Practical Posthumanism in the Philosophy of John Lachs Phillip McReynolds UNC Charlotte 1. Introduction According to Carey Wolfe, the term “posthumanism” has been around since the 1990s though its roots go back at least to the work of Norbert Weiner and the of others in cybernetics that is associated with the Macy Conferences during the 1940s and 1950s (Wolfe 2010, xii and Hayles 1999, 50-75). Like its fellow “post”, postmodernism, posthumanism suffers from some confusion regarding its relationship to the –ism that it modifies.1 According to different interpretations, the posthuman is variously what comes after the human, a return to a viewpoint that precedes the rise of humanism, or an interruption of the humanist temporal narrative in such a way that one can no longer coherently speak of a before or an after to humanism. In any case a common thread among various posthumanisms has been the idea that something called humanism (again, which could mean many different things) is more or less problematic and should be at least modified or, perhaps abandoned, if possible.2 Recent developments in the physical sciences have strengthened interest in this idea, in particular planetary climate change and the advent of what has come to be known as the Anthropocene. Coined in the year 2000 by Crutzen and Stoermer, the term “Anthropocene” underlines the fact that recently, perhaps for the first time, human beings have become a geophysical force of nature on par with other non-human forces that have likewise transformed the biosphere to such an extent that they have left planetary-scale imprints in the geological 1 record (Crutzen and Stoermer 2000). As a result, the problem of scale introduced by this idea seems to threaten humanism by challenging traditional conceptions of human agency, disturbing the once seemingly sharp lines between humans/nonhumans and living/non-living, and troubling a human-centered orientation toward history and time.3 John Lachs has been thinking and writing about human nature(s), human beings, and being human for quite some time now and his work bears upon issues many of the key issues that posthumanist literature seeks to address. Lachs’s position with regard to humanism is at once extremely thoughtful, highly nuanced, difficult to place exclusively in one school or another, and, above all, extremely practical. In this paper I identify tendencies in his thought that place him closer to what we might call a classically humanist position. I also point out positions he articulates that lend support to something like posthumanism, or that tend to raise doubts about the viability of some humanist claims and commitments. Finally, I raise the question of the degree to which Lachs’s mature philosophy as found in his Stoic Pragmatism (2012) is committed to anything like a humanism or could be conceived as a kind of posthumanism. My conclusions are mixed though in the end I think that Lachs’s proposals move toward a kind of posthumanism even as he embraces a variety of limited, practical humanism. His commitment to humanism is pragmatic and his definition of the human is nominalistic. The stoic aspects of his philosophy allow for a double perspective regarding the significance of human beings that squares with that of posthumanism while offering a corrective to classical pragmatism regarding the nature of human limitations. Additionally, if 2 there is any value to be found in posthumanism, I argue that Lachs’s philosophy serves the important function of bringing what can seem like relatively abstract academic discussions down to earth, thus maximizing that value from a practical point of view. 2. Lachs’s Humanism Lachs identifies himself, at least in some respects, as a pragmatist, and as such, his philosophical interests and methods are broadly humanistic. This is because pragmatism, at least in many incarnations, is a self-consciously, even proudly, humanist philosophy. Dewey provides a good example of this tendency. He gets called a humanist often enough, at any rate. John Shook writes, for example, that, “Among twentieth-century humanists, none stands higher than John Dewey” (2010, p. 18). Paul Kurtz similarly writes, “Dewey is probably the most important humanist philosopher that the United States has thus far produced,” (1992, p. 16). Sydney Ratner helpfully spells out in some detail what humanism means in this context: As I see it, Dewey’s distinctive place in the long sweep of the history of philosophy rests on his unique concern for sustained inquiry into the origins, import, and consequences of all problems in their proposed solutions in terms of the life and the destiny of human beings as individuals. (1954, 81) What does it mean, however, to say that Dewey or other pragmatists tend to be humanists? F.S.C. Schiller said, “Pragmatism…is in reality only the application of Humanism to the theory of knowledge,” (Schiller 1912, xxv). If we view the rise of 3 Renaissance humanism as the displacement of the centrality of divine authority in discovering truth, we can see that there is some plausibility to this view. For the pragmatists, we cannot look to some antecedent, external authority in order to learn what the world is like. Rather, we must begin with human experience and reap whatever satisfactions we might gain from “merely human” (rather than transcendent) truths.4 However, starting with human experience means taking seriously human values and interests that give rise to and are expressed in our various quests for knowledge. As such, for