The Wider The Choice, The Greater The Responsibility The Balance Between Selfishness And Altruism In Daily School Life Angela Gastager The main purpose of the following articlei is to ask for teachers’ decision-making in prosocial moral dilemmas on the one hand, and on the other hand to ask generally if it is appropriate for teachers to bring their own values into the classroom at all (Damon). The different social conflicts arise from conflicting values. A realistic teaching dilemma will be discussed. In the narrative, the protagonist believes two things must be done; one for personal reasons and one for his or her students. What determines a moral consideration and what should the arrangements for making decisions in certain situations be? Facets of authenticity concerning teachers’ judgments will be discussed. There are many simultaneous values and goals, therefore internal plurality of values will also be discussed (Patry). The internal tension between selfish and altruistic demands (McClintock/ van Avermaet) requires a balance between interests specific to the individual and those of others in many different situations in daily life, and a solution in search of “justice as fairness“ (Rawls) as the most acceptable. Ideal forms of changing the roles in a democratic discourse of all involved individuals are a cry for sympathy without being required to ask the question “Why should I not be permitted to do something good for me?“ In professional teachers’ consideration, it seems to be difficult to claim. In this context, one has to discuss some conditions which enhance the development of a so-called altruistic personality (Hunt). Some of the social influences will also be mentioned (Staub). How do teachers react to the dilemma between duty and personal needs? Some of the results of the conferenceii will also be presented. About a month ago I had a discussion with the father of a 14 year old girl and a 17 year old boy. I listened very attentively to his stories concerning his daily dilemmas at home. Should he decide in favor of his children? What is the amount of freedom he and his wife should grant them? At once I compared his dilemmas with teaching experiences I had some years ago. From the moment I entered school until I left I was almost permanently tense. The world in which teachers, pupils, and - indirectly - parents are connected to one another is a living and dynamic human community where decisions must be taken (see Oser & Patry, 1994, p. 6048) and norms clash. What should be done? It is primarily the task of the teacher responsible to make decisions quickly which are in agreement with his/ her own values. In all the varied situations in daily school life, (s)he cannot escape from making decisions. Therefore responsibility is demanded. 1. Introduction Ann’s trilemma: Betty, a student who is in the 6th year of secondary school is very bad at Mathematics. Her last test takes place tomorrow. If she fails again, she will have to repeat the class. Her maths teacher, Ann, knows this and could help her by working with her in extra lessons during the afternoon. However, at the same time, she ought to be earning extra money by teaching 10 children in her private dance group. She earns 70 ECUs for this. This same afternoon, her best friend has arranged a birthday party in a cottage in the mountains. The friends invited will be taking a coach up to the cottage. Therefore there will be no chance for Ann to join the group later, i.e. after helping Betty or teaching the dance group. This relatively realistic story requires that a decision be made in a short period of time. Being confronted with three different choices, what should Ann do? A central consideration could be “Is Ann primarily committed to helping the student, or is she also entitled to fulfill her personal needs? And why?“ Is the response “Yes, I’ll help my student without any question of ‘What will I receive for my unselfish help?’“ appropriate? What about the contrary „Why should I not be permitted to do something good for myself?“ Considerations such as these are important in a teacher’s daily life. In general, questions like these cannot be reduced as relating to people of a certain culture, or of a certain age or developing stage. Questions like these are moral questions and play an important role in every kind of human system: in the family, in the relationship between two life-partners, in school, in a political party and in a learning group, etc. To consider questions like these is in agreement with considering moral activity as a basic human need (see Heller, 1975, quoted from: Gronemeyer, 1988, p. 84). Here the human concept is a holistic one, which means that there is equivalence between physiological and psychosocial needs. In Ann’s trilemma the protagonist has several choices, which means