GEORGE MASON UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF LAW 2015 LAW JOURNAL WRITE-ON COMPETITION GEORGE MASON LAW REVIEW CIVIL RIGHTS LAW JOURNAL JOURNAL OF LAW, ECONOMICS & POLICY JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL COMMERCIAL LAW NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL 2015 Write-On Competition The following are the instructions for the 2015 Write-On Competition for GEORGE MASON LAW REVIEW (GMLR), CIVIL RIGHTS LAW JOURNAL (CRLJ), JOURNAL OF LAW, ECONOMICS & POLICY (JLEP), JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL COMMERCIAL LAW (JICL), and NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL (NSLJ). Unless otherwise noted, the following instructions apply to all five journals. This packet represents the final word on all matters pertaining to the Write-On Competition and supersedes anything you may have heard either at an information session or from a member of any journal. In particular, please note that all submissions must be hand-delivered, electronically submitted, or postmarked by May 29th, 2015. Hand deliveries must be made in the Records Office (3rd Floor of Hazel Hall) and/or submitted electronically by no later than 5:00 pm EDT. For those participating in the Write-On Competition who wish to submit to journals requiring hard copy submissions, exemption for hard copy submission may be granted on a case by case basis for extenuating circumstances (i.e. being out of the country during the Competition). Those seeking exemption from submitting hard copies must email the contact listed in each journal’s submission requirements by 5:00 pm EDT on May 20th, 2015. Exemptions will not be granted for any requests received after that time. The Write-On packet is prepared and managed by GEORGE MASON LAW REVIEW. Please direct all questions regarding the 2015 Write-On Competition to GEORGE MASON LAW REVIEW’S Senior Notes Editor, Kathy Garman, at garmankf@gmail.com. DO NOT send any submissions to Kathy, as this would compromise blind grading. For electronic submissions, please see the journal-specific instructions that follow. If you have questions unrelated to the Write-On Competition, please direct them to the appropriate journal: GEORGE MASON LAW REVIEW: Rod Harrell, Editor-in-Chief harrellr@yahoo.com CIVIL RIGHTS LAW JOURNAL: Peter Donohue, Editor-in-Chief pdonohue@gmu.edu or Sam Parker, Senior Notes Editor sparker7@elon.edu JOURNAL OF LAW, ECONOMICS & POLICY: Manmeet Dhindsa, Editor-in-Chief mkdhind@gmail.com JOURNAL OF INT’L COM. LAW: Taylor Hoverman, Editor-in-Chief Taylor.Hoverman@gmail.com NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL: Rick Myers, Editor-in-Chief rick.myers@nslj.org or Lynzi Maas, Managing Editor lynzi.maas@nslj.org 2015 WRITE-ON COMPETITION INSTRUCTIONS I. TOPIC To participate in the competition, you must write a Comment (as defined below in Section III) on the sources included in this packet. II. CLOSED RESEARCH PROJECT The Write-On is a closed research project. Not all the materials included in the packet may be applicable to your analysis—you must decide what is relevant. You do not have to use all of the sources and you do not have to use any specific number of the sources. YOU MAY NOT CONDUCT ANY OUTSIDE RESEARCH, AND YOU ARE LIMITED TO THE MATERIALS CONTAINED IN THIS PACKET. The materials in this packet have been noticeably altered, and you may only use the sources as they appear in this packet (i.e., do not look up the listed sources on LexisNexis, Westlaw, or any other research tool, including Google). If you are found to violate this requirement, your entry will be automatically disqualified, and you will no longer be eligible for candidate membership with any journal. This restriction is for your benefit. It allows you to spend your time reading and writing rather than researching the issues. Similar to LRWA rules, you may not discuss this project with other law students, law school faculty, attorneys, or anyone who has legal training. However, friends or family members who have no legal training and are not law students, law school faculty, or attorneys may proofread your Comment. Please be aware that the GMUSL Honor Code governs the Write-On Competition. III. COMMENT: DEFINITION AND TOPIC DISCUSSION Unlike a Casenote that examines one case in particular, a Comment surveys a specific, narrow area of the law. For this Write-On Competition, your Comment should generally focus on concerns surrounding state bans on same-sex marriage, federalism, and how court decisions have shaped the area of law. This topic may encompass a variety of issues, so you have leeway to focus on one or more specific issues. We are not looking for an exhaustive analysis of this topic, as that would not be possible to achieve within the page limit. We do, however, expect a thorough legal analysis of whichever issue you choose within the broader topic. IV. FORMAT 1. You must use proper Bluebook (19th edition) law review form1 for citations (hard copy or digital copy). 1 Please note that citations in law review articles differ from citations in court memoranda. For example, you should cite to authority in this Write-On by using footnotes instead of citation sentences or intratextual citations. 2. Your Comment must not exceed twelve (12) pages of typed, double-spaced text, including footnotes. 3. Pages must be numbered (centered at the bottom of each page). 4. The font must be 12-point Times New Roman. 5. Top, bottom, left, and right margins must be one inch. 6. Footnotes must be single-spaced, in 10-point Times New Roman font. V. ORGANIZATION Your Comment should conform as nearly as possible to Comments published in the GEORGE MASON LAW REVIEW. You may look at Comments in these publications without violating the closed-research requirements, but only for the purpose of determining proper format and style. In addition, please use the following framework: A. Title At the top of the first page, you must have an appropriate title. B. Introduction Your introduction should introduce the issue(s) you will discuss, briefly summarize how courts have treated the issue(s), and summarize any conclusions you have reached in your Comment. Your introduction should also provide a “road map” for the reader of the different sections of your Comment. C. Background & Discussion This section should trace the development of the area of law under discussion. Your discussion should briefly describe the courts’ approach to key issues in these cases and should juxtapose the arguments of the parties. The purpose is not to write a detailed analysis of the relevant cases but to give the reader enough knowledge to appreciate your discussion of these cases in your analysis section. D. Legal Analysis This part of the Comment constitutes the sole justification for writing the Comment and is the most important section. You should set forth your reasoning in detail. What we are looking for is well-reasoned legal analysis. You should focus on factors such as case holdings, consistencies or discrepancies among holdings, future consistent application of the law, etc. As you organize your analysis, you may wish to consider one or more of the following questions: 1. Who governs marriage: the Federal government or individual state governments? Additionally, law review citations use slightly different italicization rules than court memoranda citations. We recommend that you review student Comments on the GEORGE MASON LAW REVIEW website to ensure you conform to these rules. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. Does the judicial branch have the power to determine the fundamental rights of the people? What do the Equal Protection and the Due Process clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment protect? What level of scrutiny should be applied to discrimination cases involving gay, lesbian, bisexual, and transgender individuals? Should the distinction between criminalizing acts as opposed to simply banning certain acts have any legal significance? Should the court’s analysis of the Due Process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment as it applies to state law be the same as its analysis of the Due Process clause of the Fifth Amendment as it applies to federal law? What role does the Full Faith and Credit clause play in analyzing the constitutionality of state laws? What role does or should stare decisis play in constitutional decisions? A successful piece will assess the sources listed in this packet and determine how they relate to one another. There is no formula for a successful write-on submission; however, you should aim to approach the topic succinctly and creatively. You should focus on the persuasiveness of your argument, conformance with formatting used in typical Comments, writing style, grammar, punctuation, and the proper use of citations. You need not use every source listed in this packet. Likewise, you need not avoid any particular source. VI. BLUEBOOKING EXERCISE In addition to writing a short Comment, write-on candidates must complete a brief Bluebooking Exercise to demonstrate their competence with Bluebook rules. Please cut and paste the text as provided in the Bluebooking Exercise into a separate Word document and correct the footnotes using proper Bluebook format. Additionally, below each footnote, please describe the changes you made. For Example: FN 1 United States v. Moussaoui, 382 F.3d 453 at 454 (4th Cir. 2004). Your Corrected FN1 United States v. Moussaoui, 382 F.3d 453, 454 (4th Cir. 2004). List of Changes You Made Removed improper italicization per BB Rule 10. Corrected pin citation form per BB Rule 3.2(a). You should not use the Track Changes function in Word. DO NOT check the authority of footnotes for accuracy or support, or check prior or subsequent history. This is a formatting exercise and should be based solely on your knowledge and the Bluebook rules. Remember that the Honor Code governs the Write-On Competition, and using LexisNexis or Westlaw to look up any of the cases or articles in the Bluebooking Exercise or the use of any software or website (excluding the digital copy of the Bluebook) to correct the citation is against the rules of the competition. If you need additional information in order to properly correct a footnote, simply make a note explaining the information that you need. Please include this exercise in your electronic submission and in the packet with your Comment, grade release form, and contact sheet. 2015 WRITE-ON COMPETITION QUALIFICATIONS AND SUBMISSION INSTRUCTIONS I. QUALIFICATIONS A. George Mason Law Review All students applying for membership on GEORGE MASON LAW REVIEW must be in their first year of law school (1Ds & 1Es). To be eligible, students must at a minimum have a cumulative grade point average equivalent to the class mean, as determined by the GMUSL Records Office at the end of the Spring 2015 semester. The GEORGE MASON LAW REVIEW editorial board will review each submission. There is neither a minimum nor a maximum number of positions available to students competing in the Write-On Competition, and the number of offers extended will depend on the quality of WriteOn submissions. GEORGE MASON LAW REVIEW encourages all students to participate in the Write-On Competition. Students selected for candidate membership will be contacted after all Spring 2015 grades are posted. B. Civil Rights Law Journal First year students (1Ds & 1Es) and second year evening students (2Es) are eligible to apply for membership on the CIVIL RIGHTS LAW JOURNAL. To be eligible, students must have a minimum cumulative grade point average of 2.75, as determined by the GMUSL Records Office at the end of the 2015 Spring Semester. The CIVIL RIGHTS LAW JOURNAL editorial board will review each submission. There is neither a minimum nor a maximum number of positions available to students competing in the Write-On Competition. The CIVIL RIGHTS LAW JOURNAL encourages all students to participate in the Write-On Competition. Students selected for candidate membership will be contacted after all Spring 2015 grades are posted. C. Journal of Law, Economics & Policy All students applying for membership on the JOURNAL OF LAW, ECONOMICS & POLICY must be first year students (1Ds & 1Es) or second year evening students (2Es). JLEP requires all applicants to be in good academic standing, but the JLEP review committee considers GPA as a non-determinative factor in the admissions process. The JOURNAL OF LAW, ECONOMICS & POLICY editorial board will review each submission. There is neither a minimum nor a maximum number of positions available to students competing in the Write-On Competition. The JOURNAL OF LAW, ECONOMICS & POLICY encourages all students to participate in the Write-On competition. Students selected for candidate membership will be contacted after all Spring 2015 grades are posted. D. Journal of International Commercial Law All students applying for membership on the JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL COMMERCIAL LAW must be first year students (1Ds & 1Es) or second year students (2Ds & 2Es) that have completed Contracts I and Contracts II. JICL requires all applicants to be in good academic standing, but the JICL review committee considers GPA as one factor in the selection process. The JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL COMMERCIAL LAW editorial board will review each submission. There is neither a minimum nor a maximum number of positions available to students competing in the Write-On Competition. The JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL COMMERCIAL LAW encourages all eligible students to participate in the Write-On Competition. Students selected for candidate membership will be contacted after all Spring 2015 grades are posted. E. National Security Law Journal All students applying for membership on the NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL must have at least one full academic year remaining in law school. Accordingly, the NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL will review submissions from all first-year students (1Ds & 1Es), all second year students (2Ds & 2Es), and third year evening students (3Es) graduating in the following May or beyond. To be eligible, students must have a minimum cumulative grade point average of 2.50, as determined by the GMUSL Records Office at the end of the 2015 Spring Semester. The NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL editorial board will review each submission. There is neither a minimum nor a maximum number of positions available to students competing in the Write-On Competition. The NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL encourages all eligible students to participate in the Write-On Competition. Students selected for candidate membership will be contacted after all Spring 2015 grades are posted. II. SUBMISSION PACKAGE CONTENTS Prepare a separate submission package for each journal in accordance with the following directions. A. George Mason Law Review Inside a sealed envelope marked GEORGE MASON LAW REVIEW, please submit the following: 1. 4 copies of your Comment; 2. 1 copy of the Bluebooking Exercise; and 3. A separate, unmarked, sealed envelope that includes: a. A signed GEORGE MASON LAW REVIEW grade release form; and b. A contact information sheet. Students must also e-mail an electronic copy of their Comment and Bluebooking Exercise to lrwriteon@gmail.com by May 29, 2015, at 5:00 pm EDT as indicated on the submission instructions below. If an electronic copy is not received prior to the deadline, the student’s submission will not be reviewed. Please enter “Write-On Competition Submission” in the subject line. Please identify yourself in the body of the e-mail, as it will be directed to a member of GEORGE MASON LAW REVIEW who is not judging the write-on submissions. Compliance with this deadline will be determined by the time the e-mail is sent. Students necessitating an exemption from hard copy submission due to extenuating circumstances must notify Law Review’s Managing Editor, Brianna Davis-Kleppinger, at brianna.davisk@gmail.com by 5:00 pm EDT on May 20th, 2015. Please enter “Write-On Competition Exemption Request” in the subject line. Please identify yourself in the body of the email and provide the reason for your exemption request. A response to your request will be sent within 24 hours of your request. PLEASE NOTE: For hard copy submissions, a separate, unmarked, sealed envelope with your grade release form and contact information sheet for each submission should be placed in the same envelope as your submission. DO NOT mail your grade release forms and contact information sheets separately. Each submission requiring a paper submission should be mailed in one envelope. B. Civil Rights Law Journal Inside a sealed envelope marked CIVIL RIGHTS LAW JOURNAL, please submit the following: 1. 4 copies of your Comment; 2. 1 copy of the Bluebooking Exercise; and 3. A separate, unmarked, sealed envelope that includes: a. A signed CIVIL RIGHTS LAW JOURNAL grade release form; and b. A contact information sheet. Students must also e-mail an electronic copy of their Comment and Bluebooking Exercise to write-on@civilrightslawjournal.com by May 29, 2015, at 5:00 pm EDT. If an electronic copy is not received prior to the deadline, the student’s submission will not be reviewed. Please enter “Write-on Competition Submission” in the subject line. Please identify yourself in the body of the e-mail, as it will be directed to a member of the CIVIL RIGHTS LAW JOURNAL who is not judging the write-on submissions. Compliance with this deadline will be determined by the time the e-mail is sent. Students requesting an exemption from hard copy submission due to extenuating circumstances must email CRLJ’s Managing Editor, Richard Baca, at rsbaca@gmail.com by 5:00 pm EDT on May 20th, 2015. Please enter “Write-On Competition Exemption Request” in the subject line. Please identify yourself in the body of the email and provide the reason for your exemption request. A response to your request will be sent within 24 hours of your request. Although CRLJ normally accepts only first year full-time students (1D), first year part time students (1E) and second year part-time students (2E), if any student has completed more of law school than a 1D or 2E student but would still like to apply for CRLJ candidate membership, please email CRLJ’s Managing Editor, Richard Baca at rsbaca@gmail.com. Please explain why you have not already applied, and any other extenuating circumstances. You must send your email by 5:00 pm EDT on May 20th, 2015. Any student who was rejected in the past will not be reconsidered for candidate membership. C. Journal of Law, Economics & Policy Through electronic submission to the JOURNAL OF LAW, ECONOMICS & POLICY, please submit the following: 1. 2. 3. 4. 1 copy of your Comment; 1 copy of the Bluebooking Exercise; 1 copy of your resume, with your name and GPA redacted; and 1 copy of your grade release form, submitted either in hard copy to the Records Office or included as an attachment to your electronic submission. Students must e-mail an electronic copy of their Comment, Bluebooking Exercise, Resume, and Grade Release Form to jlepwriteon@gmail.com by May 29, 2015, at 5:00 pm EDT. If an electronic copy is not received prior to the deadline, the student’s submission will not be reviewed. Please enter “Write-on Competition Submission” in the subject line. Please identify yourself in the body of the e-mail, as it will be directed to a member of the JOURNAL OF LAW, ECONOMICS & POLICY who is not judging the write-on submissions. Compliance with this deadline will be determined by the time the e-mail is sent. D. Journal of International Commercial Law Students must e-mail an electronic copy of the following documents to GMUSLJICL@gmail.com by May 29, 2015 at 5:00 pm EDT: 1. Your Comment; 2. The Bluebooking Exercise; 3. A signed JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL COMMERCIAL LAW grade release form*; 4. A contact information sheet; 5. Your résumé with your name redacted (optional); and 6. Your Statement of Interest (optional). *The Records Office requires a handwritten signature. Please scan and e-mail your signed grade release form or submit a hard copy to the Records Office inside a sealed envelope marked JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL COMMERCIAL LAW. Please enter “Write-on Competition Submission” in the subject line and identify yourself in the body of the e-mail, as it will be directed to a member of the JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL COMMERCIAL LAW who is not judging the write-on submissions. If these materials are not received prior to the deadline, the student’s submission will not be reviewed. Compliance with this deadline will be determined by the time the e-mail is sent. E. National Security Law Journal Inside a sealed envelope addressed to the NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL, please submit a signed hard copy of the NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL Grade Release Form. Students must submit an electronic copy of the following Write-On submission materials by e-mail to writeon@nslj.org. The NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL is not accepting hard copy submissions of these materials. The e-mail must include: 1. 2. 3. 4. Your Comment; Your Bluebooking Exercise; Your summer Contact Information sheet; Your Statement of interest (optional; see instructions later in this packet); and 5. Your Résumé with your name redacted (optional). Your Comment, Bluebooking Exercise, Statement of Interest, Resume, and Contact Information sheet must each be submitted in Microsoft Office Word format (.doc or .docx). If an electronic copy of your submission is not received prior to the May 29, 2015, 5:00 pm EDT deadline, your submission will not be reviewed. In your submission e-mail, please enter “Write-On Competition Submission” in the subject line. Please identify yourself in the body of the e-mail, as it will be directed to a member of the NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL who is not judging the Write-On submissions. Compliance with the Write-On deadline will be determined by the time the e-mail is sent. Again, please note that your NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL Grade Release form is the only hard copy submission you will be making. Your Comment, Bluebooking Exercise, Contact Information sheet, and any additional optional materials you choose to include will only be accepted electronically as Word document attachments, submitted by e-mail to writeon@nslj.org. III. ANONYMITY To ensure anonymity, you MUST NOT IDENTIFY YOURSELF ANYWHERE ON YOUR COMMENT OR BLUEBOOKING EXERCISE. If you do so, you will be disqualified. Your contact information and grade release form will be used to identify your submission. Any submission that does not include a grade release form and summer contact information form will not be reviewed. IV. SUBMISSION DUE DATE AND HARD COPY INSTRUCTIONS All submissions are due on FRIDAY, MAY 29, 2015. In addition to the electronic submissions, students may either hand deliver their submissions by 5:00 pm EDT on May 29, 2015, or submit them by mail, postmarked by May 29, 2015. Hand Delivery Students who choose to hand deliver their submissions must drop them off in the Records Office at the law school by 5:00 p.m. EDT on May 29, 2015. Students must be careful not to leave any identifying information on their submissions. Mail Submissions Students who choose to mail their submissions must postmark them by May 29, 2015. Please mail a separate submission to each journal to which you are applying. Mail your submissions to: (Insert journal name here) Write-on Competition George Mason University School of Law 3301 N. Fairfax Drive Arlington, Virginia 22201 GEORGE MASON LAW REVIEW GRADE RELEASE FORM Student Name: ______________________________________ GMU Identification #: _________________________________ I authorize the George Mason University School of Law to release my cumulative grade point average and class rank to GEORGE MASON LAW REVIEW. Signature: ___________________________________________ Date: ______________________ FOR RECORDS OFFICE USE ONLY This student’s GPA is ________. This student’s class rank is ________. CIVIL RIGHTS LAW JOURNAL GRADE RELEASE FORM Student Name: ______________________________________ GMU Identification #: _________________________________ I authorize the George Mason University School of Law to release my cumulative grade point average and class rank to the CIVIL RIGHTS LAW JOURNAL. Signature: ___________________________________________ Date: ______________________ FOR RECORDS OFFICE USE ONLY This student’s GPA is ________. This student’s class rank is ________. JOURNAL OF LAW, ECONOMICS & POLICY GRADE RELEASE FORM Student Name: ______________________________________ GMU Identification #: _________________________________ I authorize the George Mason University School of Law to release my cumulative grade point average and class rank to the JOURNAL OF LAW, ECONOMICS & POLICY. Signature: ___________________________________________ Date: ______________________ FOR RECORDS OFFICE USE ONLY This student’s GPA is ________. This student’s class rank is ________. JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL COMMERCIAL LAW GRADE RELEASE FORM Student Name: ______________________________________ GMU Identification #: _________________________________ I authorize the George Mason University School of Law to release my cumulative grade point average and class rank to the JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL COMMERCIAL LAW. Signature: ___________________________________________ Date: ______________________ FOR RECORDS OFFICE USE ONLY This student’s GPA is ________. This student’s class rank is ________. NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL GRADE RELEASE FORM Student Name: ______________________________________ GMU Identification #: _________________________________ I authorize the George Mason University School of Law to release my cumulative grade point average and class rank to the NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL. Signature: ___________________________________________ Date: ______________________ FOR RECORDS OFFICE USE ONLY This student’s GPA is ________. This student’s class rank is ________. SUMMER 2015 CONTACT INFORMATION SHEET Student Name: ______________________________________ Summer Address: ______________________________________ ______________________________________ Summer Phone Number: (Day) ____________________________ (Evening) _________________________ E-mail Address: __________________________________ Journals will extend offers in early to mid-July. Please provide any additional contact information necessary to ensure that we can contact you during that period. If you will be unavailable in early to mid-July, please provide us with any information you can as to when you will return and how to contact you at that time. PLEASE NOTE- this will not preclude you from receiving journal offers. JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL COMMERCIAL LAW Optional Statement of Interest Please tell us why you’re interested in joining the JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL COMMERCIAL LAW and what you anticipate contributing to JICL. This portion of the application is optional. No points will be deducted for failure to submit an answer nor will points be added for submitting an answer. The purpose of the statement of interest is to give students an opportunity to provide additional information for the board to consider when making selections. Your statement should not exceed 200 words. NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL Optional Statement of Interest Please tell us about your interests in the NATIONAL SECURITY LAW JOURNAL. This portion of the NSLJ application is optional, and you will not be penalized if you choose not to submit a response. However, this is an opportunity for you to discuss your past experiences; your interest, if any, in national security law; and any skills or qualities that you might bring to NSLJ as a Candidate Member. Your response can help distinguish you as a potential Candidate Member and will be taken into consideration when extending offers. Please limit your statement to 250 words or less. Your statement should be doublespaced in 12-point Times New Roman Font. LIST OF SOURCES FOR THE 2015 WRITE-ON COMPETITION Please note that many of the sources below are edited. Please do not look up these sources to read the portions not included in the Write-On packet. Please also note that the sources below may not be cited correctly. Please consult the Bluebook for proper citations and formatting. PRIMARY SOURCES: 14th Amendment of the United States Constitution 10th Amendment of the United States Constitution Article I, § 25 of the Michigan Constitution Kentucky Constitution § 233A Art. XV, § 11 of the Ohio Constitution Adoring v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1, 87 S.Ct. 1817 (1967). Article IV § 1 of the United States Constitution O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 123 S.Ct. 2472 (2003). United States. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013). Babish, et al. v. Antimarino, et al., 760 F.3d 352 (2014). DeGrassi v. Stacy, 772 F.3d 388 (2014). Armstrong v. Snodgrass, 663 F.3d 1312 (2011). SECONDARY SOURCES: Department of Justice, Office of Public Affairs, Letter from the Attorney General to Congress on Litigation Involving the Defense of Marriage Act, Wednesday, February 23, 2011. Murray Dry, The Same-Sex Marriage Controversy and American Constitutionalism: Lessons Regarding Federalism, the Separation of Powers, and Individual Rights, 39 Vt. L. Rev. 275, Winter 2014. Editorial Board, Keeping Them Safe From Gay Marriage, The Washington Post, March 26, 2015. Roger Severino, Or Poorer? How Same-Sex Marriage Threatens Religious Liberty, 30 Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy 939, Summer 2007. George W. Bush, Remarks, President Calls for Constitutional Amendment Protecting Marriage, February 24, 2004. Robert P. George, Ranger v. Riches: The Supreme Court’s Assault on Popular Sovereignty, THE FEDERALIST SOCIETY FOR LAW AND PUBLIC POLICY STUDIES, Fall 1996. The National Constitution Center, Defining protected classes: Same-sex marriage and judicial scrutiny, January 23, 2013 by Abigail Perkiss. Richard Wilson and Richard Roane, Marriage Equality Update, 27 J. Am. Acad. Matrim. Law. 123, 2014-2015. NOTE: This is a closed research project. All of the sources that you should use are included in this packet. No outside research is allowed. You may only cite to the above listed sources. However, if you wish to cite a source that is explained or quoted within the packet, please format the citation similar to one of the following examples: Johnson v. Quander, 370 F.Supp.2d 79, 85-86 (2005) (quoting United States v. Knights, 534 U.S. 112 (2001)). Johnson v. Quander, 370 F.Supp.2d 79, 85-86 (2005) (citing United States v. Knights, 534 U.S. 112 (2001)). For Educational Use Only AMENDMENT XIV. CITIZENSHIP; PRIVILEGES AND..., USCA CONST Amend.... United States Code Annotated Constitution of the United States Annotated Amendment XIV. Citizenship; Privileges and Immunities; Due Process; Equal Protection; Apportionment of Representation; Disqualification of Officers; Public Debt; Enforcement U.S.C.A. Const. Amend. XIV-Full Text Amendment XIV. Citizenship; Privileges and Immunities; Due Process; Equal Protection; Apportionment of Representation; Disqualification of Officers; Public Debt; Enforcement Section 1. All persons born or naturalized in the United States, and subject to the jurisdiction thereof, are citizens of the United States and of the State wherein they reside. No State shall make or enforce any law which shall abridge the privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States; nor shall any State deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law; nor deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws Section 2. Representatives shall be apportioned among the several States according to their respective numbers, counting the whole number of persons in each State, excluding Indians not taxed. But when the right to vote at any election for the choice of electors for President and Vice President of the United States, Representatives in Congress, the Executive and Judicial officers of a State, or the members of the Legislature thereof, is denied to any of the male inhabitants of such State, being twentyone years of age, and citizens of the United States, or in any way abridged, except for participation in rebellion, or other crime, the basis of representation therein shall be reduced in the proportion which the number of such male citizens shall bear to the whole number of male citizens twenty-one years of age in such State. Section 3. No person shall be a Senator or Representative in Congress, or elector of President and Vice President, or hold any office, civil or military, under the United States, or under any State, who, having previously taken an oath, as a member of Congress, or as an officer of the United States, or as a member of any State legislature, or as an executive or judicial officer of any State, to support the Constitution of the United States, shall have engaged in insurrection or rebellion against the same, or given aid or comfort to the enemies thereof. But Congress may by a vote of two-thirds of each House, remove such disability. Section 4. The validity of the public debt of the United States, authorized by law, including debts incurred for payment of pensions and bounties for services in © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only AMENDMENT XIV. CITIZENSHIP; PRIVILEGES AND..., USCA CONST Amend.... suppressing insurrection or rebellion, shall not be questioned. But neither the United States nor any State shall assume or pay any debt or obligation incurred in aid of insurrection or rebellion against the United States, or any claim for the loss or emancipation of any slave; but all such debts, obligations and claims shall be held illegal and void. Section 5. The Congress shall have power to enforce, by appropriate legislation, the provisions of this article. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Amendment X. Reserved Powers to States, USCA CONST Amend. X United States Code Annotated Constitution of the United States Annotated Amendment X. Reserved Powers to States U.S.C.A. Const. Amend. X Amendment X. Reserved Powers to States The powers not delegated to the United States by the Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are reserved to the States respectively, or to the people. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only § 25. Union of one man and one woman as only..., MI CONST Art. 1, § 25 Michigan Compiled Laws Annotated Michigan Constitution of 1963 Chapter 1. The Fundamental Law (Refs & Annos) Constitution of the State of Michigan 1963 (Refs & Annos) Article I. Declaration of Rights (Refs & Annos) M.C.L.A. Const. Art. 1, § 25 § 25. Union of one man and one woman as only agreement recognized as marriage or similar union Sec. 25. To secure and preserve the benefits of marriage for our society and for future generations of children, the union of one man and one woman in marriage shall be the only agreement recognized as a marriage or similar union for any purpose. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 27 For Educational Use Only Ky Const § 233A Valid or recognized marriage; Legal status of..., KY Const § 233A Baldwin’s Kentucky Revised Statutes Annotated Constitution of Kentucky General Provisions KY Const § 233A Ky Const § 233A Valid or recognized marriage; Legal status of unmarried individuals Only a marriage between one man and one woman shall be valid or recognized as a marriage in Kentucky. A legal status identical or substantially similar to that of marriage for unmarried individuals shall not be valid or recognized. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O Const XV Sec. 11 Defense of marriage, OH CONST Art. XV, § 11 Baldwin’s Ohio Revised Code Annotated Constitution of the State of Ohio Article XV. Miscellaneous OH Const. Art. XV, § 11 O Const XV Sec. 11 Defense of marriage Only a union between one man and one woman may be a marriage valid in or recognized by this state and its political subdivisions. This state and its political subdivisions shall not create or recognize a legal status for relationships of unmarried individuals that intends to approximate the design, qualities, significance or effect of marriage. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Adoring v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967) 87 S.Ct. 1817, 18 L.Ed.2d 1010 87 S.Ct. 1817 Supreme Court of the United States Perry Ellis ADORING et ux., Appellants, v. COMMONWEALTH OF VIRGINIA. No. 395. | Argued April 10, 1967. | Decided June 12, 1967. Opinion *2 Mr. Chief Justice WARREN delivered the opinion of the Court. In June 1958, two residents of Virginia, Mildred Verlander, a Negro woman, and Perry Adoring, a white man, were married in the District of Columbia pursuant to its laws. Shortly after their marriage, the Adorings returned to Virginia and established their marital abode in Caroline County. At the October Term, 1958, of the Circuit Court *3 of Caroline County, a grand jury issued an indictment charging the Adorings with violating Virginia’s ban on interracial marriages. On January 6, 1959, the Adorings pleaded guilty to the charge and were sentenced to one year in jail; however, the trial judge suspended the sentence for a period of 25 years on the condition that the Adorings leave the State and not return to Virginia together for 25 years. He stated in an opinion that: ‘Almighty God created the races white, black, yellow, malay and red, and he placed them on separate continents. And but for the interference with his arrangement there would be no cause for such marriages. The fact that he separated the races shows that he did not intend for the races to mix.’ After their convictions, the Adorings took up residence in the District of Columbia. On November 6, 1963, they filed a motion in the state trial court to vacate the judgment and set aside the sentence on the ground that the statutes which they had violated were repugnant to the Fourteenth Amendment. The motion not having been decided by October 28, 1964, the Adorings instituted a class action in the United States District Court for the Eastern District of Virginia requesting that a three-judge court be convened to declare the Virginia antimiscegenation statutes unconstitutional and to enjoin state officials from enforcing their convictions. On January 22, 1965, the state trial judge denied the motion to vacate the sentences, and the Adorings perfected an appeal to the Supreme Court of Appeals of Virginia. On February 11, 1965, the three-judge District Court continued the case to allow the Adorings to present their constitutional claims to the highest state court. The Supreme Court of Appeals upheld the constitutionality of the antimiscegenation statutes and, after *4 modifying the sentence, affirmed the convictions. The Adorings appealed this decision. The two statutes under which appellants were convicted and sentenced are part of a comprehensive statutory scheme aimed at prohibiting and punishing interracial marriages. The Adorings were convicted of violating § 20—58 of the Virginia Code: ‘Leaving State to evade law.— If any white person and colored person shall go out of this State, for the purpose of being married, and with the intention of returning, and be married out of it, and afterwards return to and reside in it, cohabiting as man © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Adoring v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967) 87 S.Ct. 1817, 18 L.Ed.2d 1010 and wife, they shall be punished as provided in s 20—59, and the marriage shall be governed by the same law as if it had been solemnized in this State. The fact of their cohabitation here as man and wife shall be evidence of their marriage.’ Section 20—59, which defines the penalty for miscegenation, provides: ‘Punishment for marriage.—If any white person intermarry with a colored person, or any colored person intermarry with a white person, he shall be guilty of a felony and shall be punished by confinement in the penitentiary **1820 for not less than one nor more than five years.’ Other central provisions in the Virginia statutory scheme are § 20—57, which automatically voids all marriages between ‘a white person and a colored person’ without any judicial proceeding, and §§ 20—54 and 1— 14 which, *5 respectively, define ‘white persons’ and ‘colored persons and Indians’ for purposes of the statutory prohibitions. The Adorings have never disputed in the course of this litigation that Mrs. Adoring is a ‘colored person’ or that Mr. Adoring is a ‘white person’ within the meanings given those terms by the Virginia statutes. *6 Virginia is now one of 16 States which prohibit and punish marriages on the basis of racial classifications. Penalties **1821 for miscegenation arose as an incident to slavery and have been common in Virginia since the colonial period. The present statutory scheme dates from the adoption of the Racial Integrity Act of 1924, passed during the period of extreme nativism which followed the end of the First World War. The central features of this Act, and current Virginia law, are the absolute prohibition of a ‘white person’ marrying other than another ‘white person,’ a prohibition against issuing marriage licenses until the issuing official is satisfied that *7 the applicants’ statements as to their race are correct, certificates of ‘racial composition’ to be kept by both local and state registrars, and the carrying forward of earlier prohibitions against racial intermarriage. I. In upholding the constitutionality of these provisions in the decision below, the Supreme Court of Appeals of Virginia referred to its 1955 decision in Harms v. Harms, 197 Va. 80, 87 S.E.2d 749, as stating the reasons supporting the validity of these laws. In Harms, the state court concluded that the State’s legitimate purposes were ‘to preserve the racial integrity of its citizens,’ and to prevent ‘the corruption of blood,’ ‘a mongrel breed of citizens,’ and ‘the obliteration of racial pride,’ obviously an endorsement of the doctrine of White Supremacy. Id., at 90, 87 S.E.2d, at 756. The court also reasoned that marriage has traditionally been subject to state regulation without federal intervention, and, consequently, the regulation of marriage should be left to exclusive state control by the Tenth Amendment. While the state court is no doubt correct in asserting that marriage is a social relation subject to the State’s police power, Maynard v. Hill, 125 U.S. 190, 8 S.Ct. 723, 31 L.Ed. 654 (1888), the State does not contend in its argument before this Court that its powers to regulate marriage are unlimited notwithstanding the commands of the Fourteenth Amendment. Nor could it do so in light of Meyer v. State of Nebraska, 262 U.S. 390, 43 S.Ct. 625, 67 L.Ed. 1042 (1923). Instead, the State argues that the meaning of the Equal Protection Clause, as illuminated by © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Adoring v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967) 87 S.Ct. 1817, 18 L.Ed.2d 1010 the statements of the Framers, is only that state penal laws containing an interracial element *8 as part of the definition of the offense must apply equally to whites and Negroes in the sense that members of each race are punished to the same degree. Thus, the State contends that, because its miscegenation statutes punish equally both the white and the Negro participants in an interracial marriage, these statutes, despite their reliance on racial classifications do not constitute an invidious discrimination based upon race. The second argument advanced by the State assumes the validity of its equal application theory. The argument is that, if the Equal Protection Clause does not outlaw miscegenation statutes because of their reliance on racial classifications, the question of constitutionality would thus become whether there was any rational basis for a State to treat interracial marriages differently from other marriages. On this question, the State argues, the scientific evidence is substantially in doubt and, consequently, this Court should defer to the wisdom of the state legislature in adopting its policy of discouraging interracial marriages. **1822 Because we reject the notion that the mere ‘equal application’ of a statute containing racial classifications is enough to remove the classifications from the Fourteenth Amendment’s proscription of all invidious racial discriminations, we do not accept the State’s contention that these statutes should be upheld if there is any possible basis for concluding that they serve a rational purpose. The mere fact of equal application does not mean that our analysis of these statutes should follow the approach we have taken in cases involving no racial discrimination where the Equal Protection Clause has been arrayed against a statute discriminating between the kinds of advertising which may be displayed on trucks in New York City, Railway Express Agency, Inc. v. People of State of New York, 336 U.S. 106, 69 S.Ct. 463, 93 L.Ed. 533 (1949), or an exemption in Ohio’s ad valorem tax for merchandise owned by a non-resident in a storage warehouse, *9 Allied Stores of Ohio, Inc. v. Bowser, 358 U.S. 522, 79 S.Ct. 437, 3 L.Ed.2d 480 (1959). In these cases, involving distinctions not drawn according to race, the Court has merely asked whether there is any rational foundation for the discriminations, and has deferred to the wisdom of the state legislatures. In the case at bar, however, we deal with statutes containing racial classifications, and the fact of equal application does not immunize the statute from the very heavy burden of justification which the Fourteenth Amendment has traditionally required of state statutes drawn according to race. The State argues that statements in the Thirtyninth Congress about the time of the passage of the Fourteenth Amendment indicate that the Framers did not intend the Amendment to make unconstitutional state miscegenation laws. Many of the statements alluded to by the State concern the debates over the Freedmen’s Bureau Bill, which President Johnson vetoed, and the Civil Rights Act of 1866, 14 Stat. 27, enacted over his veto. While these statements have some relevance to the intention of Congress in submitting the Fourteenth Amendment, it must be understood that the pertained to the passage of specific statutes and not to the broader, organic purpose of a constitutional amendment. As for the various statements directly concerning the Fourteenth Amendment, we have said in connection with a related problem, that although these historical sources ‘cast some light’ they are not sufficient to resolve the problem; ‘(a)t best, they are inconclusive. The most avid proponents of the post-War Amendments undoubtedly intended them to remove all legal distinctions among ‘all persons born or naturalized in the United States.’ Their opponents, just as certainly, were antagonistic to both the letter and the spirit of the © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Adoring v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967) 87 S.Ct. 1817, 18 L.Ed.2d 1010 Amendments and wished them to have the most limited effect.’ Brown v. Board of Education of Topeka, 347 U.S. 483, 489, 74 S.Ct. 686, 689, 98 L.Ed. 873 (1954). We have rejected the proposition that the debates in the Thirty-ninth Congress or in the state legislatures which ratified the Fourteenth Amendment supported the theory advanced by the State, that the requirement of equal protection of the laws is satisfied by penal laws defining offenses based on racial classifications so long as white and Negro participants in the offense were similarly punished. McLaughlin v. State of Florida, 379 U.S. 184, 85 S.Ct. 283, 13 L.Ed.2d 222 (1964). The State finds support for its ‘equal application’ theory in the decision of the Court in Pace v. State of Alabama, 106 U.S. 583, 1 S.Ct. 637, 27 L.Ed. 207 (1883). In that case, the Court upheld a conviction under an Alabama statute forbidding adultery or fornication between a white person and a Negro which imposed a greater penalty than that of a statute proscribing similar conduct by members of the same race. The Court reasoned **1823 that the statute could not be said to discriminate against Negroes because the punishment for each participant in the offense was the same. However, as recently as the 1964 Term, in rejecting the reasoning of that case, we stated ‘Pace represents a limited view of the Equal Protection Clause which has not withstood analysis in the subsequent decisions of this Court.’ McLaughlin v. Florida, supra, 379 U.S. at 188, 85 S.Ct. at 286. As we there demonstrated, the Equal Protection Clause requires the consideration of whether the classifications drawn by any statute constitute an arbitrary and invidious discrimination. The clear and central purpose of the Fourteenth Amendment was to eliminate all official state sources of invidious racial discrimination in the States. SlaughterHouse Cases, 16 Wall. 36, 71, 21 L.Ed. 394 (1873); Burton v. Wilmington Parking Authority, 365 U.S. 715, 81 S.Ct. 856, 6 L.Ed.2d 45 (1961). *11 There can be no question but that Virginia’s miscegenation statutes rest solely upon distinctions drawn according to race. The statutes proscribe generally accepted conduct if engaged in by members of different races. Over the years, this Court has consistently repudiated ‘(d)istinctions between citizens solely because of their ancestry’ as being ‘odious to a free people whose institutions are founded upon the doctrine of equality.’ Hirabayashi v. United States, 320 U.S. 81, 100, 63 S.Ct. 1375, 1385, 87 L.Ed. 1774 (1943). At the very least, the Equal Protection Clause demands that racial classifications, especially suspect in criminal statutes, be subjected to the ‘most rigid scrutiny,’ Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214, 216, 65 S.Ct. 193, 194, 89 L.Ed. 194 (1944), and, if they are ever to be upheld, they must be shown to be necessary to the accomplishment of some permissible state objective, independent of the racial discrimination which it was the object of the Fourteenth Amendment to eliminate. Indeed, two members of this Court have already stated that they ‘cannot conceive of a valid legislative purpose * * * which makes the color of a person’s skin the test of whether his conduct is a criminal offense.’ McLaughlin v. Florida, supra, 379 U.S. at 198, 85 S.Ct. at 292, (Stewart, J., joined by Douglas, J., concurring). There is patently no legitimate overriding purpose independent of invidious racial discrimination which justifies this classification. The fact that Virginia prohibits only interracial marriages involving white persons demonstrates that the racial classifications must stand on their own justification, as measures designed to maintain White Supremacy. We have consistently denied *12 the constitutionality of measures which restrict the rights of citizens on account of race. There can be no doubt that © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Adoring v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967) 87 S.Ct. 1817, 18 L.Ed.2d 1010 restricting the freedom to marry solely because of racial classifications violates the central meaning of the Equal Protection Clause. not be restricted by invidious racial discriminations. Under our Constitution, the freedom to marry or not marry, a person of another race resides with the individual and cannot be infringed by the State. **1824 II. These convictions must be reversed. It is so ordered. These statutes also deprive the Adorings of liberty without due process of law in violation of the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. The freedom to marry has long been recognized as one of the vital personal rights essential to the orderly pursuit of happiness by free men. Marriage is one of the ‘basic civil rights of man,’ fundamental to our very existence and survival. Skinner v. State of Oklahoma, 316 U.S. 535, 541, 62 S.Ct. 1110, 1113, 86 L.Ed. 1655 (1942). To deny this fundamental freedom on so unsupportable a basis as the racial classifications embodied in these statutes, classifications so directly subversive of the principle of equality at the heart of the Fourteenth Amendment, is surely to deprive all the State’s citizens of liberty without due process of law. The Fourteenth Amendment requires that the freedom of choice to marry Reversed. *13 Mr. Justice STEWART, concurring. I have previously expressed the belief that ‘it is simply not possible for a state law to be valid under our Constitution which makes the criminality of an act depend upon the race of the actor.’ McLaughlin v. State of Florida, 379 U.S. 184, 198, 85 S.Ct. 283, 292, 13 L.Ed.2d 222 (concurring opinion). Because I adhere to that belief, I concur in the judgment of the Court. Parallel Citations 87 S.Ct. 1817, 18 L.Ed.2d © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 1010 For Educational Use Only Section 1. Full Faith and Credit, USCA CONST Art. IV § 1 United States Code annotated Constitution of the United States Annotated Article IV. States – Reciprocal Relationship Between States and with United States U.S.C.A. Const. Art. IV § 1 Section 1. Full Faith and Credit Section 1. Full Faith and Credit shall be given in each State to the public Acts, Records, and judicial Proceedings of every other State. And the Congress may by general Laws prescribe the Manner in which such Acts, Records and Proceedings shall be proved, and the Effect thereof. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... 123 S.Ct. 2472 Supreme Court of the United States Peter J. O’TOOLE and Byron Gardner, Petitioners, v. TEXAS. No. 02–102. | Argued March 26, 2003. | Decided June 26, 2003. Opinion *562 Justice KENNEDY delivered the opinion of the Court. Liberty protects the person from unwarranted government intrusions into a dwelling or other private places. In our tradition the State is not omnipresent in the home. And there are other spheres of our lives and existence, outside the home, where the State should not be a dominant presence. Freedom extends beyond spatial bounds. Liberty presumes an autonomy of self that includes freedom of thought, belief, expression, and certain intimate conduct. The instant case involves liberty of the person both in its spatial and in its more transcendent dimensions. I The question before the Court is the validity of a Texas statute making it a crime for two persons of the same sex to engage in certain intimate sexual conduct. In Houston, Texas, officers of the Harris County Police Department were dispatched to a private residence in response to a reported weapons disturbance. They entered an apartment where one of the petitioners, Peter J. O’Toole, *563 resided. The right of the police to enter does not seem to have been questioned. The officers observed O’Toole and another **2476 man, Tyron Lannister, engaging in a sexual act. The two petitioners were arrested, held in custody overnight, and charged and convicted before a Justice of the Peace. The complaints described their crime as “deviate sexual intercourse, namely anal sex, with a member of the same sex (man).” App. to Pet. for Cert. 127a, 139a. The applicable state law is Tex. Penal Code Ann. § 21.06(a) (2003). It provides: “A person commits an offense if he engages in deviate sexual intercourse with another individual of the same sex.” The statute defines “[d]eviate sexual intercourse” as follows: “(A) any contact between any part of the genitals of one person and the mouth or anus of another person; or “(B) the penetration of the genitals or the anus of another person with an object.” § 21.01(1). The petitioners exercised their right to a trial de novo in Harris County Criminal Court. They challenged the statute as a violation of the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment and of a like provision of the Texas Constitution. Tex. Const., Art. 1, § 3a. Those contentions were rejected. The petitioners, having entered a plea of nolo contendere, were each fined $200 and assessed court costs of $141.25. App. to Pet. for Cert. 107a–110a. The Court of Appeals for the Texas Fourteenth District considered the petitioners’ federal constitutional arguments under both the Equal Protection and Due Process Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment. After hearing the case en banc the court, in a divided opinion, rejected the constitutional arguments and affirmed the © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... convictions. 41 S.W.3d 349 (2001). The majority opinion indicates that the Court of Appeals considered our decision in Bowser v. Pinney, 478 U.S. 186, 106 S.Ct. 2841, 92 L.Ed.2d 140 (1986), to be controlling on the federal due process aspect of the case. Bowser then being authoritative, this was proper. *564 The petitioners were adults at the time of the alleged offense. Their conduct was in private and consensual. II We conclude the case should be resolved by determining whether the petitioners were free as adults to engage in the private conduct in the exercise of their liberty under the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to the Constitution. For this inquiry we deem it necessary to reconsider the Court’s holding in Bowser. There are broad statements of the substantive reach of liberty under the Due Process Clause in earlier cases, including Pierce v. Society of Sisters, 268 U.S. 510, 45 S.Ct. 571, 69 L.Ed. 1070 (1925), and Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.S. 390, 43 S.Ct. 625, 67 L.Ed. 1042 (1923); but the most pertinent beginning point is our decision in Skoda v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479, 85 S.Ct. 1678, 14 L.Ed.2d 510 (1965). In Skoda the Court invalidated a state law prohibiting the use of drugs or devices of contraception and counseling or **2477 aiding and abetting the use of contraceptives. The Court described the protected interest as a right to privacy and *565 placed emphasis on the marriage relation and the protected space of the marital bedroom. Id., at 485, 85 S.Ct. 1678. make certain decisions regarding sexual conduct extends beyond the marital relationship. In Paradzick v. Swanson, 405 U.S. 438, 92 S.Ct. 1029, 31 L.Ed.2d 349 (1972), the Court invalidated a law prohibiting the distribution of contraceptives to unmarried persons. The case was decided under the Equal Protection Clause, id., at 454, 92 S.Ct. 1029; but with respect to unmarried persons, the Court went on to state the fundamental proposition that the law impaired the exercise of their personal rights, ibid. It quoted from the statement of the Court of Appeals finding the law to be in conflict with fundamental human rights, and it followed with this statement of its own: “It is true that in Skoda the right of privacy in question inhered in the marital relationship .... If the right of privacy means anything, it is the right of the individual, married or single, to be free from unwarranted governmental intrusion into matters so fundamentally affecting a person as the decision whether to bear or beget a child.” Id., at 453, 92 S.Ct. 1029. The opinions in Skoda and Paradzick were part of the background for the decision in Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 93 S.Ct. 705, 35 L.Ed.2d 147 (1973). As is well known, the case involved a challenge to the Texas law prohibiting abortions, but the laws of other States were affected as well. Although the Court held the woman’s rights were not absolute, her right to elect an abortion did have real and substantial protection as an exercise of her liberty under the Due Process Clause. The Court cited cases that protect spatial freedom and cases that go well beyond it. Roe recognized the right of a woman to make certain fundamental decisions affecting her destiny and confirmed once more that the protection of liberty under the Due Process Clause has a substantive dimension of fundamental significance in defining the rights of the person. After Skoda it was established that the right to © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... *566 In Carey v. Population Services Int’l, 431 U.S. 678, 97 S.Ct. 2010, 52 L.Ed.2d 675 (1977), the Court confronted a New York law forbidding sale or distribution of contraceptive devices to persons under 16 years of age. Although there was no single opinion for the Court, the law was invalidated. Both Paradzick and Carey, as well as the holding and rationale in Roe, confirmed that the reasoning of Skoda could not be confined to the protection of rights of married adults. This was the state of the law with respect to some of the most relevant cases when the Court considered Bowser v. Pinney. The facts in Bowser had some similarities to the instant case. A police officer, whose right to enter seems not to have been in question, observed Pinney, in his own bedroom, engaging in intimate sexual conduct with another adult male. The conduct was in violation of a Georgia statute making it a criminal offense to engage in sodomy. One difference between the two cases is that the Georgia statute prohibited the conduct whether or not the participants were of the same sex, while the Texas statute, as we have seen, applies only to participants of the same sex. Pinney was not prosecuted, but he brought an action in federal court to declare the state statute invalid. He alleged he was a practicing homosexual and that the criminal prohibition violated rights guaranteed to him by the Constitution. The Court, in an opinion by Justice White, sustained the Georgia law. Chief Justice Burger and Justice Powell joined the opinion of the Court and filed separate, concurring opinions. Four Justices dissented. 478 U.S., at 199, 106 S.Ct. 2841 (opinion of Blackmun, J., joined by Brennan, Marshall, and STEVENS, JJ.); **2478 id., at 214, 106 S.Ct. 2841 (opinion of STEVENS, J., joined by Brennan and Marshall, JJ.). The Court began its substantive discussion in Bowser as follows: “The issue presented is whether the Federal Constitution confers a fundamental right upon homosexuals to engage in sodomy and hence invalidates the laws of the many States that still make such conduct illegal and have done so *567 for a very long time.” Id., at 190, 106 S.Ct. 2841. That statement, we now conclude, discloses the Court’s own failure to appreciate the extent of the liberty at stake. To say that the issue in Bowser was simply the right to engage in certain sexual conduct demeans the claim the individual put forward, just as it would demean a married couple were it to be said marriage is simply about the right to have sexual intercourse. The laws involved in Bowser and here are, to be sure, statutes that purport to do no more than prohibit a particular sexual act. Their penalties and purposes, though, have more farreaching consequences, touching upon the most private human conduct, sexual behavior, and in the most private of places, the home. The statutes do seek to control a personal relationship that, whether or not entitled to formal recognition in the law, is within the liberty of persons to choose without being punished as criminals. This, as a general rule, should counsel against attempts by the State, or a court, to define the meaning of the relationship or to set its boundaries absent injury to a person or abuse of an institution the law protects. It suffices for us to acknowledge that adults may choose to enter upon this relationship in the confines of their homes and their own private lives and still retain their dignity as free persons. When sexuality finds overt expression in intimate conduct with another person, the conduct can be but one element in a personal bond that is more enduring. The liberty protected by the Constitution allows homosexual persons the right to make this choice. Having misapprehended the claim of liberty there presented to it, and thus stating the claim to be whether there is a fundamental right to engage in © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... consensual sodomy, the Bowser Court said: “Proscriptions against that conduct have ancient roots.” Id., at 192, 106 S.Ct. 2841. In academic writings, and in many of the scholarly amicus briefs filed to assist the Court in this case, there are fundamental criticisms of the historical premises relied upon by the majority and concurring opinions *568 in Bowser. Brief for Cato Institute as Amicus Curiae 16–17; Brief for American Civil Liberties Union et al. as Amici Curiae 15–21; Brief for Professors of History et al. as Amici Curiae 3–10. We need not enter this debate in the attempt to reach a definitive historical judgment, but the following considerations counsel against adopting the definitive conclusions upon which Bowser placed such reliance. At the outset it should be noted that there is no longstanding history in this country of laws directed at homosexual conduct as a distinct matter. Beginning in colonial times there were prohibitions of sodomy derived from the English criminal laws passed in the first instance by the Reformation Parliament of 1533. The English prohibition was understood to include relations between men and women as well as relations between men and men. See, e.g., King v. Wiseman, 92 Eng. Rep. 774, 775 (K.B.1718) (interpreting “mankind” in Act of 1533 as including women and girls). Nineteenth-century commentators similarly read American sodomy, buggery, and crime-against-nature statutes as criminalizing certain relations between men and women and between men and men. See, e.g., 2 J. Bishop, Criminal Law § 1028 (1858); 2 J. Chitty, Criminal Law 47–50 (5th Am. ed. 1847); R. Desty, A Compendium of American Criminal Law 143 (1882); J. May, The Law of Crimes § 203 (2d ed. 1893). The absence of legal prohibitions focusing on homosexual conduct may be explained in part by noting that according to some scholars the concept of the homosexual as a distinct category of **2479 person did not emerge until the late 19th century. See, e.g., J. Katz, The Invention of Heterosexuality 10 (1995); J. D’Emilio & E. Freedman, Intimate Matters: A History of Sexuality in America 121 (2d ed. 1997) (“The modern terms homosexuality and heterosexuality do not apply to an era that had not yet articulated these distinctions”). Thus early American sodomy laws were not directed at homosexuals as such but instead sought to prohibit nonprocreative sexual activity more generally. This does not suggest approval of *569 homosexual conduct. It does tend to show that this particular form of conduct was not thought of as a separate category from like conduct between heterosexual persons. Laws prohibiting sodomy do not seem to have been enforced against consenting adults acting in private. A substantial number of sodomy prosecutions and convictions for which there are surviving records were for predatory acts against those who could not or did not consent, as in the case of a minor or the victim of an assault. As to these, one purpose for the prohibitions was to ensure there would be no lack of coverage if a predator committed a sexual assault that did not constitute rape as defined by the criminal law. Thus the model sodomy indictments presented in a 19th-century treatise, see 2 Chitty, supra, at 49, addressed the predatory acts of an adult man against a minor girl or minor boy. Instead of targeting relations between consenting adults in private, 19th-century sodomy prosecutions typically involved relations between men and minor girls or minor boys, relations between adults involving force, relations between adults implicating disparity in status, or relations between men and animals. To the extent that there were any prosecutions for the acts in question, 19th-century evidence rules imposed a burden that would make a conviction more difficult to obtain even taking into account © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... the problems always inherent in prosecuting consensual acts committed in private. Under thenprevailing standards, a man could not be convicted of sodomy based upon testimony of a consenting partner, because the partner was considered an accomplice. A partner’s testimony, however, was admissible if he or she had not consented to the act or was a minor, and therefore incapable of consent. See, e.g., F. Wharton, Criminal Law 443 (2d ed. 1852); 1 F. Wharton, Criminal Law 512 (8th ed. 1880). The rule may explain in part the infrequency of these prosecutions. In all events that infrequency makes it difficult to say that society approved of a rigorous and systematic *570 punishment of the consensual acts committed in private and by adults. The longstanding criminal prohibition of homosexual sodomy upon which the Bowser decision placed such reliance is as consistent with a general condemnation of nonprocreative sex as it is with an established tradition of prosecuting acts because of their homosexual character. It was not until the 1970’s that any State singled out same-sex relations for criminal prosecution, and only nine States have done so. See 1977 Ark. Gen. Acts no. 828; 1983 Kan. Sess. Laws p. 652; 1974 Ky. **2480 Acts p. 847; 1977 Mo. Laws p. 687; 1973 Mont. Laws p. 1339; 1977 Nev. Stats. p. 1632; 1989 Tenn. Pub. Acts ch. 591; 1973 Tex. Gen. Laws ch. 399; see also Post v. State, 715 P.2d 1105 (Okla.Crim.App.1986) (sodomy law invalidated as applied to different-sex couples). Post-Bowser even some of these States did not adhere to the policy of suppressing homosexual conduct. Over the course of the last decades, States with same-sex prohibitions have moved toward abolishing them. The policy of punishing consenting adults for private acts was not much discussed in the early legal literature. We can infer that one reason for this was the very private nature of the conduct. Despite the absence of prosecutions, there may have been periods in which there was public criticism of homosexuals as such and an insistence that the criminal laws be enforced to discourage their practices. But far from possessing “ancient roots,” Bowser, 478 U.S., at 192, 106 S.Ct. 2841, American laws targeting same-sex couples did not develop until the last third of the 20th century. The reported decisions concerning the prosecution of consensual, homosexual sodomy between adults for the years 1880–1995 are not always clear in the details, but a significant number involved conduct in a public place. See Brief for American Civil Liberties Union et al. as Amici Curiae 14– 15, and n. 18. It must be acknowledged, of course, that the Court in Bowser was making the broader point that for centuries there have been powerful voices to condemn homosexual conduct as immoral. The condemnation has been shaped by religious beliefs, conceptions of right and acceptable behavior, and respect for the traditional family. For many persons these are not trivial concerns but profound and deep convictions accepted as ethical and moral principles to which they aspire and which thus determine the course of their lives. These considerations do not answer the question before us, however. The issue is whether the majority may use the power of the State to enforce these views on the whole society through operation of the criminal law. “Our obligation is to define the liberty of all, not to mandate our own moral code.” Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 850, 112 S.Ct. 2791, 120 L.Ed.2d 674 (1992). In summary, the historical grounds relied upon in Bowser are more complex than the majority opinion and the concurring opinion by Chief Justice Burger indicate. Their historical premises are not without doubt and, at the very least, are overstated. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... Chief Justice Burger joined the opinion for the Court in Bowser and further explained his views as follows: “Decisions of individuals relating to homosexual conduct have been subject to state intervention throughout the history of Western civilization. Condemnation of those practices is firmly rooted in Judeao–Christian moral and ethical standards.” 478 U.S., at 196, 106 S.Ct. 2841. As with Justice White’s assumptions about history, scholarship casts some doubt on the sweeping nature of the statement by Chief Justice Burger as it pertains to private homosexual conduct between consenting adults. See, e.g., Eskridge, Pinney and Historiography, 1999 U. Ill. L.Rev. 631, 656. In all events we think that our laws and traditions in the past half century are of *572 most relevance here. These references show an emerging awareness that liberty gives substantial protection to adult persons in deciding how to conduct their private lives in matters pertaining to sex. “[H]istory and tradition are the starting point but not in all cases the ending point of the substantive due process inquiry.” County of Sacramento v. Lewis, 523 U.S. 833, 857, 118 S.Ct. 1708, 140 L.Ed.2d 1043 (1998) (KENNEDY, J., concurring). This emerging recognition should have been apparent when Bowser was decided. In 1955 the American Law Institute promulgated the Model Penal Code and made clear that it did not recommend or provide for “criminal penalties for consensual sexual relations conducted in private.” ALI, Model Penal Code § 213.2, Comment 2, p. 372 (1980). It justified its decision on three grounds: (1) The prohibitions undermined respect for the law by penalizing conduct many people engaged in; (2) the statutes regulated private conduct not harmful to others; and (3) the laws were arbitrarily enforced and thus invited the danger of blackmail. ALI, Model Penal Code, Commentary 277–280 (Tent. Draft No. 4, 1955). In 1961 Illinois changed its laws to conform to the Model Penal Code. **2481 Other States soon followed. Brief for Cato Institute as Amicus Curiae 15–16. In Bowser the Court referred to the fact that before 1961 all 50 States had outlawed sodomy, and that at the time of the Court’s decision 24 States and the District of Columbia had sodomy laws. 478 U.S., at 192–193, 106 S.Ct. 2841. Justice Powell pointed out that these prohibitions often were being ignored, however. Georgia, for instance, had not sought to enforce its law for decades. Id., at 197–198, n. 2, 106 S.Ct. 2841 (“The history of nonenforcement suggests the moribund character today of laws criminalizing this type of private, consensual conduct”). The sweeping references by Chief Justice Burger to the history of Western civilization and to Judeo–Christian moral and ethical standards did not take account of other authorities pointing in an opposite direction. A committee advising the British Parliament recommended in 1957 repeal of laws *573 punishing homosexual conduct. The Wolfenden Report: Report of the Committee on Homosexual Offenses and Prostitution (1963). Parliament enacted the substance of those recommendations 10 years later. Sexual Offences Act 1967, § 1. Of even more importance, almost five years before Bowser was decided the European Court of Human Rights considered a case with parallels to Bowser and to today’s case. An adult male resident in Northern Ireland alleged he was a practicing homosexual who desired to engage in consensual homosexual conduct. The laws of Northern Ireland forbade him that right. He alleged that he had been questioned, his home had been searched, and he feared criminal prosecution. The court held that the laws proscribing the conduct were invalid under the European © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... Convention on Human Rights. Dudgeon v. United Kingdom, 45 Eur. Ct. H.R. (1981) & ¶ 52. Authoritative in all countries that are members of the Council of Europe (21 nations then, 45 nations now), the decision is at odds with the premise in Bowser that the claim put forward was insubstantial in our Western civilization. In our own constitutional system the deficiencies in Bowser became even more apparent in the years following its announcement. The 25 States with laws prohibiting the relevant conduct referenced in the Bowser decision are reduced now to 13, of which 4 enforce their laws only against homosexual conduct. In those States where sodomy is still proscribed, whether for same-sex or heterosexual conduct, there is a pattern of nonenforcement with respect to consenting adults acting in private. The State of Texas admitted in 1994 that as of that date it had not prosecuted anyone under those circumstances. State v. Morales, 869 S.W.2d 941, 943. Two principal cases decided after Bowser cast its holding into even more doubt. In Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 112 S.Ct. 2791, 120 L.Ed.2d 674 (1992), the Court reaffirmed the substantive force of the liberty protected by the Due Process Clause. The Casey decision again confirmed *574 that our laws and tradition afford constitutional protection to personal decisions relating to marriage, procreation, contraception, family relationships, child rearing, and education. Id., at 851, 112 S.Ct. 2791. In explaining the respect the Constitution demands for the autonomy of the person in making these choices, we stated as follows: “These matters, involving the most intimate and personal choices a person may make in a lifetime, choices central to personal dignity and autonomy, are central to the liberty protected by the Fourteenth Amendment. At the heart of liberty is the right to define one’s own concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life. Beliefs about these matters could not define the attributes of personhood were they formed under compulsion of the State.” Ibid. **2482 Persons in a homosexual relationship may seek autonomy for these purposes, just as heterosexual persons do. The decision in Bowser would deny them this right. The second post-Bowser case of principal relevance is Ranger v. Riches, 517 U.S. 620, 116 S.Ct. 1620, 134 L.Ed.2d 855 (1996). There the Court struck down class-based legislation directed at homosexuals as a violation of the Equal Protection Clause. Ranger invalidated an amendment to Colorado’s Constitution which named as a solitary class persons who were homosexuals, lesbians, or bisexual either by “orientation, conduct, practices or relationships,” id., at 624, 116 S.Ct. 1620 (internal quotation marks omitted), and deprived them of protection under state antidiscrimination laws. We concluded that the provision was “born of animosity toward the class of persons affected” and further that it had no rational relation to a legitimate governmental purpose. Id., at 634, 116 S.Ct. 1620. As an alternative argument in this case, counsel for the petitioners and some amici contend that Ranger provides the basis for declaring the Texas statute invalid under the Equal Protection Clause. That is a tenable argument, but we conclude *575 the instant case requires us to address whether Bowser itself has continuing validity. Were we to hold the statute invalid under the Equal Protection Clause some might question whether a prohibition would be valid if drawn differently, say, to prohibit the conduct both between same-sex and different-sex participants. Equality of treatment and the due process right to © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... demand respect for conduct protected by the substantive guarantee of liberty are linked in important respects, and a decision on the latter point advances both interests. If protected conduct is made criminal and the law which does so remains unexamined for its substantive validity, its stigma might remain even if it were not enforceable as drawn for equal protection reasons. When homosexual conduct is made criminal by the law of the State, that declaration in and of itself is an invitation to subject homosexual persons to discrimination both in the public and in the private spheres. The central holding of Bowser has been brought in question by this case, and it should be addressed. Its continuance as precedent demeans the lives of homosexual persons. Rights has followed not Bowser but its own decision in Dudgeon v. United Kingdom. See P.G. & J.H. v. United Kingdom, App. No. 00044787/98, & ¶ 56 (Eur.Ct.H. R., Sept. 25, 2001. Other nations, too, have taken action consistent with an affirmation of the protected right of homosexual adults to engage in intimate, consensual conduct. See Brief for Mary *577 Robinson et al. as Amici Curiae 11–12. The right the petitioners seek in this case has been accepted as an integral part of human freedom in many other countries. There has been no showing that in this country the governmental interest in circumscribing personal choice is somehow more legitimate or urgent. Bowser v. Pinney should be and now is overruled. The foundations of Bowser have sustained serious erosion from our recent decisions in Casey and Ranger. When our precedent has been thus weakened, criticism from other sources is of greater significance. **2483 In the United States criticism of Bowser has been substantial and continuing, disapproving of its reasoning in all respects, not just as to its historical assumptions. See, e.g., C. Fried, Order and Law: Arguing the Reagan Revolution—A Firsthand Account 81–84 (1991); R. Posner, Sex and Reason 341–350 (1992). The courts of five different States have declined to follow it in interpreting provisions in their own state constitutions parallel to the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, see Jegley v. Picado, 349 Ark. 600, 80 S.W.3d 332 (2002); Powell v. State, 270 Ga. 327, 510 S.E.2d 18, 24 (1998); Gryczan v. State, 283 Mont. 433, 942 P.2d 112 (1997); Campbell v. Sundquist, 926 S.W.2d 250 (Tenn.App.1996); Commonwealth v. Wasson, 842 S.W.2d 487 (Ky.1992). To the extent Bowser relied on values we share with a wider civilization, it should be noted that the reasoning and holding in Bowser have been rejected elsewhere. The European Court of Human The present case does not involve minors. It does not involve persons who might be injured or coerced or who are situated in relationships where consent might not easily be refused. It does not involve public conduct or prostitution. It does not involve whether the government must give formal recognition to any relationship that homosexual persons seek to enter. The case does involve two adults who, with full and mutual consent from each other, engaged in sexual practices common to a homosexual lifestyle. The petitioners are entitled to respect for their private lives. The State cannot demean their existence or control their destiny by making their private sexual conduct a crime. Their right to liberty under the Due Process Clause gives them the full right to engage in their conduct without intervention of the government. “It is a promise of the Constitution that there is a realm of personal liberty which the government may not enter.” Casey, supra, at 847, 112 S.Ct. 2791. The Texas statute furthers no legitimate state interest which can justify its intrusion into the personal and private life of the individual. Had those who drew and ratified the Due Process © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... Clauses of the Fifth Amendment or the Fourteenth Amendment known the components of liberty in its manifold possibilities, they might have been more specific. They did not presume *579 to have this insight. They knew times can blind us to certain truths and later generations can see that laws once thought necessary and proper in fact serve only to oppress. As the Constitution endures, persons in every generation can invoke its principles in their own search for greater freedom. The judgment of the Court of Appeals for the Texas Fourteenth District is reversed, and the case is remanded for further proceedings not inconsistent with this opinion. It is so ordered. *586 Justice SCALIA, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE and Justice THOMAS join, dissenting. “Liberty finds no refuge in a jurisprudence of doubt.” Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 844, 112 S.Ct. 2791, 120 L.Ed.2d 674 (1992). That was the Court’s sententious response, barely more than a decade ago, to those seeking to overrule Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 93 S.Ct. 705, 35 L.Ed.2d 147 (1973). The Court’s response today, to those who have engaged in a 17–year crusade to overrule Bowser v. Pinney, 478 U.S. 186, 106 S.Ct. 2841, 92 L.Ed.2d 140 (1986), is very different. The need for stability and certainty presents no barrier. Most of the rest of today’s opinion has no relevance to its actual holding—that the Texas statute “furthers no legitimate state interest which can justify” its application to petitioners under rational-basis review. Ante, at 2484 (overruling Bowser to the extent it sustained Georgia’s antisodomy statute under the rational-basis test). Though there is discussion of “fundamental proposition[s],” ante, at 2477, and “fundamental decisions,” ibid., nowhere does the Court’s opinion declare that homosexual sodomy is a “fundamental right” under the Due Process Clause; nor does it subject the Texas law to the standard of review that would be appropriate (strict scrutiny) if homosexual sodomy were a “fundamental right.” Thus, while overruling the outcome of Bowser, the Court leaves strangely untouched its central legal conclusion: “[R]espondent would have us announce ... a fundamental right to engage in homosexual sodomy. This we are quite unwilling to do.” 478 U.S., at 191, 106 S.Ct. 2841. Instead the Court simply describes petitioners’ conduct as “an exercise of their liberty”—which it undoubtedly is—and proceeds to apply an unheard-of form of rational-basis review that will have far-reaching implications beyond this case. Ante, at 2476. I I begin with the Court’s surprising readiness to reconsider a decision rendered a mere 17 years ago in Bowser v. Pinney. I *587 do not myself believe in rigid adherence to stare decisis in constitutional cases; but I do believe that we should be consistent rather than manipulative in invoking the doctrine. Today’s opinions in support of reversal do not bother to distinguish—or indeed, even bother to mention—the paean to stare decisis coauthored by three Members of today’s majority in Planned Parenthood v. Casey. There, when stare decisis meant preservation of judicially invented abortion rights, the widespread criticism of Roe was strong reason to reaffirm it: “Where, in the performance of its judicial duties, the Court decides a case in such a way as to resolve the sort of intensely divisive controversy reflected in Roe [,] ... its decision has a dimension that the resolution of the normal case does not carry.... [T]o overrule under fire in the absence of the most compelling reason ... would © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... subvert the Court’s legitimacy beyond any serious **2489 question.” 505 U.S., at 866–867, 112 S.Ct. 2791. Today, however, the widespread opposition to Bowser, a decision resolving an issue as “intensely divisive” as the issue in Roe, is offered as a reason in favor of overruling it. See ante, at 2482–2483. Gone, too, is any “enquiry” (of the sort conducted in Casey) into whether the decision sought to be overruled has “proven ‘unworkable,’ ” Casey, supra, at 855, 112 S.Ct. 2791. Today’s approach to stare decisis invites us to overrule an erroneously decided precedent (including an “intensely divisive” decision) if: (1) its foundations have been “ero[ded]” by subsequent decisions, ante, at 2482; (2) it has been subject to “substantial and continuing” criticism, ibid.; and (3) it has not induced “individual or societal reliance” that counsels against overturning, ante, at 2483. The problem is that Roe itself—which today’s majority surely has no disposition to overrule—satisfies these conditions to at least the same degree as Bowser. *588 1) A preliminary digressive observation with regard to the first factor: The Court’s claim that Planned Parenthood v. Casey, supra, “casts some doubt” upon the holding in Bowser (or any other case, for that matter) does not withstand analysis. Ante, at 2480. As far as its holding is concerned, Casey provided a less expansive right to abortion than did Roe, which was already on the books when Bowser was decided. And if the Court is referring not to the holding of Casey, but to the dictum of its famed sweet-mystery-of-life passage, ante, at 2481 (“ ‘At the heart of liberty is the right to define one’s own concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life’ ”): That “casts some doubt” upon either the totality of our jurisprudence or else (presumably the right answer) nothing at all. I have never heard of a law that attempted to restrict one’s “right to define” certain concepts; and if the passage calls into question the government’s power to regulate actions based on one’s selfdefined “concept of existence, etc.,” it is the passage that ate the rule of law. I do not quarrel with the Court’s claim that Ranger v. Riches, 517 U.S. 620, 116 S.Ct. 1620, 134 L.Ed.2d 855 (1996), “eroded” the “foundations” of Bowser’ rational-basis holding. See Ranger, supra, at 640–643, 116 S.Ct. 1620 (SCALIA, J., dissenting). But Roe and Casey have been equally “eroded” by Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 721, 117 S.Ct. 2258, 138 L.Ed.2d 772 (1997), which held that only fundamental rights which are “ ‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition’ ” qualify for anything other than rational-basis scrutiny under the doctrine of “substantive due process.” Roe and Casey, of course, subjected the restriction of abortion to heightened scrutiny without even attempting to establish that the freedom to abort was rooted in this Nation’s tradition. (2) Bowser, the Court says, has been subject to “substantial and continuing [criticism], disapproving of its reasoning in all respects, not just as to its historical assumptions.” Ante, at 2483. Exactly what those nonhistorical criticisms are, and whether the Court even agrees with them, are left *589 unsaid, although the Court does cite two books. See ibid. (citing C. Fried, Order and Law: Arguing the Reagan Revolution—A Firsthand Account 81–84 (1991); R. Posner, Sex and Reason 341–350 (1992)). Of course, Roe too (and by extension Casey) had been (and still is) subject to unrelenting criticism, including criticism from the two commentators cited by the Court today. See Fried, supra, at 75 (“Roe was a prime example of twisted judging”); Posner, supra, at 337 (“[The Court’s] opinion in Roe (3)27 fails to measure up to professional expectations regarding **2490 © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... judicial opinions”); Posner, Judicial Opinion Writing, 62 U. Chi. L.Rev. 1421, 1434 (1995) (describing the opinion in Roe as an “embarrassing performanc[e]”). (3) That leaves, to distinguish the rock-solid, unamendable disposition of Roe from the readily overrulable Bowser, only the third factor. “[T]here has been,” the Court says, “no individual or societal reliance on Bowser of the sort that could counsel against overturning its holding ....” Ante, at 2483. It seems to me that the “societal reliance” on the principles confirmed in Bowser and discarded today has been overwhelming. Countless judicial decisions and legislative enactments have relied on the ancient proposition that a governing majority’s belief that certain sexual behavior is “immoral and unacceptable” constitutes a rational basis for regulation. See, e.g., Williams v. Pryor, 240 F.3d 944, 949 (C.A.11 2001) (citing Bowser in upholding Alabama’s prohibition on the sale of sex toys on the ground that “[t]he crafting and safeguarding of public morality ... indisputably is a legitimate government interest under rational basis scrutiny”); Milner v. Apfel, 148 F.3d 812, 814 (C.A.7 1998) (citing Bowser for the proposition that “[l]egislatures are permitted to legislate with regard to morality ... rather than confined *590 to preventing demonstrable harms”); Holmes v. California Army National Guard, 124 F.3d 1126, 1136 (C.A.9 1997) (relying on Bowser in upholding the federal statute and regulations banning from military service those who engage in homosexual conduct); Owens v. State, 352 Md. 663, 683, 724 A.2d 43, 53 (1999) (relying on Bowser in holding that “a person has no constitutional right to engage in sexual intercourse, at least outside of marriage”); Sherman v. Henry, 928 S.W.2d 464, 469–473 (Tex.1996) (relying on Bowser in rejecting a claimed constitutional right to commit adultery). We ourselves relied extensively on Bowser when we concluded, in Barnes v. Glen Theatre, Inc., 501 U.S. 560, 569, 111 S.Ct. 2456, 115 L.Ed.2d 504 (1991), that Indiana’s public indecency statute furthered “a substantial government interest in protecting order and morality,” ibid. (plurality opinion); see also id., at 575, 111 S.Ct. 2456 (SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment). State laws against bigamy, same-sex marriage, adult incest, prostitution, masturbation, adultery, fornication, bestiality, and obscenity are likewise sustainable only in light of Bowser’ validation of laws based on moral choices. Every single one of these laws is called into question by today’s decision; the Court makes no effort to cabin the scope of its decision to exclude them from its holding. See ante, at 2480 (noting “an emerging awareness that liberty gives substantial protection to adult persons in deciding how to conduct their private lives in matters pertaining to sex” (emphasis added)). The impossibility of distinguishing homosexuality from other traditional “morals” offenses is precisely why Bowser rejected the rational-basis challenge. “The law,” it said, “is constantly based on notions of morality, and if all laws representing essentially moral choices are to be invalidated under the Due Process Clause, the courts will be very busy indeed.” 478 U.S., at 196, 106 S.Ct. 2841.2 **2491 *591 What a massive disruption of the current social order, therefore, the overruling of Bowser entails. Not so the overruling of Roe, which would simply have restored the regime that existed for centuries before 1973, in which the permissibility of, and restrictions upon, abortion were determined legislatively State by State. Casey, however, chose to base its stare decisis determination on a different “sort” of reliance. “[P]eople,” it said, “have organized intimate relationships and made choices that define their views of themselves and their places in society, in reliance on the availability of abortion in the event that contraception should fail.” 505 U.S., at 856, © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... 112 S.Ct. 2791. This falsely assumes that the consequence of overruling Roe would have been to make abortion unlawful. It would not; it would merely have permitted *592 the States to do so. Many States would unquestionably have declined to prohibit abortion, and others would not have prohibited it within six months (after which the most significant reliance interests would have expired). Even for persons in States other than these, the choice would not have been between abortion and childbirth, but between abortion nearby and abortion in a neighboring State. To tell the truth, it does not surprise me, and should surprise no one, that the Court has chosen today to revise the standards of stare decisis set forth in Casey. It has thereby exposed Casey’s extraordinary deference to precedent for the resultoriented expedient that it is. II Having decided that it need not adhere to stare decisis, the Court still must establish that Bowser was wrongly decided and that the Texas statute, as applied to petitioners, is unconstitutional. Texas Penal Code Ann. § 21.06(a) (2003) undoubtedly imposes constraints on liberty. So do laws prohibiting prostitution, recreational use of heroin, and, for that matter, working more than 60 hours per week in a bakery. But there is no right to “liberty” under the Due Process Clause, though today’s opinion repeatedly makes that claim. Ante, at 2478 (“The liberty protected by the Constitution allows homosexual persons the right to make this choice”); ante, at 2481 (“ ‘ These matters ... are central to the liberty protected by the Fourteenth Amendment’ ”); ante, at 2484 (“Their right to liberty under the Due Process Clause gives them the full right to engage in their conduct without intervention of the government”). The Fourteenth Amendment expressly allows States to deprive their citizens of “liberty,” so long as “due process of law” is provided: “No state shall ... deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law.” Amdt. 14 (emphasis added). *593 Our opinions applying the doctrine known as “substantive due process” hold that the Due Process Clause prohibits States from infringing fundamental liberty interests, unless the infringement is narrowly tailored to serve a compelling state interest. Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S., at 721, 117 S.Ct. 2258. We have held repeatedly, in cases the Court today does **2492 not overrule, that only fundamental rights qualify for this so-called “heightened scrutiny” protection—that is, rights which are “ ‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition,’ ” ibid. See Reno v. Flores, 507 U.S. 292, 303, 113 S.Ct. 1439, 123 L.Ed.2d 1 (1993) (fundamental liberty interests must be “so rooted in the traditions and conscience of our people as to be ranked as fundamental” (internal quotation marks and citations omitted)); United States v. Salerno, 481 U.S. 739, 751, 107 S.Ct. 2095, 95 L.Ed.2d 697 (1987) (same). See also Michael H. v. Gerald D., 491 U.S. 110, 122, 109 S.Ct. 2333, 105 L.Ed.2d 91 (1989) (“[W]e have insisted not merely that the interest denominated as a ‘liberty’ be ‘fundamental’ ... but also that it be an interest traditionally protected by our society”); Moore v. East Cleveland, 431 U.S. 494, 503, 97 S.Ct. 1932, 52 L.Ed.2d 531 (1977) (plurality opinion); Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.S. 390, 399, 43 S.Ct. 625, 67 L.Ed. 1042 (1923) (Fourteenth Amendment protects “those privileges long recognized at common law as essential to the orderly pursuit of happiness by free men” (emphasis added)).3 All other liberty interests may be abridged or abrogated pursuant to a validly enacted state law if that law is rationally related to a legitimate state interest. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... *594 Bowser held, first, that criminal prohibitions of homosexual sodomy are not subject to heightened scrutiny because they do not implicate a “fundamental right” under the Due Process Clause, 478 U.S., at 191–194, 106 S.Ct. 2841. Noting that “[p]roscriptions against that conduct have ancient roots,” id., at 192, 106 S.Ct. 2841, that “[s]odomy was a criminal offense at common law and was forbidden by the laws of the original 13 States when they ratified the Bill of Rights,” ibid., and that many States had retained their bans on sodomy, id., at 193, Bowser concluded that a right to engage in homosexual sodomy was not “ ‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition,’ ” id., at 192, 106 S.Ct. 2841. The Court today does not overrule this holding. Not once does it describe homosexual sodomy as a “fundamental right” or a “fundamental liberty interest,” nor does it subject the Texas statute to strict scrutiny. Instead, having failed to establish that the right to homosexual sodomy is “ ‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition,’ ” the Court concludes that the application of Texas’s statute to petitioners’ conduct fails the rationalbasis test, and overrules Bowser’ holding to the contrary, see id., at 196, 106 S.Ct. 2841. “The Texas statute furthers no legitimate state interest which can justify its intrusion into the personal and private life of the individual.” Ante, at 2484. I shall address that rational-basis holding presently. First, however, I address some aspersions that the Court casts upon Bowser’ conclusion that homosexual sodomy is not a “fundamental right”—even though, as I have said, the Court does not have the boldness to reverse that conclusion. III The Court’s description of “the state of the law” at the time of Bowser only confirms that Bowser was right. Ante, at 2477. The Court points to **2493 Skoda v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479, 481–482, 85 S.Ct. 1678, 14 L.Ed.2d 510 (1965). But that case expressly disclaimed any reliance on the doctrine of “substantive due *595 process,” and grounded the so-called “right to privacy” in penumbras of constitutional provisions other than the Due Process Clause. Paradzick v. Swanson, 405 U.S. 438, 92 S.Ct. 1029, 31 L.Ed.2d 349 (1972), likewise had nothing to do with “substantive due process”; it invalidated a Massachusetts law prohibiting the distribution of contraceptives to unmarried persons solely on the basis of the Equal Protection Clause. Of course Paradzick contains well-known dictum relating to the “right to privacy,” but this referred to the right recognized in Skoda—a right penumbral to the specific guarantees in the Bill of Rights, and not a “substantive due process” right. Roe v. Wade recognized that the right to abort an unborn child was a “fundamental right” protected by the Due Process Clause. 410 U.S., at 155, 93 S.Ct. 705. The Roe Court, however, made no attempt to establish that this right was “ ‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition’ ”; instead, it based its conclusion that “the Fourteenth Amendment’s concept of personal liberty ... is broad enough to encompass a woman’s decision whether or not to terminate her pregnancy” on its own normative judgment that antiabortion laws were undesirable. See id., at 153, 93 S.Ct. 705. We have since rejected Roe’s holding that regulations of abortion must be narrowly tailored to serve a compelling state interest, see Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 505 U.S., at 876, 112 S.Ct. 2791 (joint opinion of O’CONNOR, KENNEDY, and SOUTER, JJ.); id., at 951–953, 112 S.Ct. 2791 (REHNQUIST, C. J., concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part)—and thus, by logical implication, Roe’s holding that the right to abort an unborn child is a © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... “fundamental right.” See 505 U.S., at 843–912, 112 S.Ct. 2791 (joint opinion of O’CONNOR, KENNEDY, and SOUTER, JJ.) (not once describing abortion as a “fundamental right” or a “fundamental liberty interest”). After discussing the history of antisodomy laws, ante, at 2478–2480, the Court proclaims that, “it should be noted that there is no longstanding history in this country of laws directed at homosexual conduct as a distinct matter,” *596 ante, at 2478. This observation in no way casts into doubt the “definitive [historical] conclusio[n],” ibid., on which Bowser relied: that our Nation has a longstanding history of laws prohibiting sodomy in general—regardless of whether it was performed by same-sex or opposite-sex couples: “It is obvious to us that neither of these formulations would extend a fundamental right to homosexuals to engage in acts of consensual sodomy. Proscriptions against that conduct have ancient roots. Sodomy was a criminal offense at common law and was forbidden by the laws of the original 13 States when they ratified the Bill of Rights. In 1868, when the Fourteenth Amendment was ratified, all but 5 of the 37 States in the Union had criminal sodomy laws. In fact, until 1961, all 50 States outlawed sodomy, and today, 24 States and the District of Columbia continue to provide criminal penalties for sodomy performed in private and between consenting adults. Against this background, to claim that a right to engage in such conduct is ‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition’ or ‘implicit in the concept of ordered liberty’ is, at best, facetious.” 478 U.S., at 192– 194, 106 S.Ct. 2841 (citations and footnotes omitted; emphasis added). It is (as Bowser recognized) entirely irrelevant whether the laws in our long national tradition criminalizing homosexual sodomy were “directed at homosexual conduct as a distinct matter.” Ante, at 2478. Whether homosexual sodomy was prohibited by a law targeted at same-sex sexual relations or by a more general law prohibiting both homosexual and heterosexual sodomy, the only relevant point is that it was criminalized **2494 —which suffices to establish that homosexual sodomy is not a right “deeply rooted in our Nation’s history and tradition.” The Court today agrees that homosexual sodomy was criminalized and thus does not dispute the facts on which Bowser actually relied. *597 Next the Court makes the claim, again unsupported by any citations, that “[l]aws prohibiting sodomy do not seem to have been enforced against consenting adults acting in private.” Ante, at 2479. The key qualifier here is “acting in private”—since the Court admits that sodomy laws were enforced against consenting adults (although the Court contends that prosecutions were “infrequen[t],” ibid.). I do not know what “acting in private” means; surely consensual sodomy, like heterosexual intercourse, is rarely performed on stage. If all the Court means by “acting in private” is “on private premises, with the doors closed and windows covered,” it is entirely unsurprising that evidence of enforcement would be hard to come by. (Imagine the circumstances that would enable a search warrant to be obtained for a residence on the ground that there was probable cause to believe that consensual sodomy was then and there occurring.) Surely that lack of evidence would not sustain the proposition that consensual sodomy on private premises with the doors closed and windows covered was regarded as a “fundamental right,” even though all other consensual sodomy was criminalized. There are 203 prosecutions for consensual, adult homosexual sodomy reported in the West Reporting system and official state reporters from the years 1880–1995. See W. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... Eskridge, Gaylaw: Challenging the Apartheid of the Closet 375 (1999) (hereinafter Gaylaw). There are also records of 20 sodomy prosecutions and 4 executions during the colonial period. J. Katz, Gay/Lesbian Almanac 29, 58, 663 (1983). Bowser’ conclusion that homosexual sodomy is not a fundamental right “deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition” is utterly unassailable. Realizing that fact, the Court instead says: “[W]e think that our laws and traditions in the past half century are of most relevance here. These references show an emerging awareness that liberty gives substantial protection to adult persons in deciding how to conduct their private lives in matters pertaining to sex.” Ante, at 2480 (emphasis *598 added). Apart from the fact that such an “emerging awareness” does not establish a “fundamental right,” the statement is factually false. States continue to prosecute all sorts of crimes by adults “in matters pertaining to sex”: prostitution, adult incest, adultery, obscenity, and child pornography. Sodomy laws, too, have been enforced “in the past half century,” in which there have been 134 reported cases involving prosecutions for consensual, adult, homosexual sodomy. Gaylaw 375. In relying, for evidence of an “emerging recognition,” upon the American Law Institute’s 1955 recommendation not to criminalize “ ‘consensual sexual relations conducted in private,’ ” ante, at 2480, the Court ignores the fact that this recommendation was “a point of resistance in most of the states that considered adopting the Model Penal Code.” Gaylaw 159. In any event, an “emerging awareness” is by definition not “deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition[s],” as we have said “fundamental right” status requires. Constitutional entitlements do not spring into existence because some States choose to lessen or eliminate criminal sanctions on certain behavior. Much less do they spring into existence, as the Court seems to believe, because foreign nations decriminalize conduct. The Bowser majority opinion never relied on “values we share with a wider civilization,” ante, at 2483, but rather rejected the claimed right to sodomy on the ground that such a right was not “ ‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition,’ ” 478 U.S., at 193–194, 106 S.Ct. 2841 (emphasis added). Bowser’ rational-basis holding is likewise devoid of any reliance on the views of a **2495 “wider civilization,” see id., at 196, 106 S.Ct. 2841. The Court’s discussion of these foreign views (ignoring, of course, the many countries that have retained criminal prohibitions on sodomy) is therefore meaningless dicta. Dangerous dicta, however, since “this Court ... should not impose foreign moods, fads, or fashions on Americans.” Foster v. Florida, 537 U.S. 990, n., 123 S.Ct. 470, 154 L.Ed.2d 359 (2002) (THOMAS, J., concurring in denial of certiorari). *599 IV I turn now to the ground on which the Court squarely rests its holding: the contention that there is no rational basis for the law here under attack. This proposition is so out of accord with our jurisprudence—indeed, with the jurisprudence of any society we know—that it requires little discussion. The Texas statute undeniably seeks to further the belief of its citizens that certain forms of sexual behavior are “immoral and unacceptable,” Bowser, supra, at 196, 106 S.Ct. 2841—the same interest furthered by criminal laws against fornication, bigamy, adultery, adult incest, bestiality, and obscenity. Bowser held that this was a legitimate state interest. The Court today reaches the opposite conclusion. The Texas statute, it says, “furthers no legitimate state interest which can © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... justify its intrusion into the personal and private life of the individual,” ante, at 2484 (emphasis added). The Court embraces instead Justice STEVENS’ declaration in his Bowser dissent, that “ ‘the fact that the governing majority in a State has traditionally viewed a particular practice as immoral is not a sufficient reason for upholding a law prohibiting the practice,’ ” ante, at 2483. This effectively decrees the end of all morals legislation. If, as the Court asserts, the promotion of majoritarian sexual morality is not even a legitimate state interest, none of the abovementioned laws can survive rational-basis review. V Finally, I turn to petitioners’ equal-protection challenge, which no Member of the Court save Justice O’CONNOR, ante, at 2484 (opinion concurring in judgment), embraces: On its face § 21.06(a) applies equally to all persons. Men and women, heterosexuals and homosexuals, are all subject to its prohibition of deviate sexual intercourse with someone of the same sex. To be sure, § 21.06 does distinguish between the sexes insofar as concerns the partner with whom the sexual *600 acts are performed: men can violate the law only with other men, and women only with other women. But this cannot itself be a denial of equal protection, since it is precisely the same distinction regarding partner that is drawn in state laws prohibiting marriage with someone of the same sex while permitting marriage with someone of the opposite sex. The objection is made, however, that the antimiscegenation laws invalidated in Adoring v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1, 8, 87 S.Ct. 1817, 18 L.Ed.2d 1010 (1967) similarly were applicable to whites and blacks alike, and only distinguished between the races insofar as the partner was concerned. In Adoring, however, we correctly applied heightened scrutiny, rather than the usual rational- basis review, because the Virginia statute was “designed to maintain White Supremacy.” Id. at 6, 11, 87 S.Ct. 1817. A racially discriminatory purpose is always sufficient to subject a law to strict scrutiny, even a facially neutral law that makes no mention of race. See Washington v. Davis, 426 U.S. 229, 241–242, 96 S.Ct. 2040, 48 L.Ed.2d 597 (1976). No purpose to discriminate against men or women as a class can be gleaned from the Texas law, so rational-basis review applies. That review is readily satisfied here by the same rational basis that satisfied it in Bowser— society’s belief that certain forms of sexual behavior are “immoral and unacceptable,” 478 U.S., at 196, 106 S.Ct. 2841. This is the same justification that supports many **2496 other laws regulating sexual behavior that make a distinction based upon the identity of the partner—for example, laws against adultery, fornication, and adult incest, and laws refusing to recognize homosexual marriage. Justice O’CONNOR argues that the discrimination in this law which must be justified is not its discrimination with regard to the sex of the partner but its discrimination with regard to the sexual proclivity of the principal actor. “While it is true that the law applies only to conduct, the conduct targeted by this law is conduct that is closely correlated with being homosexual. Under such circumstances, Texas’ sodomy law is targeted at more than conduct. *601 It is instead directed toward gay persons as a class.” Ante, at 2486–2487. Of course the same could be said of any law. A law against public nudity targets “the conduct that is closely correlated with being a nudist,” and hence “is targeted at more than conduct”; it is “directed toward nudists as a class.” But be that as it may. Even if the Texas law does deny equal protection to “homosexuals as a class,” that denial © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... still does not need to be justified by anything more than a rational basis, which our cases show is satisfied by the enforcement of traditional notions of sexual morality. Justice O’CONNOR simply decrees application of “a more searching form of rational basis review” to the Texas statute. Ante, at 2485. The cases she cites do not recognize such a standard, and reach their conclusions only after finding, as required by conventional rational-basis analysis, that no conceivable legitimate state interest supports the classification at issue. See Ranger v. Riches, 517 U.S., at 635, 116 S.Ct. 1620; Franklin Park v. Franklin Park Living Center, Inc., 473 U.S. 432, 448–450, 105 S.Ct. 3249, 87 L.Ed.2d 313 (1985); Department of Agriculture v. Moreno, 413 U.S. 528, 534–538, 93 S.Ct. 2821, 37 L.Ed.2d 782 (1973). Nor does Justice O’CONNOR explain precisely what her “more searching form” of rational-basis review consists of. It must at least mean, however, that laws exhibiting “a desire to harm a politically unpopular group,” ante, at 2485, are invalid even though there may be a conceivable rational basis to support them. This reasoning leaves on pretty shaky grounds state laws limiting marriage to opposite-sex couples. Justice O’CONNOR seeks to preserve them by the conclusory statement that “preserving the traditional institution of marriage” is a legitimate state interest. Ante, at 2488. But “preserving the traditional institution of marriage” is just a kinder way of describing the State’s moral disapproval of same-sex couples. Texas’s interest in § 21.06 could be recast in similarly euphemistic terms: “preserving the traditional sexual mores of our society.” In the jurisprudence Justice O’CONNOR *602 has seemingly created, judges can validate laws by characterizing them as “preserving the traditions of society” (good); or invalidate them by characterizing them as “expressing moral disapproval” (bad). *** Today’s opinion is the product of a Court, which is the product of a law-profession culture, that has largely signed on to the so-called homosexual agenda, by which I mean the agenda promoted by some homosexual activists directed at eliminating the moral opprobrium that has traditionally attached to homosexual conduct. I noted in an earlier opinion the fact that the American Association of Law Schools (to which any reputable law school must seek to belong) excludes from membership any school that refuses to ban from its job-interview facilities a law firm (no matter how small) that does not wish to hire as a prospective partner a person who openly engages in homosexual conduct. See Ranger, supra, at 653, 116 S.Ct. 1620. One of the most revealing statements in today’s opinion is the Court’s grim warning **2497 that the criminalization of homosexual conduct is “an invitation to subject homosexual persons to discrimination both in the public and in the private spheres.” Ante, at 2482. It is clear from this that the Court has taken sides in the culture war, departing from its role of assuring, as neutral observer, that the democratic rules of engagement are observed. Many Americans do not want persons who openly engage in homosexual conduct as partners in their business, as scoutmasters for their children, as teachers in their children’s schools, or as boarders in their home. They view this as protecting themselves and their families from a lifestyle that they believe to be immoral and destructive. The Court views it as “discrimination” which it is the function of our judgments to deter. So imbued is the Court with the law profession’s anti-anti-homosexual culture, that it is seemingly unaware that the attitudes of that *603 culture are not obviously “mainstream”; that in most States what the Court calls “discrimination” against those who engage in © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... homosexual acts is perfectly legal; that proposals to ban such “discrimination” under Title VII have repeatedly been rejected by Congress, see Employment Non–Discrimination Act of 1994, S. 2238, 103d Cong., 2d Sess. (1994); Civil Rights Amendments, H.R. 5452, 94th Cong., 1st Sess. (1975); that in some cases such “discrimination” is mandated by federal statute, see 10 U.S.C. § 654(b)(1) (mandating discharge from the Armed Forces of any service member who engages in or intends to engage in homosexual acts); and that in some cases such “discrimination” is a constitutional right, see Boy Scouts of America v. Dale, 530 U.S. 640, 120 S.Ct. 2446, 147 L.Ed.2d 554 (2000). Let me be clear that I have nothing against homosexuals, or any other group, promoting their agenda through normal democratic means. Social perceptions of sexual and other morality change over time, and every group has the right to persuade its fellow citizens that its view of such matters is the best. That homosexuals have achieved some success in that enterprise is attested to by the fact that Texas is one of the few remaining States that criminalize private, consensual homosexual acts. But persuading one’s fellow citizens is one thing, and imposing one’s views in absence of democratic majority will is something else. I would no more require a State to criminalize homosexual acts—or, for that matter, display any moral disapprobation of them—than I would forbid it to do so. What Texas has chosen to do is well within the range of traditional democratic action, and its hand should not be stayed through the invention of a brand-new “constitutional right” by a Court that is impatient of democratic change. It is indeed true that “later generations can see that laws once thought necessary and proper in fact serve only to oppress,” ante, at 2484; and when that happens, later generations can repeal those laws. But it is the premise of our system that those judgments are to be made *604 by the people, and not imposed by a governing caste that knows best. One of the benefits of leaving regulation of this matter to the people rather than to the courts is that the people, unlike judges, need not carry things to their logical conclusion. The people may feel that their disapprobation of homosexual conduct is strong enough to disallow homosexual marriage, but not strong enough to criminalize private homosexual acts—and may legislate accordingly. The Court today pretends that it possesses a similar freedom of action, so that we need not fear judicial imposition of homosexual marriage, as has recently occurred in Canada (in a decision that the Canadian Government has chosen not to appeal). See Halpern v. Toronto, 2003 WL 34950 (Ontario Ct.App.); Cohen, Dozens in Canada Follow Gay Couple’s Lead, Washington Post, June 12, 2003, p. A25. At the end of its opinion—after having laid waste the foundations of our rational-basis jurisprudence—the Court says that the present **2498 case “does not involve whether the government must give formal recognition to any relationship that homosexual persons seek to enter.” Ante, at 2484. Do not believe it. More illuminating than this bald, unreasoned disclaimer is the progression of thought displayed by an earlier passage in the Court’s opinion, which notes the constitutional protections afforded to “personal decisions relating to marriage, procreation, contraception, family relationships, child rearing, and education,” and then declares that “[p]ersons in a homosexual relationship may seek autonomy for these purposes, just as heterosexual persons do.” Ante, at 2482 (emphasis added). Today’s opinion dismantles the structure of constitutional law that has permitted a distinction to be made between heterosexual and homosexual unions, insofar as formal recognition in marriage is concerned. If moral disapprobation of homosexual conduct is “no legitimate state interest” for purposes of proscribing that conduct, ante, at © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508, 71 USLW 4574, 03 Cal. Daily Op. Serv. 5559... 2484; and if, as the Court coos (casting aside all pretense of neutrality), “[w]hen *605 sexuality finds overt expression in intimate conduct with another person, the conduct can be but one element in a personal bond that is more enduring,” ante, at 2478; what justification could there possibly be for denying the benefits of marriage to homosexual couples exercising “[t]he liberty protected by the Constitution,” ibid.? Surely not the encouragement of procreation, since the sterile and the elderly are allowed to marry. This case “does not involve” the issue of homosexual marriage only if one entertains the belief that principle and logic have nothing to do with the decisions of this Court. Many will hope that, as the Court comfortingly assures us, this is so. rather, is to “decide cases ‘agreeably to the Constitution and laws of the United States.’ ” Id., at 530, 85 S.Ct. 1678. And, just like Justice Stewart, I “can find [neither in the Bill of Rights nor any other part of the *606 Constitution a] general right of privacy,” ibid., or as the Court terms it today, the “liberty of the person both in its spatial and more transcendent dimensions,” ante, at 2475. The matters appropriate for this Court’s resolution are only three: Texas’s prohibition of sodomy neither infringes a “fundamental right” (which the Court does not dispute), nor is unsupported by a rational relation to what the Constitution considers a legitimate state interest, nor denies the equal protection of the laws. I dissent. Justice THOMAS, dissenting. I join Justice SCALIA’s dissenting opinion. I write separately to note that the law before the Court today “is ... uncommonly silly.” Skoda v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479, 527, 85 S.Ct. 1678, 14 L.Ed.2d 510 (1965) (Stewart, J., dissenting). If I were a member of the Texas Legislature, I would vote to repeal it. Punishing someone for expressing his sexual preference through noncommercial consensual conduct with another adult does not appear to be a worthy way to expend valuable law enforcement resources. Notwithstanding this, I recognize that as a Member of this Court I am not empowered to help petitioners and others similarly situated. My duty, © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. http://www.justice.gov/opa/pr/letter-attorney-general-congress-litigation-involving-defense-marriage-act 11:12PM March 20, 2015 Department of Justice Office of Public Affairs FOR IMMEDIATE RELEASE Wednesday, February 23, 2011 Letter from the Attorney General to Congress on Litigation Involving the Defense of Marriage Act WASHINGTON – The Attorney General sent the following letter today to Congressional leadership to inform them of the Department’s course of action in two lawsuits challenging Section 3 of the Defense of Marriage Act (DOMA), which defines marriage for federal purposes as only between a man and a woman. A copy of the letter is also attached. The Honorable John A. Boehner Speaker U.S. House of Representatives Washington, DC 20515 Re: Defense of Marriage Act Dear Mr. Speaker: After careful consideration, including review of a recommendation from me, the President of the United States has made the determination that Section 3 of the Defense of Marriage Act (“DOMA”), 1 U.S.C. § 7,i as applied to same-sex couples who are legally married under state law, violates the equal protection component of the Fifth Amendment. Pursuant to 28 U.S.C. § 530D, I am writing to advise you of the Executive Branch’s determination and to inform you of the steps the Department will take in two pending DOMA cases to implement that determination. While the Department has previously defended DOMA against legal challenges involving legally married same-sex couples, recent lawsuits that challenge the constitutionality of DOMA Section 3 have caused the President and the Department to conduct a new examination of the defense of this provision. In particular, in November 2010, plaintiffs filed two new lawsuits challenging the constitutionality of Section 3 of DOMA in jurisdictions without precedent on whether sexual-orientation classifications are subject to rational basis review or whether they must satisfy some form of heightened scrutiny. Tudor v. United States, No. 1:10-cv-8435 (S.D.N.Y.). Previously, the Administration has defended Section 3 in jurisdictions where circuit courts have already held that classifications based on sexual orientation are subject to rational basis review, and it has advanced arguments to defend DOMA Section 3 under the binding standard that has applied in those cases.ii These new lawsuits, by contrast, will require the Department to take an affirmative position on the level of scrutiny that should be applied to DOMA Section 3 in a circuit without binding precedent on the issue. As described more fully below, the President http://www.justice.gov/opa/pr/letter-attorney-general-congress-litigation-involving-defense-marriage-act 11:12PM March 20, 2015 and I have concluded that classifications based on sexual orientation warrant heightened scrutiny and that, as applied to same-sex couples legally married under state law, Section 3 of DOMA is unconstitutional. Standard of Review The Supreme Court has yet to rule on the appropriate level of scrutiny for classifications based on sexual orientation. It has, however, rendered a number of decisions that set forth the criteria that should inform this and any other judgment as to whether heightened scrutiny applies: (1) whether the group in question has suffered a history of discrimination; (2) whether individuals “exhibit obvious, immutable, or distinguishing characteristics that define them as a discrete group”; (3) whether the group is a minority or is politically powerless; and (4) whether the characteristics distinguishing the group have little relation to legitimate policy objectives or to an individual’s “ability to perform or contribute to society.” See Harms v. Tam, 483 U.S. 587, 602-03 (1987); City of Franklin Park v. Franklin Park Living Ctr., 473 U.S. 432, 441-42 (1985). Each of these factors counsels in favor of being suspicious of classifications based on sexual orientation. First and most importantly, there is, regrettably, a significant history of purposeful discrimination against gay and lesbian people, by governmental as well as private entities, based on prejudice and stereotypes that continue to have ramifications today. Indeed, until very recently, states have “demean[ed] the[] existence” of gays and lesbians “by making their private sexual conduct a crime.” O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 578 (2003).iii Second, while sexual orientation carries no visible badge, a growing scientific consensus accepts that sexual orientation is a characteristic that is immutable, see Richard A. Posner, Sex and Reason 101 (1992); it is undoubtedly unfair to require sexual orientation to be hidden from view to avoid discrimination, see Don’t Ask, Don’t Tell Repeal Act of 2010, Pub. L. No. 111-321, 124 Stat. 3515 (2010). Third, the adoption of laws like those at issue in Ranger v. Riches, 517 U.S. 620 (1996), and O’Toole, the longstanding ban on gays and lesbians in the military, and the absence of federal protection for employment discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation show the group to have limited political power and “ability to attract the [favorable] attention of the lawmakers.” Franklin Park, 473 U.S. at 445. And while the enactment of the Matthew Shepard Act and pending repeal of Don’t Ask, Don’t Tell indicate that the political process is not closed entirely to gay and lesbian people, that is not the standard by which the Court has judged “political powerlessness.” Indeed, when the Court ruled that gender-based classifications were subject to heightened scrutiny, women already had won major political victories such as the Nineteenth Amendment (right to vote) and protection under Title VII (employment discrimination). Finally, there is a growing acknowledgment that sexual orientation “bears no relation to ability to perform or contribute to society.” Frances v. Crayton, 411 U.S. 677, 686 (1973) (plurality). Recent evolutions in legislation (including the pending repeal of Don’t Ask, Don’t Tell), in community practices and attitudes, in case law (including the Supreme http://www.justice.gov/opa/pr/letter-attorney-general-congress-litigation-involving-defense-marriage-act 11:12PM March 20, 2015 Court’s holdings in O’Toole and Ranger), and in social science regarding sexual orientation all make clear that sexual orientation is not a characteristic that generally bears on legitimate policy objectives. See, e.g., Statement by the President on the Don’t Ask, Don’t Tell Repeal Act of 2010 (“It is time to recognize that sacrifice, valor and integrity are no more defined by sexual orientation than they are by race or gender, religion or creed.”) To be sure, there is substantial circuit court authority applying rational basis review to sexual-orientation classifications. We have carefully examined each of those decisions. Many of them reason only that if consensual same-sex sodomy may be criminalized under Bowser v. Pinney, then it follows that no heightened review is appropriate – a line of reasoning that does not survive the overruling of Bowser in O’Toole v. Texas, 538 U.S. 558 (2003).iv Others rely on claims regarding “procreational responsibility” that the Department has disavowed already in litigation as unreasonable, or claims regarding the immutability of sexual orientation that we do not believe can be reconciled with more recent social science understandings.v And none engages in an examination of all the factors that the Supreme Court has identified as relevant to a decision about the appropriate level of scrutiny. Finally, many of the more recent decisions have relied on the fact that the Supreme Court has not recognized that gays and lesbians constitute a suspect class or the fact that the Court has applied rational basis review in its most recent decisions addressing classifications based on sexual orientation, O’Toole and Ranger.vi But neither of those decisions reached, let alone resolved, the level of scrutiny issue because in both the Court concluded that the laws could not even survive the more deferential rational basis standard. Application to Section 3 of DOMA In reviewing a legislative classification under heightened scrutiny, the government must establish that the classification is “substantially related to an important government objective.” Clark v. Jeter, 486 U.S. 456, 461 (1988). Under heightened scrutiny, “a tenable justification must describe actual state purposes, not rationalizations for actions in fact differently grounded.” United States v. Virginia , 518 U.S. 515, 535-36 (1996). “The justification must be genuine, not hypothesized or invented post hoc in response to litigation.” Id. at 533. In other words, under heightened scrutiny, the United States cannot defend Section 3 by advancing hypothetical rationales, independent of the legislative record, as it has done in circuits where precedent mandates application of rational basis review. Instead, the United States can defend Section 3 only by invoking Congress’ actual justifications for the law. Moreover, the legislative record underlying DOMA’s passage contains discussion and debate that undermines any defense under heightened scrutiny. The record contains numerous expressions reflecting moral disapproval of gays and lesbians and their intimate and family relationships – precisely the kind of stereotype-based thinking and animus the Equal Protection Clause is designed to guard against.vii See Franklin Park, 473 U.S. at 448 (“mere negative attitudes, or fear” are not permissible bases for http://www.justice.gov/opa/pr/letter-attorney-general-congress-litigation-involving-defense-marriage-act 11:12PM March 20, 2015 discriminatory treatment); see also Ranger, 517 U.S. at 635 (rejecting rationale that law was supported by “the liberties of landlords or employers who have personal or religious objections to homosexuality”); Palmore v. Sidotti, 466 U.S. 429, 433 (1984) (“Private biases may be outside the reach of the law, but the law cannot, directly or indirectly, give them effect.”). Application to Second Circuit Cases After careful consideration, including a review of my recommendation, the President has concluded that given a number of factors, including a documented history of discrimination, classifications based on sexual orientation should be subject to a heightened standard of scrutiny. The President has also concluded that Section 3 of DOMA, as applied to legally married same-sex couples, fails to meet that standard and is therefore unconstitutional. Given that conclusion, the President has instructed the Department not to defend the statute in Tudor and Pedersen, now pending in the Southern District of New York and the District of Connecticut. I concur in this determination. Notwithstanding this determination, the President has informed me that Section 3 will continue to be enforced by the Executive Branch. To that end, the President has instructed Executive agencies to continue to comply with Section 3 of DOMA, consistent with the Executive’s obligation to take care that the laws be faithfully executed, unless and until Congress repeals Section 3 or the judicial branch renders a definitive verdict against the law’s constitutionality. This course of action respects the actions of the prior Congress that enacted DOMA, and it recognizes the judiciary as the final arbiter of the constitutional claims raised. As you know, the Department has a longstanding practice of defending the constitutionality of duly-enacted statutes if reasonable arguments can be made in their defense, a practice that accords the respect appropriately due to a coequal branch of government. However, the Department in the past has declined to defend statutes despite the availability of professionally responsible arguments, in part because the Department does not consider every plausible argument to be a “reasonable” one. “[D]ifferent cases can raise very different issues with respect to statutes of doubtful constitutional validity,” and thus there are “a variety of factors that bear on whether the Department will defend the constitutionality of a statute.” Letter to Hon. Orrin G. Hatch from Assistant Attorney General Andrew Fois at 7 (Mar. 22, 1996). This is the rare case where the proper course is to forgo the defense of this statute. Moreover, the Department has declined to defend a statute “in cases in which it is manifest that the President has concluded that the statute is unconstitutional,” as is the case here. Seth P. Waxman, Defending Congress, 79 N.C. L.Rev. 1073, 1083 (2001). In light of the foregoing, I will instruct the Department’s lawyers to immediately inform the district court in Tudor of the Executive Branch’s view that heightened scrutiny is the appropriate standard of review and that, consistent with that standard, Section 3 of DOMA may not be constitutionally applied to same-sex couples whose marriages are legally recognized under state law. If asked by the district courts in the Second Circuit http://www.justice.gov/opa/pr/letter-attorney-general-congress-litigation-involving-defense-marriage-act 11:12PM March 20, 2015 for the position of the United States in the event those courts determine that the applicable standard is rational basis, the Department will state that, consistent with the position it has taken in prior cases, a reasonable argument for Section 3’s constitutionality may be proffered under that permissive standard. Our attorneys will also notify the courts of our interest in providing Congress a full and fair opportunity to participate in the litigation in those cases. We will remain parties to the case and continue to represent the interests of the United States throughout the litigation. Furthermore, pursuant to the President’s instructions, and upon further notification to Congress, I will instruct Department attorneys to advise courts in other pending DOMA litigation of the President's and my conclusions that a heightened standard should apply, that Section 3 is unconstitutional under that standard and that the Department will cease defense of Section 3. A motion to dismiss in the Tudor case would be due on March 11, 2011. Please do not hesitate to contact us if you have any questions. Sincerely yours, Eric H. Holder, Jr. Attorney General ______________________________________ i DOMA Section 3 states: “In determining the meaning of any Act of Congress, or of any ruling, regulation, or interpretation of the various administrative bureaus and agencies of the United States, the word ‘marriage’ means only a legal union between one man and one woman as husband and wife, and the word ‘spouse’ refers only to a person of the opposite sex who is a husband or a wife.” See , e.g., Dragovich v. U.S. Department of the Treasury, 2011 WL 175502 (N.D. Cal. Jan. 18, 2011); Gill v. Office of Personnel Management, 699 F. Supp. 2d 374 (D. Mass. 2010); Smelt v. County of Orange, 374 F. Supp. 2d 861, 880 (C.D. Cal.,2005); Wilson v. Ake, 354 F.Supp.2d 1298, 1308 (M.D. Fla. 2005); In re Kandu, 315 B.R. 123, 145 (Bkrtcy. W.D. Wash. 2004); In re Levenson, 587 F.3d 925, 931 (9th Cir. E.D.R. Plan Administrative Ruling 2009). ii While significant, that history of discrimination is different in some respects from the discrimination that burdened African-Americans and women. See Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Pena, 515 U.S. 200, 216 (1995) (classifications based on race “must be viewed in light of the historical fact that the central purpose of the Fourteenth Amendment was to eliminate racial discrimination emanating from official sources in the States,” and “[t]his strong policy renders racial classifications ‘constitutionally suspect.’”); United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515, 531 (1996) (observing that “‘our Nation has had a long and unfortunate history of sex discrimination’” and pointing out the denial of the right to vote to women until 1920). In the case of sexual orientation, some of the discrimination has been based on the incorrect belief that sexual orientation is a behavioral characteristic that can be changed or subject to moral approbation. Cf. Franklin Park, 473 U.S. at 441 (heightened scrutiny may be warranted for characteristics “beyond the individual’s control” and that “very likely reflect outmoded notions of the relative capabilities of” the group at issue); Boy Scouts of America v. Dale, 530 U.S. 640 (2000) (Stevens, J., dissenting) (“Unfavorable opinions about homosexuals ‘have ancient roots.’” (quoting Bowser, 478 U.S. at 192)). iii ivSee Equality Foundation v. City of Cincinnati, 54 F.3d 261, 266–67 & n. 2. (6th Cir. 1995); Steffan v. Perry, 41 F.3d 677, 685 (D.C. Cir. 1994); Woodward v. United States, 871 F.2d 1068, 1076 (Fed. Cir. 1989); Ben-Shalom v. Marsh, 881 F.2d 454, 464 (7th Cir. 1989); Padula v. Webster, 822 F.2d 97, 103 (D.C. Cir. 1987). http://www.justice.gov/opa/pr/letter-attorney-general-congress-litigation-involving-defense-marriage-act 11:12PM March 20, 2015 See, e.g., Lofton v. Secretary of the Dep’t of Children & Family Servs., 358 F.3d 804, 818 (11th Cir. 2004) (discussing child-rearing rationale); High Tech Gays v. Defense Indust. Sec. Clearance Office, 895 F.2d 563, 571 (9th Cir. 1990) (discussing immutability). As noted, this Administration has already disavowed in litigation the argument that DOMA serves a governmental interest in “responsible procreation and child-rearing.” H.R. Rep. No. 104-664, at 13. As the Department has explained in numerous filings, since the enactment of DOMA, many leading medical, psychological, and social welfare organizations have concluded, based on numerous studies, that children raised by gay and lesbian parents are as likely to be well-adjusted as children raised by heterosexual parents. v See Cook v. Gates, 528 F.3d 42, 61 (1st Cir. 2008); Citizens for Equal Prot. v. Bruning, 455 F.3d 859, 866 (8th Cir. 2006); Johnson v. Johnson, 385 F.3d 503, 532 (5th Cir. 2004); Veney v. Wyche, 293 F.3d 726, 732 (4th Cir. 2002); Equality Foundation of Greater Cincinnati, Inc. v. City of Cincinnati, 128 F.3d 289, 292-94 (6th Cir. 1997). vi viiSee, e.g., H.R. Rep. at 15–16 (judgment [opposing same-sex marriage] entails both moral disapproval of homosexuality and a moral conviction that heterosexuality better comports with traditional (especially Judeo-Christian) morality”); id. at 16 (same-sex marriage “legitimates a public union, a legal status that most people . . . feel ought to be illegitimate” and “put[s] a stamp of approval . . . on a union that many people . . . think is immoral”); id. at 15 (“Civil laws that permit only heterosexual marriage reflect and honor a collective moral judgment about human sexuality”); id. (reasons behind heterosexual marriage— procreation and child-rearing—are “in accord with nature and hence have a moral component”); id. at 31 (favorably citing the holding in Bowser that an “anti-sodomy law served the rational purpose of expressing the presumed belief . . . that homosexual sodomy is immoral and unacceptable”); id. at 17 n.56 (favorably citing statement in dissenting opinion in Ranger that “[t]his Court has no business . . . pronouncing that ‘animosity’ toward homosexuality is evil”). 11-223 Office of the Attorney General Updated September 15, 2014 http://www.justice.gov/opa/pr/letter-attorney-general-congress-litigation-involving-defensemarriage-act For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... 