the pragmatists, the centrality of human agency (and human limitations) in epistemological matters goes hand in hand with a focus on human, rather than nonhuman, values and interests, such as those of God, angels, or perhaps other species. Indeed, one of the most distinctive features of pragmatism as a philosophical tradition is its commitment to addressing problems embedded within the bounds of human experience and human history. As Steven Fesmire has observed, ethics for Dewey is fundamentally related to the idea of the human, insofar as it is defined as “the art of helping people to live richer, more responsive, and more emotionally engaged life" (2004, 43). Compare this with Lachs’s own statement about his philosophy in Stoic Pragmatism: “Stoic pragmatists are committed to making life better until their powers are overwhelmed…[Stoic Pragmatism] invites us to live long and well” (2012: 1-2). “Life” here, I think clearly, means human life, insofar as the “us” being invited are creatures who are capable of understanding and applying the insights of stoic pragmatism. 4 Part of the pragmatists’ rationale for relating philosophical questions to the arena of human lives, aims, and interests involves a desire to avoid positing anything as ontologically basic and, more importantly, a demand that philosophy produce practical results. These two issues are intimately connected. Pragmatism is not a positivism for the sake of being a positivism.5 Rather, it avoids ontology (when it can)—or engages exclusively in what Larry Hickman calls “low-rise” metaphysics (2015)—because ontology is so easy to get lost in, forgetting the practical problems that gave rise to the philosophical conundrums in the first place. Lachs, as we shall see, similarly wants to avoid unproductive ontological disputes and the reason for this is the same: we need to make informed choices in order to improve life.6 Thus, for pragmatists like Lachs, the idea of “the human” plays an important role in “earthing” the philosophical enterprise—that is, “keeping its feet on the ground”—if not grounding it per se. The basic orientation of classical pragmatism has been toward our (human) communities, as they exist today, or perhaps in the relative near term, an orientation that links pragmatism to its enlightenment and postenlightenment philosophical progenitors.7 I think Lachs shares this basic orientation with other pragmatists given what he has had to say about human nature(s), human beings, being human, and the importance of this category for living good lives. In these broad ways—understanding that human knowledge must be related to and certified by human experience and taking as a central focus the amelioration of human existence—pragmatists tend to be humanists and, in this respect, so is John Lachs. 5 But humanism has tended to mean something more than just exhibiting a focus on human needs and interests. Consider the idea of human rights as expressed in the United Nations’ Declaration of Human Rights: Whereas recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of freedom, justice and peace in the world…All human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights. They are endowed with reason and conscience and should act towards one another in a spirit of brotherhood. (UN 1948) The document goes on to assert a number of rights that every human being has simply because they are human. Implicit in this view is the idea that “all members of the human family” possess a dignity and inherent worth simply in virtue of being human beings. Now, the declaration doesn’t explicitly claim that non-humans don’t possess dignity and self worth nor does it propose that we treat nonhumans “inhumanely”. However, it is a humanistic document by singling human beings out for a particular sort of treatment in virtue of their humanness. This is a second aspect of humanism that we find in many of the pragmatists including Lachs. It is worth attending to the practicality of this document. Although its declarative language suggests that it is stating objective facts about human beings— that they possess reason and conscience, that they are born free and equal in dignity and rights—it is actually asserting that they should be treated as if they have these things and are born in these ways. After all, many human beings are not actually born free, and, unfortunately in practice, too many are not treated equally or afforded much dignity at all. If all human beings were equal in rights in actual 6 practice there would be no need for the document. On this interpretation,8 the declaration is neither a statement of objective reality nor is it a categorical imperative. Rather, the declaration is a hypothetical imperative. It begins by asserting that the recognition of these things is “the foundation of freedom, justice, and peace in the world”. If we want to pursue these human goals, we should treat humans as if they had inherent dignity and value by respecting their rights in the prescribed ways. In short, the humanism of the UN Declaration is a practical humanism: It is neither an empirical claim about the way the world is nor an ontological claim about the deep nature of the reality of humanness but a proposal for achieving certain ends, specifically, promoting human freedom, justice, and peace in the world. Lachs’s work exhibits a similarly practical humanism. Being human is an example of what Lachs has called a “choice-inclusive fact” (1990, 30). “Such judgment calls,” he says, bring our purposes and values