that there are several conflicting values. This trilemma for the teacher is both difficult and challenging, because there are three values emerging from this conflict. Each value is one that she wants to consider (approach). Responsibility in making a triple-faceted decision like this is greater than in a conflict in which only two values conflict. “The wider the choice, the greater the responsibility“ (Lukas, 1989, pp. 79ff, my translation). The choice is always between two or more conflicting values. This is characteristic in responsibility: the values are attractive, positive and exclusive of each other. Additionally, responsibility will only become relevant if people do indeed have a choice. Both are applicable in Ann’s case. 2. Values in the classroom 2.1 Teaching and values It is commonly accepted that teaching has a moral dimension. But nevertheless there is a curious ambivalence in the profession concerning a teacher’s proper stance on moral issues. The following chapter is based on Damon’s article “Teaching as a Moral Craft and Developmental Expedition“. Damon began his seminars by asking the following general question: “Is it appropriate for teachers to bring their values into the classroom at all?“ A wide range of opinion and disagreement is provoked. But in many discussions of teaching-goals, Damon found strong consensus that teaching should foster - if nothing else - tolerance and critical thinking. “Within our educational culture, these two goals are so widely accepted and are rarely questioned that I often have trouble getting teachers to see them as values at all“ (Damon, 1992, p. 140). He expresses his astonishment about many teachers seeing a commitment to absolute tolerance in the classroom as perfectly consistent with the belief that teachers should not allow their values to affect their classroom judgments and behavior. Teachers often show a tendency to place the goal of critical thinking in a kind of natural metacategory outside the realm of values, as if there were no rational choice to be made in the matter. Since critical thinking is seen as an objective procedure for subjecting choices to the tests of reason and truth, it is not usually seen as itself being subject to evaluation (see Damon, 1992, p. 140f). How can ethical dilemmas be managed in the classroom, is a further important question asked Damon. Ethical dilemmas frequently arise in the classroom in contexts that are not part of the immediate teacher-student relationship. For example, students may have conflicts with one another, or they may report on other moral problems that they have experienced, in school or out. Moreover, in schools where moral education is explicitly part of the educational agenda, ethical dilemmas may be presented directly to students for purposes of analysis and reflection (see Damon, 1992, p. 145). “The question of how (or even whether) to express one’s own values in the classroom troubles many teachers” (Lyons, 1990, quoted from: Damon, 1992, p. 145). Some field have standards operating metaphors, such as teaching as a fine art, teaching as an expert profession, and teaching as an applied science. According to Tom many of these standard operating metaphors are leading educators astray. He proposes the „moral craft“ metaphor as an antidote to the misconceived standards by which a teacher’s work is being guided and judged (see Tom, 1984, quoted from: Damon, 1992, p. 139). Teaching is fundamentally a practical activity directed by explicit or implicit values. 2.2 Intrapersonal plurality of values In his article “One person - several values; some considerations about intrapersonal plurality of values” Patry (1997) says that there are several or many factors which are occasioning a protagonist to a certain action. That means that an act is not caused by one argument but rather by several arguments and adequate values. In most situations the reasons for concrete action are not mentioned or explained, not even if it would be necessary to justify one’s behavior. There are many reasons for our actions. Each person - and in this context especially teachers - wants to reach several goals and values. One has many simultaneous values, so that we speak about the plurality of values within a person. Men look out for different simultaneous goals. In our social behavior we try to reach justice and utility for ourselves at the same time. In education, teachers always recognise several goals (see Patry, 1997, pp. 64ff, my translation). Dilemmas can be very different types of situations with different characteristics of norms. For example, at school, teachers are very often in the following dilemma-situation: “Do I have to give up my own interests or needs in order to help my students?