Lachs, Liberty, and the Pursuit of Happiness Andrew Fiala California State University, Fresno Once we overcome our dread of the different, the richness of the world engulfs us as a wave and leaves our cleansed souls with gratitude and amazement. --John Lachs, Stoic Pragmatism, 127 I am extremely grateful to John Lachs for his guidance and mentorship (and to the organizers of this conference for including me). And I am grateful for Lachs’ work, which reminds us to savor the wonderful diversity of things. The apparent simplicity of Lachs’ philosophy grows out of a sustained critique of much of what is wrong with academic philosophy, abstract ethics, and disengaged political theory. Lachs offers a simple recipe for peace and prosperity. If more of us took Lachs seriously, violence would diminish, happiness would increase, and personalities would flourish. His humane vision of the world celebrates life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. Lachs is an empiricist, a pragmatist, and a relativist of sorts. His avoids dogmatism. Instead of pontificating, he wants us to develop insight grounded in the world of experience. Such insight is partial and fragmentary—and not revolutionary. By recognizing the diversity of human natures and pluralism in the realm of theory, Lachs leaves us without that singular Archimedean lever that could move the world. Lachs is 1 also aware that for every challenging social and ethical problem we confront, there are multiple answers, including the very real possibility that the status quo is an improvement over the past. This conciliatory and piecemeal approach can be disappointing for those who want splashy social theory that is more critical, more systematic, and more revolutionary. But throughout his work, Lachs reminds us of the dangers of allencompassing systems and totalizing critique. He routinely warns us against “grand history,” “abstract moralizing,” and “grand dreams of perfect people” (to quote phrases found in the titles of some of Lachs’ essays). Instead, Lachs returns us to ordinary life and everyday people. He engages in the real world, where means and ends are integrated and open to the broad range of human experience. This “eliminates the prerogatives of the eternal” as he says in his essay on “The Rat Race.”i Lachs is disenchanted with the revolutionary dreams of utopian thinkers. His anti-utopian approach turns away from perfectionism, while encouraging us to embrace the readily available joys of immediacy.ii Lachs’ work is obviously influenced by the notable names in American philosophy— Santayana, Dewey, James, Emerson, and the rest. Lachs also has much in common with Thomas Jefferson. Jefferson wrote that all men are endowed by their creator with the right to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. Jefferson’s affirmation of life, liberty, and happiness reflected his worldview, which was a mix of Epicureanism, Stoicism, Christian morality, and Enlightenment hope for progress.iii Jefferson explained that he wanted to bring Jesus, Epicurus, and Epictetus together—and to defend the philosophy of this triumvirate against Plato and the Christian fathers. There is no doubt that Jefferson would have approved of much of Lachs’ philosophy of life—with the fatal exception of Jefferson’s revolutionary agenda. 2 Lachs advocates a practical unity of theory and life. He says that, “our books should be the author of our deeds”—and he encourages us to “present ourselves as living examples of what we teach” (Relevance, 10). But given his conciliatory approach to ethics and to social and political theory, it is not clear that Lachs would approve of something as drastic as a revolution. Lachs appears wary of revolution because he is first and foremost a teacher. We teach others by living well.iv Force and coercion teach the wrong lesson. Of God and Human Rights Lachs’ conciliatory and cautious approach to social change is connected to his approach to human rights and theology. Jefferson claims that we are endowed by our Creator with inalienable rights to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. I suspect that Lachs would not agree. He does not begin from a claim about a divine endowment of rights; nor does he think that our rights are absolutely inalienable. Lachs’ discussions of epiphenomenalism and God in Mind and Philosophers provide us with a starting point in theology. Lachs returns us, in that work, to the realm of common sense and a basically conciliatory approach to metaphysical disputes. Lachs resolves the dispute between dualists and materialists in favor of an account of mind that is nonreductive: the phenomenon of mind is preserved, even if the material basis of mind is acknowledged along with the mind’s impotence. Lachs resolves disputes between theists and atheists in favor of a view of God that is similarly conciliatory. In the theological case, Lachs hones in on the contradiction inherent in the idea of divine omniscience and omnipotence. With regard to omniscience, Lachs discovers a basic 3 contradiction: God cannot be omniscience since an omniscient divinity cannot experience doubt—and if the divinity cannot experience something, He cannot have knowledge of it—and so God cannot be omniscient. With regard to omnipotence Lachs argues: if God has effective power, He