into play. This makes it sensible to ask what good it does to sort creatures into the single, uniform category of humans. (1990, 305) In answer to this question, he writes, …saying that someone is human conveys less about what they are like than about how we are to treat them. The humanity of a being is not a fact discovered but a status conferred. It means, among other things, that if found hurt or ill, it is to be taken to a doctor, not a vet. As a signal to us, moreover, that it is to be taken for help instead of being discarded or being allowed to 7 bleed to death by the highway, it exposes us to blame and perhaps even legal action if we fail. (1990, 305-306, emphasis mine) Although Lachs believes that there is a background of facts against which we confer this status—more about that later—identifying someone as human is not a valueneutral fact about the world but something that we do in pursuit of certain ends. Note the similarity between Lachs’s ends and those sought by the UN Declaration. Lachs writes, Establishing effective signals of this sort in relation to a broad range of individuals constitutes a grand but late achievement in history. The idea of expanding the compass of humanity, and with it caring, beyond the tribe or beyond the confines of beings narrowly like us, is the foundation of decency and the guaranty of at least the possibility of a happy life. Being classed with humans endows individuals with rights and dignity. (1990, 306, emphasis mine) People don’t naturally have rights and dignity (though we sometimes speak as if they do). (I use “naturally” here in the way that it is often used, in order to provide seemingly objective cover for what is a political judgment.)9 Rather, identifying people as human endows them with rights and dignity, which is a good thing to do because it “is the foundation of decency and the guaranty of at least the possibility of a happy life.” Given all this I think that one can say of John Lachs, that he’s practically a humanist. 3. Posthumanist Features of Lachs’s Philosophy 8 And yet there are a number of significant aspects to his thinking about humans and nonhumans that we might call posthumanist. One of these aspects derives from pragmatism, which, in spite of its humanist heritage and associations can be thought of as a proto-posthumanism in some respects. As I have already outlined, in its refusal to look to superhuman realities for truth pragmatism shows itself as an offspring of enlightenment humanism. In fact, however, pragmatism has a dual lineage, with one line of descent emerging from enlightenment and post-enlightenment humanism and the other from evolutionary theory, the latter qualifying the former. As such, pragmatism is a naturalized humanism. The human is not seen as apart from nature but as a part of nature.10 One thing that evolutionary theory contributes to pragmatism is fallibilism. Whereas other enlightenment philosophies tended to view human reason as unlimited,11 pragmatism recognizes the human being as an evolved creature with an intellect that is grounded in and limited by its evolutionary history. In this way pragmatism avoids the optimistic highs of enlightenment thinkers such as Rousseau, the sense of inevitable progress found in post-enlightenment thinkers such as Hegel and Spencer, and the pessimistic lows of some anti-enlightenment philosophies. In place of these pragmatism opts for its own homely brand of humanistic meliorism, content to try to make human life better, not perfect (James 138). I’ll have more to say about this later with respect to Lachs’s stoic pragmatism and the ways in which its sense of human limitations (and how to respond to them) put it farther than classical pragmatism along the road to a practical posthumanism. In any case, classical pragmatism is an evolutionary humanism, stressing continuities between 9 nature and culture and, at times, even between the human and the non-human,12 in spite of its anthropocentrism. Thus, insofar as it tends to deemphasize radical dichotomies including those between the human and the non-human, pragmatism is already on its way toward being a posthumanist philosophy even as it has tended to be associated with humanism. This relates to a second key idea that pragmatism adopted in response to evolutionary theory, which is the idea that there are no fixed, natural species. There are two central aspects to this idea. The first is, of course, that species change over time. Some species go extinct and others emerge to take their place. One important implication of this discovery is that not only have humans not always existed but also that one day they will cease to exist. Thus pragmatism takes change to be the norm and not some sort of exception within a perfect universe that must be explained away. The second aspect that evolution contributed to pragmatism is that because one species can evolve into another, the idea of a “species” is a relatively arbitrary marker (or a marker for certain purposes) that groups together a set of creatures over a period of time for purposes of classification. Lachs takes this view quite seriously and it has important implications for his views regarding humanness and human nature. He writes that searching for the discrete, immutable forms of species of living organisms, including humans, seems neither necessary nor appropriate over a hundred years after the general acceptance of the theory of evolution. For Darwin and his followers established the continuity of life forms on the