Book Review Time and Revolution: Marxism and the Design of Soviet Institutions Stephen Hanson, Time and Revolution: Marxism and the Design of Soviet Institutions (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1997), 258 pp. It has long been the practice of historians and social scientists to ignore the effects of ideas and ideologies on the design of political institutions. In particular, some scholars have argued that Communism had a negligible influence on the behavior of Soviet leaders. Instead, scholars have preferred to explain the decisions and policies of world leaders on the basis of rational calculation, interest group pressure, or bureaucratic politics. It is therefore refreshing to come across books like Stephen Hanson's Time and Revolution that seek to focus our attention on the importance of Communist ideology for the making (and unmaking) of the Soviet Union. Hanson isolates and describes the Marxist understanding of the concept of time, persuasively demonstrating its significance for Soviet politics. He argues, quite rightly, that it is necessary for scholars to show "concretely, rather than speculatively, how ideological visions get translated into institutional outcomes" (p. xiii). Nonetheless, because the book relies almost exclusively on published material, it too remains somewhat in the realm of the "speculative." Valuable as Hanson's contribution is, future scholars will need to use the newly available archival sources to trace more concretely the effects of ideology on Soviet institutions. Explicitly borrowing Max Weber's categories of "legitimate domination," Hanson distinguishes three general categories of attitudes toward time: traditional, rational, and charismatic. Traditional conceptions of time, Hanson explains, measure time according to the occurrence of certain events (such as festivals on a religious calendar) or according to the duration of certain processes (harvesttime, summertime, the length of a day). Rational time, which emerges in modern, industrial societies, is defined as [End Page 119] "an abstract grid outside all concrete events" (p. 11). It becomes a regulated system of reference, according to which all other events and processes are scheduled, and it is considered impersonal because it is seen as lying beyond all subjective interpretations. Finally, there is charismatic time, which, like Weber's "charismatic leadership," emerges during crises or revolutionary situations and claims to transcend all ordinary rational and traditional conceptions of time. According to Hanson, revolutionaries wish to manipulate time so that their actions can exist "in the unpredictable realm of the extraordinary" (p. 12). Charismatic groups and leaders claim that they can rearrange time to suit their own purposes and for the greater good, and they often argue that they are able to "start time over again" (p. 13). Hanson traces the development of this last, charismatic, conception of time through the work of Immanuel Kant, Georg Hegel, Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Vladimir Lenin, and Josif Stalin, all the way through the Gorbachev era. The book is clever and convincing in its interpretation of Marx's revolutionary philosophy, arguing that in calling for revolution Marx desired to transcend "rational" time. For Marx, the capitalist mode of production used rational time as another means of exploiting labor: By measuring productivity in work hours, it failed to respect the intrinsic value of a worker's product. The Communist revolution, according to Marx, would smash the tyranny of the abstract, impersonal chaining of humans to time lines and, in apocalyptic fashion, would thrust the power to control time back into human hands. Marx was, however, simultaneously fascinated with the efficiency of rationally organized modern industry. In his view, only the assembly line, with its timesaving methods, would allow workers to find the leisure time needed for their own fulfillment. Hanson labels Marx's desire to combine these two opposed approaches to time as "charismatic-rational" (p. 33). For Hanson, Marx's problem in reconciling the rational and charismatic notions of time was analogous to other major contradictions in his revolutionary theory, and his successors inherited these difficulties. In what is arguably the most interesting and convincing part of his book, Hanson reveals how Lenin and Stalin shared Marx's dilemma, seeking to avoid overreliance on either the charismatic or the rational in their approaches to time. According to Hanson, Lenin insisted that rationalism and charisma be balanced in all approaches to the revolutionary struggle. The difficulty of balancing these two conceptions of time caused Lenin to adopt contradictory economic policies at the start of the Soviet era. On the one hand, as Hanson demonstrates, Lenin was fascinated by the precision of Henry Ford's and Frederick Taylor's attempts to