor suddenly finds him or herself as a legitimate target of lethal defensive force when that is necessary to save the victim. Yet how can such a large leap be justified by a slight increase in moral culpability? There is no such unaccounted-for gap if one accepts the moral significance of being an innocent contributor. According to the asymmetrical fair share procedure the first incremental step comes as a consequence of merely being a contributor, with liability increasing stepwise as a function of the contributor’s culpability. Perhaps even more puzzling for proponents of the on-par-with-a-bystander view is the wide discrepancy between negligent contributors and negligent bystanders that their view would seem to entail. Almost everybody accepts that negligent contributors are liable to lethal defensive force, while hardly anyone seems to think the same about negligent bystanders. But if one denies the significance of mere contribution, it becomes difficult to explain why negligence in causing harm is so much more significant than negligence in letting harm happen. Why is it worse – implying that significantly more might be done towards such a person – to initiate or sustain a harmful causal sequence rather than to let it happen if mere contribution lacks moral significance? The slight increase is in moral culpability, one might retort, and that is significant. But observe that the effect of increased culpability is not supposed to be equal across all situations. Culpability is supposed to be subject-dependent in the sense that culpability arising from a failure to save is taken to be very different from a failure in not harming. It is only culpability in contribution that is supposed to have such significant implications. But then it seems as if one backslides into the question of contribution again. And at this point, one cannot say it is significant because one person is contributing to harm, while the other is not, as one has already denied its moral significance. Why moral responsibility for causing harm should be regarded as particularly important if one denies that mere causality is morally significant seems to hang in mid-air.13 with this emphasis on awareness, we can say that while a negligent person would take the fact that he is exposing others to undue risk as a reason against so acting, a reckless person would not. 13 One might observe that a slight increase in causality has such a huge impact. But then, contribution to harm is typically something that comes in discrete jumps. If what is needed from you in one situation is to bend a 10 Contractual considerations I have previously argued on contractual grounds that in conflicts between innocent aggressors and their innocent victims we ought to give preference to the party who did not initiate the lethal conflict.14 I did not then consider the option of dividing the harm. Nor did I focus on causal connections since I was interested in situations of what I called “apparent aggressors”. The latter implied invoking the notion of reasonableness. An apparent aggressor is a person that it is reasonable to interpret as threatening, but who in fact is not a danger to anyone. There might be situations in which a person constitutes no causal threat to others but is morally responsible for behaving in such a way that it is reasonable to interpret him or her as threatening. In such cases it is uncontroversial to assume that when deciding where to allocate the cost, the apparent aggressor would be the one. But there could be situations in which an agent is not to blame for engaging in a certain activity but appears threatening all the same. In those cases, I have argued, if it is a reasonable interpretation of the agent’s behaviour, he or she still has to carry the cost. In this paper I put apparent aggressors to one side and focus on standard cases involving real aggressors or threats. I invoke hypothetical contractual reasoning to illuminate how harm should be divided among innocent people, and will consider the asymmetrical fair share procedure from the perspective of a hypothetical contract situation. The first thing to decide is who is to be a part in the contract. It seems plausible to assume agreement about the permissibility of giving priority to the innocent at the cost of the culpable, at least when the difference in culpability is above a certain threshold. We can accordingly restrict participation in the contract to innocent people or to people whose culpability is below this threshold. By appealing to hypothetical consent, the point is to identify who would have reason to give their consent in the contractual situation. In general, people make contracts because they have reason for doing so. Good reasons for entering into a contract are prospects of a good outcome for the contracted parties. In a hypothetical contract we let certain information be concealed from the participants, and the veil of ignorance I envisage could be called a “conflict veil”. As the name suggests, it is only a question of revealing the identity of those involved in a particular conflict where harm has to be distributed among innocent people. All finger, while in another you are required to push a handle as hard as possible with the force of your whole body, no one would take that difference to be significant. 14 See my ‘Self-Defence among Innocent People’ Journal of Moral Philosophy 2.2 (2005): 127–146. 