planet, developing an account of how changes in the germ plasm and subsequent 10 reproductive success lead to the emergence of novel groups of beings. (1997, 298) It is significant from the point of view of thinking about humanism and posthumanism that Lachs, as a pragmatist, understands all concepts—including that of the human—as tools rather than objective states of affairs or mirrors of an antecedent reality. Pulling no punches he says that “species are made, not found” (1997, 299) and doesn’t hesitate to apply this principle to the idea of a human species: What is true of classifying living organisms in general is true also of classifying humans. The conception of a human species is pieced together out of characteristics observed in large populations of individuals. No single feature or invariable set of traits is necessary and sufficient for someone to be declared a human being. Such pronouncements result from complex judgments made on the basis of considering candidates with regard to dozens of features. (303) As such, whether we call something human or nonhuman is fundamentally a matter of choice, a choice, Lachs cautions, that must be made responsibly (303). What is remarkable about this is how far, I think, Lachs goes beyond the classical pragmatists in taking a posthumanist perspective. Whereas the idea of the human forms a kind of unexamined backdrop to ethical considerations for the pragmatists, Lachs is willing to place the very idea of the human in question, and to entertain most if not all comers as candidates for humanity, an idea that seems not to have occurred to the classical pragmatists. 11 One should perhaps not fault the classical pragmatists for not throwing the door open to questioning what it might mean to be a human being as wide as Lachs has insofar as Lachs has had the benefit of hindsight regarding a rather rapid pace of technological and political development. Technology has created issues where perhaps none existed during the time that Peirce, James, and Dewey were working, as is to be expected. Lachs notes, referring to contentious issues in biomedical ethics, that, “The decision about where to draw the line between the living and the dead, for example, is now being made through the political process,” (1990, 31). Developments in computer technology have also influenced Lachs in ways that might have seemed fanciful to the classical pragmatists.13 Regarding prospects of artificial intelligence, he writes, It is unproductive to ask whether human beings might not, after all, be machines, and how complex a machine would have to be in order to it to be or become a human being. These are not matters of objective fact, of how things are. They are, instead, matters of conscious or unconscious human decision. The proper question to ask, accordingly, is concerning the circumstances that would have to obtain in order for us to decide that, for purposes of classification, the obvious differences between human beings and machines can be overlooked. (1990, 34) In urging us to look to consequences, Lachs is thoroughly pragmatic even as he moves beyond the pragmatists in the scope of his thought. Lachs considers whether some machines might be considered human by asking after what similarities between machines (candidate-humans) and (stipulated) humans would have to 12 entail such that the consequences of not making such an assignment would inspire our moral outrage. As a pragmatist, he looks to the consequences of such an assignment in order to evaluate it (1990, 34-35). Lachs even considers the question of the monstrous in evaluating who or what might or might not be considered human or fully human, fitting in quite easily with many of the posthumanists’ interest in monsters and the monstrous.14 As I have argued, in making these moves and being open to these possibilities, Lachs is forwarding the project of pragmatism rather than breaking with it. When he says that “we must…see our attempts to classify living beings as variable, optional ways of ordering the wilderness of facts” (1997, 303), I hear more than a hint of William James’ belief in a pluralistic universe coupled with a very Deweyan interest in considering what practical effects such a belief actually have in the knock-about world. Another way that Lachs, particularly in stoic pragmatism, moves beyond other forms of pragmatism and approaches posthumanism is in his avoidance of humanist chauvinism. This aspect of Lachs’s thought fits well with posthumanist critiques of “human exceptionalism”—the practice of treating humans as better or more worthy than other organisms based on some single or small set of qualities that humans have but that other creatures supposedly lack. Lachs’s position has its roots, I think, in Lachs’s fascination with ineffability, immediacy, and embodiment and his impatience with the philosopher’s tendency to convert everything to language. Although other pragmatists are “guilty” of human exceptionalism (see Dewey on communication in Experience and Nature, for example, or even his various 13 references to “savages” and beasts”)15, Lachs’s lack of patience with this position comes through clearly in his critique of Nicholas Rescher’s cognitive pragmatism. Before moving onto the criticism, it is worth noting, briefly, one of Lachs’s points of agreement with Rescher, which is a shared belief in the independent existence of a world (2012, 64). Lachs’s non-essentialist realism is something that one finds hints of in much writing that is labeled posthumanist (and that