must be in time; but if God is an omniscient spectator, he must be a passive observer outside of time. Lachs resolves the God question with an epiphenomenal account of the divinity. Lachs’ account of God is humanistic. In Mind and Philosophers, God is the unity of the totality of happiness and value in the world—and who is thus an object worthy of our worship and an expression of our highest ideals (Mind and Philosophers, p. 63-66). Lachs explains that this God is brought into existence by the complex diversity of the flux of nature: “He is the sum of the whitecaps on that restless sea” (64). “He is the compete record of the world’s achievement… God, then, is an ever-increasing whole to which each conscious being—human animal, and whatever other kind exists—may make its contribution. Any experience that is of value permanently swells the aggregate” (64). Lachs concludes that God is not a tyrant who wants obedience—but a process that results from the way that our happiness contributes to the totality of good in the world.v This idea of God inspires us with its humanity.vi Lachs’ view of religion is not merely as a consolation for our fragility and finitude. In apparent agreement with Santayana, Lachs explains that he embraced “the mysteries of Christianity” in his own way (Freedom and Limits, 18). His recent writing attempts to “articulate ways in which a commitment to transcendence can be combined with cold-eyed naturalism.” He continues, “My interest is in seeing religion as a 4 celebration of life, rather than as a consolation for its losses and our finitude” (Freedom and Limits, 18). There are some mysteries of religion here, about which Lachs may yet inform us. But it is clear that Lachs cannot believe in the God of Divine Command theory, a Catholic natural law theory, or even the deistic God who endows his creatures with natural rights. Lachs does not think that human rights (if there even are such things in Lachs’ ontology) come from an endowing Creator or can be grounded in an account of the nature of things. Lachs holds that human rights are “choice-inclusive facts,” and that the language of “rights” is simply a way of emphasizing how important these facts are for us.vii Unlike Jefferson, who grounds life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness in an Enlightenment claim about the inalienable endowment of the Creator, Lachs leaves us with life, liberty, and happiness as important goods to be developed in the world—among the vast diversity of goods. And he suggests that through the development of these goods, we move toward a higher unity, which we might call God. But this higher unity is always on the way and in process. In a sense, Lachs turns Jefferson on his head. Instead of seeing the inalienable endowment of our rights as a non-negotiable fundamental ground for political life, Lachs encourages us to explore life, liberty, and happiness—and he suggests that good judgment and common sense teaches that even life can become a burden. Instead of declaiming life, liberty, and prosperity as rights that are not exchangeable, Lachs seems to suggest that these are privileges which we can enjoy and develop, when we are willing to put forth the effort to contribute to our own living, our freedom, and our own happiness. 5 Letting a Hundred Flowers Bloom Lachs’ basic view of ethics is that we ought to care about the happiness of others while respecting their liberty. This rules out paternalism and meddling—and it permits broad latitude for free choice with regard to a variety of topics (drugs, suicide, sexual morality, and so on). Lachs’ basic libertarianism and his relativism (or as he says in places, his “relationalism”) leads to a robust social and political philosophy. Lachs’ basic political philosophy is grounded in tolerance and pluralistic affirmation of the radical diversity of human natures. He laments the “monstrous egotism displayed in judging another” (Relevance, 27). He criticizes dogmatism and monism, while celebrating pluralism. He concludes: “Society would not collapse if we were to let a hundred flowers bloom. To be sure, it would be different in structure and operation from what it is today. It would be different and it would be better” (Relevance, 28). The idea of letting a hundred flowers bloom comes to us from Chairman Mao—who used this a ploy to draw out social critics—who were then re-educated or executed. Mao used the hundred flowers movement to entice “snakes out of their lairs” so the state could chop of their heads.viii Lachs is clearly not advocating Maoism—but the history of the phrase is useful for reminding us of one critical problem: sometimes liberty and happiness are understood in ideological fashion. The Maoists encouraged a false kind of liberty—they expected the hundred flowers to bloom in conformity with Maoism. Lachs does not expect that kind of conformity. But one objection to Lachs is that there is a risk that libertarian ideas are not either neutral or good. Some worry, for example, that libertarianism can mask a kind of ideology. For religious fundamentalists and others, 6 liberty looks like a bad idea that is foisted upon them in the name of social improvement (but which comes with associated costs in terms of the demise of traditional cultural values). Multicultural