Two problems with the last argument for the immortality of the soul in Plato’s Phaedo. A problem with the argument as outlined in your handout is that C1 (souls must be alive and cannot be dead) in fact does not follow logically from P1 (An organism has a soul if and only if it is alive). Logicians call such a leap in reasoning a non sequitur. After all, P1 is talking about organisms, not souls. In logical terms: P1: For all organisms O, O has a soul if and only if O is alive. C1: For all souls S, S is alive. We could also modify the argument, so that it uses the concept of necessity. There are a few ways to define “necessity.” One would be that a proposition is necessary if and only if it’s the negation of a self-contradictory proposition. Another would be that a proposition is necessary if and only if it must be true at all times, no matter what else is or is not the case. In logic, “it is necessary that…” is expressed by a box, “”. This modified argument would thus go as follows: P1: (Socrates has a soul if and only if Socrates is alive) P2: Socrates has a soul. (Note that this is just a contingent fact; in other words, it’s possible that Socrates might never have been born.) C1: (Socrates is alive) – and thus Socrates cannot die. In other words, he is immortal. This argument makes the same mistake as: P1: (1+2=3) P2: I have exactly 1 coin in my pocket and add exactly 2 more. C1: (I have exactly 3 coins in my pocket) The problem here is that the conclusion does not follow from the premises. Admittedly, the proposition “I have exactly 3 coins in my pocket” does follow logically, but not C1, which asserts that I must necessarily have exactly 3 coins in my pocket. After all, this is just a contingent fact – in other words, it’s possible that I might have 4 coins in my pocket. Now admittedly, we could modify this argument as follows to make it valid: P1: (Socrates has a soul if and only if Socrates is alive) P2: (Socrates has a soul) C1: (Socrates is alive) – and thus Socrates cannot die. In other words, he is immortal. But this argument would commit the logical fallacy of begging the question, i.e., assuming the conclusion as a premise. For naturally anyone who believes that it’s necessary that Socrates has a soul would also believe that it’s necessary that he’s alive. Thus the argument fails to do what arguments are supposed to do: give someone who doesn’t already believe the conclusion a good reason to believe it. Interpretations of Socrates’ final words: “We ought to give a cock to Aesclepius.” 1. The translator’s interpretation, which is the “standard” one: Socrates is certain that he has purified his personal soul so that it is completely free from his body and its desires, and advises his friends to offer a sacrifice to Aesclepius (the god of healing) in thanks for his personal soul’s being cured of the “disease” of bodily life. Problem with this interpretation: In fact, sacrifices appear to be made to Aesclepius by sick people hoping for a cure, not (just) in thanks for having been cured. 2. A modified interpretation: Socrates is certain that he has purified his personal soul so that it is completely free from his body and its desires, and advises his friends to offer a sacrifice to Aesclepius (the god of healing) in hopes that his personal soul will be cured of the “disease” of bodily life. Problem with this interpretation: If Socrates is certain that he has cured his personal soul of the “disease” of life, then he doesn’t need Asclepius to cure him. 3. OK, one more interpretation: Socrates is not certain that he has purified his personal soul so that it is completely free from his body and its desires, and thus advises his friends to offer a sacrifice to Aesclepius (the god of healing) in hopes that his personal soul will be cured of the “disease” of bodily life. Problem with this interpretation: Socrates’ theory (as presented by Plato in the Phaedo) is that one’s personal soul is guaranteed to have been cured of the “disease” of life if and only if one gains pure knowledge. And (for Plato, at least) knowledge must be certain. Thus if Socrates isn’t certain that he has purified his personal soul, then his personal soul cannot be cured of the “disease” of bodily life. Even Aesclepius couldn’t help him out for this “disease”! Conclusion: We must find an interpretation of Socrates’ last words that meets the following criteria: 1. The sacrifice to Aesclepius is intended to get him to heal some kind of soul from some kind of “disease.” 2. Socrates is thus uncertain that the kind of soul he’s concerned about will survive. 3. This kind of soul isn’t Socrates’ personal soul. Argument: Socrates in the Phaedo was either concerned with his personal immortality, i.e., the survival of his soul after his physical death; or he was concerned with something else. Let’s assume that Socrates’ concern was with the immortality of his personal soul. Now according to a view he espouses toward the beginning (cite), and then toward the end of the Phaedo (cite), philosophy is a preparation for death. During his natural life, that is, a philosopher tries to free himself as much as possible from the distractions of his body, including importantly his senses, in order to better contemplate the true objects of knowledge: the forms. To the extent to which a philosopher has accomplished this goal, the philosopher has freed his separable soul from his body, thus allowing it to survive the death of the body and live forever in contemplation of the forms, never again to be reincarnated. (Note that the argument at the beginning of the Phaedo assumes that genuine knowledge is possible, that it can’t be gained through the bodily senses, and that it’s gained only by the soul’s attending to something else (the forms). This doesn’t imply that the soul is immortal, but only that if genuine knowledge is possible, then the soul is separated from the body for the time at which the soul has genuine knowledge. The story told toward the end of the Phaedo is just that – a story – and contains no argument. Let’s now focus on the view – never actually argued for in the Phaedo – that the genuine philosopher’s soul has secured immortality by gaining true knowledge of the forms. (The ‘clothes’ argument, the ‘harmony’ argument, and the If the argument is unsound, then Socrates has not successfully gained true knowledge, but is instead deceived by his senses. That is, he makes a claim about a relation between the forms of soulness, life, and indestructibility that does not in fact hold. The correct relations seem to be that it’s necessary that if x has a soul then x is alive. Furthermore (it’s necessary that) if it’s necessary that x is alive, then x is indestructible. In this way, the form of soulness does not stand to the form of life in the same way that the form of 3 stands to the form of numerical oddness. The problem here is a category error: one can’t argue (without begging the question) that a person is a soul (which would imply that the person is alive); rather,. This is quite different from: (the Beatles) are a quintet; all quintets participate in the form of 4ness, and the form of 4ness participates in the form of numerical evenness. P1: Qb P2: nec: (x)(Qx > 4x) P3: nec: (x)(4x > Ex), From which follows C1: nec: (bQ > Ex) And hence Cs: Eb In the case of the forms of soulness, life, and indestructibility, the argument would be: P1: Ss P2: nec: (x)(Sx > Lx) P3: (x)(nec: Lx > Ix) From which follows: C1: Ls But not Is This is because the argument fails to establish that it’s necessary that Ls The confusion here can also be seen in the 2 premises: the first speaks of persons having a soul; the second speaks of souls (but not persons) being alive. The second premise should simply state that Sp = Lp. The subject of both propositions is a person, not a soul. The form of soulness, that is, is a predicate, not a subject. If one considers the form of soulness as a subject, then perhaps it would be correct to say that the form of soulness falls under the form of life. But it’s no more necessary that Socrates has a soul than that the Beatles are a quintet. (Note that there are 2 problems here: the confusion (on the obvious construal of the argument) of the subject in the first and second premises; and (on a different construal of the argument) the slippage between a necessary conditional and a necessary consequent. From which follows C1: nec: (bQ > Ex) And hence Cs: Eb pHs =def. Lp. But this definition doesn’t imply that Ls. Throughout the text, he does give numerous hints that this is in fact the case (cite).