of related movements like the new materialism). Those who hold these views share an interest prying human language, thought, and culture from the center of the natural universe and undoing some of the idealistic excesses of postmodernism and some recent forms of pragmatism. Rescher, according to Lachs, thinks very highly of human practices of inquiry and communication. In fact, inquiry and communication form the basis for Rescher’s curiously transcendental argument for the existence of an independently existing world (2012, 66). Rescher thinks that what makes us human and sets us apart from all other creatures is that we engage in inquiry and construct propositional knowledge about the world. This may be true, but Lachs is not as impressed with our distinctively human form of life as Rescher is. For Lachs, propositional knowledge is an aspect of our human form of life, but only a small part of it. As a brief aside, one indication that Lachs is navigating outside of the safe waters of familiar humanism is the appearance of so much varied wildlife in his works. Consider this characteristic example: 14 Rescher is not satisfied with the sort of inquiry in which a bird might engage in looking around for predators and the kind of communication common among monkeys when they warn each other of danger. (2012, 66) One could multiply examples of wildlife showing up and taking center stage in Lachs’s philosophical texts. I think the birds and squirrels show up when they so— which is often—for a very good reason: Lachs is simply not as impressed with the human facility for complex communication as is Rescher. In Lachs’s view, to take such a high view of human cognition as one finds in Rescher’s cognitive pragmatism is to promote beyond all reasonableness what is, in the end, a relatively marginal and uncommon aspect of human existence. This is an orientation that finds Lachs well at home in the company of posthumanists. So much philosophy—because philosophers like to talk—revolves around talk and forgets that we are animals, with animal bodies that need to eat. Philosophers tend to place an inordinate amount of focus on the human mind, which is only one part of the human being. (I will hazard that Lachs developed this attitude toward the relative unimportance of the mind during his ten years defending Santayana, as, he speculates, the world’s only living epiphenomenalist.16) One can trace Lachs’s interest in animal bodies, their needs, and satisfactions from Santayana, and he shares this interest with many posthumanists. Lachs explains, Stoic pragmatism takes human existence in all its nonintellectual complexity as its datum and the quality of life it can secure as an indication of its value. Although statable in propositional form, it points away from theory toward 15 action…Philosophy must deal with the whole human being, not only with the mind. (2012, 71). As we have seen, like posthumanists, Lachs seems to be interested in emphasizing the continuities between humans and other animals that relate to the way that we live in and through our common animal bodies. He writes, characteristically, “Focusing on our social predicaments and on what we share with other animals…enables us to develop a picture of human life in all its complexity” (2012, 71).17 A third way in which Lachs moves beyond the classical pragmatists toward something like a posthumanism comes with the stoic correction that he applies to classical pragmatism. Although Lachs does not accuse the classical pragmatists of lacking a sense of the tragic as others have (and certainly the pragmatists were no strangers to tragedy in their own lives), he does point out that they have very little use for whatever they have very little use for. Even with tragedy and death, the pragmatists seem to be interested only in what they can do with them, with how they might be reconstructed into something in the future. Lachs observes that this attitude, while potentially beneficial when there is something one can do about one’s situation, is not appropriate to every situation. Here I think it is helpful to hear Lachs in his own voice, and so I will quote him at length: The stoic in stoic pragmatists reminds them of the contingency of life, the vastness of the universe, the finitude of everything human, the tragic cost of whatever we do, and the possibility that our efforts will be of no avail. Stoics whisper “memento mori,” as religion used to but perhaps no longer does, 16 calling the attention of communities to the larger, historical cycles over which they exercise no control. Without a cosmic perspective, we cannot present a just assessment of our situation. With this prospect clearly in mind, we can never place ourselves at the center of the universe. Stoic detachment is a powerful antidote to the hype that elevates science to the level of savior and social effort above natural limits. (2012: 52). It is this “cosmic perspective” that one finds not only in stoic pragmatism but also in posthumanism that one finds it largely lacking in pragmatism. With the pragmatic emphasis on making a difference there is very little attention to our human limitations. Awareness of our limitations is, by contrast, fundamental to posthumanism and it comes up, among other contexts, in that of the idea of extinction. As I have noted, pragmatism emerged, in part, as a response to Darwin’s discovery of the process of evolution by natural selection. Extinction is, of course, one of the fundamental features of Darwinian evolution. As such, one