theorists, feminists, communitarians, and other social and political philosophers have struggled with this problem—and associated worries about the extent to which we have to tolerate the intolerant, about the damage to local cultures that occurs when economic and political globalization arrives, and concerns about the injustices woven into the ideology of free market capitalism. To my knowledge, Lachs does not engage directly with this sort of critique. Rather, he straightforwardly affirms the vision of a world that is opened by liberty. Lachs is one of the few contemporary social and political philosophers who has defended the idea that the world we live in is actually better, and who encourages us to overcome the “all-encompassing guilt” that flows through Western culture (Stoic Pragmatism, 115). As Lachs explains in In Love with Life: “Not only are we in love with life; life now is more worthy of love” (In Love with Life, 14). Lachs maintains that socially, politically, scientifically, and educationally we are doing better (in the Western world) than we once did. One reason we are doing better may be that we are also more sensitive to the worries of the communitarians and multiculturalists. Lachs’ libertarian tent is expansive— although one wonders what he would say about the question of what to do about intolerant and closed cultures. One solution is to note that Lachs does not deny that there is progress to be made. But there are limits woven into reality. Lachs is not a metaphysical optimist. He admits the fact of death and the existence of evil (we each contain a bit of Karl the Nazi, as Lachs once explained). But from Lachs’ vantage point, experience teaches that we are 7 “both better and better off” (to quote the titles of another of Lachs’ essays). Lachs is also not naïve about the facticity of death. His extensive reflection on end of life issues provides an existential anchor to his philosophizing. He is not naïve about suffering— even though he thinks that respect for autonomy should allow suicide as a solution to suffering. But clearly, Lachs does not think that suffering can be redeemed in either the Hegelian philosopher’s spiritual vantage point or in a more religious theodicy. His existential solution is to weave Stoic indifference together with the pragmatic effort to amerliorate things. As he puts it in In Love with Life, “Of course we die. By why should that spoil breakfast?” (109). With regard to the challenge of multiculturalism, Lachs might respond that it is true that there are closed and recalcitrant culture—but why should that spoil our slow and steady progress? Peace, Prosperity, and Education Lachs embraces finitude with a grain of salt and a cup of cheer—and witty turns of phrase that themselves provide solace and energize the spirit. Lachs’ good-humored approach to philosophizing about life, politics, and society is infectious. There is no denying the stamp of his personality on his work: his enthusiasm, good sense, and pithy phraseology. Sometimes you can hear him smiling as you read his work. His own energetic love for life helps to explain his celebration of the prosperity that results from human creativity and labor. After all, teaching and writing are human creative arts: Lachs clearly enjoys both—and they give meaning and joy to life. For Lachs, material and technological development are wonderful things, which make life better. These improvements are the result of common sense, philosophical honesty, and human 8 ingenuity. In celebrating prosperity and technology in his own lively writing, Lachs reminds us of the fun of being human. At bottom, the goodness of the life Lachs imagines is grounded in “activity” of the Aristotelian sense. While Aristotlelian activity is an end in itself, it is also socially useful. Lachs argues that productive labor and material wealth help to defuse religious intolerance, nationalistic fervor, and ethnic division (Stoic Pragmatism, p. 168). He also suggests that philosophical enlightenment and understanding lead toward a recognition of pluralism. At the level of theory, Lachs works to defuse absolutism and dogmatism, which he thinks leads to oppressive conformity. At a more practical level, he advocates the spread of commerce, trade, and technology as a solution to violence and war.ix Lachs suggests that political life ought to be understood as a means of protecting happiness in its diverse manifestations—rather than as a way of imposing one idea of happiness on people (or even worse, as a Machiavellian or Nietzschean game of power). Political and religious conflict results from ideas about a promised land and a place and time of ideological domination. Lachs suggests that the antidote for all of that is material well-being accompanied by liberty and philosophical education. Lachs is not utopian. He knows that the task of amelioration is on-going. But since Lachs is not interested in developing or defending a strong Platonic or Hegelian notion of the state, his solution is educational. Lachs grounds his diagnosis of social dysfunction with the problem of mediation. Violence can be understood, he argues, as a response to alienation. He suggests that there is a sort of aesthetic and psychological benefit to violence: “violence restores the aesthetic magnificence of the directly present” (Relevance, 