“ However, not satisfying one’s needs results in frustration. Can one require this from a teacher? If I neglect my own needs often the so called „Burn-out-Syndrome” may possibly be the consequence. Patry supposes that people who are able take responsibility for a longer time “live” a certain “healthy selfishness”; probably the balancing between altruistic and selfish interests is much easier for them than for others. The demand for „psycho-hygiene” arises. But in which dose would it be appropriate? How is it made acceptable? Not too much and not too little. It can be expressed in other words, “the mesotical principle”. In ethics one often speaks about the middle (according to Aristotle). “The good“ is valid as the right measure between two extremes, for instance sincerity between overstatement and irony, justice between grudge and malicious joy. Especially justice is an important virtue for a community (see Kunzmann et al., 1995, p. 51, my translation). 2.3 Justice as primary value Among values, “justice as fairness“ seems to be central. According to Hunt three norms or moral principles determine altruism (see Hunt, 1992, pp. 73f, my translation): * reciprocity: all forms of cooperation and interchangeable help * help or social responsibility: help for those who depend on you * fairness: It is a kind of summary of several norms advocating equality, humanity and justice. In the seventies the US-American philosopher Rawls developed a theory of justice. He says that a reasonable man and a complete member of a liberal and democratic society (he adds in 1992) strives for social basic goods. They are proposed in a kind of list including the social basis of persons’ self-reliance (see Koller, 1994, pp. 85ff, my translation). Justice as fairness is the most acceptable solution in search of a balance between selfishness and altruism. The claim of an ideal change of roles for all people involved requires the ability to express sympathy in different forms and helps to prepare for a democratic discourse. Rawls supposes that people want to contribute to an equality of chances within a society and among all members of the society. A minimal individual obligation for social cooperation is the consequence (see Ganthaler, 1995, pp. 84f, my translation). In the classroom, teachers as well as pupils, “should practice“ justice in realistic dilemma-discussions. 3. Selfish and altruistic demands 3.1 Definition of altruism - the internal tension „Altruism“ is a very complex issue. For an appropriate discussion, a clear definition of the term “prosocial“ is required. Staub defines a positive or prosocial act as an act which furthers the wellbeing of others (see Staub, 1982, p.1, my translation). Human beings have to overcome their selfish interests in order to favour the development of caring and acting for others (according to Comte, 1875). What is altruism? McClintock and van Avermaet propose a definition of altruism which shows the internal tension between selfishness and altruism visually (see figure 1) and can be considered in this manner: „If one supposes that the values of an actor are consistent over a longer time and one supposes that these values reflect a linear combination of ’payments’ to ‘ego’ and ‘alter’, then social values can be represented as utility function, which is constituted by linear vectors“ (McClintock & van Avermaet, 1982, quoted from: Harbach, 1992, p. 82, my translation). utility to „alter“ cooperation individualism utility to „ego“ Figure 1: vectors defining a part of social values (modified after McClintock & van Avermaet, 1982, quoted from: Harbach, 1992, p. 83, my translation) 3.2 The teacher as an altruistic personality 3.2.1 Characteristics Which characteristics does an altruistic personality have? It is possible to draw a picture of an altruistic personality in childhood and adulthood according to Hunts’ results and examples (see Hunt, 1992, pp. 117ff, my translation): * Mood in general: Adults in a positive mood usually are more prosocial than adults in a bad mood which includes that happy people are more prosocial than unhappy. * Empathy: Independent of their mood children and adults, who have a good sense for the feelings of others, are more likely to be altruistic. * Popularity: Popular children and adults are very helpful in general, which is an expression of some kind of need for connecting with others, outsiders are probably less helpful. * Self-concept: Persons having a high emotional value for their ego are more altruistic than persons with a low one. A positive image of oneself has the effect of a positive connection to others. * Attitude towards other people: Adults with a positive image of men are more helpful than others. That is the so called prosocial orientation (Staub). It is a combination of positive attitude towards other people, care for their well-being and feelings of responsibility. * Moral standards: Internal