would think that pragmatists would be comfortable with the idea of extinction. Indeed, pragmatists (but not only pragmatists) are, perhaps, too comfortable with the idea of extinction. As Claire Colebrook phrases the problem (though not addressing pragmatism specifically), …the uses of Darwin today…actually have the effect of reducing the force not only of Darwinism but of another temporal event, extinction: not only have we humanized the emergence of humans from deep time (by regarding 17 evolution as being oriented towards adaptation), but we have also domesticated the sense of the human end. (2011) The trouble is that a humanistic perspective on evolution tends to see “life as functional, oriented towards our types of complexity and order, and inevitably leading towards the types of complexity exemplified by humans [emphasis added] (2011).” To understand evolutionary processes strictly in terms of fitness, that is, in terms of survival, is to miss their “decentering randomness and rogue temporalities (2011).” Indeed, Peirce writes, “Almost everyone will now agree that the ultimate good lies in the evolutionary process in some way” (1902). It is difficult to imagine how Peirce might hold such a view without imagining the good as human in some way. Whatever “good” evolution may bring it is likely to bring about something that is probably unrecognizable as good from the point of view of our species as it exists today. With Santayana, Lachs criticizes the notion that “we are ‘too good for extinction,’ that what happens to ‘mere’ animals cannot happen to us” (2012, 57). In recognizing “the contingency of life, the vastness of the universe, the finitude of everything human, the tragic cost of whatever we do, and the possibility that our efforts will be of no avail,” Lachs is on the same page with and might well be considered one among posthumanists. 4. Practical Posthumanism The Anthropocene presents us with a problem of scale in which human activity appears as a mode of agency that appears to exceed individual or possibly even communal control. The emergence of the Anthropocene suggests that humanity is out of control and possibly that it cannot be controlled, or at least that 18 we might need to rethink our conventional, humanistic concept of agency which has proved so useful in dealing with human beings and their effects upon “mediumsized dry goods” but that might not be so well geared to deal with human speciesaction in the age of the Anthropocene.18 For pragmatists, concepts are not fixed representations of the world but are rather tools for dealing with it. When a concept fails to fit the problematic situations that we face it is time to retool it or to replace it with a better tool (concept). The problem with humanism in this context is that it is a perspective that seems designed to render everything on a human scale. However, with the emergence of the Anthropocene we find ourselves confronted with temporal and spatial scales that break the human frame. Lachs’s stoic pragmatism provides a better sense of scale and the relative important of human beings with respect to the earth and larger forces than we find in the toolbox of the classical pragmatists. Lachs and the posthumanists share an interest in taking seriously a cosmic perspective in which the ephemeral nature of humanity as with all species is manifest, a perspective that seems all too relevant today. As Claire Colebrook notes, “Darwinism was a thought event that placed humanity within time, but the pulse of extinction awareness that is coming to the fore in the twenty-first century adds the sense of an ending to the broader awareness of the historical emergence of the human species,” (Colebrook, 2011). Dipesh Chakrabarty observes that “History is no longer a human narrative, and human narratives themselves seem to incorporate forces that are no longer human” (Chakrabarty 2012, 1-2). Pragmatism, however, is firmly situated within human history, a history that the appearance of the Anthropocene threatens to usurp. As 19 Colebrook notes, “While the human species – and all other species – face other threats of extinction (including nuclear disaster, viral pandemic, global terrorism and systemic collapse), climate change has become the icon of the thorough event of extinction” (Colebrook 2011). Climate change, it has been noted, is a slow-motion catastrophe, a post-apocalypse.19 According to Srinivas Aravamudan, the Anthropocene is Catachonistic, that is it “re-characterizes the past and the present in terms of a future proclaimed as determinate but that is of course not yet fully realized” (Aravamuda 2013, 8). It closes the open-endedness of the enlightenment with the specter of species death, projectively imagined as embedded in a geological stratum (Aravamunda 2013, pp. 9 and 12). As such, it runs directly counter to Deweyan humanism. Dewey writes, [What] humanism means to me…is an expansion, not a contraction, of human life, an expansion in which nature and the science of nature are made the willing servants of human good. (LW 5: 266) Pragmatism isn’t geared (at present) to think or talk about annihilation, an apocalypse without meaning or redemption. Dewey remarks at one point at experiencing “obscure irritation” in the “apocalyptic flights” of the fiction of H.G. Wells (MW 10: 310). We find an antidote to this lack of preparedness to talk frankly about our situation in stoic pragmatism as in posthumanism. However, one might well ask how practical it is to think or talk about our inevitable