107). The solution to this is to foster immediacy in other ways. And for this 9 to happen we must first understand the problem of mediation and alienation. And then we must educate people better. We must see that “the mediated world is our own creation” (Relevance, 112). Once we see that, we can change the world and improve it further. Lachs (along with his co-author, Shirley Lachs) argues that education is one of the most intimate and important of social projects. He laments the fact, however, that education has come to be seen as a merely “bureaucratic job” (Relevance, 107). In that circumstance, we end up with “uncaring irresponsibility” (Relevance, 136). The solution to the ills of our educational bureaucracy is more caring, more community, and more virtue. Furthermore, Lachs suggests that the role of the state is an educational one. Lachs suggests that the state should be less focused on employing force to mandate solutions to social problems—and more focused on educating the public. Lachs wants teaching to retain its origin as a “calling” and to not become a bureaucratic or mechanical act. In his reflections on the value of universities in the age of the internet, Lachs points out the role of faculty as “mature human beings” who embody “living knowledge” (Community of Individuals, 27). Teachers and professors are most beneficial when they are engaged with students as real persons, embodying wisdom and providing a source of intergenerational friendship. Instead of a promised land, Lachs argues, people need a “land of promise, of actualizable hope for peace and the contentment of material goods” (Stoic Pragmatism, 168). Lachs explains that this is why immigrants scramble to come to America—and he suggests that the path toward world peace is to find ways to extend material prosperity and liberty to all people of the world.x A good and satisfying life involves “work and 10 consumption.” This leads Lachs to reject welfarism that produces dependency and disempowers people (a point about which the details matter—and which I think Lachs is a bit too quick to judge). Relativism and World Peace Lachs’ recipe for world peace is deceptive simple: to celebrate human diversity and allow people the freedom to work while trying to help them become happy without meddling. Respect for life and liberty are fundamental—and combined with holding people responsible for their misdeeds.xi With regard to diversity, Lachs’ discussions of “human natures” (in the plural) is important for understanding his critique of violence. Diversity and relativism make it difficult to justify violence and hatred.xii Of course, Lachs is clearly not an absolute pacifist. He clearly understands the problem power as found in sources such as Plato, Hegel, Schopenhauer, and Nietzsche. Lachs makes it clear that our desire for operational independence and stability can easily extend toward the desire to control others. Citing William James’ idea about the need for a moral equivalent of war, Lachs notes, “some people love war and adventure with all their souls, and nothing but fights and danger and risky exploration can make their existence worthwhile… some people just cannot be happy without being pugilists” (Community of Individuals 57).xiii In the terms of Lachs’ larger social and psychological theory, the problem of violence and war is a problem of mediation: violence and war are seductive because they can return us to immediacy. To prevent the desire for immediacy to become anti-social and violent, education is needed. Lachs suggests that the desire for immediacy can be 11 transformed in a nonviolent direction, when we come to understand both our felt dissatisfaction with mediation and the need to work diligently to make the social and political world more humane.xiv Given these insights, Lachs warns that pacifism (although he does not use the term) is a threat to liberal democracies. In Meddling, Lachs explains that liberal democrats engage in the “comfortable illusion” that everyone is enlightened and willing to talk about their differences. But his analysis of violence and will-to-power make it clear that not everyone is a well-adjusted liberal who wants to talk things over. A significant problem occurs, according to Lachs, when liberal democracies lack the will to fight—and totalitarian states and warrior regimes attack, taking advantage of their complacence. Lachs concludes, “there may come a time when war will seem a childhood disease of humankind, but that time has not arrived” (Meddling, 111). Again, Lachs hints that the solution is material progress: more liberty, opportunity, prosperity, and education. A Critique of Lachs’ Poetic Simplicity It should be clear that I think that Lachs’ philosophy and worldview are inspirational. However, let’s note another point of critique. Lachs’ work can appear to consist of much anecdotal evidence, moralistic exhortation, and wishful thinking. As one early critic put it in a review of Intermediate Man, sometimes it seems that in Lachs’ work the poet gets the better of the philosopher.xv Consider Lachs’ use of homespun analogies, anecdotes, and examples. This is central to his philosophizing. One recurrent theme is food and drink; another theme 12 focuses on animals; and still other themes come from domestic and family life. Lachs