organize work. Lenin wished to use all of the modern approaches to production, including the precise timing of worker movements on the assembly line, to maximize the productivity of Russian industry--a necessity if the Soviet Union was to compensate for its economic backwardness. On the other hand, this mastering of the rational approach to time was, for Lenin, simply not sufficient. Another step could be taken by Communist workers, one that would use revolutionary enthusiasm to transcend the limits of the ordinary workweek. Lenin supported the creation of subbotniki, in which workers came to work on Saturdays; he was particularly pleased that workers who took part were often willing to expend twice their normal effort. [End Page 120] No less interesting is Hanson's analysis of Stalin's contradictory goals in implementing the first Five-Year Plan, which he describes as part of Stalin's attempt to bring charisma back into a social and economic system that lost its revolutionary edge during the New Economic Policy (NEP) in the 1920s. The tension between charismatic and rational reappeared and was expressed, as Hanson points out, in Stalin's stated aim to combine "American efficiency" with "Russian revolutionary sweep" and in his use of the term "planned heroism" to describe what was required of the Soviet worker (p. 149). In particular, the slogan "Fulfill the Five-Year Plan in Four Years!" is a perfect illustration of Hanson's point that Stalin set up a series of rational, abstract norms and targets and then expected them to be transcended or "overfulfilled." As Hanson explains, "If five years could be compressed into four, then, in principle, four years could be compressed into three, three into one, and so on. . . . The socialist economy would, in theory, thus give rise to an upward spiral of achievement beyond anything witnessed before in human history" (p. 149). Those who sought to fulfill Stalin's wishes by challenging the limits of human productive effort were rewarded. It was, however, extremely dangerous to misunderstand the difficult combination of charisma and rationality. Many of Stalin's victims were accused of being "bourgeois wreckers" when they did not adhere to a revolutionary "heroic" approach to industrial production (p. 154). Hanson ends his book with a novel interpretation of Mikhail Gorbachev's policy of perestroika as an attempt to inject "charisma" back into the Soviet economy. According to Hanson, Gorbachev knew that it was necessary to reinvigorate the now stagnant Soviet economic system to forestall the total collapse of the Communist state. Despite the original and insightful qualities of the book, there are a few significant difficulties. In the first place, Hanson overreaches in the implications of his thesis. In certain parts of the book, he suggests that conceptions of time determine all other religious and philosophical concepts. When he describes various religious approaches to time, for example, he overemphasizes the importance of the question, arguing in one place that the entire history of Protestantism was determined by debates over time. Similarly, in the sections on Kant and Hegel, Hanson seems to argue that attitudes toward time shaped the philosophers' approaches to other philosophical questions, such as morality or freedom. In his explication of the ideas of Marx, Lenin, and Stalin, he also often conflates attitudes toward history with attitudes toward time, even though history and time are distinct concepts. The other, more difficult, problem in the book is Hanson's nearly exclusive reliance on the published speeches, writings, and philosophical tracts of Soviet leaders. His use of this material to trace the evolution of an idea is effective, but it is less persuasive when he attempts to determine the effect of this idea on institutional design. To trace the influence of Marxist conceptions of time on the Soviet state, it would have been more convincing to look at a few concrete institutions in detail, perhaps using newly available archival sources. The notions of time embedded in bureaucratic structures, specific laws, and economic and social organizations need to be studied more carefully. How, for example, did the design of a collective farm reflect Soviet notions of the way time should be managed in agricultural work? It was very easy for Soviet leaders such as Lenin and Stalin to talk about charismatic approaches toward time, but [End Page 121] one would imagine that many of these ideas were transformed in the process of implementation. In short, Time and Revolution is an interesting reevaluation of the centrality of Marxist ideas in the creation and administration of the Soviet state. Hanson has managed to point the way for future scholars, who will, it is hoped, use new and accessible archival material to examine the concrete implementation of ideas in Soviet institutional design. Ana Siljak Harvard University