moral norms are integral (consistence) for prosocial orientation and an altruistic personality. The possibility that men with altruistic moral standards, are also altruistic in their way of acting, is very high. 3.2.2 Conditions of the development of an altruistic personality and social influences Some special influences seem to enhance personal characteristics of children which raise the probability for prosocial acting. Staub designs a system of coordinates which enhances a prosocial orientation (see figure 2). categories of influences on children 1.socialization through parents (adults) a) quality and style of interaction; warmth and affection, effective control, rational arguments for the child b) aspects with regard to the contents: demonstrated acting, induction 2.natural socialization, participation in prosocial activities 3.socialization through the peer-group 4.environmental conditions, grade of structuring kind of rules, distribution of the authority and other aspects principles of learning and developing 1.conditioning: punishment consequences or I.characteristics of a personality 1.orientation of values and affective orientations 2.identification 2.specific values, standards 3.loosening a cognitive imbalance or a cognitive discrepancy 4.learning by observation 3.convictions and valuations of persons, events and situations 4.tendencies of perception, sympathetic understanding, speed in defining events results II.acting: the function of a personality’s different characteristics and situative circumstances 5.opening of qualities 5.self-respect of the own person (selfperception) and of the environment 6.competencies, locus of control, plans and strategies, specific competencies 1.-3.: personal aims Figure 2: coordinates which enhance a prosocial orientation (according to Staub, 1982, p. 303, my translation) 4. Conflicting values 4.1 Conflict types Based on Dollard and Miller’s conflict types; approach-approach, approach-avoidance, and avoidance-avoidance (see Patry, 1997, p. 67), we distinguish “approach values“ and “avoidance values“. In the former, the high value lies in doing something, in the latter in notdoing something. The character of the conflict is inherent in the different values. A compromise never is possible. * Avoidance-avoidance: A person has to decide on two or more values which she or he does not want in reality or does not approach, for instance the „Corea dilemma“ (see Oser & Althof, 1992, p. 199). * Approach-avoidance: The famous „Heinz-dilemma” by Kohlberg (see Oser & Althof, 1992, pp. 171f) is an example where an approaching value (He wants the medicine for his wife.) and an avoiding value (Heinz will be punished for steeling the medicine.) clash. * Approach-approach: Two or more values which a person wants, wishes, or desires, conflict. While most dilemmas in the ethics literature are approach-avoidance or avoidanceavoidance conflicts, teacher Ann’s problem is an approach-approach-conflict, or even an approach-approach-approach trilemma. 4.2. Analysis of an approach-approach-approach trilemma Remembering Ann’s trilemma, which was presented in the introduction, in the following chapter the results of the group-discussions (see figure 3) of the conference will be presented. Questions of the trilemma-discussions: 1. What should Ann do? Why? 2. Is there an obligation to help her student in her spare-time? 3. Is the private birthday party more important than the extra lessons or the dancinggroup? 4. Ought teachers in general try to enhance their students’ ability in learning? Why or why not? 4.3 Aspects of an authentic teachers’ decision-making The use of different facets of teachers’ decision-making are possible and necessary in the following proposed steps. * In situations of choice you cannot flee from decision making and balancing; you have to consider all your possibilities. * In situations of choice it is very important that you do not balance and consider a very long time. You have to get used to it. After recognizing the meaningful decision you have to decide at once, although it is risky. In the process of balancing one can find an astonishing parallel to a situation which concerns justice (see Lukas, 1989, pp. 82f, my translation). What do authenticity and responsibility mean? Two main ideas, which can be trained and practiced in teachers’ decision-making, are proposed by Längle: * “To be responsible means to play a certain role. It is the place, where I am important, where I am acting. In this sense freedom is the basis for responsibility. * Freedom and responsibility are connected and cannot be divided“ (Längle, 1991, pp. 84f, my translation). Results of the trilemma-discussions 1st group 1. - no point in helping just before test - friendship is very important - money is not all in life +last exam is important + pupil will be very grateful 2. part of responsibility schooling is not about competition reference norms are criterial norms discrimination parents complaints 2nd group 1. Ann could try to see the problem, find a new perspective/ solution (e.g. other children could help her before the test.). 