suggests that we can learn much from our desire for food, for example. The desire for more and new things is “embraced in cooking, where we seek surprising ways to enhance the taste of meals” (Stoic Pragmatism, 107). From this and other examples Lachs concludes that we believe that nothing is good enough. Or consider Lachs’ discussion of backyard raccoons in his account of how welfare handouts create dependency. “Even animals display this tendency. At one point we put out some leftovers for a group of raccoons; the next night, they brought their friends and waited for the handout. Generally, when something desirable is free for the taking, intelligent creatures of all sorts avail themselves of it” (Meddling, 92). There is much fun and enjoyment in reading Lachs, since these examples and anecdotes keep us grounded in the world of lived experience. But one wonders about the data with regard to issues such as welfare, poverty, unemployment, and healthcare. Are human welfare recipients really like hungry raccoons? Is the craving after the divine and the perfect really similar to our desire for a tasty meal? Despite his obvious awareness of the complexity of the issues, Lachs’ writing often appears a bit simplistic. Indeed, Lachs tendency to simplify may be what led Dennis Schmidt to once accuse Lachs of being a modern day Dr. Pangloss who has fallen for the trap of “one-dimensional” thinking (which Schmidt invokes with a nod to Marcuse).xvi Cynthia Willett has added to the critique of Lachs by implying that Lachs has been seduced by affluence and comfort and that this leaves him complacent about the injustices of the world and perhaps also complicit, insofar as he (and most other affluent 13 Americans) enjoys a life that is built upon the backs of slaves.xvii Even fans of Lachs’ work worry that it is at times too rosy and optimistic.xviii One could approach this critique in an ad hominem fashion, arguing that Lachs privileged vantage point in the ivy covered walls at Vanderbilt prevents him from seeing the suffering and injustice that reside just down the street and across the bridge. Is Lachs merely reporting what the world looks like from his own point of view? Or is he able to ground his philosophy in something more objective. Consider the question of loving life. For those already in love with life—and for those fortunate enough to live in North America and to teach philosophy for a living—the love of life is obvious. But what about children suffering from Ebola in Africa? What about women and girls oppressed by their families, religions, and governments? What about war, rape, arson, disease, ignorance, and so on? Lachs does not deny that we die— as we noted above. But when he follows this with by asking why we should let that “spoil breakfast,” we might point out that there are some who die precisely because they do not have enough to eat for breakfast. A critic might argue that Lachs’ tendency to simplify is a type of denial: to insist that life is worth loving is to deny the experience of a large number of people, whose lives are not worth living. Let’s make this concrete by returning to the question of violence, war, peace, and military power. Lachs does look askance at those who “exalt the glory of dying for country or for God”: he links voluntary and mechanical sacrifice to the “values of the ant hill” (Meddling, 108). And yet he praises military service, especially when employed in defense of liberty (Meddling, 126-7). There is a contradiction here that needs resolution. Perhaps a more thorough explanation of the just war theory would help, along with a 14 more detailed account of the necessity of the division of labor in society. And beneath this, one wishes that Lachs would weigh in on questions about the military-industrial complex, American imperialism, and the other moral complexities introduced by those who are critical of the power of institutionalized and structural violence.xix Conclusion: Engaged and Limited Public Philosophy In reply to this type of criticism, I believe we ought to consider the facticity of philosophizing. Consider the audience and intent of Lachs’ work. Lachs’ audience varies. In Love with Life is a popular work—and different in tone from something like Stoic Pragmatism, which is primarily addressed to other philosophers. We should recognize the plurality of authorial voices in Lachs’ work. This pluralism in method fits his larger idea: one of his strategies is to argue against the monistic and dogmatic absolutism of some philosophers who speak as if they have taken flight with Hegel and the owl of Minerva. Lachs’ strategy is often deflationary and mischievous. The homespun examples and anecdotes are a dialectical antidote to Hegelian pretentiousness and world-weary critical theory. Lachs teaches that philosophy arises in the middle of things. Its contributions are minor and limited. We are constrained by context, history, and point of view. No philosopher can deal with all questions and problems at once. There is darkness. But Lachs choses to look on the bright side. That’s a welcome breath of fresh air in a world that is afflicted by negativity and death. Instead of piling on complexity with the critical theorists, existentialists, and postmodernists, Lachs offers a simple retort: open your eyes and your hearts to the world and 15 you will find that there is much to love, that happiness does happen, that most of us share a commitment to the value of liberty, and that we are making progress toward a better world. Lachs represents an antithesis to the image of the philosopher as the recondite whiner and nihilistic doomsayer. There is much to criticize in the world; but there is also much to celebrate if we only allow the richness of the world to engulf us, leaving us filled with gratitude and amazement. 