end even if (especially if) it appears to be approaching more quickly than we had anticipated? It is here that Lachs’s response to Shelly’s “Ozymandias” is instructive. Lachs paraphrases the poem thus, 20 Shelley’s point is that in the end nothing remains: the generations that come after us forget our names, destroy our monuments, and lay waste to our plans…What is the point of doing anything if it is all undone and the death of everything precious leaves only a world of atoms moving in the dark? (2012, 58). Lachs responds to this viewpoint by arguing that even if in the end all comes to naught, this fact can do nothing to diminish the value that we experience now. He argues “the possibility of distant disaster is an inadequate reason for ceasing our efforts and failing to enjoy the moment” (2012, 59). Lachs can take this perspective because of the double perspective that stoic pragmatism employs in the immanent transcendence that Lachs learns from Santayana. In stoic pragmatism, together with an extremely tough-minded acknowledgment of our finitude, we find a consciousness of the timelessness of value. According to Lachs, if anything is ever of value, it is always of value. This recognition is ultimately extremely practical insofar as it gives us reason to work for value, to preserve it where we can, even if it will inevitably pass away. Here, I think, Lachs brings a mature sense of limitation to pragmatism while adding a hardheaded practicality to posthumanism. References Aravamudan, Srinivas. 2013. “The Catachronism of Climate Change.” diacritics 41(3). Braidotti, Rosi. 2013. The Posthuman. Polity Press. Brandom, Robert. 2004. “The Pragmatist Enlightenment (and its Problematic Semantics.” European Journal of Philosophy. 21(1): 1-16. 21 Chakrabarty, Dipesh. 2009. “The Climate of History: Four Theses.” Critical Inquiry 35(2): 197-222. -----. 2012. “Postcolonial studies and the Challenge of Climate Change.” New Literary History 43:1. Colebrook, Claire. 2011. Extinction. NC: Open Humanities Press. Crutzen, Paul and Eugene F. Stoermer. “The Anthropocene.” Global Change Newsletter 41. Dewey, John. Middle Works (MW) and Later Works (LW). Jo Ann Boydston, Ed. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press. Ferry, Luc. 1995. The New Ecological Order, Carol Volk, trans. Chicago & London: The University of Chicago Press. Fesmire, Steven. 2004. “Dewey and Animal Ethics.” In Animal Pragmatism: Rethinking Human-Nonhuman Relationships. Ed. Erin McKenna and Andrew Light. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Gilabert, Pablo. 2011. “Humanist and Political Perspectives on Human Rights.” Political Theory. 39(4): 439-467. Gomel, Alana. 2000. “The Plague of Utopias: Pestilence and the Apocalyptic Body.” Twentieth Century Literature 46(4). Graham, Elaine. 2002. Representations of the Post/Human: Monsters, Aliens and Others in Popular Culture. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press. Haraway, Donna. 1991. Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention of Nature. New York, Routledge. Hayles, N. Katherine. 1999. How We Became Posthuman: Virtual Bodies in Cybernetics, Literature, and Informatics. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Hickman, Larry. 2015. “Philosophy as Technology for Living.” In The American Philosopher: Interviews on the Meaning of Life and Truth. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books. James, William. Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking in The Works of William James, Electronic Edition, Volume 1: Pragmatism. Kurtz, Paul. 1992. “Remembering John Dewey: America’s Leading Humanist Philosopher.” Free Inquiry 13(1): 16-18. 22 Kurzweil, Ray. The Singularity Is Near: When Humans Transcend Biology. Penguin Books. Lachs, John. 1990. “Human Natures.” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association. 63(7): 29-39. -----. 1997. “Valuational Species.” The Review of Metaphysics. 51:2: 297-311. -----. 2002. “The Insignificance of Individuals.” Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. 38(1): 79-93. -----. 2012. Stoic Pragmatism. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Latour, Bruno. 2004. Politics of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences Into Democracy. Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press. -----. 2014. “Agency at the Time of the Anthropocene.” New Literary History 45(1): 118. Lyotard, Jean-François. 1984. The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Minneapolis: The University of Minnesota Press. McReynolds, Phillip. 2000. John Dewey’s Science of Ethics. (Ph.D. Dissertation) Nashville, TN: Vanderbilt University. Moravec, Hans. 1998. Mind Children: The Future of Robot and Human Intelligence. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press. Pearce, Trevor. 2015. “’Science Organized’: Positivism and the Metaphysical Club, 1865-1875.” Journal of the History of Ideas. 76: 441-465. Pepperell, Robert. 2009. The Posthuman Condition. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Putnam, Hilary. 2001. Pragmatism and Enlightenment. Amsterdam: Van Gorcum Ltd. Ratner, Sydney. 1954. “The Naturalistic Humanism of John Dewey and Arthur F. Bentley.” Humanist: A magazine of critical inquiry and social comment 14: 8187. Rorty, Richard. 2003. “Comments on Jeffrey Stout’s Democracy and Tradition” (paper delivered at the annual meeting of the American Academy of Religion, Atlanta, GA, November 23, 2003). Russell, Bertrand. 