11 other information remains available to the parties. In particular, they have access to the best available knowledge about their respective probabilities to end up in such conflicts. As prospective interveners, our central concern is what we know about the participants in virtue of which they would have reason to consent to rules dictating how third parties should interfere in the conflict. Clearly, their reasons would depend on their interests. One important interest, however, would be to reduce their risk of being harmed and of dying. I leave out other reasons they might have for selecting procedure to keep things simple. Reasons for accepting rules for regulating actions of self- and other-defence would accordingly be to avoid harm to the innocent while expending those of the culpable. Assumptions about the implicated parties’ preferences justify certain actions because by appealing to these preferences, we can make informed predictions about which rules they would have consented to. If these assumptions prove wrong, we can no longer plausibly claim that they would have consented to the rule by which our actions are guided. Hypothetical (actual preference) contractualism does not exhaust morality. Against a background of deontological restrictions, its aim is to explain when it might be permissible to violate specific restrictions. The basic idea is that such violations might be permissible provided they are in the interest of the implicated parties. As for deontological restrictions, I take them to be best understood as being in the interests of the individuals they protect. In particular, deontological restrictions are meant to prevent the sacrifice of individuals for the benefit of others. Given such restrictions, hypothetical contractualism aims to demonstrate that it may be occasionally in the interest of the implicated parties to sidestep certain restrictions. And when that occurs it would not count as unfair treatment if a particular person ended up as victim of the sidestepping. In the case at hand, the restriction to be circumvented is the alleged impermissibility of harming or killing an innocent person for a comparable benefit. Epistemic uncertainty We can first observe that being an initiating causal factor will often serve as a proxy for culpability. In a conflict between two people, the contributor will tend to bear more responsibility for the situation than a prospective victim. Even if a contributor is not morally culpable to the fullest extent, they may be guilty of some negligence or recklessness. And, since being an initiating causal factor is a discernable external feature, as opposed to moral culpability, sacrificing the initiator is likely to save more innocent people in the long run as we are less likely to get it wrong. Epistemic uncertainty therefore elicits a presumption in 12 favour of having a rule that gives priority to the defending party, i.e. the victim, because it will give (innocent) contracting parties a higher chance of survival and of avoiding harm. As contributors tend to be morally culpable more often than bystanders, participants in the contract have reason to consent to a rule that supports such priorities. It is difficult for people under attack to know whether or not aggressors are innocent. A rule that gives priority to those who respond to a causal threat will therefore enable people to avoid giving up their life on wrong occasions. Wrong occasions are instances in which the defender erroneously believes the aggressors to be innocent and therefore fails to defend herself. If we were to choose a rule that permits self-defence only in cases in which the contributors were known to be culpable, there would be instances in which innocent people were killed while the culpable got off scot-free. To avoid this, we should adopt a rule permitting prospective victims the use of defensive force against initiators of harmful causal sequences. Participants in the hypothetical contract therefore have good reason to allow a rule permitting the use of defensive force against initiators inasmuch as compliance to the rule would not cause innocent deaths while saving the culpable. On the contrary, it would sometimes save the innocent at the cost of the culpable. Moreover, it would help third parties coordinate intervention. Third parties might lack time and ability to coordinate their intervention, and would appreciate a simple rule helping them decide on which side to intervene. Being a contributor to prospective harm is a discernible external feature of conduct that can be used for this purpose. We might observe an incentive-based argument as well. Adopting a rule according to which the contributor has to carry the cost would minimize the likelihood of such situations arising in the first place, since people would take pains to avoid becoming contributors. This goal could perhaps be achieved best by saying that those who initiate a threat are not fully innocent unless they have taken every reasonable precaution to avoid becoming contributors and that only fully innocent contributors are without liability. This would give people an incentive to take all reasonable precautions against becoming contributors. Only people who had taken such precautions would be treated as innocent parties. A problem with this is that moral responsibility is not an easily observable feature. It will often be difficult to establish whether the agent has taken the required precautions. A rule giving priority to the defending party might serve the contracting parties better. Of course, any known moral responsibility on part of the contributor would consolidate priorities further and do so according to the degree of moral culpability. 