3rd group 1. help the pupil ...because the time is now ...responsibility of the teacher ...last exam (no consensus) 2. Betty has some responsibility 2. No, not obligated, because of her own. spare-time is very important for the teacher. She is a human being besides being a teacher. 3. same importance - depends on situations (personal emotional feeling) 4. It is the main task of a teacher: „School is the place to learn success in learning.“ Figure 3: Results of the trilemma-discussions of the conference ( means that Ann should study with the pupil and + means that Ann should not study with the pupil.) 5. Conclusions Often teachers have more freedom and more opportunities than they believe. Teachers have to take the consequences. In teacher-training, two kinds of preparations are possible and necessary: * The general type of preparation or the central question “What can I do in a dilemmasituation?“ * And second, the problems of teachers are always the same “What can I do, when it happens again?“ So teachers and students have to be prepared for quick decision-making; but to figure out the relevant features of a situation takes time. Decision-making under a time constraint therefore demands the decider to be consciencious about potential problems even before the critical situation occurs. In daily school life, especially in situations concerning the internal tension between selfish and altruistic demands of a teacher and a student, teachers have to be aware of the specific conditions of each situation. Maximum perception of the many different factors and coordinates of a situation is a visionary goal. But one might as well try. References Damon, W. (1992). Teaching as a moral craft and developmental expedition. In: F. Oser, A. Dick, & J.-L. Patry (Eds.), Effective and responsible teaching: The New Synthesis (pp. 139-153). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Ganthaler, H. (1995). Ethik in einer pluralistischen Gesellschaft (Ethics in a pluralistic society). In: I. Hodovsky & P. Zima (Eds.), Svobodna spolecnost-svobodna moralka. Freie Gesellschaft - freie Moral. Der Wertpluralismus und die ethische Verantwortung (pp. 81-85). Olomouc: Pedagogicke fakulte UP v Olomouci. Gronemeyer, M. (1988). Die Macht der Bedürfnisse. Reflexionen über ein Phantom (The power of needs. Reflections on a phantom). Reinbek/ Hamburg: Rowohlt. Harbach, H. (1992). Altruismus und Moral (Altruism and morality). Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag. Hunt, M. (1992). Das Rätsel der Nächstenliebe: der Mensch zwischen Egoismus und Altruismus (The compassionate beast). Frankfurt - New York: Campus. Koller, P. (1994). Soziale Güter und soziale Gerechtigkeit (Social goods and social justice). In: H.-J. Koch, M. Köhler, & K. Seelmann (Eds.), Theorien der Gerechtigkeit (Theories of justice). 15. Tagung der deutschen Sektion der internationalen Vereinigung für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie (pp. 79-104). Stuttgart: Steiner. Kunzmann, P., Burkard, F.-P., Wiedmann, F. (19955). Philosophisches Lexikon (Philosophical lexicon). München: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag. Längle, A. (1991). Sinnvoll leben (Living meaningfully). Wien: Verlag Niederösterreichisches Pressehaus. Lukas, E. (1989). Psychologische Vorsorge. Krisenprävention und Innenweltschutz aus logotherapeutischer Sicht (Psychological prevention for crisis and protection for inner life in logotherapeutical perspectives). Freiburg/ Breisgau: Herder. Oser, F., Althof, W. (1992). Moralische Selbstbestimmung. Modelle der Entwicklung und Erziehung im Wertebereich (Moral self-determination. Models of development and education in the field of values). Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta. Oser, F., Patry, J.-L. (1994). Teacher responsibility. In: L. Anderson (Ed.), The international encyclopedia of education, 2nd edition, volume „Teacher education“ (pp. 6048-6053). Oxford, England: Pergamon. Patry, J.-L. (1997). Eine Person - mehrere Werte. Überlegungen zum intrapersonalen Wertpluralismus (One person - several values. Some considerations about intrapersonal plurality of values). Pädagogische Rundschau, 51, 63-81. Staub, E. (1982). Entwicklung prosozialen Verhaltens. Zur Psychologie der Mitmenschlichkeit (Positive social behavior and morality). München-Wien-Baltimore: Urban und Schwarzenberg. i In: J.-L. Patry & J. Lethovaara (Eds.) 1998, Teacher ethics and responsibility, Tampere: University of Tampere Press, 63-74. ii Conference on Teacher Ethics, Tampere/ FIN: May 1996.