1907. Transatlantic “Truth”. NP. 23 Schiller, F.C.S. 1912. Humanism: Philosophical Essays, 2nd edition. London: Macmillan. Shook, John. 2010. “The Humanism of John Dewey.” Free Inquiry 30(3): 18-19. United Nations. 1948. Universal Declaration of Human Rights. (http://www.un.org/en/documents/udhr/, accessed 7/28/2015). Wolfe, Cary. 2010. What is Posthumanism? Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota Press. It is worth recalling that what Lyotard did not say was that postmodernism comes after modernism. Rather, he said that in order to be a fully modern work, a word must be postmodern in the sense that it aims to represent the unrepresentable. In this way, the postmodern is the birth of the modern, according to Lyotard. See Lyotard 1984. 2 For examples of posthumanist literature see, for example, Braidotti 2013, Haraway 1991, Hayles 1999, Pepperell 2009, and Wolfe 2010. 3 On agency and time, see, for example, Latour 2014. On time and scale, see Aravamudan 2013, Chakrabarty 2009, and Colebrook. 4 Bertrand Russell parodied this standpoint, at least as William James expressed it, in a book called Transatlantic “Truth” (1907). Richard Rorty takes this epistemological (and indeed ethical) humanism to its logical limit when he writes, “As I see it, the whole point of pragmatism is to insist that we human beings are answerable only to one another. We are answerable only to those who answer to us—only to conversation partners. We are not responsible to the atoms or to God, at least not until they start conversing with us” (2003). This interpretation of pragmatism as humanism not only takes the extreme epistemological position that there is nothing beyond human practices and conversations that can warrant our truth claims but also is an example of the human chauvinism that I will criticize later. Animals can’t talk and so we don’t bear any responsibility toward them. 5 For a thoughtful discussion of the relationship between pragmatism and positivism see Pearce 2015. 6 See, for example, Lachs 1990, especially pp. 35-37. Lachs also reminds us that “Metaphysics must…always remain in the service of ethics,” (Lachs 1997, 311). 7 Regarding pragmatism and Enlightenment see Brandom and Putnam. 8 Pablo Gilabert calls this the political or practical perspective in contrast to the humanist or naturalist one, though I think the issue is more complicated than that and, indeed, Gilabert argues that the two positions complement one another. See Gilabert 2011. 9 On the political uses of “nature” see Latour 2004, especially pp. 1-8. 10 Dewey, for example, refuses any sort of absolute break between nature and culture, which is to say, between the “natural” and the human, respectively. See LW 1. 1 24 Of Rousseau Luc Ferry writes, “For him, history is not tradition, it is creation, innovation, perfectibility,” (Ferry 1995, p. 10). See also pp. 8-9. 12 Digestion, Dewey says, is as much a matter of the food as the person who does the digesting (MW 6: 115). 13 Moreover, as Lachs notes the consensus of who counts as human has expanded in the twentieth century to a much greater degree than had occurred by the time the classical pragmatists finished publishing. Whereas Dewey still refers to “savages” from time to time (See McReynolds 2000), Lachs is able to note, “Little by little, we, or influential groups among us, made decisions to overlook the differences due to class, race, sex, religion, national origin, intelligence, drive and physical endowment, and to treat a very broad selection of individuals as equally entitled to consideration and respect.” (Lachs 1990, 36) 14 For Lachs, see, for example, Lachs 1997, pp. 304-305. For posthumanist literature about monsters see, for example, Graham 2002. 15 LW 1: 132-161. There are more examples of Dewey’s references to “savages” than there is space here to document. For just one example, see MW 12: 246. I have documented and explored Dewey’s use of this term extensively in McReynolds 2000. 16 See Lachs 2012, p. 183. 17 Lachs’s emphasis on the limitations of our animal bodies accords with quite a lot of posthumanism. However, there is one type of literature that is sometimes called posthumanist but that is more commonly called “transhumanism” that is diametrically opposed to this idea. In transhumanist literature, “the posthuman” is a term that is sometimes used to refer to our state once we have transcended the limitations of our animal bodies, either by uploading our minds into digital computers, or by enhancing ourselves with various kinds of cybernetic or genetic technologies. The mainstream of what I am calling posthumanism stands in opposition to transhumanism. For examples of transhumanism see Moravec 1998 and Kurzweil. For a posthumanist critique of this view see Hayles 1999. In my view, which I share with others, transhumanism is not posthumanism at all but a kind of enlightenment humanism on steroids. 18 It is important to note that the advent of the Anthropocene moves ecological and environmental debate well beyond ideas of sustainability, sustainable growth, and so on since the idea of sustainability depends on the idea that humans can assert control over their own agency in order to bring our interactions with and effects upon the environment under rational control. Such control is exactly what the Anthropocene throws into question. See Latour 2014. 19 Elana Gomel contrasts apocalypse with postapocalypse, writing “Postapocalypse seems to be concerned not with the sharp moment of death but rather with the interminable duration of dying.” See Gomel, 2000, p. 421. 11 25