16 Works by John Lachs Cited A Community of Individuals. New York: Routledge, 2003. Freedom and Limits. Ed. by Pat Shade. Bronx, NY, USA: Fordham University Press, 2014. In Love With Life: Reflections on the Joy of Living and Why We Hate to Die. Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press, 1998. Meddling: On the Virtue of Leaving Others Alone. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2014. Mind and Philosophers. Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press, 1987. The Relevance of Philosophy to Life. Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press, 1995. Stoic Pragmatism. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2012 i He continues in that essay, describing his pragmatic, Deweyan ideal of philosophy and social theory as follows: “It restores the dignity of everyday activities and establishes them as proper elements in meaningful lives. It refuses to view the totality of our condition as flawed… and looks, instead, for concrete ways to enhance enjoyment in the present and to increase it in the future” (Relevance, 90). [The idea of “good enough”] rejects the relevance of the ideal of perfection and strikes at the root of our compulsion to pursue unreachable ideals. It liberates us to the enjoyment of the possible without eliminating standards or moral effort. It enables us to still our will by achieving what we can and celebrating what we do. By no means least, it dissolves the eternal dissatisfaction that permeates Western industrial society, and it substitutes joy in the immediacies of life for all-encompassing guilt (Stoic Pragmatism, 114-15). ii Thomas Jefferson, “Letter to William Short Monticello, October 31, 1819” in Jefferson: Political Writings (Cambridge University Press, 1999), 313-16. iii iv One hint about this is found in his critical discussion of colonialism—which is another form of meddling, which Lachs rejects. “The fact that one nation may be ahead of another in moral growth does not entitle it to take over the other’s life. Contrary to what aggressive colonial power supposed, no civilized state has a right or an obligation to civilize the world. Open communication, a shared life, and setting a good example suffice to make the ways of liberal democracies attractive to many nations “(Stoic Pragmatism, 35). Lachs also says “We learn to pursue our true good the way we learn to fish: by experience… (Relevance, 36). “I am quite certain that a God of the sort I have described actually exists. For if there is a single experience that has intrinsic value, there is a sum or totality of such experiences. Each feeling of happiness or joy, therefore, confirms the existence of the Deity. Finally, I am persuaded of the religious adequacy of this living God. Machines do not worship, but there are few men who do not find or look for a god to serve. The ideal of maximizing value that this concept of God expresses is thoroughly civilized and humane. If this notion of God took the place of the older ones in our great religions, the believer could v 17 adore a Being of pure value instead of a kindly tyrant. Then each time we achieved a suitable state of mind, we could rejoice in the certain knowledge that that small part of us will live forever as a part of God” (Mind and Philosophers, 66). Lachs’ theology echoes the wisdom of Emerson, Santayana, Royce, and Bertrand Russell—along with Harstshorne and Feuerbach. Lest this be dismissed as an early work without lasting impact for understanding Lachs’ work, note that Lachs appears to continue to affirm this idea of God. One hint comes from an essay Lachs published in 2004 (“The Difference God Makes” in Midwestern Philosophy Journal— republished in Stoic Pragmatism) where he contrasts Royce, who affirms God with Santayana, who does not. Lachs concludes: “Although we hear much about the decline of religion, the promise of safe haven provided by caring omnipotence continues to attract masses of people. Rejecting the hypothesis that God governs all, on the other hand, leaves us with a bleak universe of temporary joy and ultimate demise. It may be easy to adopt this attitude in the strutting fullness of life, but age and debility tend to turn the mind to searching for aid from a higher power” (Stoic Pragmatism, 157). vi vii Declaring certain values natural rights, for example, puts us in a more powerful position than if we simply announced our intention to fight for them. Asserting that certain social structures, political arrangements or modes of behavior are direct outcomes of human nature makes them appear more weighty than if we merely said that we favor them (Relevance, 237). “The Silence that Preceded China’s Great Leap into Famine” Smithsonian Magazine, September 26, 2012 (http://www.smithsonianmag.com/history/the-silence-that-preceded-chinas-great-leap-into-famine51898077/#hSRj9E5CSzcLjMRj.99) viii