13 Epistemic uncertainty tips the balance in favour of the defending party. How far will depend on estimates of likely contributor’s culpability. How often is a contributor about whom we have no particular knowledge in fact an innocent contributor? Without attempting precise estimates, it seems uncontroversial to assume that contributors are more likely to at least have been guilty of negligence or recklessness than the victim who is at the receiving end of their harmful conduct. Of course, sometimes the rule to prefer the defending party will be wrong, and what looks like a victim may in fact be the aggressor, or that harming this person may have been justified for some other reason. But although this is true, the frequency of such mistakes will hardly be sufficient to give the contracting parties a reason against favouring prospective victims. Now, the preference with which prospective victims should be treated will depend on the epistemic conditions. It is easy to judge wrongly with regard to innocence. If determining priority on the basis of slightly greater numbers would not save more innocent people than would be saved by giving priority to the defending party – because, perhaps, some of the aggressors were culpable – the contracting parties would have reason to support a rule that gave priority to the defending party even when there are minor asymmetries in numbers.15 Hence, the contractual argument also recommends giving priority to the defending party in situations with more than one contributor, but at some point, the asymmetry in numbers will suggest giving priority to the assumed innocent contributors. Epistemic transparency I have indicated reasons for selecting a rule that gives priority to the defending party. These arguments traded on epistemic uncertainty. But although contribution is often correlated with culpability, there are instances in which we know this is not the case. Division From a contractual perspective, the fact that an individual has bad luck and becomes a contributor has no bearing on choice of distributive pattern. The contracting participants want to reduce the risk of being harmed. Assuming transparency and full knowledge of the parties’ innocence, there might be no grounds to decide either way. An equal split would possibly be in their interest. But why should the contractors be interested in having harm divided? Why locate a particular duty on innocent contributors? Why not just leave them on par with bystanders? Assuming knowledge, the uncertainty 15 See my ‘Killing Soldiers’ Ethics & International Affairs 20:4 (2006): 455–475. 14 argument does not apply, although it might be worth mentioning that we seldom have full certainty in real life anyway. The incentive-based argument still carries some weight though. By knowing one will be held accountable as an innocent contributor, one has reason to make serious efforts to avoid becoming one.16 Again, the expansive responsibility argument would probably provide much of the same incentive. But besides the limits alluded to above, a further problem with this argument is that it gives people an incentive to feign innocence since so much is at stake. This incentive is reduced if one requires innocent contributors to take on a fair share. A slight increase in culpability would only add a minor cost-related duty, as one would already be required to shoulder a fair share by merely being an innocent contributor. The latter would, of course, have an incentive to pretend not being a contributor at all. But that is a more difficult enterprise. Another important reason to adopt a fair share procedure, rather than letting the victim bear the whole cost, comes from the observation that it is better to take a fifty percent loss than a fifty percent risk of sustaining the whole cost. For instance, it is better to lose one arm than have a fifty percent risk of losing both. There is likely to be some disagreement here, but I would guess most people would generally prefer a defined loss to a fifty percent risk of the double loss. Think of any dividable entity of value in your possession, like money, property, life span, health, or body parts, and consider whether you would prefer losing fifty percent of any one of them or a chance of keeping the whole of it at the cost of fifty percent risk of loosing the whole entity. It may pay to observe that there is no reason to give priority to the innocent contributor from the perspective of the contractual position. An alternative to fair share, namely letting harm fall where fate dictates – on the victim normally – may nevertheless merit consideration. According to this proposal, when both parties are innocent neither of them would have any particular duty to shoulder cost, and both would be permitted to use defensive force on the other. Third parties would have no reason to intervene. But letting the involved parties fight themselves out of the problem mostly exacerbates the harm, giving the contractual parties reason to reject this option. Allowing third parties to prevent escalations could partly mitigate the problem, but it would be unreasonable to expect complete success. Moreover, this kind of procedure would favour certain groups and types, of people, giving those who are member of neither reason to reject it. 16 We see this at play in civil law, as strict liability, where innocent contributors are held accountable for damages that they cannot be held morally responsible for. 15 Asymmetry Why give moral significance to causal connections at all? If one thinks