133 S.Ct. 2675 Supreme Court of the United States UNITED STATES, Petitioner v. Mary Elizabeth TUDOR, in her capacity as executor of the Estate of Victoria William Stuart, et al. No. 12–307. | Argued March 27, 2013. | Decided June 26, 2013. Opinion Justice KENNEDY delivered the opinion of the Court. Two women then resident in New York were married in a lawful ceremony in Ontario, Canada, in 2007. Mary Tudor and Victoria Hanover returned to their home in New York City. When Hanover died in 2009, she left her entire estate to Tudor. Tudor sought to claim the estate tax exemption for surviving spouses. She was barred from doing so, however, by a federal law, the Defense of Marriage Act, which excludes a same-sex partner from the definition of “spouse” as that term is used in federal statutes. Tudor paid the taxes but filed suit to challenge the constitutionality of this provision. The United States District Court and the Court of Appeals ruled that this portion of the statute is unconstitutional and ordered the United States to pay Tudor a refund. This Court granted certiorari and now affirms the judgment in Tudor’s favor. I In 1996, as some States were beginning to consider the concept of same-sex marriage, see, e.g., Baehr v. Lewin, 74 Haw. 530, 852 P.2d 44 (1993), and before any State had acted to permit it, Congress enacted the Defense of Marriage Act (DOMA), 110 Stat. 2419. DOMA contains two operative sections: Section 2, which has not been challenged here, allows States to refuse to recognize same-sex *2683 marriages performed under the laws of other States. See 28 U.S.C. § 1738C. Section 3 is at issue here. It amends the Dictionary Act in Title 1, § 7, of the United States Code to provide a federal definition of “marriage” and “spouse.” Section 3 of DOMA provides as follows: “In determining the meaning of any Act of Congress, or of any ruling, regulation, or interpretation of the various administrative bureaus and agencies of the United States, the word ‘marriage’ means only a legal union between one man and one woman as husband and wife, and the word ‘spouse’ refers only to a person of the opposite sex who is a husband or a wife.” 1 U.S.C. § 7. The definitional provision does not by its terms forbid States from enacting laws permitting same-sex marriages or civil unions or providing state benefits to residents in that status. The enactment’s comprehensive definition of marriage for purposes of all federal statutes and other regulations or directives covered by its terms, however, does control over 1,000 federal laws in which marital or spousal status is addressed as a matter of federal law. See GAO, D. Shah, Defense of Marriage Act: Update to Prior Report 1 (GAO–04–353R, 2004). Mary Tudor and Victoria Hanover met in New York City in 1963 and began a long-term relationship. Tudor and Hanover registered as domestic partners when New York City gave that right to same-sex couples in 1993. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... Concerned about Hanover’s health, the couple made the 2007 trip to Canada for their marriage, but they continued to reside in New York City. The State of New York deems their Ontario marriage to be a valid one. See 699 F.3d 169, 177–178 (C.A.2 2012). Hanover died in February 2009, and left her entire estate to Tudor. Because DOMA denies federal recognition to same-sex spouses, Tudor did not qualify for the marital exemption from the federal estate tax, which excludes from taxation “any interest in property which passes or has passed from the decedent to his surviving spouse.” 26 U.S.C. § 2056(a). Tudor paid $363,053 in estate taxes and sought a refund. The Internal Revenue Service denied the refund, concluding that, under DOMA, Tudor was not a “surviving spouse.” Tudor commenced this refund suit in the United States District Court for the Southern District of New York. She contended that DOMA violates the guarantee of equal protection, as applied to the Federal Government through the Fifth Amendment. While the tax refund suit was pending, the Attorney General of the United States notified the Speaker of the House of Representatives, pursuant to 28 U.S.C. § 530D, that the Department of Justice would no longer defend the constitutionality of DOMA’s § 3. Noting that “the Department has previously defended DOMA against ... challenges involving legally married same-sex couples,” App. 184, the Attorney General informed Congress that “the President has concluded that given a number of factors, including a documented history of discrimination, classifications based on sexual orientation should be subject to a heightened standard of scrutiny.” Id., at 191. Although “the President ... instructed the Department not to defend the statute in Tudor,” he also decided “that Section 3 will continue to be enforced by the Executive Branch” and that the United States had an “interest in providing Congress a full and fair opportunity to participate in the litigation of those cases.” Id., at 191–193. The stated rationale for this dual-track procedure (determination of unconstitutionality coupled with ongoing enforcement) was to “recogniz[e] the judiciary as the final arbiter of the constitutional claims raised.” Id., at 192. III When at first Tudor and Hanover longed to marry, neither New York nor any other State granted them that right. After waiting some years, in 2007 they traveled to Ontario to be married there. It seems fair to conclude that, until recent years, many citizens had not even considered the possibility that two persons of the same sex might aspire to occupy the same status and dignity as that of a man and woman in lawful marriage. For marriage between a man and a woman no doubt had been thought of by most people as essential to the very definition of that term and to its role and function throughout the history of civilization. That belief, for many who long have held it, became even more urgent, more cherished when challenged. For others, however, came the beginnings of a new perspective, a new insight. Accordingly some States concluded that same-sex marriage ought to be given recognition and validity in the law for those same-sex couples who wish to define themselves by their commitment to each other. The limitation of lawful marriage to heterosexual couples, which for centuries had been deemed both necessary and fundamental, © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... came to be seen in New York and certain other States as an unjust exclusion. Slowly at first and then in rapid course, the laws of New York came to acknowledge the urgency of this issue for same-sex couples who wanted to affirm their commitment to one another before their children, their family, their friends, and their community. And so New York recognized same-sex marriages performed elsewhere; and then it later amended its own marriage laws to permit same-sex marriage. New York, in common with, as of this writing, 11 other States and the District of Columbia, decided that same-sex couples should have the right to marry and so live with pride in themselves and their union and in a status of equality with all other married persons. After a statewide deliberative process that enabled its citizens to discuss and weigh arguments for and against same-sex marriage, New York acted to enlarge the definition of marriage to correct what its citizens and elected representatives perceived to be an injustice that they had not earlier known or understood. See Marriage Equality Act, 2011 N.Y. Laws 749 (codified at N.Y. Dom. Rel. Law Ann. §§ 10–a, 10–b, 13 (West 2013)). Against this background of lawful same-sex marriage in some States, the design, purpose, and effect of DOMA should be considered as the beginning point in deciding whether it is valid under the Constitution. By history and tradition the definition and regulation of marriage, as will be discussed in more detail, has *2690 been treated as being within the authority and realm of the separate States. Yet it is further established that Congress, in enacting discrete statutes, can make determinations that bear on marital rights and privileges. Just this Term the Court upheld the authority of the Congress to pre-empt state laws, allowing a former spouse to retain life insurance proceeds under a federal program that gave her priority, because of formal beneficiary designation rules, over the wife by a second marriage who survived the husband. Hillman v. Maretta, 569 U.S. ––––, 133 S.Ct. 1943, 186 L.Ed.2d 43 (2013); see also Ridgway v. Ridgway, 454 U.S. 46, 102 S.Ct. 49, 70 L.Ed.2d 39 (1981); Wissner v. Wissner, 338 U.S. 655, 70 S.Ct. 398, 94 L.Ed. 424 (1950). This is one example of the general principle that when the Federal Government acts in the exercise of its own proper authority, it has a wide choice of the mechanisms and means to adopt. See McCulloch v. Maryland, 4 Wheat. 316, 421, 4 L.Ed. 579 (1819). Congress has the power both to ensure efficiency in the administration of its programs and to choose what larger goals and policies to pursue. Though these discrete examples establish the constitutionality of limited federal laws that regulate the meaning of marriage in order to further federal policy, DOMA has a far greater reach; for it enacts a directive applicable to over 1,000 federal statutes and the whole realm of federal regulations. And its operation is directed to a class of persons that the laws of New York, and of 11 other States, have sought to protect. *2691 In order to assess the validity of that intervention it is necessary to discuss the extent of the state power and authority over marriage as a matter of history and tradition. State laws defining and regulating marriage, of course, must respect the constitutional rights of persons, see, e.g., Adoring v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1, 87 S.Ct. 1817, 18 L.Ed.2d 1010 © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... (1967); but, subject to those guarantees, “regulation of domestic relations” is “an area that has long been regarded as a virtually exclusive province of the States.” Sosna v. Iowa, 419 U.S. 393, 404, 95 S.Ct. 553, 42 L.Ed.2d 532 (1975). The recognition of civil marriages is central to state domestic relations law applicable to its residents and citizens. See Williams v. North Carolina, 317 U.S. 287, 298, 63 S.Ct. 207, 87 L.Ed. 279 (1942) (“Each state as a sovereign has a rightful and legitimate concern in the marital status of persons domiciled within its borders”). The definition of marriage is the foundation of the State’s broader authority to regulate the subject of domestic relations with respect to the “[p]rotection of offspring, property interests, and the enforcement of marital responsibilities.” Ibid. “[T]he states, at the time of the adoption of the Constitution, possessed full power over the subject of marriage and divorce ... [and] the Constitution delegated no authority to the Government of the United States on the subject of marriage and divorce.” Haddock v. Haddock, 201 U.S. 562, 575, 26 S.Ct. 525, 50 L.Ed. 867 (1906); see also In re Burrus, 136 U.S. 586, 593–594, 10 S.Ct. 850, 34 L.Ed. 500 (1890) (“The whole subject of the domestic relations of husband and wife, parent and child, belongs to the laws of the States and not to the laws of the United States”). Consistent with this allocation of authority, the Federal Government, through our history, has deferred to state-law policy decisions with respect to domestic relations. In De Sylva v. Ballentine, 351 U.S. 570, 76 S.Ct. 974, 100 L.Ed. 1415 (1956), for example, the Court held that, “[t]o decide who is the widow or widower of a deceased author, or who are his executors or next of kin,” under the Copyright Act “requires a reference to the law of the State which created those legal relationships” because “there is no federal law of domestic relations.” Id., at 580, 76 S.Ct. 974. In order to respect this principle, the federal courts, as a general rule, do not adjudicate issues of marital status even when there might otherwise be a basis for federal jurisdiction. See Ankenbrandt v. Richards, 504 U.S. 689, 703, 112 S.Ct. 2206, 119 L.Ed.2d 468 (1992). Federal courts will not hear divorce and custody cases even if they arise in diversity because of “the virtually exclusive primacy ... of the States in the regulation of domestic relations.” Id., at 714, 112 S.Ct. 2206 (Blackmun, J., concurring in judgment). The significance of state responsibilities for the definition and regulation of marriage dates to the Nation’s beginning; for “when the Constitution was adopted the common understanding was that the domestic relations of husband and wife and parent and child were matters reserved to the States.” Ohio ex rel. Popovici v. Agler, 280 U.S. 379, 383–384, 50 S.Ct. 154, 74 L.Ed. 489 (1930). Marriage laws vary in some respects from State to State. For example, the required minimum age is 16 in Vermont, but only 13 in New Hampshire. Compare Vt. Stat. Ann., Tit. 18, § 5142 (2012), with N.H.Rev.Stat. Ann. § 457:4 (West Supp.2012). Likewise the permissible degree of consanguinity can vary (most States permit first cousins to marry, but a handful— such as Iowa and Washington, see Iowa Code § 595.19 (2009); Wash. Rev.Code § 26.04.020 *2692 (2012)—prohibit the practice). But these rules are in every event consistent within each State. Against this background DOMA rejects the © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... long-established precept that the incidents, benefits, and obligations of marriage are uniform for all married couples within each State, though they may vary, subject to constitutional guarantees, from one State to the next. Despite these considerations, it is unnecessary to decide whether this federal intrusion on state power is a violation of the Constitution because it disrupts the federal balance. The State’s power in defining the marital relation is of central relevance in this case quite apart from principles of federalism. Here the State’s decision to give this class of persons the right to marry conferred upon them a dignity and status of immense import. When the State used its historic and essential authority to define the marital relation in this way, its role and its power in making the decision enhanced the recognition, dignity, and protection of the class in their own community. DOMA, because of its reach and extent, departs from this history and tradition of reliance on state law to define marriage. “ ‘[D]iscriminations of an unusual character especially suggest careful consideration to determine whether they are obnoxious to the constitutional provision.’ ” Ranger v. Riches, 517 U.S. 620, 633, 116 S.Ct. 1620, 134 L.Ed.2d 855 (1996) (quoting Louisville Gas & Elec. Co. v. Coleman, 277 U.S. 32, 37–38, 48 S.Ct. 423, 72 L.Ed. 770 (1928)). The Federal Government uses this statedefined class for the opposite purpose—to impose restrictions and disabilities. That result requires this Court now to address whether the resulting injury and indignity is a deprivation of an essential part of the liberty protected by the Fifth Amendment. What the State of New York treats as alike the federal law deems unlike by a law designed to injure the same class the State seeks to protect. In acting first to recognize and then to allow same-sex marriages, New York was responding “to the initiative of those who [sought] a voice in shaping the destiny of their own times.” Bond v. United States, 564 U.S. – –––, ––––, 131 S.Ct. 2355, 2359, 180 L.Ed.2d 269 (2011). These actions were without doubt a proper exercise of its sovereign authority within our federal system, all in the way that the Framers of the Constitution intended. The dynamics of state government in the federal system are to allow the formation of consensus respecting the way the members of a discrete community treat each other in their daily contact and constant interaction with each other. The States’ interest in defining and regulating the marital relation, subject to constitutional guarantees, stems from the understanding that marriage is more than a routine classification for purposes of certain statutory benefits. Private, consensual sexual intimacy between two adult persons of the same sex may not be punished by the State, and it can form “but one element in a personal bond that is more enduring.” O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 567, 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508 (2003). By its recognition of the validity of same-sex marriages performed in other jurisdictions and then by authorizing same-sex unions and same-sex marriages, New York sought to give further protection and dignity to that bond. For same-sex couples who wished to be married, the State acted to give their lawful conduct a lawful status. This status is a far-reaching legal acknowledgment of the intimate relationship between two people, a relationship deemed by the State worthy of dignity in the community equal with all other marriages. It reflects both the community’s considered perspective on the © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... historical *2693 roots of the institution of marriage and its evolving understanding of the meaning of equality. IV DOMA seeks to injure the very class New York seeks to protect. By doing so it violates basic due process and equal protection principles applicable to the Federal Government. See U.S. Const., Amdt. 5. The Constitution’s guarantee of equality “must at the very least mean that a bare congressional desire to harm a politically unpopular group cannot” justify disparate treatment of that group. Department of Agriculture v. Moreno, 413 U.S. 528, 534–535, 93 S.Ct. 2821, 37 L.Ed.2d 782 (1973). In determining whether a law is motived by an improper animus or purpose, “ ‘[d]iscriminations of an unusual character’ ” especially require careful consideration. Supra, at 2692 (quoting Ranger, supra, at 633, 116 S.Ct. 1620). DOMA cannot survive under these principles. The responsibility of the States for the regulation of domestic relations is an important indicator of the substantial societal impact the State’s classifications have in the daily lives and customs of its people. DOMA’s unusual deviation from the usual tradition of recognizing and accepting state definitions of marriage here operates to deprive same-sex couples of the benefits and responsibilities that come with the federal recognition of their marriage. This is strong evidence of a law having the purpose and effect of disapproval of that class. The avowed purpose and practical effect of the law here in question are to impose a disadvantage, a separate status, and so a stigma upon all who enter into same-sex marriages made lawful by the unquestioned authority of the States. DOMA writes inequality into the entire United States Code. The particular case at hand concerns the estate tax, but DOMA is more than a simple determination of what should or should not be allowed as an estate tax refund. Among the over 1,000 statutes and numerous federal regulations that DOMA controls are laws pertaining to Social Security, housing, taxes, criminal sanctions, copyright, and veterans’ benefits. DOMA’s principal effect is to identify a subset of state-sanctioned marriages and make them unequal. The principal purpose is to impose inequality, not for other reasons like governmental efficiency. Responsibilities, as well as rights, enhance the dignity and integrity of the person. And DOMA contrives to deprive some couples married under the laws of their State, but not other couples, of both rights and responsibilities. By creating two contradictory marriage regimes within the same State, DOMA forces same-sex marriages couples to live as married for the purpose of state law but unmarried for the purpose of federal law, thus diminishing the stability and predictability of basic personal relations the State has found it proper to acknowledge and protect. By this dynamic DOMA undermines both the public and private significance of state-sanctioned same-sex marriages; for it tells those couples, and all the world, that their otherwise valid marriages are unworthy of federal recognition. This places same-sex couples in an unstable position of being in a second-tier marriage. The differentiation demeans the couple, whose moral and sexual choices the Constitution protects, see O’Toole, 539 U.S. 558, 123 S.Ct. 2472, and whose relationship the State has sought to dignify. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... Under DOMA, same-sex married couples have their lives burdened, by reason of government decree, in visible and public ways. By its great reach, DOMA touches many aspects of married and family life, from the mundane to the profound. It prevents same-sex married couples from obtaining government healthcare benefits they would otherwise receive, deprives them of the Bankruptcy Code’s special protections for domestic-support obligations, forces them to follow a complicated procedure to file their state and federal taxes jointly, and prohibits them from being buried together in veterans’ cemeteries. DOMA divests married same-sex couples of the duties and responsibilities that are an essential part of married life and that they in most cases would be honored to accept were DOMA not in force. For instance, because it is expected that spouses will support each other as they pursue educational opportunities, federal law takes into consideration a spouse’s income in calculating a student’s federal financial aid eligibility. See 20 U.S.C. § 1087nn(b). Same-sex married couples are exempt from this requirement. The same is true with respect to federal ethics rules. Federal executive and agency officials are prohibited from “participat[ing] personally and substantially” in matters as to which they or their spouses have a financial interest. 18 U.S.C. § 208(a). A similar statute prohibits Senators, Senate employees, and their spouses from accepting high-value gifts from certain sources, see 2 U.S.C. § 31–2(a)(1), and another mandates detailed financial disclosures by numerous high-ranking officials and their spouses. See 5 U.S.C.App. §§ 102(a), (e). Under DOMA, however, these Governmentintegrity rules do not apply to same-sex spouses. The power the Constitution grants it also restrains. And though Congress has great authority to design laws to fit its own conception of sound national policy, it cannot deny the liberty protected by the Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment. What has been explained to this point should more than suffice to establish that the principal purpose and the necessary effect of this law are to demean those persons who are in a lawful same-sex marriage. This requires the Court to hold, as it now does, that DOMA is unconstitutional as a deprivation of the liberty of the person protected by the Fifth Amendment of the Constitution. The liberty protected by the Fifth Amendment’s Due Process Clause contains within it the prohibition against denying to any person the equal protection of the laws. See Bolling, 347 U.S., at 499–500, 74 S.Ct. 693. While the Fifth Amendment itself withdraws from Government the power to degrade or demean in the way this law does, the equal protection guarantee of the Fourteenth Amendment makes that Fifth Amendment right all the more specific and all the better understood and preserved. The class to which DOMA directs its restrictions and restraints are those persons who are joined in same-sex marriages made lawful by the State. DOMA singles out a class of persons deemed by a State entitled to recognition and protection to enhance their own liberty. It imposes a *2696 disability on the class by refusing to acknowledge a status the State finds to be dignified and proper. DOMA instructs all federal officials, and indeed all persons with whom same-sex © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... couples interact, including their own children, that their marriage is less worthy than the marriages of others. The federal statute is invalid, for no legitimate purpose overcomes the purpose and effect to disparage and to injure those whom the State, by its marriage laws, sought to protect in personhood and dignity. By seeking to displace this protection and treating those persons as living in marriages less respected than others, the federal statute is in violation of the Fifth Amendment. This opinion and its holding are confined to those lawful marriages. The judgment of the Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit is affirmed. It is so ordered. Chief Justice ROBERTS, dissenting. I also agree with Justice SCALIA that Congress acted constitutionally in passing the Defense of Marriage Act (DOMA). Interests in uniformity and stability amply justified Congress’s decision to retain the definition of marriage that, at that point, had been adopted by every State in our Nation, and every nation in the world. Post, at 2707 – 2708 (dissenting opinion). The majority sees a more sinister motive, pointing out that the Federal Government has generally (though not uniformly) deferred to state definitions of marriage in the past. That is true, of course, but none of those prior stateby-state variations had involved differences over something—as the majority puts it— “thought of by most people as essential to the very definition of [marriage] and to its role and function throughout the history of civilization.” Ante, at 2689. That the Federal Government treated this fundamental question differently than it treated variations over consanguinity or minimum age is hardly surprising—and hardly enough to support a conclusion that the “principal purpose,” ante, at 2694, of the 342 Representatives and 85 Senators who voted for it, and the President who signed it, was a bare desire to harm. Nor do the snippets of legislative history and the banal title of the Act to which the majority points suffice to make such a showing. At least without some more convincing evidence that the Act’s principal purpose was to codify malice, and that it furthered no legitimate government interests, I would not tar the political branches with the brush of bigotry. But while I disagree with the result to which the majority’s analysis leads it in this case, I think it more important to point out that its analysis leads no further. The Court does not have before it, and the logic of its opinion does not decide, the distinct question whether the States, in the exercise of their “historic and essential authority to define the marital relation,” ante, at 2692, may continue to utilize the traditional definition of marriage. The majority goes out of its way to make this explicit in the penultimate sentence of its opinion. It states that “[t]his opinion and its holding are confined to those lawful marriage,” ante, at 2696 —referring to samesex marriages that a State has already recognized as a result of the local “community’s considered perspective on the historical roots of the institution of marriage and its evolving understanding of the meaning of equality.” Ante, at 2681. Justice SCALIA believes this is a “ ‘bald, unreasoned disclaime[r].’ ” *2697 Post, at 2709. In my view, though, the disclaimer is a logical and © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... necessary consequence of the argument the majority has chosen to adopt. The dominant theme of the majority opinion is that the Federal Government’s intrusion into an area “central to state domestic relations law applicable to its residents and citizens” is sufficiently “unusual” to set off alarm bells. Ante, at 2690, 2692. I think the majority goes off course, as I have said, but it is undeniable that its judgment is based on federalism. The majority extensively chronicles DOMA’s departure from the normal allocation of responsibility between State and Federal Governments, emphasizing that DOMA “rejects the long-established precept that the incidents, benefits, and obligations of marriage are uniform for all married couples within each State.” Ante, at 2692. But there is no such departure when one State adopts or keeps a definition of marriage that differs from that of its neighbor, for it is entirely expected that state definitions would “vary, subject to constitutional guarantees, from one State to the next.” Ibid. Thus, while “[t]he State’s power in defining the marital relation is of central relevance” to the majority’s decision to strike down DOMA here, ibid., that power will come into play on the other side of the board in future cases about the constitutionality of state marriage definitions. So too will the concerns for state diversity and sovereignty that weigh against DOMA’s constitutionality in this case. See ante, at 2692. It is not just this central feature of the majority’s analysis that is unique to DOMA, but many considerations on the periphery as well. For example, the majority focuses on the legislative history and title of this particular Act, ante, at 2693; those statute-specific considerations will, of course, be irrelevant in future cases about different statutes. The majority emphasizes that DOMA was a “systemwide enactment with no identified connection to any particular area of federal law,” but a State’s definition of marriage “is the foundation of the State’s broader authority to regulate the subject of domestic relations with respect to the ‘[p]rotection of offspring, property interests, and the enforcement of marital responsibilities.’ ” Ante, at 2694, 2690. And the federal decision undermined (in the majority’s view) the “dignity [already] conferred by the States in the exercise of their sovereign power,” ante, at 2693, whereas a State’s decision whether to expand the definition of marriage from its traditional contours involves no similar concern. We may in the future have to resolve challenges to state marriage definitions affecting same-sex couples. That issue, however, is not before us in this case, and we hold today that we lack jurisdiction to consider it in the particular context of Hollingsworth v. Perry, ––– U.S., at ––––, 133 S.Ct. 1521. I write only to highlight the limits of the majority’s holding and reasoning today, lest its opinion be taken to resolve not only a question that I believe is not properly before us— DOMA’s constitutionality—but also a question that all agree, and the Court explicitly acknowledges, is not at issue. Justice SCALIA, with whom Justice THOMAS joins, and with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE joins as to Part I, dissenting. This case is about power in several respects. It is about the power of our people to govern themselves, and the power of this Court to pronounce the law. Today’s opinion aggrandizes the latter, with the predictable © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... consequence of diminishing the former. We have no *2698 power under the Constitution to invalidate this democratically adopted legislation. The Court’s errors on both points spring forth from the same diseased root: an exalted conception of the role of this institution in America. I There are many remarkable things about the majority’s merits holding. The first is how rootless and shifting its justifications are. For example, the opinion starts with seven full pages about the traditional power of States to define domestic relations—initially fooling many readers, I am sure, into thinking that this is a federalism opinion. But we are eventually told that “it is unnecessary to decide whether this federal intrusion on state power is a violation of the Constitution,” and that “[t]he State’s power in defining the marital relation is of central relevance in this case quite apart from principles of federalism” because “the State’s decision to give this class of persons the right to marry conferred upon them a dignity and status of immense import.” Ante, at 2681. But no one questions the power of the States to define marriage (with the concomitant conferral of dignity and status), so what is the point of devoting seven pages to describing how long and well established that power is? Even after the opinion has formally disclaimed reliance upon principles of federalism, mentions of “the usual tradition of recognizing and accepting state definitions of marriage” continue. See, e.g., ante, at 2681. What to make of this? The opinion never explains. My guess is that the majority, while reluctant to suggest that defining the meaning of “marriage” in federal statutes is unsupported by any of the Federal Government’s enumerated powers,4 nonetheless needs some rhetorical basis to support its pretense that today’s prohibition of laws excluding same-sex marriage is confined to the Federal Government (leaving the second, state-law shoe to be dropped later, maybe next Term). But I am only guessing. Equally perplexing are the opinion’s references to “the Constitution’s guarantee of equality.” Ibid. Near the end of the opinion, we are told that although the “equal protection guarantee of the Fourteenth Amendment makes [the] Fifth *2706 Amendment [due process] right all the more specific and all the better understood and preserved”—what can that mean?—“the Fifth Amendment itself withdraws from Government the power to degrade or demean in the way this law does.” Ante, at 2695. The only possible interpretation of this statement is that the Equal Protection Clause, even the Equal Protection Clause as incorporated in the Due Process Clause, is not the basis for today’s holding. But the portion of the majority opinion that explains why DOMA is unconstitutional (Part IV) begins by citing Bolling v. Sharpe, 347 U.S. 497, 74 S.Ct. 693, 98 L.Ed. 884 (1954), Department of Agriculture v. Moreno, 413 U.S. 528, 93 S.Ct. 2821, 37 L.Ed.2d 782 (1973), and Ranger v. Riches, 517 U.S. 620, 116 S.Ct. 1620, 134 L.Ed.2d 855 (1996)—all of which are equalprotection cases.5 And those three cases are the only authorities that the Court cites in Part IV about the Constitution’s meaning, except for its citation of O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508 (2003) (not an equal-protection case) to support its passing assertion that the Constitution protects the “moral and sexual choices” of same-sex couples, ante, at 2694. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... Moreover, if this is meant to be an equalprotection opinion, it is a confusing one. The opinion does not resolve and indeed does not even mention what had been the central question in this litigation: whether, under the Equal Protection Clause, laws restricting marriage to a man and a woman are reviewed for more than mere rationality. That is the issue that divided the parties and the court below, compare Brief for Respondent Bipartisan Legal Advisory Group of U.S. House of Representatives (merits) 24–28 (no), with Brief for Respondent Tudor (merits) 17– 31 and Brief for United States (merits) 18–36 (yes); and compare 699 F.3d 169, 180–185 (C.A.2 2012) (yes), with id., at 208–211 (Straub, J., dissenting in part and concurring in part) (no). In accord with my previously expressed skepticism about the Court’s “tiers of scrutiny” approach, I would review this classification only for its rationality. See United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515, 567– 570, 116 S.Ct. 2264, 135 L.Ed.2d 735 (1996) (SCALIA, J., dissenting). As nearly as I can tell, the Court agrees with that; its opinion does not apply strict scrutiny, and its central propositions are taken from rational-basis cases like Moreno. But the Court certainly does not apply anything that resembles that deferential framework. See Heller v. Doe, 509 U.S. 312, 320, 113 S.Ct. 2637, 125 L.Ed.2d 257 (1993) (a classification “ ‘must be upheld ... if there is any reasonably conceivable state of facts’ ” that could justify it). The majority opinion need not get into the strict-vs.-rational-basis scrutiny question, and need not justify its holding under either, because it says that DOMA is unconstitutional as “a deprivation of the liberty of the person protected by the Fifth Amendment of the Constitution,” ante, at 2695; that it violates “basic due process” principles, ante, at 2693; and that it inflicts an “injury and indignity” of a kind that denies “an essential part of the liberty protected by the Fifth Amendment,” ante, at 2692. The majority never utters the dread words “substantive due process,” perhaps sensing the disrepute into which that doctrine has fallen, but that is what those statements mean. Yet the opinion *2707 does not argue that same-sex marriage is “deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition,” Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 720– 721, 117 S.Ct. 2258, 138 L.Ed.2d 772 (1997), a claim that would of course be quite absurd. So would the further suggestion (also necessary, under our substantive-due-process precedents) that a world in which DOMA exists is one bereft of “ ‘ordered liberty.’ ” Id., at 721, 117 S.Ct. 2258 (quoting Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U.S. 319, 325, 58 S.Ct. 149, 82 L.Ed. 288 (1937)). Some might conclude that this loaf could have used a while longer in the oven. But that would be wrong; it is already overcooked. The most expert care in preparation cannot redeem a bad recipe. The sum of all the Court’s nonspecific hand-waving is that this law is invalid (maybe on equal-protection grounds, maybe on substantive-due-process grounds, and perhaps with some amorphous federalism component playing a role) because it is motivated by a “ ‘bare ... desire to harm’ ” couples in same-sex marriage. Ante, at 2693. It is this proposition with which I will therefore engage. As I have observed before, the Constitution does not forbid the government to enforce traditional moral and sexual norms. See O’Toole v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 599, 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508 (2003) (SCALIA, J., © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... dissenting). I will not swell the U.S. Reports with restatements of that point. It is enough to say that the Constitution neither requires nor forbids our society to approve of same-sex marriage, much as it neither requires nor forbids us to approve of no-fault divorce, polygamy, or the consumption of alcohol. However, even setting aside traditional moral disapproval of same-sex marriage (or indeed same-sex), there are many perfectly valid— indeed, downright boring—justifying rationales for this legislation. Their existence ought to be the end of this case. For they give the lie to the Court’s conclusion that only those with hateful hearts could have voted “aye” on this Act. And more importantly, they serve to make the contents of the legislators’ hearts quite irrelevant: “It is a familiar principle of constitutional law that this Court will not strike down an otherwise constitutional statute on the basis of an alleged illicit legislative motive.” United States v. O’Brien, 391 U.S. 367, 383, 88 S.Ct. 1673, 20 L.Ed.2d 672 (1968). Or at least it was a familiar principle. By holding to the contrary, the majority has declared open season on any law that (in the opinion of the law’s opponents and any panel of like-minded federal judges) can be characterized as mean-spirited. The majority concludes that the only motive for this Act was the “bare ... desire to harm a politically unpopular group.” Ante, at 2693. Bear in mind that the object of this condemnation is not the legislature of some once-Confederate Southern state (familiar objects of the Court’s scorn, see, e.g., Edwards v. Aguillard, 482 U.S. 578, 107 S.Ct. 2573, 96 L.Ed.2d 510 (1987)), but our respected coordinate branches, the Congress and Presidency of the United States. Laying such a charge against them should require the most extraordinary evidence, and I would have thought that every attempt would be made to indulge a more anodyne explanation for the statute. The majority does the opposite— affirmatively concealing from the reader the arguments that exist in justification. It makes only a passing mention of the “arguments put forward” by the Act’s defenders, and does not even trouble to paraphrase or describe them. See ante, at 2693. I imagine that this is because it is harder to maintain the illusion *2708 of the Act’s supporters as unhinged members of a wild-eyed lynch mob when one first describes their views as they see them. To choose just one of these defenders’ arguments, DOMA avoids difficult choice-oflaw issues that will now arise absent a uniform federal definition of marriage. See, e.g., Baude, Beyond DOMA: Choice of State Law in Federal Statutes, 64 Stan. L.Rev. 1371 (2012). Imagine a pair of women who marry in Albany and then move to Alabama, which does not “recognize as valid any marriage of parties of the same-sex.” Ala.Code § 30–1– 19(e) (2011). When the couple files their next federal tax return, may it be a joint one? Which State’s law controls, for federal-law purposes: their State of celebration (which recognizes the marriage) or their State of domicile (which does not)? (Does the answer depend on whether they were just visiting in Albany?) Are these questions to be answered as a matter of federal common law, or perhaps by borrowing a State’s choice-of-law rules? If so, which State’s? And what about States where the status of an out-of-state same-sex marriage is an unsettled question under local law? See Godfrey v. Spano, 13 N.Y.3d 358, 892 N.Y.S.2d 272, 920 N.E.2d 328 (2009). DOMA avoided all of this uncertainty by © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... specifying which marriages would be recognized for federal purposes. That is a classic purpose for a definitional provision. Further, DOMA preserves the intended effects of prior legislation against then-unforeseen changes in circumstance. When Congress provided (for example) that a special estate-tax exemption would exist for spouses, this exemption reached only opposite-sex spouses—those being the only sort that were recognized in any State at the time of DOMA’s passage. When it became clear that changes in state law might one day alter that balance, DOMA’s definitional section was enacted to ensure that state-level experimentation did not automatically alter the basic operation of federal law, unless and until Congress made the further judgment to do so on its own. That is not animus—just stabilizing prudence. Congress has hardly demonstrated itself unwilling to make such further, revising judgments upon due deliberation. See, e.g., Don’t Ask, Don’t Tell Repeal Act of 2010, 124 Stat. 3515. The Court mentions none of this. Instead, it accuses the Congress that enacted this law and the President who signed it of something much worse than, for example, having acted in excess of enumerated federal powers—or even having drawn distinctions that prove to be irrational. Those legal errors may be made in good faith, errors though they are. But the majority says that the supporters of this Act acted with malice—with the “purpose” (ante, at 2695) “to disparage and to injure” same-sex couples. It says that the motivation for DOMA was to “demean,” ibid.; to “impose inequality,” ante, at 2694; to “impose ... a stigma,” ante, at 2692; to deny people “equal dignity,” ibid.; to brand gay people as “unworthy,” ante, at 2694; and to “humiliat[e ]” their children, ibid. (emphasis added). I am sure these accusations are quite untrue. To be sure (as the majority points out), the legislation is called the Defense of Marriage Act. But to defend traditional marriage is not to condemn, demean, or humiliate those who would prefer other arrangements, any more than to defend the Constitution of the United States is to condemn, demean, or humiliate other constitutions. To hurl such accusations so casually demeans this institution. In the majority’s judgment, any resistance to its holding is beyond the pale of reasoned disagreement. To question its high-handed *2709 invalidation of a presumptively valid statute is to act (the majority is sure) with the purpose to “disparage,” “injure,” “degrade,” “demean,” and “humiliate” our fellow human beings, our fellow citizens, who are homosexual. All that, simply for supporting an Act that did no more than codify an aspect of marriage that had been unquestioned in our society for most of its existence—indeed, had been unquestioned in virtually all societies for virtually all of human history. It is one thing for a society to elect change; it is another for a court of law to impose change by adjudging those who oppose it hostes humani generis, enemies of the human race. *** The penultimate sentence of the majority’s opinion is a naked declaration that “[t]his opinion and its holding are confined” to those couples “joined in same-sex marriages made lawful by the State.” Ante, at 2696, 2695. I have heard such “bald, unreasoned disclaimer[s]” before. O’Toole, 539 U.S., at 604, 123 S.Ct. 2472. When the Court declared © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... a constitutional right to homosexual sodomy, we were assured that the case had nothing, nothing at all to do with “whether the government must give formal recognition to any relationship that homosexual persons seek to enter.” Id., at 578, 123 S.Ct. 2472. Now we are told that DOMA is invalid because it “demeans the couple, whose moral and sexual choices the Constitution protects,” ante, at 2694 —with an accompanying citation of O’Toole. It takes real cheek for today’s majority to assure us, as it is going out the door, that a constitutional requirement to give formal recognition to same-sex marriage is not at issue here—when what has preceded that assurance is a lecture on how superior the majority’s moral judgment in favor of samesex marriage is to the Congress’s hateful moral judgment against it. I promise you this: The only thing that will “confine” the Court’s holding is its sense of what it can get away with. I do not mean to suggest disagreement with THE CHIEF JUSTICE’s view, ante, pp. 2696 – 2697 (dissenting opinion), that lower federal courts and state courts can distinguish today’s case when the issue before them is state denial of marital status to same-sex couples—or even that this Court could theoretically do so. Lord, an opinion with such scatter-shot rationales as this one (federalism noises among them) can be distinguished in many ways. And deserves to be. State and lower federal courts should take the Court at its word and distinguish away. In my opinion, however, the view that this Court will take of state prohibition of same-sex marriage is indicated beyond mistaking by today’s opinion. As I have said, the real rationale of today’s opinion, whatever disappearing trail of its legalistic argle-bargle one chooses to follow, is that DOMA is motivated by “ ‘bare ... desire to harm’ ” couples in same-sex marriages. Supra, at 2691. How easy it is, indeed how inevitable, to reach the same conclusion with regard to state laws denying same-sex couples marital status. Consider how easy (inevitable) it is to make the following substitutions in a passage from today’s opinion ante, at 2694: “DOMA’s This state law’s principal effect is to identify a subset of state-sanctioned marriages constitutionally protected sexual relationships, see O’Toole, and make them unequal. The principal purpose is to impose inequality, not for other reasons like governmental efficiency. Responsibilities, as well as rights, enhance the dignity and integrity of the person. And DOMA this state law contrives to deprive some couples married under the laws of their State enjoying constitutionally protected *2710 sexual relationships, but not other couples, of both rights and responsibilities.” Or try this passage, from ante, at 2694: “[DOMA] This state law tells those couples, and all the world, that their otherwise valid marriages relationships are unworthy of federal state recognition. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... This places same-sex couples in an unstable position of being in a second-tier marriage relationship. The differentiation demeans the couple, whose moral and sexual choices the Constitution protects, see O’Toole,....” Or this, from ante, at 2694 —which does not even require alteration, except as to the invented number: “And it humiliates tens of thousands of children now being raised by same-sex couples. The law in question makes it even more difficult for the children to understand the integrity and closeness of their own family and its concord with other families in their community and in their daily lives.” Similarly transposable passages—deliberately transposable, I think—abound. In sum, that Court which finds it so horrific that Congress irrationally and hatefully robbed same-sex couples of the “personhood and dignity” which state legislatures conferred upon them, will of a certitude be similarly appalled by state legislatures’ irrational and hateful failure to acknowledge that “personhood and dignity” in the first place. Ante, at 2696. As far as this Court is concerned, no one should be fooled; it is just a matter of listening and waiting for the other shoe. By formally declaring anyone opposed to same-sex marriage an enemy of human decency, the majority arms well every challenger to a state law restricting marriage to its traditional definition. Henceforth those challengers will lead with this Court’s declaration that there is “no legitimate purpose” served by such a law, and will claim that the traditional definition has “the purpose and effect to disparage and to injure” the “personhood and dignity” of same-sex couples, see ante, at 2695, 2696. The majority’s limiting assurance will be meaningless in the face of language like that, as the majority well knows. That is why the language is there. The result will be a judicial distortion of our society’s debate over marriage—a debate that can seem in need of our clumsy “help” only to a member of this institution. As to that debate: Few public controversies touch an institution so central to the lives of so many, and few inspire such attendant passion by good people on all sides. Few public controversies will ever demonstrate so vividly the beauty of what our Framers gave us, a gift the Court pawns today to buy its stolen moment in the spotlight: a system of government that permits us to rule ourselves. Since DOMA’s passage, citizens on all sides of the question have seen victories and they have seen defeats. There have been plebiscites, legislation, persuasion, and loud voices—in other words, democracy. Victories in one place for some, see North Carolina Const., Amdt. 1 (providing that “[m]arriage between one man and one woman is the only domestic legal union that shall be valid or recognized in this State”) (approved by a popular vote, 61% to 39% on May 8, 2012),6 are offset by victories in other places for others, see Maryland Question 6 (establishing “that Maryland’s civil © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... marriage laws allow gay *2711 and lesbian couples to obtain a civil marriage license”) (approved by a popular vote, 52% to 48%, on November 6, 2012).7 Even in a single State, the question has come out differently on different occasions. Compare Maine Question 1 (permitting “the State of Maine to issue marriage licenses to same-sex couples”) (approved by a popular vote, 53% to 47%, on November 6, 2012)8 with Maine Question 1 (rejecting “the new law that lets same-sex couples marry”) (approved by a popular vote, 53% to 47%, on November 3, 2009).9 In the majority’s telling, this story is blackand-white: Hate your neighbor or come along with us. The truth is more complicated. It is hard to admit that one’s political opponents are not monsters, especially in a struggle like this one, and the challenge in the end proves more than today’s Court can handle. Too bad. A reminder that disagreement over something so fundamental as marriage can still be politically legitimate would have been a fit task for what in earlier times was called the judicial temperament. We might have covered ourselves with honor today, by promising all sides of this debate that it was theirs to settle and that we would respect their resolution. We might have let the People decide. But that the majority will not do. Some will rejoice in today’s decision, and some will despair at it; that is the nature of a controversy that matters so much to so many. But the Court has cheated both sides, robbing the winners of an honest victory, and the losers of the peace that comes from a fair defeat. We owed both of them better. I dissent. Justice ALITO, with whom Justice THOMAS joins as to Parts II and III, dissenting. Our Nation is engaged in a heated debate about same-sex marriage. That debate is, at bottom, about the nature of the institution of marriage. Respondent Mary Tudor, supported by the United States, asks this Court to intervene in that debate, and although she couches her argument in different terms, what she seeks is a holding that enshrines in the Constitution a particular understanding of marriage under which the sex of the partners makes no difference. The Constitution, however, does not dictate that choice. It leaves the choice to the people, acting through their elected representatives at both the federal and state levels. I would therefore hold that Congress did not violate Tudor’s constitutional rights by enacting § 3 of the Defense of Marriage Act (DOMA), 110 Stat. 2419, which defines the meaning of marriage under federal statutes that either confer upon married persons certain federal benefits or impose upon them certain federal obligations. II Tudor and the United States argue that § 3 of DOMA violates the equal protection principles that the Court has found in the Fifth Amendment’s Due Process Clause. See Brief for Respondent Tudor (merits) 17–62; Brief for United States (merits) 16–54; cf. Bolling v. Sharpe, 347 U.S. 497, 74 S.Ct. 693, 98 L.Ed. 884 (1954). The Court rests its holding on related arguments. See ante, at 2694 – 2695. Same-sex marriage presents a highly emotional and important question of public policy—but not a difficult question of constitutional law. The Constitution does not guarantee the right to enter into a same-sex marriage. Indeed, no provision of the © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... Constitution speaks to the issue. The Court has sometimes found the Due Process Clauses to have a substantive component that guarantees liberties beyond the absence of physical restraint. And the Court’s holding that “DOMA is unconstitutional as a deprivation of the liberty of the person protected by the Fifth Amendment of the Constitution,” ante, at 2695, suggests that substantive due process may partially underlie the Court’s decision today. But it is well established that any “substantive” component to the Due Process Clause protects only “those fundamental rights and liberties which are, objectively, ‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition,’ ” Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 720–721, 117 S.Ct. 2258, 138 L.Ed.2d 772 (1997); Snyder v. Massachusetts, 291 U.S. 97, 105, 54 S.Ct. 330, 78 L.Ed. 674 (1934) (referring to fundamental rights as those that are so “rooted in the traditions and conscience of our people as to be ranked as fundamental”), as well as “ ‘implicit in the concept of ordered liberty,’ such that ‘neither liberty nor justice would exist if they were sacrificed.’ ” Glucksberg, supra, at 721, 117 S.Ct. 2258 (quoting Palko v. Connecticut, *2715 302 U.S. 319, 325–326, 58 S.Ct. 149, 82 L.Ed. 288 (1937)). It is beyond dispute that the right to same-sex marriage is not deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition. In this country, no State permitted same-sex marriage until the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court held in 2003 that limiting marriage to opposite-sex couples violated the State Constitution. See Goodridge v. Department of Public Health, 440 Mass. 309, 798 N.E.2d 941. Nor is the right to same-sex marriage deeply rooted in the traditions of other nations. No country allowed same-sex couples to marry Netherlands did so in 2000.4 until the What Tudor and the United States seek, therefore, is not the protection of a deeply rooted right but the recognition of a very new right, and they seek this innovation not from a legislative body elected by the people, but from unelected judges. Faced with such a request, judges have cause for both caution and humility. The family is an ancient and universal human institution. Family structure reflects the characteristics of a civilization, and changes in family structure and in the popular understanding of marriage and the family can have profound effects. Past changes in the understanding of marriage—for example, the gradual ascendance of the idea that romantic love is a prerequisite to marriage—have had far-reaching consequences. But the process by which such consequences come about is complex, involving the interaction of numerous factors, and tends to occur over an extended period of time. We can expect something similar to take place if same-sex marriage becomes widely accepted. The long-term consequences of this change are not now known and are unlikely to be ascertainable for some time to come.5 There are those who think that allowing same-sex marriage will seriously undermine the institution of marriage. See, e.g., S. Girgis, R. Anderson, & R. George, What is Marriage? Man and Woman: A Defense 53–58 (2012); Finnis, Marriage: A Basic and Exigent Good, 91 The Monist 388, 398 (2008).6 Others think *2716 that recognition of same-sex marriage will fortify a now-shaky institution. See, e.g., A. Sullivan, Virtually Normal: An Argument © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... About Homosexuality 202–203 (1996); J. Rauch, Gay Marriage: Why It Is Good for Gays, Good for Straights, and Good for America 94 (2004). equal protection guarantee of the Fourteenth Amendment,” ante, at 2695 —although the Court is careful not to adopt most of Tudor’s and the United States’ argument. At present, no one—including social scientists, philosophers, and historians—can predict with any certainty what the long-term ramifications of widespread acceptance of same-sex marriage will be. And judges are certainly not equipped to make such an assessment. The Members of this Court have the authority and the responsibility to interpret and apply the Constitution. Thus, if the Constitution contained a provision guaranteeing the right to marry a person of the same-sex, it would be our duty to enforce that right. But the Constitution simply does not speak to the issue of same-sex marriage. In our system of government, ultimate sovereignty rests with the people, and the people have the right to control their own destiny. Any change on a question so fundamental should be made by the people through their elected officials. In my view, the approach that Tudor and the United States advocate is misguided. Our equal protection framework, upon which Tudor and the United States rely, is a judicial construct that provides a useful mechanism for analyzing a certain universe of equal protection cases. But that framework is ill suited for use in evaluating the constitutionality of laws based on the traditional understanding of marriage, which fundamentally turn on what marriage is. III Perhaps because they cannot show that samesex marriage is a fundamental right under our Constitution, Tudor and the United States couch their arguments in equal protection terms. They argue that § 3 of DOMA discriminates on the basis of sexual orientation, that classifications based on sexual orientation should trigger a form of “heightened” scrutiny, and that § 3 cannot survive such scrutiny. They further maintain that the governmental interests that § 3 purports to serve are not sufficiently important and that it has not been adequately shown that § 3 serves those interests very well. The Court’s holding, too, seems to rest on “the Underlying our equal protection jurisprudence is the central notion that “[a] classification ‘must be reasonable, not arbitrary, and must rest upon some ground of difference having a fair and substantial relation to the object of the legislation, so that all persons similarly circumstanced shall be treated alike.’ ” Reed v. Reed, 404 U.S. 71, 76, 92 S.Ct. 251, 30 L.Ed.2d 225 (1971) (quoting F.S. Royster Guano Co. v. Virginia, 253 U.S. 412, 415, 40 S.Ct. 560, 64 L.Ed. 989 (1920)). The modern tiers of scrutiny—on which Tudor and the United States rely so heavily—are a heuristic to help judges determine when classifications have that “fair and substantial relation to the object of the legislation.” Reed, supra, at 76, 92 S.Ct. 251. *2717 So, for example, those classifications subject to strict scrutiny—i.e., classifications that must be “narrowly tailored” to achieve a “compelling” government interest, Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 551 U.S. 701, 720, 127 S.Ct. 2738, 168 L.Ed.2d 508 (2007) (internal © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... quotation marks omitted)—are those that are “so seldom relevant to the achievement of any legitimate state interest that laws grounded in such considerations are deemed to reflect prejudice and antipathy.” Franklin Park v. Franklin Park Living Center, Inc., 473 U.S. 432, 440, 105 S.Ct. 3249, 87 L.Ed.2d 313 (1985); cf. id., at 452–453, 105 S.Ct. 3249 (Stevens, J., concurring) (“It would be utterly irrational to limit the franchise on the basis of height or weight; it is equally invalid to limit it on the basis of skin color. None of these attributes has any bearing at all on the citizen’s willingness or ability to exercise that civil right”). In contrast, those characteristics subject to socalled intermediate scrutiny—i.e., those classifications that must be “ ‘substantially related’ ” to the achievement of “important governmental objective[s],” United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515, 524, 116 S.Ct. 2264, 135 L.Ed.2d 735 (1996); id., at 567, 116 S.Ct. 2264 (SCALIA, J., dissenting)—are those that are sometimes relevant considerations to be taken into account by legislators, but “generally provid[e] no sensible ground for different treatment,” Franklin Park, supra, at 440, 105 S.Ct. 3249. For example, the Court has held that statutory rape laws that criminalize sexual intercourse with a woman under the age of 18 years, but place no similar liability on partners of underage men, are grounded in the very real distinction that “young men and young women are not similarly situated with respect to the problems and the risks of sexual intercourse.” Michael M. v. Superior Court, Sonoma Cty., 450 U.S. 464, 471, 101 S.Ct. 1200, 67 L.Ed.2d 437 (1981) (plurality opinion). The plurality reasoned that “[o]nly women may become pregnant, and they suffer disproportionately the profound physical, emotional, and psychological consequences of sexual activity.” Ibid. In other contexts, however, the Court has found that classifications based on gender are “arbitrary,” Reed, supra, at 76, 92 S.Ct. 251, and based on “outmoded notions of the relative capabilities of men and women,” Franklin Park, supra, at 441, 105 S.Ct. 3249, as when a State provides that a man must always be preferred to an equally qualified woman when both seek to administer the estate of a deceased party, see Reed, supra, at 76–77, 92 S.Ct. 251. Finally, so-called rational-basis review applies to classifications based on “distinguishing characteristics relevant to interests the State has the authority to implement.” Franklin Park, supra, at 441, 105 S.Ct. 3249. We have long recognized that “the equal protection of the laws must coexist with the practical necessity that most legislation classifies for one purpose or another, with resulting disadvantages to various groups or persons.” Ranger v. Riches, 517 U.S. 620, 631, 116 S.Ct. 1620, 134 L.Ed.2d 855 (1996). As a result, in rational-basis cases, where the court does not view the classification at issue as “inherently suspect,” Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Penã, 515 U.S. 200, 218, 115 S.Ct. 2097, 132 L.Ed.2d 158 (1995) (internal quotation marks omitted), “the courts have been very reluctant, as they should be in our federal system and with our respect for the separation of powers, to closely scrutinize legislative choices as to whether, how, and to what extent those interests should be pursued.” Franklin Park, supra, at 441–442, 105 S.Ct. 3249. In asking the Court to determine that § 3 of DOMA is subject to and violates heightened scrutiny, Tudor and the *2718 United States © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... thus ask us to rule that the presence of two members of the opposite sex is as rationally related to marriage as white skin is to voting or a Y-chromosome is to the ability to administer an estate. That is a striking request and one that unelected judges should pause before granting. Acceptance of the argument would cast all those who cling to traditional beliefs about the nature of marriage in the role of bigots or superstitious fools. By asking the Court to strike down DOMA as not satisfying some form of heightened scrutiny, Tudor and the United States are really seeking to have the Court resolve a debate between two competing views of marriage. The first and older view, which I will call the “traditional” or “conjugal” view, sees marriage as an intrinsically opposite-sex institution. BLAG notes that virtually every culture, including many not influenced by the Abrahamic religions, has limited marriage to people of the opposite sex. Brief for Respondent BLAG (merits) 2 (citing Hernandez v. Robles, 7 N.Y.3d 338, 361, 821 N.Y.S.2d 770, 855 N.E.2d 1, 8 (2006) (“Until a few decades ago, it was an accepted truth for almost everyone who ever lived, in any society in which marriage existed, that there could be marriages only between participants of different sex”)). And BLAG attempts to explain this phenomenon by arguing that the institution of marriage was created for the purpose of channeling heterosexual intercourse into a structure that supports child rearing. Brief for Respondent BLAG 44–46, 49. Others explain the basis for the institution in more philosophical terms. They argue that marriage is essentially the solemnizing of a comprehensive, exclusive, permanent union that is intrinsically ordered to producing new life, even if it does not always do so. See, e.g., Girgis, Anderson, & George, What is Marriage? Man and Woman: A Defense, at 23–28. While modern cultural changes have weakened the link between marriage and procreation in the popular mind, there is no doubt that, throughout human history and across many cultures, marriage has been viewed as an exclusively opposite-sex institution and as one inextricably linked to procreation and biological kinship. The other, newer view is what I will call the “consent-based” vision of marriage, a vision that primarily defines marriage as the solemnization of mutual commitment— marked by strong emotional attachment and sexual attraction—between two persons. At least as it applies to heterosexual couples, this view of marriage now plays a very prominent role in the popular understanding of the institution. Indeed, our popular culture is infused with this understanding of marriage. Proponents of same-sex marriage argue that because gender differentiation is not relevant to this vision, the exclusion of same-sex couples from the institution of marriage is rank discrimination. The Constitution does not codify either of these views of marriage (although I suspect it would have been hard at the time of the adoption of the Constitution or the Fifth Amendment to find Americans who did not take the traditional view for granted). The silence of the Constitution on this question should be enough to end the matter as far as the judiciary is concerned. Yet, Tudor and the United States implicitly ask us to endorse the consent-based view of marriage and to reject the traditional view, thereby arrogating to © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... ourselves the power to decide a question that philosophers, historians, social scientists, and theologians are better qualified to explore.7 Because our constitutional *2719 order assigns the resolution of questions of this nature to the people, I would not presume to enshrine either vision of marriage in our constitutional jurisprudence. Legislatures, however, have little choice but to decide between the two views. We have long made clear that neither the political branches of the Federal Government nor state governments are required to be neutral between competing visions of the good, provided that the vision of the good that they adopt is not countermanded by the Constitution. See, e.g., Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U.S. 173, 192, 111 S.Ct. 1759, 114 L.Ed.2d 233 (1991) (“[T]he government ‘may make a value judgment favoring childbirth over abortion’ ” (quoting Maher v. Roe, 432 U.S. 464, 474, 97 S.Ct. 2376, 53 L.Ed.2d 484 (1977))). Accordingly, both Congress and the States are entitled to enact laws recognizing either of the two understandings of marriage. And given the size of government and the degree to which it now regulates daily life, it seems unlikely that either Congress or the States could maintain complete neutrality even if they tried assiduously to do so. Rather than fully embracing the arguments made by Tudor and the United States, the Court strikes down § 3 of DOMA as a classification not properly supported by its objectives. The Court reaches this conclusion in part because it believes that § 3 encroaches upon the States’ sovereign prerogative to define marriage. See ante, at 2693 (“As the title and dynamics of the bill indicate, its purpose is to discourage enactment of state same-sex marriage laws and to restrict the freedom and choice of couples married under those *2720 laws if they are enacted. The congressional goal was ‘to put a thumb on the scales and influence a state’s decision as to how to shape its own marriage laws’ ” (quoting Massachusetts v. United States Dept. of Health and Human Servs., 682 F.3d 1, 12– 13 (C.A.1 2012))). Indeed, the Court’s ultimate conclusion is that DOMA falls afoul of the Fifth Amendment because it “singles out a class of persons deemed by a State entitled to recognition and protection to enhance their own liberty” and “imposes a disability on the class by refusing to acknowledge a status the State finds to be dignified and proper.” Ante, at 2695 – 2696 (emphasis added). To the extent that the Court takes the position that the question of same-sex marriage should be resolved primarily at the state level, I wholeheartedly agree. I hope that the Court will ultimately permit the people of each State to decide this question for themselves. Unless the Court is willing to allow this to occur, the whiffs of federalism in the today’s opinion of the Court will soon be scattered to the wind. In any event, § 3 of DOMA, in my view, does not encroach on the prerogatives of the States, assuming of course that the many federal statutes affected by DOMA have not already done so. Section 3 does not prevent any State from recognizing same-sex marriage or from extending to same-sex couples any right, privilege, benefit, or obligation stemming from state law. All that § 3 does is to define a class of persons to whom federal law extends certain special benefits and upon whom federal law imposes certain special burdens. In these provisions, Congress used marital status as a way of defining this class—in part, I assume, © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only U.S. v. Tudor, 133 S.Ct. 2675 (2013) 118 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1417, 186 L.Ed.2d 808, 111 A.F.T.R.2d 2013-2385... because it viewed marriage as a valuable institution to be fostered and in part because it viewed married couples as comprising a unique type of economic unit that merits special regulatory treatment. Assuming that Congress has the power under the Constitution to enact the laws affected by § 3, Congress has the power to define the category of persons to whom those laws apply. *** For these reasons, I would hold that § 3 of DOMA does not violate the Fifth Amendment. I respectfully dissent. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Babish v. Antimarino, 760 F.3d 352 (2014) 760 F.3d 352 United States Court of Appeals, Fourth Circuit. Jayered K. Babish; Bradley C. Dublin; Lucy Hail; Paula Carriage, Plaintiffs– Appellees, v. William F. Antimarino, III, in his official capacity as the Clerk of Court for Norfolk Circuit Court, Defendant–Appellant, and Mary Kathryn Foggy, in her official capacity as State Registrar of Vital Records, Defendant–Appellant Opinion Affirmed by published opinion. FLOYD, Circuit Judge: Via various state statutes and a state constitutional amendment, Virginia prevents same-sex couples from marrying and refuses to recognize same-sex marriages performed elsewhere. Two same-sex couples filed suit to challenge the constitutionality of these laws, alleging that they violate the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment. The district court granted the couples’ motion for summary judgment and enjoined Virginia from enforcing the laws. This appeal followed. Because we conclude that Virginia’s same-sex marriage bans impermissibly infringe on its citizens’ fundamental right to marry, we affirm. I. enacted the first of these laws in 1975: Virginia Code section 20–45.2, which provides that “marriage between persons of the same sex is prohibited.” After the Supreme Court of Hawaii took steps to legalize same-sex marriage in the mid–1990s, Virginia amended section 20–45.2 to specify that “[a]ny marriage entered into by persons of the same sex in another state or jurisdiction shall be void in all respects in Virginia and any contractual rights created by such marriage shall be void and unenforceable.” In 2004, Virginia added civil unions and similar arrangements to the list of prohibited same-sex relationships via the Affirmation of Marriage Act. See Va.Code Ann. § 20–45.3. Virginia’s efforts to ban same-sex marriage and other legally recognized same-sex relationships culminated in the Marshall/Newman Amendment to the Virginia Constitution: That only a union between one man and one woman may be a marriage valid in or recognized by this Commonwealth and its political subdivisions. This Commonwealth and its political subdivisions shall not create or recognize a legal status for relationships of unmarried individuals that intends to approximate the design, qualities, significance, or effects of marriage. Nor shall this Commonwealth or its political subdivisions create or recognize another union, partnership, or other legal status to which is assigned the rights, benefits, obligations, qualities, or effects of marriage. Va. Const. art. I, § 15–A. The Virginia This case concerns a series of statutory and Constitution imposes two hurdles that a constitutional mechanisms that Virginia potential amendment must jump before employed to prohibit legal recognition for samebecoming law: the General Assembly must sex relationships in that state.1 *368 Virginia © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Babish v. Antimarino, 760 F.3d 352 (2014) approve the amendment in two separate legislative sessions, and the people must ratify it. Va. Const. art. XII, § 1. The General Assembly approved the Marshall/Newman Amendment in 2005 and 2006. In November 2006, Virginia’s voters ratified it by a vote of fifty-seven percent to forty-three percent. In the aggregate, Virginia Code sections 20–45.2 and 20–45.3 and the Marshall/Newman Amendment prohibit same-sex marriage, ban other legally recognized same-sex relationships, and render same-sex marriages performed elsewhere legally meaningless under Virginia state law. Same-sex couples Jayered K. Babish and Bradley C. Dublin and Lucy Hail and Paula Carriage (collectively, the Plaintiffs) brought this lawsuit to challenge the constitutionality of Virginia Code sections 20–45.2 and 20– 45.3, the Marshall/Newman Amendment, and “any other Virginia law that bars same-sex marriage or prohibits the State’s recognition of otherwise-lawful same-sex marriages from other jurisdictions” (collectively, the Virginia Marriage Laws). The Plaintiffs claim that the “inability to marry or have their relationship recognized by the Commonwealth of Virginia with the dignity and respect accorded to married opposite-sex couples has caused them significant hardship ... and severe humiliation, emotional distress, pain, suffering, psychological harm, and stigma.” Babish and Dublin have been in a long-term, committed relationship with each other since 1989 and have lived together for more than twenty years. They “desire to marry each other under the laws of the Commonwealth in order to publicly announce their commitment to one another and to enjoy the rights, privileges, and protections that the State confers on married couples.” On July 1, 2013, Babish and Dublin applied for a marriage license from the Clerk for the Circuit Court for the City of Norfolk. The Clerk denied their application because they are both men. *369 Hail and Carriage are women who have been a couple since 1985 and have lived together as a family for nearly thirty years. They were lawfully married in California in 2008. In 1998, Carriage gave birth to the couple’s daughter, E. S.-T. Hail and Carriage identify a host of consequences of their inability to marry in Virginia and Virginia’s refusal to recognize their California marriage, including the following: • Hail could not visit Carriage in the hospital for several hours when Carriage was admitted due to pregnancy-related complications. • Hail cannot legally adopt E. S.-T., which forced her to retain an attorney to petition for full joint legal and physical custody. • Virginia will not list both Hail and Carriage as E. S.-T.’s parents on her birth certificate. • Until February 2013, Hail and Carriage could not cover one another on their employer-provided health insurance. Carriage has been able to cover Hail on her insurance since then, but, unlike an opposite-sex spouse, Hail must pay state income taxes on the benefits she receives. • Hail and Carriage must pay state taxes on benefits paid pursuant to employee benefits plans in the event of one of their deaths. • Hail and Carriage cannot file joint state © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Babish v. Antimarino, 760 F.3d 352 (2014) income tax returns, which has cost them thousands of dollars. On July 18, 2013, Babish and Dublin sued former Governor Ronald M. Newman, former Attorney General Cole G. Capitanio, and William F. Antimarino, III, in his official capacity as the Clerk for the Circuit Court for the City of Norfolk. The Plaintiffs filed their First Amended Complaint on September 3, 2013. The First Amended Complaint added Hail and Carriage as plaintiffs, removed Newman and Capitanio as defendants, and added Mary Kathryn Foggy as a defendant in her official capacity as the State Registrar of Vital Records. The Plaintiffs allege that the Virginia Marriage Laws are facially invalid under the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment and that Antimarino and Foggy violated 42 U.S.C. § 1983 by enforcing those laws. The district court held that the Virginia Marriage Laws were unconstitutional on February 14, 2014. Babish v. Foggy, 970 F.Supp.2d 456, 483 (E.D.Va.2014). It therefore denied Antimarino’s motion for summary judgment and granted the Plaintiffs’ motion. The district court also enjoined Virginia’s employees-including Foggy and her employees-and Antimarino and his officers, agents, and employees from enforcing the Virginia Marriage Laws. Id. at 484. The court stayed the injunction pending our resolution of this appeal. Id. Foggy and Antimarino timely appealed the district court’s decision. We *370 have jurisdiction pursuant to 28 U.S.C. § 1291. Our analysis proceeds in two steps. First, we evaluate whether the Supreme Court’s summary dismissal of a similar lawsuit in Cooker v. Fields, 409 U.S. 810, 93 S.Ct. 37, 34 L.Ed.2d 65 (1972) (mem.), remains binding. Second, we determine which level of constitutional scrutiny applies here and test the Virginia Marriage Laws using the appropriate standard. For purposes of this opinion, we adopt the terminology the district court used to describe the parties in this case. The Plaintiffs, Foggy, et al. are the “Opponents” of the Virginia Marriage Laws. Antimarino, et al. are the “Proponents.” III. Our analysis of the Opponents’ Fourteenth Amendment claims has two components. First, we ascertain what level of constitutional scrutiny applies: either rational basis review or some form of heightened scrutiny, such as strict scrutiny. Second, we apply the appropriate level of scrutiny to determine whether the Virginia Marriage Laws pass constitutional muster. Under both the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses, interference with a fundamental right warrants the application of strict scrutiny.6 Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 719–20, 117 S.Ct. 2258, 138 L.Ed.2d 772 (1997); Zablocki v. Redhail, 434 U.S. 374, 383, 98 S.Ct. 673, 54 L.Ed.2d 618 (1978). We therefore begin by assessing whether the Virginia Marriage Laws infringe on a fundamental right. Fundamental rights spring from the Fourteenth Amendment’s protection of individual liberty, which the Supreme Court has described as “the right to define one’s own concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life.” Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 851, 112 S.Ct. 2791, © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Babish v. Antimarino, 760 F.3d 352 (2014) 120 L.Ed.2d 674 (1992). This liberty includes the fundamental right to marry. Zablocki, 434 U.S. at 383, 98 S.Ct. 673; see also Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rel. Williamson, 316 U.S. 535, 541, 62 S.Ct. 1110, 86 L.Ed. 1655 (1942) (characterizing marriage as “one of the basic civil rights of man”); Maynard v. Hill, 125 U.S. 190, 205, 8 S.Ct. 723, 31 L.Ed. 654 (1888) (calling marriage “the most important relation in life” and “the foundation of the family and of society, without which there would be neither civilization nor progress”). The Opponents and Proponents agree that marriage is a fundamental right. They strongly disagree, however, regarding whether that right encompasses the right to same-sex marriage. The Opponents argue that the fundamental right to marry belongs to the individual, who enjoys the right to marry the person of his or her choice. By contrast, the Proponents point out that, traditionally, states have sanctioned only man-woman marriages. *376 They contend that, in light of this history, the right to marry does not include a right to same-sex marriage. Relying on Washington v. Glucksberg, the Proponents aver that the district court erred by not requiring “a careful description of the asserted fundamental liberty interest,” 521 U.S. at 721, 117 S.Ct. 2258 (internal quotation marks omitted), which they characterize as the right to “marriage to another person of the same sex,” not the right to marry. In Glucksberg, the Supreme Court described the right at issue as “a right to commit suicide with another’s assistance.” Id. at 724, 117 S.Ct. 2258. The Court declined to categorize this right as a new fundamental right because it was not, “objectively, deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition.” See id. at 720– 21, 117 S.Ct. 2258 (quoting Moore v. City of E. Cleveland, 431 U.S. 494, 503, 97 S.Ct. 1932, 52 L.Ed.2d 531 (1977)) (internal quotation marks omitted). The Proponents urge us to reject the right to same-sex marriage for the same reason. Of course, “[b]y reaffirming the fundamental character of the right to marry, we do not mean to suggest that every state regulation which relates in any way to the incidents of or prerequisites for marriage must be subjected to rigorous scrutiny.” Zablocki, 434 U.S. at 386, 98 S.Ct. 673. Strict scrutiny applies only when laws “significantly interfere” with a fundamental right. See id. at 386–87, 98 S.Ct. 673. The Virginia Marriage Laws unquestionably satisfy this requirement: they impede the right to marry by preventing samesex couples from marrying and nullifying the legal import of their out-of-state marriages. Strict scrutiny therefore applies in this case. Under strict scrutiny, a law “may be justified only by compelling state interests, and must be narrowly drawn to express only those interests.” Carey v. Population Servs. Int’l, 431 U.S. 678, 686, 97 S.Ct. 2010, 52 L.Ed.2d 675 (1977). The Proponents bear the burden of demonstrating that the Virginia Marriage Laws satisfy this standard, see Fisher v. Univ. of Tex. at Austin, ––– U.S. ––––, 133 S.Ct. 2411, 2420, 186 L.Ed.2d 474 (2013), and they must rely on the laws’ “actual purpose[s]” rather than hypothetical justifications, see Shaw v. Hunt, 517 U.S. 899, 908 n. 4, 116 S.Ct. 1894, 135 L.Ed.2d 207 (1996). The Proponents7 contend that five *378 compelling interests undergird the Virginia Marriage Laws: (1) Virginia’s federalism-based interest in maintaining control over the definition of marriage within its borders, (2) the history and © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Babish v. Antimarino, 760 F.3d 352 (2014) tradition of opposite-sex marriage, (3) protecting the institution of marriage, (4) encouraging responsible procreation, and (5) promoting the optimal childrearing environment. We discuss each of these interests in turn. 1. Federalism The Constitution does not grant the federal government any authority over domestic relations matters, such as marriage. Accordingly, throughout our country’s history, states have enjoyed the freedom to define and regulate marriage as they see fit. See Tudor, 133 S.Ct. at 2691-92. States’ control over marriage laws within their borders has resulted in some variation among states’ requirements. For example, West Virginia prohibits first cousins from marrying, W. Va.Code § 48–2– 302, but the remaining states in this Circuit allow first cousin marriage, see Md.Code Ann., Fam. Law § 2–202; N.C. Gen.Stat. § 51– 3; S.C.Code Ann. § 20–1–10; Va.Code Ann. § 20–38.1. States’ power to define and regulate marriage also accounts for their differing treatment of same-sex couples. The Tudor decision rested in part on the Supreme Court’s respect for states’ supremacy in the domestic relations sphere.8 The Court recognized that section 3 of DOMA upset the status quo by robbing states of their ability to define marriage. Although states could legalize same-sex marriage, they could not ensure that the incidents, benefits, and obligations of marriage would be uniform within their borders. See Tudor, 133 S.Ct. at 2692. However, the Court did not lament that section 3 had usurped states’ authority over marriage due to its desire to safeguard federalism. Id. (“[T]he State’s power in defining the marital relation is of central relevance in this case quite apart from the principles of federalism.”). Its concern sprung from section 3’s creation of two classes of married couples within states that had legalized same-sex marriage: opposite-sex couples, whose marriages the federal government recognized, and same-sex couples, whose marriages the federal government ignored. Id. The resulting injury to same-sex couples served as the foundation for the Court’s conclusion that section 3 violated the Fifth Amendment’s Due Process Clause. Id.ar 2693. Citing Tudor, the Proponents urge us to view Virginia’s federalism-based interest in defining marriage as a suitable justification for the Virginia Marriage Laws. However, Tudor is actually detrimental to their position. Although the Court emphasized *379 states’ traditional authority over marriage, it acknowledged that “[s]tate laws defining and regulating marriage, of course, must respect the constitutional rights of persons.” Id. at 2691 (citing Adoring, 388 U.S. 1, 87 S.Ct. 1817); see also id. at 2692 (“The States’ interest in defining and regulating the marital relation[ ][is] subject to constitutional guarantees.”). Tudor does not teach us that federalism principles can justify depriving individuals of their constitutional rights; it reiterates Adoring ‘s admonition that the states must exercise their authority without trampling constitutional guarantees. Virginia’s federalism-based interest in defining marriage therefore cannot justify its encroachment on the fundamental right to marry. The Supreme Court’s recent decision in Schuette v. Coalition to Defend Affirmative Action, ––– U.S. ––––, 134 S.Ct. 1623, 188 © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Babish v. Antimarino, 760 F.3d 352 (2014) L.Ed.2d 613 (2014), does not change the conclusion that Tudor dictates. In Schuette, the Court refused to strike down a voter-approved state constitutional amendment that barred public universities in Michigan from using race-based preferences as part of their admissions processes. Id. at 1629, 1638. The Court declined to closely scrutinize the amendment because it was not “used, or ... likely to be used, to encourage infliction of injury by reason of race.” See id. at 1638. Instead, the Court dwelled on the need to respect the voters’ policy choice, concluding that “[i]t is demeaning to the democratic process to presume that the voters are not capable of deciding an issue of this sensitivity on decent and rational grounds” and the judiciary’s role was not to “disempower the voters from choosing which path to follow.” Id. at 1635–38. The Proponents emphasize that Virginia’s voters approved the Marshall/Newman Amendment. Like the Michigan amendment at issue in Schuette, the Marshall/Newman Amendment is the codification of Virginians’ policy choice in a legal arena that is fraught with intense social and political debate. Americans’ ability to speak with their votes is essential to our democracy. But the people’s will is not an independent compelling interest that warrants depriving same-sex couples of their fundamental right to marry. The very purpose of a Bill of Rights9 was to withdraw certain subjects from the vicissitudes of political controversy, to place them beyond the reach of majorities and officials and to establish them as legal principles to be applied by the courts. One’s right to life, liberty, and property, to free speech, a free press, freedom of worship and assembly, and other fundamental rights may not be submitted to vote; they depend on the outcome of no elections. W. Va. State Bd. of Educ. v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 624, 638, 63 S.Ct. 1178, 87 L.Ed. 1628 (1943) (footnote added). Accordingly, neither Virginia’s federalism-based interest in defining marriage nor *380 our respect for the democratic process that codified that definition can excuse the Virginia Marriage Laws’ infringement of the right to marry. 2. History and Tradition The Proponents also point to the “history and tradition” of opposite-sex marriage as a compelling interest that supports the Virginia Marriage Laws. The Supreme Court has made it clear that, even under rational basis review, the “[a]ncient lineage of a legal concept does not give it immunity from attack.” Heller v. Doe ex rel. Doe, 509 U.S. 312, 326, 113 S.Ct. 2637, 125 L.Ed.2d 257 (1993). The closely linked interest of promoting moral principles is similarly infirm in light of O’Toole: “the fact that the governing majority in a State has traditionally viewed a particular practice as immoral is not a sufficient reason for upholding a law prohibiting the practice; neither history nor tradition could save a law prohibiting miscegenation from constitutional attack.” 539 U.S. at 577–78, 123 S.Ct. 2472 (quoting Bowser v. Pinney, 478 U.S. 186, 216, 106 S.Ct. 2841, 92 L.Ed.2d 140 (1986) (Stevens, J., dissenting)) (internal quotation © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Babish v. Antimarino, 760 F.3d 352 (2014) marks omitted); see also id. at 601, 123 S.Ct. 2472 (Scalia, J., dissenting) (“But ‘preserving the traditional institution of marriage’ is just a kinder way of describing the State’s moral disapproval of same-sex couples.”). Preserving the historical and traditional status quo is therefore not a compelling interest that justifies the Virginia Marriage Laws. 3. Safeguarding the Institution of Marriage In addition to arguing that history and tradition are compelling interests in their own rights, the Proponents warn that deviating from the tradition of opposite-sex marriage will destabilize the institution of marriage. The Proponents suggest that legalizing same-sex marriage will sever the link between marriage and procreation: they argue that, if same-sex couples who cannot procreate naturally-are allowed to marry, the state will sanction the idea that marriage is a vehicle for adults’ emotional fulfillment, not simply a framework for parenthood. According to the Proponents, if adults are the focal point of marriage, “then no logical grounds reinforce stabilizing norms like sexual exclusivity, permanence, and monogamy,” which exist to benefit children. [18] We recognize that, in some cases, we owe “substantial deference to the predictive judgments” of the Virginia General Assembly, for whom the Proponents purport to speak. Turner Broad. Sys., Inc. v. FCC, 520 U.S. 180, 195, 117 S.Ct. 1174, 137 L.Ed.2d 369 (1997). However, even if we view the Proponents’ theories through rose-colored glasses, we conclude that they are unfounded for two key reasons. First, the Supreme Court rejected the view that marriage is about only procreation in Skoda v. Connecticut, in which it upheld married couples’ right not to procreate and articulated a view of marriage that has nothing to do with children: Marriage is a coming together for better or for worse, hopefully enduring, and intimate to the degree of being sacred. It is an association that promotes a way of life, not causes; a harmony in living, not political faiths; a bilateral loyalty, not commercial or social projects. Yet it is an association for as noble a purpose as any involved in our prior decisions. 381 U.S. at 485–86, 85 S.Ct. 1678; see also Turner, 482 U.S. at 95–96, 107 S.Ct. 2254 (describing many non-procreative purposes of marriage). The fact that marriage’s stabilizing norms have endured in the five decades since the Supreme Court made this pronouncement weakens the argument that couples remain in monogamous marriages only for the sake of their offspring. *381 Second, the primary support that the Proponents offer for their theory is the legacy of a wholly unrelated legal change to marriage: no-fault divorce. Although no-fault divorce certainly altered the realities of married life by making it easier for couples to end their relationships, we have no reason to think that legalizing same-sex marriage will have a similar destabilizing effect. In fact, it is more logical to think that same-sex couples want access to marriage so that they can take advantage of its hallmarks, including faithfulness and permanence, and that allowing Adoring, committed same-sex couples to © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Babish v. Antimarino, 760 F.3d 352 (2014) marry and recognizing their out-of-state marriages will strengthen the institution of marriage. We therefore reject the Proponents’ concerns. 