ix It is no overstatement that replacing war with commerce is a turning point in the moral evolution of humankind. Instead of wanting other people dead, we want them to live and prosper. Our relation to them becomes internal: in trade, their good is essentially linked to ours, so what harms them harms us, as well. A momentous expansion of the self follows inevitably. We begin to view our trading partners in the same favorable light in which we bathe ourselves. Their habits become interesting, their choices respectable, their fates important (“Better and Better Off” in Community of Individuals, 106-7). “Although affluence in a commercial world brings with it all the problems of overconsumption, there is in the end no alternative way to eradicate nationalist, ethnic, and religious violence” (Stoic Pragmatism, 169). x “In humane societies people are free to do much or all that relates to them alone, but not to hurt or murder others. To hold people responsible is to teach them responsibility… The same approach may slowly reduce the desire of terrorists and warlike states to create conflagrations around the globe. No person or state should want to run the lives of others. So we need to say clearly that we respect independence and wish to leave everyone alone, but we will not tolerate aggressive and destructive acts” (In Love with Life, 88). xi “Condemnation of other persons and nations becomes difficult in proportion as we see the legitimacy of differing ideals. Accordingly, justifications of hatred and war would be recognized as specious and dismissed by all who take the relativity of values seriously” (Relevance, 27). A slightly different version of these sentences can be found in Lachs, “Pluralism and Choice Inclusive Facts” in Shade, ed. Freedom and Limits (Bronx, NY, USA: Fordham University Press, 2014), p. 228. xii Or as he explains in The Relevance of Philosophy to Life, the desire to “do something of moment” can lead individuals to turn to violence. “There is a surprising, positive side to the horrors of war. Many people report that great danger leads to an exhilaration that renders experience vibrant…The routine of a safe society obliterates the momentousness of life; war reacquaints us with energizing danger, with death, contingency, and finitude… The exercise of great power, especially physical power that threatens damage, vitalizes experience. The predictable triviality of life is gone, and we are suddenly exposed to the sacred depths of existence, the finality and irreversibility of what happens to us” (Relevance, 106-7). xiii 18 “If we see the modern world as of our own making, it will not seem so oppressive and alien. The more we view it as our own, the less we shall be content to blow it up or to see it burn” (Relevance, 111-12). xv James Chesher, Review of John Lachs, Intermediate Man in Reason Papers 11 (Spring 1986) at http://reasonpapers.com/pdf/11/rp_11_10.pdf xvi Dennis J. Schmidt, “Scales: Human or Otherwise: On Moral and Material Complexity” The Journal of Speculative Philosophy 15.3 (2001) 190-194 xvii Willett argues with regard to Lachs: “His defense of the American way of life encourages us to overlook the damage that modernization and capitalist production have done to our emotive and social lives. It is good to be comfortable, but comfort is not enough. The attitude of complacency that comfort instills allows us to ignore the fact that we do not live on the island called America, but at the top of a social and economic pyramid of global proportions, and that this pyramid is built by slaves” [Cynthia Willett, “The Pyramid that Slaves Built: A Reply to John Lachs” The Journal of Speculative Philosophy 15.3 (2001) 184189]. xviii One review of In Love With Life by Richard Hart raises a significant question. “The book’s title and subtitle, In Love with Life: Reflections on the Joy of Living and Why We Hate To Die, may strike some as too optimistic or idealistic, as painting too rosy a picture of human experience. Perhaps to some it even begs the question, for Lachs seems to presume that (1) we humans do essentially love life (or ought to if we see clearly), and (2) that as a result of this passionate love we truly hate to die. Is this a given or is it true only foe some fortunate souls, for instance, philosophers or artists who revel in pondering life? [Richard E. Hart, “Review of In Love with Life,” Metaphilosophy Vol. 32, No. 5, October 2001]. xiv xix Lachs is clearly suspicious of overweaning legislation, and he is not overly fond of the wisdom of political representatives. It is surprising that he appears to sanguinely endorse military solutions to global problems. I have no doubt that some limited military solutions may be needed in the real world. But there are deep structural and ethical problems connected to militarism: from the absurdity of nuclear deterrence to the problem of unilateralism in military and foreign affairs. Lachs does touch upon some of these problems in Intermediate Man—in his discussion of the moral slippage that leads to war crimes. But one wants a more sustained and deeper critique. Similar complaints against Lachs can be lodged from those who would prefer that he say more about racism, sexism, environmental degradation, and a host of other ills. 19