luck-factors like being an innocent contributor to harm are irrelevant, one might think the burden at stake should be divided with no regard to causal connection. The contracting parties could likewise let all innocents be on par in order to reduce harm, and include victims, contributors, and bystanders alike. On the face of it, it would seem to benefit all participants by reducing risk of being harmed and killed. I previously appealed to the counterintuitive upshots of such views, which would leave the innocent with no special protection. That will not do contractually. Explaining restrictions contract-wise entails asking whether the parties in a hypothetical contract situation have non-moral reasons for accepting them. We cannot assume, for example, that harming innocent bystanders is morally worse than harming innocent contributors. On the contrary, the argument should explain the impermissibility of widening the net with reference to the situation we would end up with if it were permissible to use force against victims and bystanders. When parties evaluate reasons for accepting rules, they are interested in long-term consequences across a broad range of circumstances, not how they work in special or restricted cases. It may be reasonable to discount future consequences, but not to consider them at all seems irrational. The argument from epistemic uncertainty distinguished between contributors and victims. While contribution is often correlated with culpability, victim-hood is normally associated with innocence. The latter is true of bystanders as well.17 These observations singled out innocent contributors. But when there is no uncertainty, the contracting participants may have no reason to discriminate between innocent contributors, victims, and bystanders. However, a version of what I elsewhere have called “the undermining argument”18 explains why it is wise to draw a distinction between contributors on the one hand, and victims and bystanders on the other. The general point is that if there are no constraints, unfortunate long-term consequences will undermine the antecedent rationality of including everyone in the general lot. The argument has two steps, of which the first concerns the danger of intervening with force, as recipients are unlikely to accept it without defence. Fear of resistance will reduce the number of interventions. Whether anything will be gained by 17 Of course, they may have failed to assist the victim at moderate cost, and in that sense be morally responsible. I do not discuss such failures here. 18 See my ‘Contractual Killing’. 16 permitting force against bystanders is therefore a moot question, as people would be wary of involving themselves. The second step trades on the previous reduction and says that successful interventions by force might cost more than the achieved level of harm reduction because people will want to avoid being used for harm reduction purposes. If people are aware of the danger of being used in a bid to temper overall harm, they will take steps to avoid getting involved in the first place.19 Contracting participants have reason therefore to grant some people protection against use of force. The degree of protection depends on how calculations pan out for innocent bystanders, victims, and contributors. Remember the typical situation we are discussing. Bill innocently harms Alice, who is not in a position to defend herself. Cathy is close by and able to intervene in the causal chain to avert the threatened harm. A fourth person, David, who is an innocent bystander, is also present. Cathy and David are bystanders. There are good reasons why Cathy should be allowed to prevent Bill from harming Alice, but that she should not interfere with David. If Cathy were permitted to use force against David in order to reduce overall harm, David would be permitted to intervene against her. They are unlikely to accept this kind of risk in order to help protect Alice, who we assume is a stranger to them. Generally, this norm would provide bystanders an incentive to move away rather than helping those already involved. These negative consequences will have to be measured against the likely benefits of permitting the use of force in the first place. Some benefits are to be expected. A certain number of people, who would otherwise not be saved from harm would now be saved. However, it is unlikely that number thus saved would exceed the number not saved because bystanders will look to avoid accidents for fear of being used to reduce overall harm. The contracting parties would therefore have reason to prohibit use of force against bystanders.20 The same reasoning does not apply to innocent contributors. Permitting use of force against them has, on average, more positive than negative effects. In some situations it will lead to fewer people being harmed or reduce the severity of the harm; in others it will secure a fair distribution of the harm. There are, of course, unwelcome consequences of using force against innocent contributors as well. It will invite defensive force, giving prospective 19 One could perhaps have a rule allowing only use of force against those who do not intend to assist? But that doesn’t sound very operative. 