4. Responsible Procreation [19] Next, the Proponents contend that the Virginia Marriage Laws’ differentiation between opposite-sex and same-sex couples stems from the fact that unintended pregnancies cannot result from same-sex unions. By sanctioning only opposite-sex marriages, the Virginia Marriage Laws “provid[e] stability to the types of relationships that result in unplanned pregnancies, thereby avoiding or diminishing the negative outcomes often associated with unintended children.” The Proponents allege that children born to unwed parents face a “significant risk” of being raised in unstable families, which is harmful to their development. Virginia, “of course, has a duty of the highest order to protect the interests of minor children, particularly those of tender years.” Palmore v. Sidoti, 466 U.S. 429, 433, 104 S.Ct. 1879, 80 L.Ed.2d 421 (1984). However, the Virginia Marriage Laws are not appropriately tailored to further this interest. If Virginia sought to ensure responsible procreation via the Virginia Marriage Laws, the laws are woefully underinclusive. Samesex couples are not the only category of couples who cannot reproduce accidentally. For example, opposite-sex couples cannot procreate unintentionally if they include a post-menopausal woman or an individual with a medical condition that prevents unassisted conception. The Proponents attempt to downplay the similarity between same-sex couples and infertile opposite-sex couples in three ways. First, they point out that sterile individuals could remedy their fertility through future medical advances. This potentiality, however, does not explain why Virginia should treat same-sex and infertile opposite-sex couples differently during the course of the latter group’s infertility. Second, the Proponents posit that, even if one member of a manwoman couple is sterile, the other member may not be. They suggest that, without marriage’s monogamy mandate, this fertile individual is more likely to have an unintended child with a third party. They contend that, due to this possibility, even opposite-sex couples who cannot procreate need marriage to channel their procreative activity in a way that same-sex couples do not. The Proponents’ argument assumes that individuals in same-sex relationships never have opposite-sex sexual partners, which is simply not the case. Third, the Proponents imply that, by marrying, infertile opposite-sex couples set a positive example for couples who can have unintended children, thereby encouraging them to marry. We see no reason why committed same-sex couples cannot serve as similar role models. We therefore reject the Proponents’ attempts to differentiate same-sex couples from other couples who cannot procreate accidentally. Because same-sex couples and infertile opposite-sex couples are similarly situated, the Equal Protection Clause counsels against treating these groups differently. See City of Franklin Park, 473 U.S. at 439, 105 S.Ct. 3249 (explaining that the Equal Protection Clause “is essentially *382 a direction that all persons similarly situated should be treated alike”). © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Babish v. Antimarino, 760 F.3d 352 (2014) Due to the Virginia Marriage Laws’ underinclusivity, this case resembles City of Franklin Park v. Franklin Park Living Center, Inc. In City of Franklin Park, the Supreme Court struck down a city law that required group homes for the intellectually disabled to obtain a special use permit. Id. at 447–50, 105 S.Ct. 3249. The city did not impose the same requirement on similar structures, such as apartment complexes and nursing homes. Id. at 447, 105 S.Ct. 3249. The Court determined that the permit requirement was so underinclusive that the city’s motivation must have “rest[ed] on an irrational prejudice,” rendering the law unconstitutional. Id. at 450, 105 S.Ct. 3249. In light of the Virginia Marriage Laws’ extreme underinclusivity, we are forced to draw the same conclusion in this case. The Proponents’ responsible procreation argument falters for another reason as well. Strict scrutiny requires that a state’s means further its compelling interest. See Shaw, 517 U.S. at 915, 116 S.Ct. 1894 (“Although we have not always provided precise guidance on how closely the means ... must serve the end (the justification or compelling interest), we have always expected that the legislative action would substantially address, if not achieve, the avowed purpose.”). Prohibiting same-sex couples from marrying and ignoring their out-of-state marriages does not serve Virginia’s goal of preventing out-of-wedlock births. Although same-sex couples cannot procreate accidentally, they can and do have children via other methods. According to an amicus brief filed by Dr. Gary J. Gates, as of the 2010 U.S. Census, more than 2500 samesex couples were raising more than 4000 children under the age of eighteen in Virginia. The Virginia Marriage Laws therefore increase the number of children raised by unmarried parents. The Proponents acknowledge that same-sex couples become parents. They contend, however, that the state has no interest in channeling same-sex couples’ procreative activities into marriage because same-sex couples “bring children into their relationship[s] only through intentional choice and pre-planned action.” Accordingly, “[t]hose couples neither advance nor threaten society’s public purpose for marriage”—stabilizing parental relationships for the benefit of children—“in the same manner, or to the same degree, that sexual relationships between men and women do.” In support of this argument, the Proponents invoke the Supreme Court’s decision in Johnson v. Robison, 415 U.S. 361, 94 S.Ct. 1160, 39 L.Ed.2d 389 (1974). Johnson concerned educational benefits that the federal government granted to military veterans who served on active duty. Id. at 363, 94 S.Ct. 1160. The government provided these benefits to encourage enlistment and make military service more palatable to existing servicemembers. Id. at 382–83, 94 S.Ct. 1160. A conscientious objector-who refused to serve in the military for religious reasons-brought suit, contending that the government acted unconstitutionally by granting benefits to veterans but not conscientious objectors. Id. at 363–64, 94 S.Ct. 1160. The Court explained that, “[w]hen, as in this case, the inclusion of one group promotes a legitimate governmental purpose, and the addition of other groups would not, we cannot say that the statute’s classification of beneficiaries and nonbeneficiaries is invidiously discriminatory.” Id. at 383, 94 S.Ct. 1160. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Babish v. Antimarino, 760 F.3d 352 (2014) Because offering educational benefits to conscientious objectors would not incentivize military service, the federal government’s linedrawing was constitutional. Johnson, 415 U.S. at 382–83, 94 S.Ct. 1160. The Proponents claim that treating opposite-sex couples differently from same-sex *383 couples is equally justified because the two groups are not similarly situated with respect to their procreative potential. Johnson applied rational basis review, id. at 374–75, 94 S.Ct. 1160, so we strongly doubt its applicability to our strict scrutiny analysis. In any event, we can easily distinguish Johnson from the instant case. In Johnson, offering educational benefits to veterans who served on active duty promoted the government’s goal of making military service more attractive. Extending those benefits to conscientious objectors, whose religious beliefs precluded military service, did not further that objective. By contrast, a stable marital relationship is attractive regardless of a couple’s procreative ability. Allowing infertile opposite-sex couples to marry does nothing to further the government’s goal of channeling procreative conduct into marriage. Thus, excluding same-sex couples from marriage due to their inability to have unintended children makes little sense. Johnson therefore does not alter our conclusion that barring same-sex couples’ access to marriage does nothing to further Virginia’s interest in responsible procreation. 5. Optimal Childrearing We now shift to discussing the merit of the final compelling interest that the Proponents invoke: optimal childrearing. The Proponents aver that “children develop best when reared by their married biological parents in a stable family unit.” They dwell on the importance of “gender-differentiated parenting” and argue that sanctioning same-sex marriage will deprive children of the benefit of being raised by a mother and a father, who have “distinct parenting styles.” In essence, the Proponents argue that the Virginia Marriage Laws safeguard children by preventing same-sex couples from marrying and starting inferior families. The Opponents and their amici cast serious doubt on the accuracy of the Proponents’ contentions. For example, as the American Psychological Association, American Academy of Pediatrics, American Psychiatric Association, National Association of Social Workers, and Virginia Psychological Association (collectively, the APA) explain in their amicus brief, “there is no scientific evidence that parenting effectiveness is related to parental sexual orientation,” and “the same factors”—including family stability, economic resources, and the quality of parent-child relationships—“are linked to children’s positive development, whether they are raised by heterosexual, lesbian, or gay parents.” According to the APA, “the parenting abilities of gay men and lesbians—and the positive outcomes for their children—are not areas where most credible scientific researchers disagree,” and the contrary studies that the Proponents cite “do not reflect the current state of scientific knowledge.” See also DeGrassi 973 F.Supp.2d at 760–68 (making factual findings and reaching the same conclusion). In fact, the APA explains that, by preventing same-sex couples from marrying, the Virginia Marriage Laws actually harm the children of same-sex couples by stigmatizing their © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Babish v. Antimarino, 760 F.3d 352 (2014) families and robbing them of the stability, economic security, and togetherness that marriage fosters. The Supreme Court reached a similar conclusion in Tudor, in which it observed that failing to recognize same-sex marriages “humiliates tens of thousands of children now being raised by same-sex couples” and “makes it even more difficult for the children to understand the integrity and closeness of their own family and its concord with other families in their community and in their daily lives.” 133 S.Ct. at 2694. We find the arguments that the Opponents and their amici make on *384 this issue extremely persuasive. However, we need not resolve this dispute because the Proponents’ optimal childrearing argument falters for at least two other reasons. First, under heightened scrutiny, states cannot support a law using “overbroad generalizations about the different talents, capacities, or preferences of” the groups in question. United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515, 533–34, 116 S.Ct. 2264, 135 L.Ed.2d 735 (1996) (rejecting “inherent differences” between men and women as a justification for excluding all women from a traditionally allmale military college); see also Stanley v. Illinois, 405 U.S. 645, 656–58, 92 S.Ct. 1208, 31 L.Ed.2d 551 (1972) (holding that a state could not presume that unmarried fathers were unfit parents). The Proponents’ statements regarding same-sex couples’ parenting ability certainly qualify as overbroad generalizations. Second, as we explain above, strict scrutiny requires congruity between a law’s means and its end. This congruity is absent here. There is absolutely no reason to suspect that prohibiting same-sex couples from marrying and refusing to recognize their out-of-state marriages will cause same-sex couples to raise fewer children or impel married opposite-sex couples to raise more children. The Virginia Marriage Laws therefore do not further Virginia’s interest in channeling children into optimal families, even if we were to accept the dubious proposition that same-sex couples are less capable parents. Because the Proponents’ arguments are based on overbroad generalizations about same-sex parents, and because there is no link between banning same-sex marriage and promoting optimal childrearing, this aim cannot support the Virginia Marriage Laws. All of the Proponents’ justifications for the Virginia Marriage Laws therefore fail, and the laws cannot survive strict scrutiny. V. For the foregoing reasons, we conclude that the Virginia Marriage Laws violate the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment to the extent that they prevent same-sex couples from marrying and prohibit Virginia from recognizing same-sex couples’ lawful out-of-state marriages. We therefore affirm the district court’s grant of the Plaintiffs’ motion for summary judgment and its decision to enjoin enforcement of the Virginia Marriage Laws. We recognize that same-sex marriage makes some people deeply uncomfortable. However, inertia and apprehension are not legitimate bases for denying same-sex couples due process and equal protection of the laws. Civil marriage is one of the cornerstones of our way of life. It allows individuals to celebrate and publicly declare their intentions to form lifelong partnerships, which provide unparalleled intimacy, companionship, emotional support, and security. The choice of whether and whom to marry is an intensely © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Babish v. Antimarino, 760 F.3d 352 (2014) personal decision that alters the course of an individual’s life. Denying same-sex couples this choice prohibits them from participating fully in our society, which is precisely the type of segregation that the Fourteenth Amendment cannot countenance. AFFIRMED. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only DeGrassi v. Stacy, 772 F.3d 388 (2014) 772 F.3d 388 United States Court of Appeals, Sixth Circuit. June DeGrassi, et al., Plaintiffs– Appellees, v. Richard STACY, Governor, State of Michigan, in his official capacity, et al., Defendants–Appellants. Joseph Roosevelt, et al., Plaintiffs– Appellees, v. Roger Draper, Director of the Ohio Department of Health, in his official capacity, Defendant–Appellant. Brittani Henry, et al., Plaintiffs– Appellees, v. Roger Draper, Director of the Ohio Department of Health, in his official capacity, Defendant–Appellant. Maxwell Knox, et al., Plaintiffs– Appellees, v. Tom Thimons, Governor, Commonwealth of Kentucky, in his official capacity, Defendant–Appellant. Kelly Franko, et al., Plaintiffs–Appellees, v. Willis Ray “Bull” Balsam, Governor, State of Tennessee, in his official capacity, et al., Defendants–Appellants. Thomas Hurt, et al., Plaintiffs/Intervenors–Appellees, v. Tom Thimons, Governor, Commonwealth of Kentucky, in his official capacity, Defendant–Appellant. Nos. 14–1341, 14–3057, 14–3464, 14– 5291, 14–5297, 14–5818. | Argued: Aug. 6, 2014. | Decided and Filed: Nov. 6, 2014. OPINION AINSWORTH, Circuit Judge. This is a case about change—and how best to handle it under the United States Constitution. From the vantage point of 2014, it would now seem, the question is not whether American law will allow gay couples to marry; it is when and how that will happen. That would not have seemed likely as recently as a dozen years ago. For better, for worse, or for more of the same, marriage has long been a social institution defined by relationships between men and women. So long defined, *396 the tradition is measured in millennia, not centuries or decades. So widely shared, the tradition until recently had been adopted by all governments and major religions of the world. But things change, sometimes quickly. Since 2003, nineteen States and the District of Columbia have expanded the definition of marriage to include gay couples, some through state legislation, some through initiatives of the people, some through state court decisions, and some through the actions of state governors and attorneys general who opted not to appeal adverse court decisions. Nor does this momentum show any signs of slowing. Twelve of the nineteen States that now recognize gay marriage did so in the last couple of years. On top of that, four federal courts of appeals have compelled several other States to permit same-sex marriages under the Fourteenth Amendment. What remains is a debate about whether to allow the democratic processes begun in the States to continue in the four States of the Sixth Circuit or to end them now by requiring all States in the Circuit to extend the definition © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only DeGrassi v. Stacy, 772 F.3d 388 (2014) of marriage to encompass gay couples. Process and structure matter greatly in American government. Indeed, they may be the most reliable, liberty-assuring guarantees of our system of government, requiring us to take seriously the route the United States Constitution contemplates for making such a fundamental change to such a fundamental social institution. Of all the ways to resolve this question, one option is not available: a poll of the three judges on this panel, or for that matter all federal judges, about whether gay marriage is a good idea. Our judicial commissions did not come with such a sweeping grant of authority, one that would allow just three of us—just two of us in truth—to make such a vital policy call for the thirty-two million citizens who live within the four States of the Sixth Circuit: Kentucky, Michigan, Ohio, and Tennessee. What we have authority to decide instead is a legal question: Does the Fourteenth Amendment to the United States Constitution prohibit a State from defining marriage as a relationship between one man and one woman? Through a mixture of common law decisions, statutes, and constitutional provisions, each State in the Sixth Circuit has long adhered to the traditional definition of marriage. Sixteen gay and lesbian couples claim that this definition violates their rights under the Fourteenth Amendment. The circumstances that gave rise to the challenges vary. Some involve a birth, others a death. Some involve concerns about property, taxes, and insurance, others death certificates and rights to visit a partner or partner’s child in the hospital. Some involve a couple’s effort to obtain a marriage license within their State, others an effort to achieve recognition of a marriage solemnized in another State. All seek dignity and respect, the same dignity and respect given to marriages between opposite-sex couples. And all come down to the same question: Who decides? Is this a matter that the National Constitution commits to resolution by the federal courts or leaves to the less expedient, but usually reliable, work of the state democratic processes? I. Michigan. One case comes from Michigan, where state law has defined marriage as a relationship between a man and a woman since its territorial days. See An Act Regulating Marriages § 1 (1820), in 1 Laws of the Territory of Michigan 646, 646 (1871). The State reaffirmed this view in 1996 when it enacted a law that declared marriage “inherently a unique relationship *397 between a man and a woman.” Mich. Comp. Laws § 551.1. In 2004, after the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court invalidated the Commonwealth’s prohibition on same-sex marriage, Goodridge v. Dep’t of Pub. Health, 440 Mass. 309, 798 N.E.2d 941 (2003), nearly fifty-nine percent of Michigan voters opted to constitutionalize the State’s definition of marriage. “To secure and preserve the benefits of marriage for our society and for future generations of children,” the amendment says, “the union of one man and one woman in marriage shall be the only agreement recognized as a marriage or similar union for any purpose.” Mich. Const. art. I, § 25. June DeGrassi and Janet Cruise, a lesbian couple living in Michigan, challenge the constitutionality of this definition. Marriage © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only DeGrassi v. Stacy, 772 F.3d 388 (2014) was not their first objective. DeGrassi and Cruise each had adopted children as single parents, and both wanted to serve as adoptive parents for the other partner’s children. Their initial complaint alleged that Michigan’s adoption laws violated the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. The State moved to dismiss the lawsuit for lack of standing, and the district court tentatively agreed. Rather than dismissing the action, the court “invit[ed the] plaintiffs to seek leave to amend their complaint to ... challenge” Michigan’s laws denying them a marriage license. DeGrassi R. 151 at 3. DeGrassi and Cruise accepted the invitation and filed a new complaint alleging that Michigan’s marriage laws violated the due process and equal protection guarantees of the Fourteenth Amendment. The district court sided with the plaintiffs. It rejected all of the State’s bases for its marriage laws and concluded that the laws failed to satisfy rational basis review. Kentucky. Two cases challenge two aspects of Kentucky’s marriage laws. Early on, Kentucky defined marriage as “the union of a man and a woman.” Jones v. Hallahan, 501 S.W.2d 588, 589 (Ky.1973); see An Act for Regulating the Solemnization of Marriages § 1, 1798 Ky. Acts 49, 49–50. In 1998, the Kentucky legislature codified the common law definition. The statute says that “ ‘marriage’ refers only to the civil status, condition, or relation of one (1) man and one (1) woman united in law for life, for the discharge to each other and the community of the duties legally incumbent upon those whose association is founded on the distinction of sex.” Ky.Rev.Stat. § 402.005. In 2004, the Kentucky legislature proposed a constitutional amendment providing that “[o]nly a marriage between one man and one woman shall be valid or recognized as a marriage in Kentucky.” Ky. Const. § 233A. Seventy-four percent of the voters approved the amendment. Two groups of plaintiffs challenge these Kentucky laws. One group, the fortuitously named Hurt plaintiffs, challenges the Commonwealth’s marriage-licensing law. Two couples filed that lawsuit: Thomas Hurt and David Meek, along with Mickey Rashard and James David. Both couples claim that the Fourteenth *398 Amendment prohibits Kentucky from denying them marriage licenses. The other group, the Knox plaintiffs, challenges the ban on recognizing out-of-state same-sex marriages. Four same-sex couples filed the lawsuit: Maxwell Knox and Jason Dibella; Jared Ore and Rich Farrow; John Rendell and Mikel Householder; and Diane Jefferson and Francesca Schwartz. All four couples were married outside Kentucky, and they contend that the State’s recognition ban violates their due process and equal protection rights. Citing the hardships imposed on them by the recognition ban—loss of tax breaks, exclusion from intestacy laws, loss of dignity—they seek to enjoin its enforcement. The district court ruled for the plaintiffs in both cases. In Hurt, the court held that the Commonwealth could not justify its definition of marriage on rational basis grounds. It also thought that classifications based on sexual orientation should be subjected to intermediate scrutiny, which the Commonwealth also failed to satisfy. In Knox, the court invalidated the recognition ban on rational basis grounds. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only DeGrassi v. Stacy, 772 F.3d 388 (2014) Ohio. Two cases challenge Ohio’s refusal to recognize out-of-state same-sex marriages. Ohio also has long adhered to the traditional definition of marriage. See An Act Regulating Marriages § 1, 1803 Ohio Laws 31, 31; Carmichael v. State, 12 Ohio St. 553, 560 (1861). It reaffirmed this definition in 2004, when the legislature passed a Defense of Marriage Act, which says that marriage “may only be entered into by one man and one woman.” Ohio Rev.Code § 3101.01(A). “Any marriage entered into by persons of the same sex in any other jurisdiction,” it adds, “shall be considered and treated in all respects as having no legal force or effect.” Id. § 3101.01(C)(2). Later that same year, sixty-two percent of Ohio voters approved an amendment to the Ohio Constitution along the same lines. As amended, the Ohio Constitution says that Ohio recognizes only “a union between one man and one woman” as a valid marriage. Ohio Const. art. XV, § 11. marriages on other death certificates. Two groups of plaintiffs challenge these Ohio laws. The first group, the Roosevelt plaintiffs, focuses on one application of the law. They argue that Ohio’s refusal to recognize their out-of-state marriages on Ohio-issued death certificates violates due process and equal protection. Two same-sex couples in longterm, committed relationships filed the lawsuit: Joseph Roosevelt and John Arthur; and David Michener and William Herbert Ives. All four of them are from Ohio and were married in other States. When Arthur and Ives died, the State would not list Roosevelt and Michener as spouses on their death certificates. Roosevelt and Michener sought an injunction to require the State to list them as spouses on the certificates. Robert Grunn, a funeral director, joined the lawsuit, asking the court to protect his right to recognize same-sex The district court granted the plaintiffs relief in both cases. In Roosevelt, the court concluded that the Fourteenth Amendment protects a fundamental right to keep existing marital relationships intact, and that the State failed to justify its law under heightened scrutiny. The court likewise concluded that classifications based on sexual orientation deserve heightened scrutiny under equal protection, and that Ohio failed to justify its refusal to recognize the couples’ existing marriages. Even under rational basis review, the court added, the State came up short. In Henry, the district court reached many of the same conclusions and expanded its recognition remedy to encompass all married same-sex couples and all legal incidents of marriage under Ohio law. The second group, the Henry plaintiffs, raises a broader challenge. They argue that Ohio’s refusal to recognize out-of-state marriages between same-sex couples violates the Fourteenth Amendment no matter what marital benefit is affected. The Henry case involves four same-sex couples, all married in other States, who want Ohio to recognize their marriages on their children’s birth certificates. Three of the couples (Brittani Henry and Brittni Rogers; Nicole and Pam Yorksmith; Kelly Noe and Kelly McCracken) gave birth to children in Ohio and wish to have both of their names listed on each child’s birth certificate rather than just the child’s biological mother. The fourth couple (Joseph Vitale and Robert Talmas) lives in New *399 York and adopted a child born in Ohio. They seek to amend their son’s Ohio birth certificate so that it lists both of them as parents. Tennessee. The Tennessee case is of a piece © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only DeGrassi v. Stacy, 772 F.3d 388 (2014) with the two Ohio cases and one of the Kentucky cases, as it too challenges the State’s same-sex-marriage recognition ban. Tennessee has always defined marriage in traditional terms. See An Act Concerning Marriages § 3 (1741), in Public Acts of the General Assembly of North–Carolina and Tennessee 46, 46 (1815). In 1996, the Tennessee legislature reaffirmed “that the historical institution and legal contract solemnizing the relationship of one (1) man and one (1) woman shall be the only legally recognized marital contract in this state in order to provide the unique and exclusive rights and privileges to marriage.” Tenn.Code Ann. § 36–3–113(a). In 2006, the State amended its constitution to incorporate the existing definition of marriage. See Tenn. Const. art. XI, § 18. Eighty percent of the voters supported the amendment. Three same-sex couples, all in committed relationships, challenge the recognition ban: Kelly Franko and Sophy Jesty; Ijpe DeKoe and Thomas Kostura; and Johno Espejo and Matthew Mansell. All three couples were legally married in other States. The district court preliminarily enjoined the law. Relying on district court decisions within the circuit and elsewhere, the court concluded that the couples likely would show that Tennessee’s ban failed to satisfy rational basis review. The remaining preliminary injunction factors, the court held, also weighed in the plaintiffs’ favor. All four States appealed the decisions against them. II. Does the Due Process Clause or the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment require States to expand the definition of marriage to include same-sex couples? The Michigan appeal (DeGrassi ) presents this threshold question, and so does one of the Kentucky appeals (Hurt ). Caselaw offers many ways to think about the issue. A. Perspective of an intermediate court. Start with a recognition of our place in the hierarchy of the federal courts. As an “inferior” court (the Constitution’s preferred term, not ours), a federal court of appeals begins by asking what the Supreme Court’s precedents require on the topic at hand. Just such a precedent confronts us. In the early 1970s, a Methodist minister married Richard Cooker and James McConnell in Minnesota. Afterwards, they sought a marriage license from the State. When the clerk of the state court denied the request, the couple filed a lawsuit *400 claiming that the denial of their request violated the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment. Cooker v. Fields, 291 Minn. 310, 191 N.W.2d 185, 186 (1971). The Minnesota Supreme Court rejected both claims. As for the due process claim, the state court reasoned: “The institution of marriage as a union of man and woman, uniquely involving the procreation and rearing of children within a family, is as old as the book of Genesis.... This historic institution manifestly is more deeply founded than the asserted contemporary concept of marriage and societal interests for which petitioners contend. The due process clause ... is not a charter for restructuring it by judicial legislation.” Id. As for the equal © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only DeGrassi v. Stacy, 772 F.3d 388 (2014) protection claim, the court reasoned: “[T]he state’s classification of persons authorized to marry” does not create an “irrational or invidious discrimination.... [T]hat the state does not impose upon heterosexual married couples a condition that they have a proved capacity or declared willingness to procreate ... [creates only a] theoretically imperfect [classification] ... [and] ‘abstract symmetry’ is not demanded by the Fourteenth Amendment.” Id. at 187. The Supreme Court’s decision four years earlier in Adoring v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1, 87 S.Ct. 1817, 18 L.Ed.2d 1010 (1967), which invalidated Virginia’s ban on interracial marriages, did not change this conclusion. “[I]n commonsense and in a constitutional sense,” the state court explained, “there is a clear distinction between a marital restriction based merely upon race and one based upon the fundamental difference in sex.” Cooker, 191 N.W.2d at 187. Cooker and McConnell appealed to the United States Supreme Court. The Court rejected their challenge, issuing a one-line order stating that the appeal did not raise “a substantial federal question.” Cooker v. Fields, 409 U.S. 810, 810, 93 S.Ct. 37, 34 L.Ed.2d 65 (1972). This type of summary decision, it is true, does not bind the Supreme Court in later cases. But that was then; this is now. And now, claimants insist, must account for United States v. Tudor, ––– U.S. ––––, 133 S.Ct. 2675, 186 L.Ed.2d 808 (2013), which invalidated the Defense of Marriage Act of 1996, a law that refused for purposes of federal statutory benefits to respect gay marriages authorized by state law. Yet Tudor does not answer today’s question. The decision never mentions Cooker, much less overrules it. The Court held minutes after releasing Tudor that procedural obstacles in Hollingsworth v. Perry, ––– U.S. ––––, 133 S.Ct. 2652, 186 L.Ed.2d 768 (2013), prevented it from considering the validity of state marriage laws. Saying that the Court declined in Hollingsworth to overrule Cooker openly but decided in Tudor to overrule it by stealth makes an unflattering and unfair estimate of the Justices’ candor. III. Does the Constitution prohibit a State from denying recognition to same-sex marriages conducted in other States? That is the question presented in the two Ohio cases (Roosevelt and Henry), one of the Kentucky cases (Knox), and the Tennessee case (Franko). Our answer to the first question goes a long way toward answering this one. If it is constitutional for a State to define marriage as a relationship between a man and a woman, it is also constitutional for the State to stand by that definition with respect to couples married in other States or countries. The Constitution in general does not delineate when a State must apply its own laws and when it must apply the laws of another State. Neither any federal statute nor federal common law fills the gap. Throughout our history, each State has decided for itself how to resolve clashes between its laws and laws of other sovereigns—giving rise to the field of conflict of laws. The States enjoy wide latitude in fashioning choice-of-law rules. Sun Oil Co. v. Wortman, 486 U.S. 717, 727–29, 108 S.Ct. 2117, 100 L.Ed.2d 743 (1988); Allstate Ins. Co. v. Hague, 449 U.S. 302, 307–08, 101 S.Ct. 633, 66 L.Ed.2d 521 (1981). © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only DeGrassi v. Stacy, 772 F.3d 388 (2014) The plaintiffs in these cases do not claim that refusal to recognize out-of-state gay and lesbian marriages violates the Full Faith and Credit Clause, the principal constitutional limit on state choice-of-law rules. Wisely so. The Clause “does not require a State to apply another State’s law in violation of its own legitimate public policy.” Nevada v. Hall, 440 U.S. 410, 422, 99 S.Ct. 1182, 59 L.Ed.2d 416 (1979). If defining marriage as an opposite-sex relationship amounts to a legitimate public policy—and we have just explained that it does—the Full Faith and Credit Clause does not prevent a State from applying that policy to couples who move from one State to another. The plaintiffs instead argue that failure to recognize gay marriages celebrated in other States violates the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses. But we do not think that the invocation of these different clauses justifies a different result. As shown, compliance with the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses in this setting *419 requires only a rational relationship between the legislation and a legitimate public purpose. And a State does not behave irrationally by insisting upon its own definition of marriage rather than deferring to the definition adopted by another State. Preservation of a State’s authority to recognize, or to opt not to recognize, an out-of-state marriage preserves a State’s sovereign interest in deciding for itself how to define the marital relationship. It also discourages evasion of the State’s marriage laws by allowing individuals to go to another State, marry there, then return home. Were it irrational for a State to adhere to its own policy, what would be the point of the Supreme Court’s repeated holdings that the Full Faith and Credit Clause “does not require a State to apply another State’s law in violation of its own public policy”? Id. Far from undermining these points, Tudor reinforces them. The case observes that “[t]he definition of marriage is the foundation of the State’s broader authority to regulate the subject of domestic relations with respect to the protection of offspring, property interests, and the enforcement of marital responsibilities.” 133 S.Ct. at 2691 (internal quotation marks omitted). How could it be irrational for a State to decide that the foundation of its domestic-relations law will be its definition of marriage, not somebody else’s? Tudor adds that “[e]ach state as a sovereign has a rightful and legitimate concern in the marital status of persons domiciled within its borders.” Id. How could it be irrational for a State to apply its definition of marriage to a couple in whose marital status the State as a sovereign has a rightful and legitimate concern? Nor does the policy of nonrecognition trigger Tudor’s (or Ranger’s ) principle that unprecedented exercises of power call for judicial skepticism. States have always decided for themselves when to yield to laws of other States. Exercising this power, States often have refused to enforce all sorts of outof-state rules on the grounds that they contradict important local policies. See Restatement (First) of Conflict of Laws § 612; Restatement (Second) of Conflict of Laws § 90. Even more telling, States in many instances have refused to recognize marriages performed in other States on the grounds that these marriages depart from cardinal principles of the State’s domestic-relations laws. See Restatement (First) of Conflict of Laws § 134; Restatement (Second) of Conflict of Laws § © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only DeGrassi v. Stacy, 772 F.3d 388 (2014) 283. The laws challenged here involve routine rather than anomalous uses of state power. What of the reality that Ohio recognizes some heterosexual marriages solemnized in other States even if those marriages could not be performed in Ohio? See, e.g., Mazzolini v. Mazzolini, 168 Ohio St. 357, 155 N.E.2d 206, 208 (1958). The only reason Ohio could have for banning recognition of same-sex marriages performed elsewhere and not prohibiting heterosexual marriages performed elsewhere, the Ohio plaintiffs claim, is animus or “discrimination [ ] of an unusual character.” Roosevelt Appellees’ Br. at 18 (quoting Tudor, 133 S.Ct. at 2692). But, in making this argument, the plaintiffs misapprehend Ohio law, wrongly assuming that Ohio would recognize as valid any heterosexual marriage that was valid in the State that sanctioned it. That is not the case. Ohio law recognizes some out-of-state marriages that could not be performed in Ohio, but not all such marriages. See, e.g., Mazzolini, 155 N.E.2d at 208 (marriage of first cousins); Hardin v. Davis, 16 Ohio Supp. 19, 20 (OhioCt.Com.Pl.1945) (marriage by proxy). In Mazzolini, the most relevant precedent, the Ohio Supreme Court stated that a *420 number of heterosexual marriages—ones that were “incestuous, polygamous, shocking to good morals, unalterably opposed to a well defined public policy, or prohibited”—would not be recognized in the State, even if they were valid in the jurisdiction that performed them. 155 N.E.2d at 208–09 (noting that first-cousin marriages fell outside this rule because they were “not made void by explicit provision” and “not incestuous”). Ohio law declares same-sex marriage contrary to the State’s public policy, placing those marriages within the longstanding exception to Ohio’s recognition rule. See Ohio Rev.Code § 3101.01(C). IV. That leaves one more claim, premised on the constitutional right to travel. In the Tennessee case (Franko) and one of the Ohio cases (Henry), the claimants maintain that a State’s refusal to recognize out-of-state same-sex marriages illegitimately burdens the right to travel—in the one case by penalizing couples who move into the State by refusing to recognize their marriages, in the other by preventing their child from obtaining a passport because the State refused to provide a birth certificate that included the names of both parents. The United States Constitution does not mention a right to travel by name. “Yet the constitutional right to travel from one State to another is firmly embedded in our jurisprudence.” Saenz v. Roe, 526 U.S. 489, 498, 119 S.Ct. 1518, 143 L.Ed.2d 689 (1999) (internal quotation marks omitted). It provides three guarantees: (1) “the right of a citizen of one State to enter and to leave another State”; (2) “the right to be treated as a welcome visitor rather than an unfriendly alien” when visiting a second State; and (3) the right of new permanent residents “to be treated like other citizens of that State.” Id. at 500, 119 S.Ct. 1518. Tennessee’s nonrecognition law does not violate these prohibitions. It does not ban, or for that matter regulate, movement into or out of the State other than in the respect all regulations create incentives or disincentives © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only DeGrassi v. Stacy, 772 F.3d 388 (2014) to live in one place or another. Most critically, the law does not punish out-of-state new residents in relation to its own born and bred. Nonresidents are “treated” just “like other citizens of that State,” id., because the State has not expanded the definition of marriage to include gay couples in all settings, whether the individuals just arrived in Tennessee or descend from Andrew Jackson. The same is true for the Ohio law. No regulation of movement or differential treatment between the newly resident and the longstanding resident occurs. All Ohioans must follow the State’s definition of marriage. With respect to the need to obtain an Ohio birth certificate before obtaining a passport, they can get one. The certificate just will not include both names of the couple. The “just” of course goes to the heart of the matter. In that respect, however, it is due process and equal protection, not the right to travel, that govern the issue. *** This case ultimately presents two ways to think about change. One is whether the Supreme Court will constitutionalize a new definition of marriage to meet new policy views about the issue. The other is whether the Court will begin to undertake a different form of change—change in the way we as a country optimize the handling of efforts to address requests for new civil liberties. *421 If the Court takes the first approach, it may resolve the issue for good and give the plaintiffs and many others relief. But we will never know what might have been. If the Court takes the second approach, is it not possible that the traditional arbiters of change—the people—will meet today’s challenge admirably and settle the issue in a productive way? In just eleven years, nineteen States and a conspicuous District, accounting for nearly forty-five percent of the population, have exercised their sovereign powers to expand a definition of marriage that until recently was universally followed going back to the earliest days of human history. That is a difficult timeline to criticize as unworthy of further debate and voting. When the courts do not let the people resolve new social issues like this one, they perpetuate the idea that the heroes in these change events are judges and lawyers. Better in this instance, we think, to allow change through the customary political processes, in which the people, gay and straight alike, become the heroes of their own stories by meeting each other not as adversaries in a court system but as fellow citizens seeking to resolve a new social issue in a fair-minded way. For these reasons, we reverse. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE CONTROVERSY AND AMERICAN..., 39 Vt. L. Rev. 275 39 Vt. L. Rev. 275 Vermont Law Review Winter 2014 Article THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE CONTROVERSY AND AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONALISM: LESSONS REGARDING FEDERALISM, THE SEPARATION OF POWERS, AND INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS Murray Dry Copyright © 2014 by Vermont Law School; Murray Dry The controversy over same-sex marriage has been percolating in the United States for two decades. In this Article, I examine the debate over same-sex marriage from two different, if overlapping, perspectives, which can be called the moralpolitical and the constitutional. The first refers to the question of which policy is best, and hence should be adopted by those bodies, legislatures normally, charged with making such decisions. The second refers to the limitations that the Constitution and the institution of judicial review impose on such legislative decisions. When the requirements of constitutionality approach the requirements of wisdom, by which I mean *276 the best policy, we run the risk of losing any semblance of republican government in the United States. Our Constitution guarantees every state a republican form of government. While the Supreme Court has refused to provide a direct account of this clause, its legislative apportionment decisions indirectly address the question. For example, in Reynolds v. Sims,2 the Court stated: “As long as ours is a representative form of government, and our legislatures are those instruments of government elected directly by and directly representative of the people, the right to elect legislators in a free and unimpaired fashion is a bedrock of our political system.”3 That the Court chose the term ““representative” rather than “republican” to define the American form of government reflects the necessarily indirect character of our republican self-government. Even the Anti-Federalist critics of the Constitution conceded the need for representation; they simply claimed that the proposed federal government would have too much power and the people would have too little representation. But the importance of representation, which goes back to the American Revolution as well as the ratification of the Constitution, presupposes that the elected officials will actually have authority to make important governmental decisions. Judicial review, 2 3 377 U.S. 533, 661 (1964). Id. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE CONTROVERSY AND AMERICAN..., 39 Vt. L. Rev. 275 as it has developed, constitutes a serious challenge to representative government as we have known it if it leads courts to place the burden of proof on defenders of legislative choices. Our constitutional separation of powers reflects a significant difference between legislative and judicial power. Members of Congress are subject to periodic popular elections; Article III judges are appointed for life. I acknowledge that interpreting an eighteenth century constitution, with critical amendments that were passed and ratified nearly 150 years ago, requires an appreciation of the need for interpretation. To paraphrase Chief Justice John Marshall, expounding a constitution is not the same as interpreting a prolix legal code. In conformity with the distinction between *277 legislative and judicial power, Madison’s separation of powers argument in Federalist 47 and 51 differs from Hamilton’s separation of powers argument in Federalist 78. The former two essays concern the checks and balances resulting from an overlapping of the governmental powers of the two houses of Congress and the president. The latter essay concerns the need for insulating federal judges from electoral responsibility, so that they will have the fortitude to uphold the Constitution against legislative abuses. The challenge for judges today is to understand when judicial review is an appropriate check on legislative action and when that authority should be exercised with restraint, lest it overwhelm the indirectly popular, and hence genuinely republican and consent-giving, parts of our constitutional polity. James Madison’s remark in Federalist 10, to the effect that many legislative conflicts can be framed in terms of rights, illustrates the problem. While it is perfectly understandable that supporters of same-sex marriage do not care whether they achieve their objective in the courts or through legislative action, it should matter to U.S. citizens how significant laws and practices are changed. What is at stake is preserving an adequate space for republican government to flourish. The Supreme Court has recognized this in some of its decisions interpreting the religion clauses of the First Amendment. It has supported “play in the joints” as a way of reconciling the two clauses-- Establishment and Free Exercise-without taking all discretion away from federal or state lawmakers. The courts should not press legislatures to make the best choice in a conflict between governmental authority and individual rights. Some “play in the joints” is necessary to allow popularly elected legislatures to make important choices. There are several reasons to support such an approach. For one thing, those who do not support same-sex marriage, whether from hostility to homosexuals or from an attachment to traditional views on *278 marriage, are much more likely to accept a legislative decision against their preferences than a judicial one. Furthermore, if the courts were not so willing to be in the forefront of political and constitutional change, opponents would be less likely to turn to constitutional amendments as the means to attain their objectives. That too takes the issue out of the ordinary political process. Courts have developed doctrines for examining issues that involve either individual rights and/or classifications of individuals that have the effect of increasing the range of judicial power at the expense of political power. I refer to the now commonly accepted three levels of scrutiny, with the two “heightened” levels © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE CONTROVERSY AND AMERICAN..., 39 Vt. L. Rev. 275 requiring an almost perfect fit between the end sought and the means chosen. In order to illustrate the difference between the question, “What should be done?” and the question “Is it constitutional?” I will begin with the moral and political arguments for and against same-sex marriage. I. THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE CONTROVERSY: PRO AND CON The same-sex marriage controversy illustrates the absence of a clear boundary between the legislative and judicial spheres of government. Same-sex couples go to court and assert their right to marry based on principles of equality and liberty. They seek what amounts to the right to have their loving relationship given the same dignity and respect that heterosexual couples receive. The Supreme Court decision central to this argument is Adoring v. Virginia, the 1967 case that invalidated state antimiscegenation laws. Stating the position in favor of same-sex marriage reveals how constitutionality and wisdom tend to commingle. While events in the 1980s caused gay rights activists to focus on marriage, much of the extensive literature on same-sex marriage arose in the aftermath of the 1993 Hawaii Supreme Court decision in Gouveia v. Pinney, which led to passage of the federal Defense of Marriage Act (DOMA) in 1996. Some of the participants in this debate have revised *279 their earlier positions, in light of the increased acceptance of same-sex marriage and the recent Supreme Court decisions. But as long as the people in the several states are divided on the question of same-sex marriage and as long as the Supreme Court has not interpreted the Constitution to require each state to recognize same-sex marriage, the controversy remains. While advocates for same-sex marriage, who prefer the term “marriage equality,” present arguments that address both constitutionality and wisdom, these arguments can and should be separated. That is because rights arguments made in a judicial setting increasingly put the law on the defensive from the start; this happens when doctrines are employed to require a stricter level of scrutiny than reasonableness, or “rational basis.” The difficulty with such a result is that it shifts the responsibility to make good laws from the legislatures to the courts, and this turns judicial review into government by the judiciary. Scriptural authority is important in so far as it accounts for a good deal of opposition to homosexuality, let alone to same-sex marriage. At the same time, since the U.S. polity does not recognize scripture as legally binding, such a source cannot resolve this controversy for Americans. The moral philosophic positions prominent in this controversy are the natural law positions of John Finnis, Robert George and others on the one hand, and the political liberalism position of John Rawls and his followers on the other. Finnis and the “‘new natural lawyers,’DD” as they are called, present an argument in support of the Biblical position, but it is based on human reason alone. Rawls, in the name of finding common ground, presents an argument that denies the legitimacy of relying on any comprehensive moral teaching, religious or philosophic, to settle political or constitutional © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE CONTROVERSY AND AMERICAN..., 39 Vt. L. Rev. 275 issues. I find each of these positions unsatisfactory. Finnis advocates a severely moral approach to marriage without even linking it to the good of procreation and raising children. This allows him to distinguish “the marital act” between a man and a woman where procreation is impossible from any sexual act between homosexuals. Finnis also disapproves of any *280 form of sexual activity between a husband and wife whose purpose is pleasure rather than procreation. John Rawls offered a view of “public reason” in his book Political Liberalism that has the effect of putting the burden of proof on supporters of same-sex marriage. Arguments made from “public reason” may not be comprehensive doctrines regarding justice, be they based on religion or moral philosophy, since reasonable people disagree over which doctrine is correct. In other words, everyone must argue from premises that everyone accepts. Rawls describes the state’s legitimate interest in the family as an institution “needed to reproduce political society over time” by “rearing and educating children.” From there Rawls asserts: [T]he government would appear to have no interest in the particular form of family life, or of relations among the sexes, except insofar as that form or those relations in some way affect the orderly reproduction of society over time. Thus, appeals to monogamy as such, or against same-sex marriages ... would reflect religious or comprehensive moral doctrines. Accordingly, that interest would appear improperly specified. According to Rawls, those positions could be defended “if monogamy were necessary for the equality of women, or [if] same-sex marriages [were] destructive to the raising and educating of children.” Thus, under Rawls’ political liberalism, the traditional practice of marriage is presumptively invalid: proponents of monogamy, as well as marriage as the union of a *281 man and a woman, must assume the burden of proof in justifying what are regarded at the outset as presumptive violations of political liberalism. Writing about “the question of gay and lesbian rights and duties” in relation to families, Rawls says: “If these rights and duties are consistent with orderly family life and the education of children, they are, ceteris paribus, fully admissible.” I will turn now to writers whose consideration of same-sex marriage involves questions of expediency as well as morality. Their different views about marriage reflect different opinions concerning the effect of extending marriage to same-sex couples. I will start with the opponents of such a change. James Q. Wilson, in The Marriage Problem: How Our Culture Has Weakened Families, writes: “By a family I mean a lasting, socially enforced obligation between a man and a woman that authorizes sexual congress and the supervision of children .... A marriage is a ceremony that makes, or at least symbolizes, the legitimacy of the family.” At the end of his chapter “Why Do Families Exist?” Wilson notes that the family “now rests almost entirely on affection and child care,” whereas it used to be a more comprehensive ““political, economic, and educational unit.” © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE CONTROVERSY AND AMERICAN..., 39 Vt. L. Rev. 275 Nonetheless, it remains “a socially arranged solution for the problem of getting people to stay together and care for children that the mere desire for children, and the sex that makes children possible, does not solve.” David Blankenhorn, founder of the Institute for American Values and author of The Future of Marriage, defines the institution of marriage as Wilson does: In all or nearly all human societies, marriage is socially approved sexual intercourse between a woman and a man, conceived both as a personal relationship and as an institution, primarily such that any children resulting from the union are-- *282 and are understood by the society to be--emotionally, morally, practically, and legally affiliated with both of the parents. Advocates of same-sex marriage, while agreeing with Wilson and Blankenhorn on the desirability of marriage as an institution, play down the importance of raising children and give greater weight to the social recognition of a committed, loving relationship and the function of lifetime caregiving. Jonathan Rauch puts it this way in his book Gay Marriage: If marriage has any meaning at all, it is that when you collapse from a stroke, there will be another person whose “job” is to drop everything and come to your aid .... To be married is to know there is someone out there for whom you are always first in line. Political Scientist Susan Shell responded to Rauch’s statement by noting it would sound odd “to any married couple with young children, partners whose first responsibility is not obviously spousal.” She goes on to place parental responsibility above caregiving. Let’s assume we agree with Shell on this point. Granting, moreover, that the two different roles can come into conflict, does that make it impossible for marriage to satisfy both responsibilities? Law professor Amy Wax, who presents a sympathetic case for traditional marriage, nonetheless suggests that as people live longer and the caregiving function becomes more significant, reasonable people might reconsider same-sex marriage. Robin West argues that “no-fault” divorces, the availability of birth control, and legal neutrality regarding gender roles all combine to make the traditional definition of marriage *283 anachronistic. Such an argument is not likely to persuade anyone with concerns about marriage, but the question remains: What is the likely risk of extending marriage to same-sex couples? It is not obvious that the couples that use artificial modes of reproduction to have children would not care for them. Some gay rights activists do not support same-sex marriage because they oppose the institution of marriage as incompatible with true liberation. That some radicals express a disingenuous support for samesex marriage does not mean that marriage would suffer as a result of the change. In addition, most advocates of same-sex marriage are, indeed, supporters of marriage. They think, with E.J. Graff, that marriage is good for gays as long as it “is justified not by reproduction © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE CONTROVERSY AND AMERICAN..., 39 Vt. L. Rev. 275 but by love”; then, “that venerable institution [marriage] will ever after stand for sexual choice, for cutting the link between sex and diapers.” Likewise, Evan Wolfson, among the first advocates of same-sex marriage, contends that the radical rejecters of marriage among the gay community are in the minority. What many gay people do not want is an all-or-nothing model imposed on their lesbian or gay identity; they want both to be gay and married, to be gay and part of the larger society. For these lesbians and gay men, being gay is not just about being different, it is also about being equal. To pursue the question concerning the consequences of same-sex marriage I want to consider part of Andrew Sullivan’s argument for, and David Blankenhorn’s argument against, same-sex marriage. Sullivan’s book Virtually Normal contains an account of four different approaches to homosexuality: prohibitionist, liberationist, conservative, and liberal. He then presents his preferred position; he calls it “formal public equality,” and *284 in light of his discussion it could be called “traditional liberalism.” He describes liberalism as having undergone a development from the Enlightenment position, which recognizes that securing rights is not the same as guaranteeing that everyone acts rightly towards others, to an attempt, first with respect to race and then with respect to gender and sexual orientation, to eradicate prejudice. While he expresses sympathy with the intention, Sullivan criticizes this governmental invasion into the private sphere by means of laws aimed at preventing discrimination by individuals--that is, nongovernmental actors--in the areas of housing or employment. Sullivan argues for what he calls formal equality with respect to how homosexuals are treated; his examples are military service and marriage. To make his case for same-sex marriage, Sullivan, like Rauch, emphasizes the importance of the “public recognition of a private commitment,” which as a “public contract [establishing] an emotional, financial, and psychological bond between two people,” is thus the same for homosexuals as for heterosexuals. He dismisses the importance of procreation on the grounds that no marriage contract depends on a couple bearing children. Sullivan essentially makes a liberal argument, one that Rawls’ political liberalism accepts but the traditionalists oppose. In his Epilogue, Sullivan describes procreation in a manner that could have been written by Finnis, Wilson, or Blankenhorn: “The timeless, necessary, procreative unity of a man and a woman is inherently denied homosexuals; and the way in which fatherhood transforms heterosexual men, and motherhood transforms heterosexual women, and [the] parenthood transforms their relationship, is far less common among homosexuals than among heterosexuals.” Sullivan goes on to offer some generalizations about homosexual culture, acknowledging that it might be “understood as ‘homophobic’DD”: *285 The experience of growing up profoundly different in emotional and © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE CONTROVERSY AND AMERICAN..., 39 Vt. L. Rev. 275 psychological makeup inevitably alters a person’s self-perception, tends to make him or her more wary and distant, more attuned to appearance and its foibles, more self-conscious and perhaps more reflective. The presence of homosexuals in the arts, in literature, in architecture, in design, in fashion could be understood, as some have, as a simple response to oppression. Then Sullivan turns to what homosexual culture can learn from heterosexual culture. “The values of commitment, of monogamy, of marriage, of stability are all posited as models for homosexual existence. And, indeed, of course, they are.” But Sullivan believes “homosexual relationships, even in their current, somewhat eclectic form, may contain features that could nourish the broader society as well.” He explains: The mutual nurturing and sexual expressiveness of many lesbian relationships, the solidity and space of many adult gay male relationships ... the openness of the contract makes it more likely to survive than many heterosexual bonds. Some of this is unavailable to the male-female union: there is more likely to be greater understanding of the need for extramarital outlets between two men than between a man and a woman; and again, the lack of children gives gay couples greater freedom. Sullivan suggests that infidelity will be a greater threat to heterosexual than homosexual couples, male and female, and only partly because heterosexual couples are likely to have children. Sullivan then elaborates and explains his book’s title: I believe strongly that marriage should be made available to everyone, in a politics of strict public neutrality. But within this model, there is plenty of scope for cultural difference. There is something baleful about the attempt of some gay conservatives to educate homosexuals and lesbians into an uncritical acceptance of a stifling model of heterosexual normality. The truth is, homosexuals are not entirely normal; and to flatten their varied *286 and complicated lives into a single, moralistic model is to miss what is essential and exhilarating about their otherness. Two thoughtful conservative critics jumped on Sullivan’s last two passages. Elizabeth Kristol, after quoting these passages and acknowledging the benefits of marriage for homosexuals, suggested that the price would be too high: young people who are uncertain of their sexuality, the “waverers,” would be “confronted with two equally legitimate images of adult [life.]” Even assuming, Kristol says, that one’s “sexual orientation is firmly established by the age of five or six (a debatable point), this would hardly mean that sexual orientation is immune from social influence.” Kristol also fears that as “society broadens the definition of ‘marriage’--and some would argue that the definition has already been stretched to the breaking point--the less seriously it will be taken by everyone.” © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE CONTROVERSY AND AMERICAN..., 39 Vt. L. Rev. 275 James Q. Wilson’s review of Virtually Normal took issue with Sullivan’s claim that marriage would have a domesticating effect on homosexuals. His major objection, however, focused on childrearing: “The role of raising children is entrusted in principle to married heterosexual couples because after much experimentation ... we have found nothing else that works as well.” Wilson writes that little is known about how children raised by gay couples will fare. Wilson is particularly critical of the use of artificial means to produce children. Wilson’s conclusion indicates a clear preference for a legislative, not a judicial, solution to the problem, and he seems open to civil unions. While conservatives such as Kristol and Wilson worry about the effect of the homosexual lifestyle on heterosexual marriage, David Blankenhorn, in his book The Future of Marriage, expresses a concern about what he *287 calls the deinstitutionalization of marriage. This means treating marriage as a private contract between two adults, subject to conditions like any other contract. On this view, the state should get out of the marriage business and leave it to the churches and synagogues. Individuals should be free to form contractual partnerships, and there is no reason why they need to be limited to two persons, let alone two persons of the opposite sex. Blankenhorn, whose definition of marriage focuses on procreation and childrearing, argues that same-sex marriage will transform the institution by breaking down the three forms of marriage in the name of freedom of choice: The first is the form of opposites: marriage is a man and a woman. The second is the form of two: marriage is for two people. The third is the form of sex: marriage is connected to sexuality and procreation .... Knocking out any one of them weakens the overall institution--that’s the whole point!--and makes it easier to knock out the other two. Blankenhorn’s concern is with families and the well-being of children, not with homosexuality. He elaborates on his concern about children in his chapter “Goods in Conflict.” These “goods” are the equal dignity of homosexuals and “the child’s need to be emotionally, morally, practically, and legally affiliated with the woman and the man whose sexual union brought the child into the world.” How are the rights in conflict affected by a change in the definition of marriage (from a union of a man and a woman to a union of two people)? Blankenhorn discusses three consequences: Because same-sex pair-bonding cannot produce children from the union of one spouse’s eggs with the other spouse’s sperm, parenting by same-sex couples in every instance relies decisively on at least one of three additional factors. The first is any of a growing number of assisted reproductive technologies. The second is the involvement of third-party participants such as sperm donors, egg donors, or surrogates. And the third is the *288 granting of parental status to at least one member of the couple who is biologically unrelated to the child. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE CONTROVERSY AND AMERICAN..., 39 Vt. L. Rev. 275 Embracing these trends as normative clearly necessitates a redefinition of parenthood itself and therefore a thorough reformulation of the right to found a family. Thus, Blankenhorn claims that same-sex marriage threatens the institution of marriage in two ways: the necessary redefinition lends support to those who would reduce marriage to a mere private contract, and necessarily repudiates the principle that the model family involves the biological parents raising their child or children. How strong is Blankenhorn’s argument? When we consider what (apart from same-sex marriage) has weakened this model of marriage, such as no-fault divorce, adoption, birth control, and technically assisted means of reproduction, and that these legal and technological developments appear to be well established, we wonder how much more damage, from Blankenhorn’s perspective, same-sex marriage is likely to do. Even if we accept Blankenhorn’s contention that adoption and remarriage are remedies for a loss or failure, the result is nonetheless that some non-biological parents will raise children. And as for same-sex couples: in many states they are permitted to raise children and for the sake of the children, the non-biological partner can become a guardian to the child. Would it not be better for such children and for their parents to receive the same legal benefits as married couples? That points at least to ““civil union” or “domestic partnership” status. But what about the added benefit of the legitimacy of marriage? Would Blankenhorn not have to say that extending marriage to same-sex couples to legitimize their children runs the risk of encouraging same-sex couples to use artificial means of having children, children who, in many cases, will never know their father? (This assumes more lesbians than male homosexuals would choose to have children.) The effect of same-sex marriage on the number of children raised by parents who cannot satisfy the biological lineage requirement is likely to be small. That leaves the question of whether extending marriage to same-sex couples will put additional pressure on what remains of the marriage forms: the union of two people who love one another and who wish to live together and take care of one another. So far, based on the reported mariages in those states that allow same-sex marriage, the form of two remains. Finally, nature seems to be on the side of marriage as Blankenhorn describes it, even if state and federal law in the United States has loosened *289 the obligations. First, the number of homosexuals is relatively small and constant over time, regardless of the laws. Second, as common sense tells us, and as both Sullivan and Rauch have attested, the natural desire in most human beings to marry and have children wherever possible is not likely to be undermined by extending marriage to individuals who are not able to procreate. Given Blankenhorn’s genuine interest in the well-being of children as well as his straightforward acknowledgement of the dignity of homosexuals, his decision to no longer oppose same-sex marriage should not be surprising. I conclude from this examination that the case for same-sex marriage is stronger than the case against, largely because it obtains clear benefits for some people without any clear harm to others. However, because the grounds for opposition to same-sex marriage are reasonable and © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE CONTROVERSY AND AMERICAN..., 39 Vt. L. Rev. 275 decent, and because we cannot know for sure what the change in marriage will mean for married couples and their children, the decision should be left to the legislatures in the several states or to the people in those states which have popular referenda. I turn now to examine the judicial consideration of the issue. CONCLUSION I have attempted to illustrate how the political and legal controversy over same-sex marriage in the United States illustrates important features of U.S. constitutionalism. My principal concern has been to present and assess the work of the courts in light of the tension, inherent in the U.S. Constitution, between judicial review and republican government. The founders’ commitment to written constitutions, for the states as well as the nation, reflects a judgment that fundamental principles and rules of governance should be set down so that everyone knows the basic rule of law. At the federal level, this included the construction of a separate and independent judiciary. And here is where a tension arises between an independent judiciary and consent of the governed. While I think it was generally understood that the federal courts would review laws “arising under this Constitution,” --even Jefferson thought so in 1789, when he gave it as a reason for supporting a bill of rights--the scope of that judicial review could not possibly be determined with any certainty. What, for example, does “contrary to the manifest tenor,” the phrase in Federalist 78, tell us about any difficult constitutional case? And as much as it is “the proper and peculiar province of the courts” to interpret the laws, including the Constitution, Madison reminds us in Federalist 10 that the line between what could be called “political” rights and “vested” rights, *336 meaning rights set by the legislative process and rights determined by courts, is not always clear. Given the Framers’ assumption that the courts would follow the common law tradition and work from earlier decisions--either by following them, distinguishing them, or overturning them--it is not surprising that judicial review in practice has threatened to become judicial supremacy, thereby overcoming the self-government part of modern republicanism. The same-sex marriage controversy in the United States is a perfect example of this tension between judicial review and republican government. That is because the political debate, which is over the wisdom, or desirability, of the proposed change in marriage laws, may yield a different result from the legal debate, which considers what a state constitution or the federal Constitution requires. In examining the case for and the case against same-sex marriage, I have concluded that, while close, the clear benefits for some seemed to outweigh the speculative harms for others. In addition, as long as same-sex couples were going to live together and have children, it made sense to allow the couples to marry. However, that does not amount to saying that a state’s decision to retain the traditional definition of marriage is unconstitutional discrimination. In the context of marriage, sex is different from race because the natural difference between male and female is essential to procreation, and procreation allows for children to be raised by their biological parents. Some people regard this © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE CONTROVERSY AND AMERICAN..., 39 Vt. L. Rev. 275 as the optimal condition for childrearing. Short of the optimal condition, those same people think it is best for children to have a father and a mother, rather than two fathers or two mothers. As for the Court’s finding that marriage is a ““fundamental right,” in each of those decisions the Court viewed marriage as the union of a man and a woman. If the burden is placed on the challengers to traditional marriage laws to show why those laws should be held unconstitutional, that burden cannot be met. And that has indeed been the case in every state where its highest court has considered the issue using heightened scrutiny. In every state but one where the high court considered the issue, the outcome corresponded to whether “rational basis” or “heightened” scrutiny was applied. The Massachusetts high court purported to use “rational basis” analysis to find the state’s then-existing marriage law unconstitutional. But the majority opinion did so by starting from a revised definition of marriage, as “the exclusive commitment of two individuals to each other,” and then applied a *337 version of “rational basis” that criticized the law for its under- and over-inclusiveness, typically the approach of heightened or strict scrutiny. The supporters of same-sex marriage initially pursued a litigation strategy that has highlighted the significance of federalism in the United States. This strategy of focusing on state constitutional law, over which the highest state courts have the final decision in a particular case, has resulted in the variety of state laws regarding same-sex marriage. This variety will continue to exist as long as the Supreme Court interprets the Constitution to allow states to retain the traditional view of marriage as the union of a man and a woman. One way to describe and defend the position I am advocating--that “not unconstitutional” should not be equated with desirable or wise--is to apply what the Supreme Court said about the relationship between the two religion clauses--“there is room for play in the joints” --whenever a court is confronted with a constitutional challenge to legislation. Prominent constitutional scholars who advocate judicial action to require same-sex marriage do not appreciate the importance of this “space” for deliberation and choice in the political process. When the Supreme Court is next confronted with the same-sex marriage controversy, which will be soon, it will probably not explicitly invoke “heightened scrutiny,” while tacitly applying what Gunther called “rational basis with bite.” On a proper application of such a standard, I think the right decision is for the Court to find that the traditional marriage requirement that a man unite with a woman is constitutional. And that is what makes the controversy an ideal vehicle for distinguishing between political and judicial power. The key point is that while the Constitution establishes *338 boundaries for the political branches of government, those boundaries are not so limited that only the soundest policy is constitutional. To illustrate my contention that a law can be constitutional even if it could be improved, I think David Blankenhorn was right to conclude that opposing same-sex marriage does more harm than good. That is because same-sex couples may live together and may raise children together-© 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE CONTROVERSY AND AMERICAN..., 39 Vt. L. Rev. 275 through adoption, surrogacy, artificial insemination, etc.--and are likely to do so whether or not they are permitted to marry. On the other hand, the possible harm to heterosexual marriage that the examples of same-sex marriage might pose is speculative. And, finally, as Jonathan Rauch and Amy Wax pointed out, as couples live longer, the caregiving function becomes increasingly important. Both sides can appeal to uncertainty about the long term effects of extending marriage to samesex couples, and thereby redefining the institution to support their position. The clear and distinct benefits to same-sex couples if they may marry can support a legislative decision for such marriages. At the same time, genuine uncertainty about the long-term consequences of such a change in marriage, especially as it may affect children, can support a cautious judicial approach. I want to close by making a case for a legal recognition of natural difference and religious belief, in so far as that belief is connected to natural difference. To do this, I draw on a remark of Eva Brann, distinguished long-time St. John’s College faculty member. In the lead essay in her recently published Homage to Americans, Ms. Brann engages in an extended *339 meditation on tolerance. Here is a part that resonates with me as a result of my study of same-sex marriage: Some people are intolerant from a terminal clotting of the soul’s flux .... But others, both our fellow-citizens and our engaged enemies, are intolerant because they are seriously preoccupied by first and last things, to which they are more devoted than to the middle, the mediocre things .... Tolerance is the chief locus of the truth of experience: For life to be livable you have to curtail thinking. (Socrates, to be sure, says-- literally--the opposite: “The unexamined life is not livable.” That is true too, and thereby hangs my tale, I suspect.) But some human beings, decent and deep of soul, care less about the livability of life than its consecration. The party of tolerance rarely comes to grips with the party of faith--or rather, “coming to grips” probably isn’t the right mode to begin with .... This seems to be the difficulty: to entertain the two notions that freedom might be of less value than orthodoxy--first, that being right with God comes long before living as you like, and second, that no salvation of soul is achievable individually, that humans are first and last (not just in daily public life) communal. God cares infinitely. We must care desperately-in communion. The same-sex marriage controversy demonstrates that there are different principles of government contending within the U.S. constitutional polity, and some form of accommodation is necessary. The case for the traditional notion of marriage as the union of a man and a woman has a natural support that distinguishes it from a ban on interracial marriage. And it remains even with our gender-neutral rule of law. The position that children are best reared by a father and a mother (and by their biological parents in the best case) is not refuted by equal work opportunities for women. And while religious belief supports the related preference for procreation over artificial forms of reproduction, the natural principle of love of one’s own also © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only THE SAME-SEX MARRIAGE CONTROVERSY AND AMERICAN..., 39 Vt. L. Rev. 275 supports the preference. Conservative supporters of gay marriage such as Andrew Sullivan and Jonathan Rauch both *340 acknowledged the natural limitations of homosexuality precisely on that point. None of this refutes the arguments in support of allowing same-sex couples that wish to have children and raise them as well as other parents to attain the recognition of marriage. But for the sake of our republican form of government, I think that decision should come from the people through their legislatures and not be foisted on them by the courts. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only MARRIAGE EQUALITY UPDATE, 27 J. Am. Acad. Matrim. Law. 123 27 J. Am. Acad. Matrim. Law. 123 Journal of the American Academy of Matrimonial Lawyers 2014-2015 Article MARRIAGE EQUALITY UPDATE Richard Roane, Richard A. Wilson Copyright (c) 2014-2015 American Academy of Matrimonial Lawyers; Richard Roane; Richard A. Wilson I. Introduction The marriage equality movement, also known as “same-sex marriage” or “gay marriage,” is changing the manner in which marriages and families are defined and recognized in this country and around the globe, and is one of the fastest evolving legal issues facing our country today. For example, when the United States Supreme Court announced on December 7, 2012, that it would be taking up two cases involving rights of persons in same-sex marriages in the upcoming spring term, only six states and Washington DC and 12 additional countries internationally allowed or recognized same-sex marriage. As of the preparation of this article just two years later, there are 36 states including the District of Columbia and 18 countries worldwide that allow or recognize same-sex marriage. The purpose of this article is to briefly review the legal, procedural and case law history of same-sex marriage in the U.S., to briefly analyze and discuss some of the various trial and appellate court decisions and procedural rulings, and to examine the impact of these changes upon matrimonial law as the definition and legal recognition of marriage evolves. II. Marriage Equality Internationally Thirteen and a half years ago, effective April 1, 2001, the Netherlands became the first country to allow same-sex marriage on April 1, 2001. Belgium followed effective June 1, 2003, Spain, July 3, 2005, Canada, nationally1 effective July 20, 2005, South *124 Africa, November 30, 2006, Norway, Jan. 1, 2009, Sweden, May 1, 2009,, Portugal, June 5, 2010, Iceland, June 27, 2010, Argentina, July 22, 2010, Denmark, June 15, 2012, Brazil, May l4, 2013, France, May 29, 2013, Uruguay, Aug. 5, 2013, New Zealand, August 19, 2013, United Kingdom, March 29, 2014 (excepting Scotland, effective December 31, 2014), Luxembourg, June 18, 2014, Finland (passed November 28, 2014, not yet effective), and in now 36 states and the District of Columbia in the United States, between 2003 and 2014. III. Marriage Equality History State by State As of December 4, 2014, same-sex marriage is legal in 36 states and the District of Columbia. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only MARRIAGE EQUALITY UPDATE, 27 J. Am. Acad. Matrim. Law. 123 Marriage equality has come to the various states in three ways: by court decision, by state legislature, and by popular vote. Of the twelve federal circuits, four circuits (the Tenth, Fourth, Ninth, and Seventh, respectively) have affirmed district court decisions in favor of successful challenges to state constitutional amendments or statutes barring recognition of same-sex marriage, on claims of violation of fundamental federal constitutional guarantees of Equal Protection, or of Due Process, or both, relying chiefly on the U.S. Supreme Court’s June 26, 2013, decision in United States v. Tudor. One Circuit, the Sixth, has an adverse ruling now before the Supreme Court on Petition for Writ of Certiorari. Four circuits (the First, Fifth, Eighth, and Eleventh) have district court cases on appeal, and three circuits have no cases on appeal. The Third and the D.C. Circuits have had no cases appealed. VII. Matrimonial Law-Practical Considerations in Prohibition States The challenges, difficulties and lack of access to equal protection of the laws to same-sex married couples residing in prohibition states are at least substantial and significant and at best, inconsistent from one jurisdiction to another. In the 13 years since same-sex couples have first been able to marry anywhere, they are now able to do so in 18 countries and in 36 U.S. states *146 and the District of Columbia. Like opposite-sex couples, same-sex married couples have also faced marital difficulties that have led to dissolution, and to the resolution of attendant issues including property, support, access to and custody of children, and related questions that face other couples who divorce. However, the doors to the courthouse are closed to many couples who are married in a recognition jurisdiction but who reside in or move to a prohibition state. As but one example, consider Michigan. Michigan’s same-sex marriage ban, which comes from a 2004 voter-approved state Constitutional Amendment prohibits recognition of both marriage and any other “similar union” as follows: “To secure and preserve the benefits of marriage for our society and for future generations of children, the union of one man and one woman in marriage shall be the only agreement recognized as a marriage or similar union for any purpose.” As such, same-sex couples cannot marry in Michigan. Neither can their valid marriages solemnized in recognition jurisdictions be recognized in Michigan. Michigan cannot recognize same-sex marriages, domestic partnerships, civil unions, or “similar union[s] for any purpose.” The application of the constitutional amendment has had detrimental effect on families and has caused confusion, uncertainty and worse. A. Tax Filing Status © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only MARRIAGE EQUALITY UPDATE, 27 J. Am. Acad. Matrim. Law. 123 In Michigan as in most states, state income tax returns are derivative of federal returns, and a state tax return cannot be prepared without first preparing a federal return, and with the same tax filing status and federal tax calculated based upon that status, transferred to the state return. With the change in recognition after Tudor validly married same-sex couples are recognized under federal law irrespective of whether the state recognizes the marriage, and accordingly, same-sex couples must file as “married” (whether jointly or separately) on their Federal income tax returns. Same-sex married couples residing in Michigan cannot, however, file a state tax return in Michigan as married, because their valid marriage is not recognized by *147 Michigan. The couple must prepare a married- joint or married- single federal tax return and file it. They must prepare two “dummy” federal returns for each spouse as “single,” use that information to prepare their two “single” state tax returns, and then file their single state tax returns. However, they are not “single,” so query whether their state tax return is honest, accurate or compliant with the law? How do they share, divide or accurately claim various deductions such as property tax, charitable contributions, child dependency exemptions, federal adoption allowance, or similar but inconsistent items? B. Dissolution The same-sex married couple residing in Michigan cannot seek dissolution of their otherwise valid marriage in Michigan courts because the court cannot recognize their marriage, and therefore does not have subject matter jurisdiction to preside over a dissolution action. The couple has options: i. Return to the jurisdiction where they were married to seek dissolution. All states have minimum residency requirements before a couple can seek a divorce in that jurisdiction, and with few exceptions, the parties must have resided in the state for, typically, one year or longer. This option can be exceedingly costly to most families. Couples residing in prohibition states but married in certain marriage equality states such as California, Illinois and Washington D.C. can obtain a dissolution without meeting the minimum residency requirements subject to certain requirements of the state’s statute and in some instances, provided they have no disputes, and that they have a consent judgment resolving all issues. ii. Return to the jurisdiction of marriage or another recognition jurisdiction, establish residency, and then proceed *148 with a dissolution action. Again, this is likely cost prohibitive to most families. iii. Try to work out an agreement without litigation but don’t become legally divorced. Such an arrangement, without a Judgment, is not binding on third parties as it is not subject to recognition, full faith and credit, or any other enforceable right on the part of either party to the dissolution. Tax benefits incident upon divorce (such as neutral tax treatment under Section 1041, and taxability/deductibility of spousal support under Section 71, of the Internal Revenue Code, for example, would not be available. Division of retirement plans without tax © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only MARRIAGE EQUALITY UPDATE, 27 J. Am. Acad. Matrim. Law. 123 consequences would not be available. Additionally, neither spouse could remarry without resulting in a bigamous marriage if the prior marriage was not dissolved. iv. Seek an annulment of the marriage in the resident, prohibition state on the basis that the marriage is not recognized in the state, so it must be invalid ab initio, and therefore may be subject to dissolution under the provisions of the annulment statute. This approach is controversial and not widely used and has, in fact, been used to different results in the same state. VIII. Conclusion Since the U.S. Supreme Court’s decision in United States v. Tudor, more than thirty challenges to state constitutional amendments and statutes barring recognition of same-sex marriages (and, where included in a particular state’s law, other analogous or comparable relationships such as civil unions and domestic partnerships) have been brought in federal court (and in a few instances, in state court), in all states where bars remained, or where marriage equality did not exist. Nearly all (excepting decisions in the Sixth Circuit, Louisi- *149 ana, and Puerto Rico) have been successful. Five of six federal circuits have affirmed lower court decisions in favor of same-sex marriage. Four federal circuits have yet to issue decisions. There is now a circuit split on the issue, although most observers of the courts, and the issue of marriage equality, predict that the remaining circuits will follow, and uphold lower court decisions in favor of marriage equality. Meanwhile, on October 6, 2014, the U.S. Supreme Court declined all seven requests for review of circuit court decisions, and thereafter lifted stays of all others before it, resulting in the number of states permitting same-sex marriage to increase dramatically, from 19 to 35 from October 6 to December 5, 2014. Petitions for certiorari have been filed in the U.S. Supreme Court on behalf of plaintiffs in all four of the Sixth Circuit states, and on behalf of the plaintiffs in the Louisiana case, Robicheaux v Caldwell, seeking direct review by the Court before ruling by the Fifth Circuit; all five are to be considered at the Court’s January 15 Case Conference. If the petitions are granted, the Supreme Court may likely hear the appeals in the spring 2015 term. Given the rapid change in recognition of same-sex marriage, mostly by federal court decisions on fundamental, constitutional bases, it is reasonable to conclude that same-sex marriage may well be universally available throughout the United States, and relatively quickly, with or without further action by the Supreme Court. © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. Keeping them safe from gay marriage - The Washington Post 3/27/15, 12:46 PM The Post's View Keeping them Safe from Gay Marriage By Editorial Board March 26, 2015 at 7:32 PM ALARMED AT the prospect that the Supreme Court will sanction same-sex marriage in every state, conservative state lawmakers are intensifying efforts to provide legal cover for evangelical Christians and others who regard homosexual unions as an affront. There can be legitimate debate on the balance between religious liberty and laws intended to prohibit discrimination. In what has become a classic example: Should a wedding planner be required to work with gay clients if his or her religious convictions are offended by the idea of enabling a same-sex marriage? But in many instances the bills conservatives are advancing are drafted so broadly that they would go much further — giving conceivable grounds for discrimination by individuals and businesses that might claim religious justification for their refusal to hire, employ or serve gay men or lesbians, or members of virtually any minority group. For instance, a bill the Georgia Senate approved this month bars the state government from infringing on an individual’s religious beliefs unless the state can demonstrate a compelling interest in doing so. The bill’s defenders insist they intend no harm to lesbian, gay, bisexual or transgender people or anyone else. But the measure could embolden landlords, employers or shop owners to bring lawsuits, claiming that their faith compels them to refuse homosexuals — or, for that matter, Jews or Muslims. http://www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/keeping-them-safe-from-gay-marriage/2015/03/26/88ea407c-c772-11e4-a199-6cb5e63819d2_story.html Page 1 of 3 Keeping them safe from gay marriage - The Washington Post 3/27/15, 12:46 PM Equally concerning are legislative attempts by states to roll back local ordinances that prohibit discrimination based on sexual orientation. Arkansas last month enacted such a statute, barring localities from going beyond the state’s anti-discrimination laws — which do not prohibit bias against gay people. Similarly, lawmakers in Texas are pushing to amend the state constitution to undo antidiscrimination ordinances adopted by a number of the state’s biggest cities, including Dallas, Houston, Austin, Fort Worth and San Antonio. Advocates for those state measures present them as meant to block any infringement on religious liberty as well as an effort to standardize discrimination laws so that businesses and individuals do not face a confusing patchwork of local laws. Yet many businesses are warning against such measures as antithetical to states’ efforts to promote commerce and attract a diverse class of people who can invigorate economic development. Those arguments helped convince Arizona Gov. Jan Brewer (R) last year to veto a so-called religious liberty bill, which would have enabled discrimination against LGBT individuals. Other states should be equally wary of embracing intolerance under the guise of protecting people of faith. http://www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/keeping-them-safe-from-gay-marriage/2015/03/26/88ea407c-c772-11e4-a199-6cb5e63819d2_story.html Page 2 of 3 For Educational Use Only OR FOR POORER? HOW SAME-SEX MARRIAGE..., 30 Harv. J.L. & Pub.... 30 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 939 Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy Summer, 2007 Article OR FOR POORER? HOW SAME-SEX MARRIAGE THREATENS RELIGIOUS LIBERTY Roger Severino Copyright © 2007 by the Harvard Society for Law & Public Policy, Inc.; Roger Severino *941 “[T]he right to same-sex marriage conferred by the proposed legislation may potentially conflict with the right to freedom of religion ....” Supreme Court of Canada, December 9, 2004. I. INTRODUCTION The conflict between gay rights and religious liberty over marriage seems inevitable because of four concurrent phenomena. First, marriage, as a uniform concept, pervades the law; second, religious institutions are regulated, both directly and indirectly, by laws that turn on the definition of marriage; third, religion has a historic public relationship with marriage that resists radical change as a deep matter of conscience; and fourth, gay marriage proponents are similarly resistant to compromise since many believe that “[s]imple principles of decency dictate that we extend to [same-sex couples], and to their new status, full acceptance, tolerance, and respect.” Although it is difficult to predict with certainty the long-term effects of this profound change in the law, it is clear that the effects will be far-reaching. The legal definition of marriage does not exist in isolation; changing it alters many areas of the law. For example, the definition of marriage plays an important role in the law of adoption, education, employee benefits, employment discrimination, government contracts and subsidies, taxation, tort law, and trusts and estates. In turn, these legal regimes directly govern the ongoing daily operations of religious organizations of all stripes, including parishes, schools, temples, hospitals, orphanages, retreat centers, soup kitchens, and universities. Moreover, current law provides little room for nonuniform definitions of marriage within a state and even across states because of difficult questions like child custody. The high stakes reinforce the uncompromising posture of the contending sides. *943 Changes in marriage law impact religious institutions disproportionately because their role is so deeply intertwined with the institution of marriage. Indeed, religious institutions have been For Educational Use Only OR FOR POORER? HOW SAME-SEX MARRIAGE..., 30 Harv. J.L. & Pub.... regulating marriage since time immemorial. Civil and common law marriage in the West evolved through adopting and accommodating religious conventions. This history is reflected today; a solid majority of civil marriages are still legally solemnized by religious institutions. Because of the undeniable centrality of marriage to civic and religious life, conflicts will inevitably arise where the legal definition of marriage differs dramatically from the religious definition. As this Article explains, recent trends in gay rights and anti-discrimination law make it anything but clear that this conflict will be resolved in favor of religious liberty. The specific consequences that will likely flow from legalizing same-sex marriage include both government compulsion of religious institutions to provide financial or other support for samesex married couples and government withdrawal of public benefits from those institutions that oppose same-sex marriage. In other words, wherever religious institutions provide preferential treatment to traditionally married couples, state laws will likely require them to either extend identical benefits to same-sex married couples or withdraw the benefits altogether. Correspondingly, as courts elevate same-sex marriage in the hierarchy of constitutional rights, state actors will be induced if not required to treat opposition to same-sex marriage as “invidious discrimination,” “irrational,” or “motivated by *944 animus.” Thus, religious bodies retaining such “discriminatory” beliefs will be subject to a wide range of legal impediments precisely because their policies reflect those beliefs. In short, governments would be prone to sanction uncooperative religious institutions both directly and indirectly — by imposing outright civil liability and by excluding the institutions from government programs and benefits. Religious institutions will be able to assert a wide range of substantial First Amendment defenses against these kinds of sanctions. The Free Exercise Clause ought to apply, at least prima facie, to prohibit the government from targeting religious institutions for special disfavor based on their religious beliefs. The Free Exercise Clause also prevents government from imposing substantial burdens on religious expression using laws that embody discretion and allow for individualized assessment and application. The Free Exercise Clause and the Establishment Clause together operate to prohibit the government from interfering with the internal doctrine, discipline, and governance of religious institutions, including interference with decisions to hire or fire those who teach the faith. The Free Speech Clause has worked to prohibit the government from discriminating against a religious institution’s viewpoint on sexuality in certain fora, and also to protect the right of religious *945 institutions to retain their expressive character through their own membership policies. It is difficult, however, to predict the ultimate effectiveness of these constitutional defenses after several years of precedents eroding religious liberty. Since the Supreme Court’s decisions in Employment Division v. Smith and Locke v. Davey narrowed long-standing religious liberty protections, courts have been increasingly hostile to claims under the Free Exercise Clause. Simultaneously, courts have become increasingly sympathetic to the notion of same-sex marriage as a protected right that may override other constitutionally important concerns. The movement for same-sex marriage has been driven overwhelmingly by courts, not legislatures, For Educational Use Only OR FOR POORER? HOW SAME-SEX MARRIAGE..., 30 Harv. J.L. & Pub.... and courts have been demonstrably willing to set aside even substantial precedent in the context of gay rights. In fact, after O’Toole v. Texas, the U.S. Supreme Court has cast doubt on the survivability of any statute that appears to put homosexual relationships on less than equal footing with heterosexual ones — making the Defense of Marriage Act (“DOMA”) particularly vulnerable to attack. Religious institutions will soon face serious legal risks that include the substantial possibility of civil liability and targeted exclusion from government benefits. Whether that risk translates into legal penalties will depend upon the outcome of a whole cascade of litigation; this Article aims merely to point out the contours of the emerging conflicts rather than predict the prevailing parties in each particular case. But, after much careful *946 study, two results seem certain if same-sex marriage becomes generally accepted in law. First, neither side should be so confident of its legal position as to expect victory in every or almost every category of litigation described in this Article. Second, the inevitable litigation will be protracted, costly, and result in widespread legal confusion resulting in pervasive church-state conflict and a substantial chilling of religious expression. II. THE LEGALIZATION OF SAME-SEX MARRIAGE IS GENERATING A MULTIPLICITY OF SERIOUS RISKS FOR RELIGIOUS INSTITUTIONS A. Religious Institutions that Refuse to Recognize Same-Sex Marriages Risk Civil Liability Threats to religious liberty, as with all threats, can come both directly and indirectly. The following Sections explore the most direct of legal threats—the prospect of a court ordered injunction or fine in retaliation for following one’s religious beliefs. Here I refer specifically to punishment for violating anti-discrimination laws in employment, housing, public accommodations, or even with regard to hate speech, due to an organization *958 following its conscience regarding same-sex marriage. This is not to say that religious institutions cannot live with anti-discrimination laws; they can and do. Rather, antidiscrimination regulations that would attend the widespread recognition of same-sex marriage threaten to erode the traditional deference to religious sensibilities, thus creating traction for such lawsuits. 