20 That is, above what one can expect bystanders to be willing to shoulder in the first place, i.e. moderate costs. This is a good reason why the principle of assistance only tells us to assist others from severe harm if we can do so at moderate cost. 17 interveners reason for not getting involved (as we see it in real life). Bill, however, is already posing a risk, nothing new about that. And to disqualify forceful intervention altogether would leave harming and killing too often at the mercy of innocent contributors. Prospective victims are in some sense bystanders as well, but permitting force against them may nevertheless be a case apart. Granted it is permissible to impose a fair share on an innocent contributor, the idea to be considered is whether one should allow intervention to prevent a victim imposing more than a fair share on the innocent contributor. Alice may, for instance, take a shot at Bill, or flip over to the right, refusing to cushion his fall. Would the contracting parties have reason to permit forcing Alice to accept a fair share? As already noted, permitting bystanders to force Alice one way or another could encourage Alice to reply with force, giving bystanders an incentive to move away. Moreover, identifying the prospective victim will often be difficult, expanding the range of this implication. We are therefore compelled to ask what would be gained by such interventions in the first place. Not that much. After all, what we are trying to avoid here is the prospective victim subjecting the innocent contributor to excessive force. In most cases we will not know for certain whether both parties are innocent. It will therefore be used wrongly at times, and given the paucity of knowledge and the victim’s inability to use force there will be few instances of correct use. Of course, not sanctioning actions against the victim means implicitly allowing her to impose more than a fair share on the innocent contributor from time to time. This may generate reason to permit forceful intervention whenever a victim tries to impose (unconscionably) disproportionate harm on the contributor compared to what she is about to suffer. This may seem intuitively plausible, but our intuitions are likely to vary. Some may think that victims have no particular duty to protect the person who poses a danger to them; others that although they have no duty to take on a fair share, they are (slightly) more duty bound than innocent bystanders who are not under threat. For instance, they may think distance is morally significant and people close by have a (slightly) stronger duty to address a particular need than people further away. Prospective victims are pretty close. They could accordingly have a (slightly) higher duty to bear more of the burden of protecting innocent contributors from harm. Another reason for thinking more could be demanded from prospective victims, is that nature, destiny, or whatever has selected them to be victims. Any redistribution would require human intervention. Anyway, I shall assume that considerations like these, if they have any weight, will not bring the victim on par with a contributor, but may slightly set him 18 or her apart from other bystanders. We may, for instance, think you ought not duck harm to save a finger if what is at stake for the other is his or her life, though we might be less inclined to tell you to intervene if doing so would cost you a finger.21 Concluding remarks In this paper I have argued that merely being a contributor to harm is morally significant. I first indicated the intuitive plausibility of the asymmetrical fair share procedure, according to which innocent contributors have a duty to take on a fair share of the harm in question when the harm can be divided and reallocated, and a fair share of the risk of being harmed or killed when redistribution is impossible. The asymmetrical fair share procedure attempts to accommodate the view that an innocent contributor ought to be distinguished from innocent bystanders while taking into account that he or she is not at fault and should not be required to shoulder the whole load. I then developed a contractual account to explain why causal connection is morally significant. Epistemic uncertainty made contribution to harm a proxy for culpability, giving innocent contracting participants reason to prioritize defending parties. As the uncertainty was reduced, the participants had reason to favour something close to the asymmetrical fair share procedure. Generally, permitting forceful intervention has a tendency to scare people off, and must to be traded against the likely benefit of allowing force in the first place. The contracting participants had reason to permit the imposition of a fair share of the harm on innocent contributors; as we observed, the negative effects are few in number, the benefits many. For bystanders, by contrast, the negative effects would predominate, providing reason to prohibit force against them. For victims, we observed very few benefits and some negative effects. I tentatively suggested that unless the victim was engaged in very disproportionate use of force against the contributor, use of force against him or her would be impermissible. We can now make sense of the previously observed intuitive difference in luck between an innocent contributor and a prospective victim. In that situation Bill was unlucky not merely because he contributed to harm, but because he had become permissible target of force and incurred a duty to shoulder a fair share of the harm. By contrast, Alice’s bad luck On the issue of ducking harm, see Christopher Boorse and Roy A. Sorensen “Ducking Harm” The Journal of Philosophy 85 (1988): 115-134. 21 19 was essentially linked to the prospect of being harmed simply because she did not incur any additional duty to bear cost by having become a prospective victim. 20