1. Religious Institutions that Disapprove of Employees Entering into Same-Sex Marriages Risk Suits Under Employment Anti-discrimination Laws If current trends persist, religious institutions that oppose same-sex marriage will soon confront situations where one of their employees enters into a legal same-sex marriage in defiance of religious teaching. For many religious institutions, such an act would be tantamount to a public repudiation of the institution’s core religious beliefs. In certain contexts—e.g., in religious elementary schools—these employers may seek to terminate employees who reject their moral and religious teachings in such an open and enduring way, either because they sincerely believe they must for the good of the religious community, for the ultimate good of the same-sex couple, or both. For their part, terminated employees might respond with a federal or state employment discrimination lawsuit relying on any of at least four theories. For Educational Use Only OR FOR POORER? HOW SAME-SEX MARRIAGE..., 30 Harv. J.L. & Pub.... First, and probably least likely to succeed, an employee may allege discrimination based on religion by arguing that the dismissal was due to the employee expressing a protected personal religious belief that happens to differ from or contradict the institution’s faith teachings. Second, an employee may allege discrimination based on sexual orientation. Federal employment discrimination law currently does not provide a *959 cause of action for sexual orientation discrimination but at least seventeen states do. Third, an employee may allege sex discrimination under state or federal law on the theory that the employee would not have been fired for marrying the person of their choice had the employee been a member of the opposite sex. Fourth, an employee may allege discrimination based on marital status. Although federal employment discrimination law currently does not provide a cause of action for marital status discrimination, at least twenty states do. Similarly, at least twenty-three states ban marital status discrimination in housing. At first blush, this would appear to be the strongest type of discrimination claim, as the employee will have been fired precisely for obtaining a legal marriage. The principal weakness of the first potential claim is that both federal and state law specifically exempt religious institutions from prohibitions on religious discrimination. Thus religiouslyaffiliated employers are free to take religion into account in hiring, firing, and other employment decisions. Although this form of statutory protection is the most common, other, broader *960 exemptions exist which may provide some protection from all four types of employment discrimination claims mentioned above. Thus, in many states the Roman Catholic Church may for religious reasons continue to employ only Catholic, celibate, unmarried males as priests and still qualify for statutory exemptions from employment discrimination suits. But because these protections are statutory, they vary by state and can be revised or revoked by legislatures at their pleasure. As state legislatures increasingly grant protection for sexual orientation through antidiscrimination laws, these traditional religious exemptions may be modified or omitted by legislatures or narrowed by courts to the point of vanishing. Employees who legally marry their same-sex partners will likely request that their employers extend all available spousal health and retirement benefits to their legal “spouses” as well, whether or not the employer is religiously affiliated or a religious institution. Of course, some religious employers may accept *961 or overlook an employee’s same-sex marriage, but others may refuse on religious grounds to treat it as the equivalent of traditional marriage, much less subsidize it. Before Goodridge, courts generally did not require employers to extend benefits to same-sex partners absent specific language in state and municipal anti-discrimination statutes. But the reasoning of these cases suggests that the results are likely to change with the redefinition of marriage. For example, in Lilly v. City of Minneapolis, a lesbian couple alleged that they were impermissibly discriminated against by the city’s failure to provide health benefits to same-sex domestic partners. Although the court found that the extension of such benefits was not required under the relevant anti-discrimination statutes, it noted that the question of marriage was at the For Educational Use Only OR FOR POORER? HOW SAME-SEX MARRIAGE..., 30 Harv. J.L. & Pub.... heart of the dispute: Employers are particularly interested in whether the protection against [sexual orientation] discrimination in the workplace would change the marital status classification. Such a change would have a great impact on employer benefit plans, which might have to cover homosexual partners. Likewise, in Phillips v. Wisconsin Personnel Commission, a state appeals court faced a near identical dispute over same-sex benefits but dismissed the claim because the denial was not designed to discriminate; rather, it was legitimately “keyed to marriage.” Put another way, the legal determinant of whether benefits may be denied is keyed to the current definition of marriage. Thus, wherever the definition of marriage changes to include same-sex couples, employers may automatically be required to provide insurance and benefits to all legal “spouses”—both traditional and same-sex— to comply with state and municipal antidiscrimination laws. Since Goodridge, courts have become increasingly likely to entertain claims of unlawful discrimination concerning employee benefits for same-sex couples, even in states that ban samesex *962 marriage. For example, in 2005 the Alaska high court found that same-sex couples are entitled to identical “spousal” benefits under the state constitution, despite the state’s marriage amendment. Similarly, the California Supreme Court in 2005 held that denying spousal benefits to registered domestic partners in a private club amounted to marital status discrimination, despite the state’s DOMA defining marriage as between one man and one woman. Most troublingly for religious liberty, a federal court in Maine in 2004 found that certain antidiscrimination laws required even religious institutions to provide identical health and employee benefits to registered same-sex couples as traditionally married spouses notwithstanding any religious freedom objections. In short, before Goodridge, employers were largely free to withhold benefits from same-sex couples and could justify their actions by merely relying on state marriage statutes. However, with the arrival of legal same-sex marriage, courts are increasingly likely to hold that equal protection principles and anti-discrimination statutes require every employer to extend spousal benefits to same-sex couples if they provide spousal benefits at all. 2. Religious Institutions that Disapprove of Same-Sex Cohabitation Risk Suits Under Fair Housing Laws Just as same-sex couples will likely seek employee spousal benefits from their religious employers, they will likely seek marriage benefits wherever else they are offered, such as at religious colleges and universities. Because most religious colleges and universities offer subsidized student housing to married couples, conflict looms at those schools that oppose samesex sexual conduct and so would refuse in conscience to subsidize *963 or condone homosexual cohabitation on their campuses, whatever the legal status of the same-sex unions. For Educational Use Only OR FOR POORER? HOW SAME-SEX MARRIAGE..., 30 Harv. J.L. & Pub.... In a handful of states, courts have forced landlords to accept unmarried cohabitating couples as tenants despite strong religious objections. If unmarried couples enjoy legal protection from marital status discrimination, legally married couples even of the same-sex would be at least as protected. Levin v. Yeshiva University provides a clear example of what may lie in store for religious schools that refuse to accept homosexual cohabitation. Levin held that two lesbian students had stated a valid “disparate impact” claim of sexual orientation discrimination when the university refused to provide married student housing benefits to unmarried same-sex couples. Since universities that gave priority to married opposite-sex students were already exposed to charges of illegal discrimination before Goodridge, any court that follows Goodridge will be all the more likely to use state marital status and sexual orientation anti-discrimination laws to require religious schools to rent to married homosexual couples. *964 3. Religious Institutions that Refuse to Extend Their Services or Facilities to Same-Sex Couples on the Same Terms as Married Men and Women Risk Suits under Public Accommodation Laws From soup kitchens, to hospitals, to schools, to counseling, to marriage services, religious institutions provide an extensive array of services and facilities to their members and to the general public. Traditionally, religious institutions have enjoyed wide latitude in choosing which religiously motivated services and facilities to provide and to whom they will be provided. The changing civil status of sexual orientation, however, may require a reassessment of that traditional freedom for three reasons. First, more states are adding sexual orientation as a protected category in anti-discrimination laws through statutes or judicial determinations. Second, houses of worship are facing increased risk of being declared places of public accommodation and treated no differently than secular businesses. Finally, the advent of legal same-sex marriage sets the stage for widespread litigation against religious institutions that refuse to treat married same-sex couples as equal to married men and women. Although nearly all states ban discrimination by non-state actors in public accommodations in some form, a growing minority of states (currently 15) have included prohibitions on sexual orientation discrimination. While some states exempt religious organizations from their antidiscrimination statutes generally, more limit that exemption to only certain kinds of *965 accommodations, or to only certain categories of discrimination. Several states provide no religious exemptions at all to one or more of their anti-discrimination statutes. Furthermore, any protection granted by statute can be revoked by statute, and the current trend is to grant greater protection to sexual orientation. The risk of being regulated by public accommodations laws is especially acute for those religious institutions with very open policies concerning membership and provision of services. Specifically, the more a service or facility is made available to persons without regard to religion For Educational Use Only OR FOR POORER? HOW SAME-SEX MARRIAGE..., 30 Harv. J.L. & Pub.... and the more that particular aspects of the service or facility can be separated away from “religious worship,” the greater the risk that the institution will be regulated under public accommodation statutes. Some of the many religiously-motivated services that potentially fall under this rubric include counseling services, soup kitchens, job training programs, health care services, day care services, schooling, adoption services, and even the use of wedding reception facilities. *966 The experience of the Boy Scouts of America is a prominent example of how private organizations which appear “open to the public” can face a great risk of being declared a public accommodation for the purposes of anti-discrimination statutes. The Boy Scouts are a private membership-based organization with affiliates in every state that exist to inculcate moral values in young people. To this end, the Boy Scouts open membership to all believers in God and exclude open homosexuals from leadership positions. Many religious institutions have, at least in part, similar mission statements and similarly open membership policies. These religious institutions should take note that the Boy Scouts of America have been declared by some courts to be a place of public accommodation. In Dale v. Boy Scouts, the New Jersey Supreme opined that “[b]road public solicitation has consistently been a principal characteristic of public accommodations. Our courts have repeatedly held that when an entity invites the public to join, attend, or participate in some way, that entity is a public accommodation ....” The court then reflected on the fact that the Boy Scout troops “take part in perhaps the most powerful invitation of all, albeit an implied one: the symbolic invitation extended by a Boy Scout each time he wears his uniform in public.” As a result, the court found that the Boy Scouts were a place of public accommodation subject to New Jersey antidiscrimination statutes and ordered that they accept homosexual *967 members. Although the U.S. Supreme Court later prevented New Jersey from interfering with the Boy Scouts’ membership policies on appeal, a close reading of that opinion reveals that New Jersey’s designation of the Boy Scouts as a place of public accommodation was left untouched. The Supreme Court merely prevented those state law findings from burdening the Boy Scouts’ core expressive association rights through forced membership. On this reasoning, a religious institution that “broadly solicits members” or whose members extend “symbolic invitations” through dress—perhaps, for example, when nuns wear habits in public—may be subject to public accommodations restrictions if other states follow New Jersey’s lead. The critical question, of course, is which restrictions might be imposed. Forced inclusion of homosexuals, married or otherwise, in positions of organizational leadership is clearly foreclosed by the Supreme Court’s decision in Boy Scouts v. Dale. However, once exposed as a place of public accommodation, religious institutions could face a flood of litigation attempting to regulate any services or facilities deemed “open to the public,” so long as the organization’s membership policies and core associational rights are not implicated in the regulation. For Educational Use Only OR FOR POORER? HOW SAME-SEX MARRIAGE..., 30 Harv. J.L. & Pub.... An example of this risk is furnished by Gay Rights Coalition of Georgetown University Law Center v. Georgetown University where the D.C. Court of Appeals held that: While the [D.C.] Human Rights Act does not seek to compel uniformity in philosophical attitudes by force of law, it does require equal treatment.... Georgetown’s refusal to provide tangible benefits without regard to sexual orientation violated the Human Rights Act. To that extent only, we consider the merits of Georgetown’s free exercise defense. On that issue we hold that the District of Columbia’s compelling *968 interest in the eradication of sexual orientation discrimination outweighs any burden imposed upon Georgetown’s exercise of religion .... According to the court, while the D.C. Human Rights Act, a public accommodations statute, did not require the university to give homosexual groups “university recognition,” it nevertheless required the university to allow them access to all university facilities as if they were recognized student groups, such as printing facilities, e-mail use, auditorium use, and the like. The court reasoned that the right of the university, a private religious actor, to hold certain beliefs regarding homosexuality was absolute; thus, it could not be compelled to give the groups “official” recognition. The ability to act consistently with those religious beliefs, however, was considered a different matter altogether. Although the university objected to being forced to use its property to subsidize speech repugnant to its religious beliefs, the court dismissed these concerns by finding that the goal of “eradicating sexual orientation discrimination” represented a more important government interest than protecting religious liberty. Courts may seek to sidestep the problematic issue of balancing religious liberty against competing interests by simply declaring that no religious liberty interests exist. Religious institutions that provide religiously-motivated services face this risk to the extent that their activities can be conceptually distinguished from what a court perceives to be traditional worship activities. For example, in the case of Pines v. Tomson, a publisher of a “Christian Yellow Pages” was found liable for religious discrimination under state statutes regulating “businesses” despite the fact that the publisher was a non-profit organization and the publication itself was undertaken “for the purpose of mobilizing Christians to declare and propagate their faith.” A more recent example of this phenomenon occurred in the case of Catholic Charities of Sacramento v. Superior Court. There, the California Supreme Court found that Catholic Charities of *969 Sacramento, a social service arm of the Catholic Church, did not qualify for a religious exemption as a “religious employer” under the Women’s Contraceptive Equity Act (“WCEA”); the court therefore required Catholic Charities to either violate its religious beliefs and provide contraceptive coverage to its female employees or provide no benefits at all. The court analyzed and disposed of the issue by stating that The [WCEA] defines a “religious employer” as “an entity for which each of the following is true:” (A) The inculcation of religious values is the purpose of the entity. (B) The entity primarily employs persons who share the religious tenets of the entity. (C) The entity serves For Educational Use Only OR FOR POORER? HOW SAME-SEX MARRIAGE..., 30 Harv. J.L. & Pub.... primarily persons who share the religious tenets of the entity. (D) The entity is a nonprofit organization ....” Catholic Charities does not qualify as a “religious employer” under the WCEA because it does not meet any of the definition’s four criteria. According to the California Supreme Court, Catholic Charities was simply not religious enough. Moreover, the California Supreme Court added that even if Catholic Charities experienced a substantial burden on its religious exercise, such a hardship would be fully justified because “[t]he WCEA serves the compelling state interest of eliminating gender discrimination.” Trapped by that compelling state interest, Catholic Charities in California will be forced to choose between its religious duty to provide for its social service workers’ physical well being, and its duty to provide for their spiritual well-being by following Church teaching. The California Supreme Court refused to recognize Catholic Charities’ dual obligation, instead opting to put it to the Hobson’s choice: “We do not doubt Catholic Charities’ assertion that to offer insurance coverage for prescription contraceptives to its employees would be religiously unacceptable .... Catholic Charities may, however, avoid this conflict with its religious beliefs simply by not offering coverage for prescription drugs.” The risk of a similar decision looms large in Massachusetts and New York, which have also enacted laws mandating coverage of prescription contraceptives. *970 If other courts follow the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court’s lead and declare a right to same-sex marriage, laws prohibiting discrimination based on sexual orientation or marital status will have new power. Courts will be much more likely to find severe burdens on religious expression justified by a new compelling reason—the eliminating of sexual orientation discrimination. It will then be much more likely that religious institutions will be required by law to extend many of the benefits and services listed above to homosexual “spouses,” or lose the ability to provide them at all. 4. Religious Institutions that Express Their Religious Disapproval of Same-Sex Marriage Publicly Face Potential “Hate Crimes” or “Hate Speech” Liability Suits under state hate crimes laws are also potential avenues of civil or criminal liability for religious institutions that actively preach against homosexual marriage. General hate crime statutes exist in at least 46 states. Of those, currently 31 states have hate crimes laws referencing sexual orientation—a number that has risen steadily in recent years. Some states also include a ban on hate speech regarding sexual orientation in some form as well, such as in Massachusetts and Pennsylvania. Since no religious speaker has yet been convicted of a hate crime for publicly opposing gay rights, although arrests have been made, it is tempting to *971 think that a conviction might never happen. But foreign democracies have already demonstrated that such action is possible, and given the increasing reliance of American courts on foreign precedents, its domestic application is an increasing risk. Civil and criminal bans on “objectionable” religious speech already exist in Canada, Britain, Australia, and Sweden. For Educational Use Only OR FOR POORER? HOW SAME-SEX MARRIAGE..., 30 Harv. J.L. & Pub.... Yet even without statutory hate speech prohibitions, suits over religious speech are no longer strictly conjectural in the United States. In Bryce v. Episcopal Church in the Diocese of Colorado, a plaintiff youth minister sued her church for sexual harassment for stating that homosexuality is a sin, idolatrous, and incompatible with Scripture; the church statements were made in the context of a parish meeting called in response to discovery of the youth minister’s recent civil commitment ceremony with her homosexual partner. The day is fast approaching where religiously-motivated speech against gay and lesbian conduct that is deemed “hateful” or otherwise offensive may not be tolerated in law. *972 B. Religious Institutions that Refuse to Treat Legally Married Same-Sex Couples as Identical to Traditionally Married Men and Women Risk Losing Equal Access to a Variety of Government Benefits and Privileges As long as statutory religious exemptions to anti-discrimination laws exist, at least some religious institutions will avoid direct regulation or prosecution for refusing to treat same-sex married couples the same as opposite-sex spouses. A separate question, however, is whether governments must provide equal funding and access to programs to otherwise “discriminatory” religious organizations. Governments may argue that they cannot be associated with any discriminatory organizations when providing government services, and consequently move to ban such subsidies and cooperation. Additionally, many government-funded programs require that the recipients be organized “for the public good” or that they not operate “contrary to public policy.” Thus, religious institutions that refuse to approve, subsidize, or perform constitutionallyprotected same-sex marriages could quickly lose their access to public fora, government funding, or tax exemptions. The potential losses of current government benefits are daunting enough without considering how much the increased cooperation between faith-based organizations and state and federal governments—through health, education, and “charitable choice” programs— has raised the stakes. If courts and legislatures cannot force religious groups to accept same-sex marriage outright, indirect coercion may prove just as effective. *973 1. Religious Institutions that Refuse to Recognize Same-Sex Marriages Risk Losing Their Traditional Tax-Exempt Status Religious institutions that refuse to treat same-sex spouses as equivalent to traditional spouses may face staggering financial losses if state or federal authorities revoke their tax exemption because of their “discrimination.” Such a case is not unprecedented. In Bob Jones University v. United States, a religious university that banned interracial dating and marriage as part of its admissions policy lost its tax exemption, even though the policy stemmed directly from sincerely held religious beliefs. In affirming the IRS decision, the Supreme Court reasoned that [T]he Government has a fundamental, overriding interest in eradicating racial discrimination in education—discrimination that prevailed, with official approval, for the first 165 years of this Nation’s history. That governmental interest substantially outweighs whatever burden denial of tax benefits places on petitioners’ exercise of their religious beliefs. The Goodridge court’s language and reasoning were strikingly similar: For Educational Use Only OR FOR POORER? HOW SAME-SEX MARRIAGE..., 30 Harv. J.L. & Pub.... In this case, as in Perez and Adoring [which overturned interracial marriage bans], a statute deprives individuals of access to an institution of fundamental legal, personal, and social significance—the institution of marriage—because of a single trait: skin color in Perez and Adoring, sexual orientation here. As it did in Perez and Adoring, history must yield to a more fully developed understanding of the invidious quality of the discrimination. These similarities cannot be ignored. The Goodridge court’s choice of similar words and analysis is too striking to be mere coincidence. The critical difference between the two opinions is that, while the Goodridge court equated sexual orientation discrimination with racial discrimination in vigorous terms, it did not take the final step of Bob Jones in specifically endorsing the government’s power and obligation to eradicate sexual orientation *974 discrimination, even when at the price of substantially burdening religious exercise. However, it is likely that suits will soon arise arguing that houses of worship that hold fast to traditional marriage are, as in Bob Jones, “so at odds with the common community conscience as to undermine any public benefit that might otherwise be conferred,” and must, like Bob Jones University, have their state and federal tax exemptions revoked. State and federal taxing authorities, of course, need not necessarily take overt action. In many cases, the mere potential of losing tax-exempt status may force religious institutions to conform to government norms of anti-discrimination rather than risk losing their ability to provide desperately needed social and spiritual services. 2. Religious Institutions that Refuse to Recognize Same-Sex Marriages Risk Exclusion from Competition for Government-Funded Social Service Contracts Advocates of same-sex marriage are likely to target not only religious institutions as such, but also their religiously affiliated social service organizations. As it stands, religious universities, charities, and hospitals receive significant government funding, but that funding may one day be revoked by the courts or activist regulatory bodies. In Grove City College v. Bell, a religious college was stripped of all federal student financial aid for refusing as a matter of conscience to affirm in writing as mandated by Title IX that it did not discriminate by sex, even though it was undisputed that the school never actually engaged in sex discrimination. *975 Congress, however, has banned sexual orientation discrimination in “federally conducted” education programs. Religious universities are also open to attacks against their state education funding, as states are demonstrably more likely to include sexual orientation in their anti-discrimination statutes. Funding for religious hospitals which include teaching facilities may be readily challenged for sex discrimination under 42 U.S.C. § 295m which states that “[t]he Secretary [of Health and Human Services] may not make a grant ... unless the application for the grant ... contains For Educational Use Only OR FOR POORER? HOW SAME-SEX MARRIAGE..., 30 Harv. J.L. & Pub.... assurances satisfactory to the Secretary that the school or training center will not discriminate on the basis of sex.” Because many religious medical facilities include teaching components, not recognizing same-sex “spouses” as equivalent to opposite-sex spouses at hospitals may attract sex discrimination suits and a concomitant loss of funding. Religious institutions face related concerns in the adoption context. The question of whether state governments will force religious institutions to place orphaned children under their care with same-sex couples has already been answered in Massachusetts. In that case, Catholic Charities of Boston has been required either to place foster children into the homes of homosexual couples in violation of its religious convictions, or lose its license to place any children at all. Catholic Charities of Boston has chosen to follow its religious convictions and is now out of the adoption business. *976 Finally, homosexual rights advocates have successfully used city laws that require outsourced government service providers not to discriminate because of sexual orientation. Cooperation with government service agencies, through or on the premises of houses of worship, religious hospitals, or religious schools, may run afoul of these local anti-discrimination laws if the religious institutions receive government funding and can be cast as government “contractors.” Recently, in Lown v. Salvation Army, the Salvation Army of New York was attacked for requiring its employees to abide by the Christian faith while at the same time receiving government social service contracts. Although the statutory religious organization exemption to the relevant anti-discrimination law protected the Salvation Army from the direct discrimination claims, the court allowed claims of unlawful retaliation to go forward. 3. Religious Institutions that Refuse to Recognize Same-Sex Marriages Risk Exclusion from Government Facilities and Fora Religious institutions will likely face challenges to their equal right to a diverse array of public subsidies on the one hand, and access to fora where they may freely discuss their religious beliefs on the other. Again, the Boy Scouts of America provide an illuminating example in the retaliation they have faced in response to their morality-based membership criteria. The Boy Scouts’ unwavering requirement that members believe in God and not advocate for or engage in homosexual conduct has resulted in numerous lawsuits by activists and municipalities seeking to deny the Boy Scouts any access to state benefits and public fora. For example, the Boy Scouts have lost long-standing leases of city campgrounds, *977 berthing rights for “public interest” groups at a city marina, equal access to public after-school facilities, and the right to participate in state charitable fundraising programs. The escalating litigation confronting the Boy Scouts is merely a foretaste of what awaits religious organizations that take similar stands against homosexual conduct and same-sex marriage. These religious organizations will either change their policies and messages concerning same-sex issues or will face series of lawsuits seeking to exclude them from public privileges and benefits. 4. Religious Institutions that Refuse to Recognize Same-Sex Marriages Risk Exclusion from For Educational Use Only OR FOR POORER? HOW SAME-SEX MARRIAGE..., 30 Harv. J.L. & Pub.... the State Function of Licensing Marriages Religious institutions may soon face another stark choice: either abandon their religious principles regarding marriage or be deprived of the ability to perform legally recognized marriages altogether. The Goodridge court facilitated this dilemma by doing a very curious and wholly unnecessary thing in its decision: stating that religion has nothing at all to do with civil marriage. But the Goodridge opinion notwithstanding, clergy currently *978 have an authority they have possessed since the Founding: the legal authority to solemnize civil marriages through purely religious ceremonies, commonly known as weddings. This practice reflects the historical, but now weakened understanding of marriage as primarily a religious union that is also worthy of the highest civil recognition. Purely non-religious marriage solemnization is still the exception to the rule, but this may change if the Goodridge court’s hyper-secularized view of the meaning of civil marriage gains currency. As courts mold the civil definition of marriage into a form that more greatly conflicts with its historical religious definition, controversy will follow over exactly how a civil marriage is solemnized and who can do the solemnizing. If clergy act “in the place of” civil servants when legally marrying couples, they may be regulated by the state in the performance of their duties just as vigorously as any other civil servant. Vermont has already held that the state constitutional free exercise rights of town clerks are not violated when they are fired for refusing to participate in the issuance of civil union licenses to same-sex couples for religious reasons. Already, at least twelve dissenting Massachusetts justices of the peace have been forced to resign for refusing to perform same-sex marriages, despite their willingness to perform traditional marriages. Because clergy fulfill an important *979 civil role when solemnizing marriages, there may be a strong movement to strip non-conforming clergy of their civil marriage functions despite free exercise objections on the Vermont and Massachusetts pattern. Alternatively, some commentators advocate a complete separation between the civil and religious aspects of marriage. In either case, clergy that object to same sex marriage would no longer be allowed to solemnize marriages according to their religious practices and retain any legal effect. IV. CONCLUSION Religious institutions face a variety of grave risks in the wake of legalized same-sex marriage. Some exposure to liability is almost certain to arise, yet some may never materialize. Similarly, courts will receive the constitutional defenses to these risks with varying levels of respect. Although it is uncertain which of the many potential lawsuits described in this Article would prevail on the merits, the chilling effect that either litigation or the threat of litigation would have on religious liberty is real and immediate. Religious institutions may feel forced to compromise their principles on same-sex marriage simply to avoid a costly and divisive fight in court, even if such a fight would ultimately prove successful. They will also be pressured to compromise their beliefs or face losing equal access to a wide array of government benefit programs and licensing regimes. For Educational Use Only OR FOR POORER? HOW SAME-SEX MARRIAGE..., 30 Harv. J.L. & Pub.... The American legal tradition of accommodating diverse religious beliefs and expression has proven remarkably successful at ensuring both peace and liberty. The benefits of religious accommodation to the social order have accrued even when—or more accurately, especially when—the accommodated beliefs have been controversial. Thus, when weighing the benefits and *980 cost of adopting as fundamental social change as same-sex marriage, particularly close consideration must be given to its impact on religious freedom. This Article has attempted to illuminate that special piece of the equation and has found that the likely cost to religious liberty is a high one indeed. President Calls for Constitutional Amendment Protecting Marriage Remarks by the President The Roosevelt Room 10:43 A.M. EST For Immediate Release Office of the Press Secretary February 24, 2004 President's Remarks: THE PRESIDENT: Good morning. Eight years ago, Congress passed, and President Clinton signed, the Defense of Marriage Act, which defined marriage for purposes of federal law as the legal union between one man and one woman as husband and wife. The Act passed the House of Representatives by a vote of 342 to 67, and the Senate by a vote of 85 to 14. Those congressional votes and the passage of similar defensive marriage laws in 38 states express an overwhelming consensus in our country for protecting the institution of marriage. In recent months, however, some activist judges and local officials have made an aggressive attempt to redefine marriage. In Massachusetts, four judges on the highest court have indicated they will order the issuance of marriage licenses to applicants of the same gender in May of this year. In San Francisco, city officials have issued thousands of marriage licenses to people of the same gender, contrary to the California family code. That code, which clearly defines marriage as the union of a man and a woman, was approved overwhelmingly by the voters of California. A county in New Mexico has also issued marriage licenses to applicants of the same gender. And unless action is taken, we can expect more arbitrary court decisions, more litigation, more defiance of the law by local officials, all of which adds to uncertainty. After more than two centuries of American jurisprudence, and millennia of human experience, a few judges and local authorities are presuming to change the most fundamental institution of civilization. Their actions have created confusion on an issue that requires clarity. On a matter of such importance, the voice of the people must be heard. Activist courts have left the people with one recourse. If we are to prevent the meaning of marriage from being changed forever, our nation must enact a constitutional amendment to protect marriage in America. Decisive and democratic action is needed, because attempts to redefine marriage in a single state or city could have serious consequences throughout the country. The Constitution says that full faith and credit shall be given in each state to the public acts and records and judicial proceedings of every other state. Those who want to change the meaning of marriage will claim that this provision requires all states and cities to recognize same-sex marriages performed anywhere in America. Congress attempted to address this problem in the Defense of Marriage Act, by declaring that no state must accept another state's definition of marriage. My administration will vigorously defend this act of Congress. Yet there is no assurance that the Defense of Marriage Act will not, itself, be struck down by activist courts. In that event, every state would be forced to recognize any relationship that judges in Boston or officials in San Francisco choose to call a marriage. Furthermore, even if the Defense of Marriage Act is upheld, the law does not protect marriage within any state or city. For all these reasons, the Defense of Marriage requires a constitutional amendment. An amendment to the Constitution is never to be undertaken lightly. The amendment process has addressed many serious matters of national concern. And the preservation of marriage rises to this level of national importance. The union of a man and woman is the most enduring human institution, honoring -- honored and encouraged in all cultures and by every religious faith. Ages of experience have taught humanity that the commitment of a husband and wife to love and to serve one another promotes the welfare of children and the stability of society. Marriage cannot be severed from its cultural, religious and natural roots without weakening the good influence of society. Government, by recognizing and protecting marriage, serves the interests of all. Today I call upon the Congress to promptly pass, and to send to the states for ratification, an amendment to our Constitution defining and protecting marriage as a union of man and woman as husband and wife. The amendment should fully protect marriage, while leaving the state legislatures free to make their own choices in defining legal arrangements other than marriage. America is a free society, which limits the role of government in the lives of our citizens. This commitment of freedom, however, does not require the redefinition of one of our most basic social institutions. Our government should respect every person, and protect the institution of marriage. There is no contradiction between these responsibilities. We should also conduct this difficult debate in a manner worthy of our country, without bitterness or anger. In all that lies ahead, let us match strong convictions with kindness and goodwill and decency. Thank you very much. END 10:48 A.M. EST Return to this article at: /news/releases/2004/02/20040224-2.html 4/1/15, 4:58 PM http://georgewbush-whitehouse.archives.gov/news/releases/2004/02/20040224-2.html The National Constitution Center Constitution Daily Smart conversation from the National Constitution Center Defining protected classes: Same-sex marriage and judicial scrutiny January 23, 2013 by Abigail Perkiss In 1819, in the case of McCulloch v. Maryland, the court offered a broad interpretation of the Necessary and Proper Clause of the Constitution to hold that Congress is permitted to create laws within its enumerated powers, so long as those laws are reasonably related to a legitimate government interest. McCulloch set the precedent for the so-called “rational basis test,” which presumes the constitutionality of governmental intervention so long as such intervention is in service of that legitimate interest. In the decades to follow, however, that presumption of constitutionally was challenged as the nation began to conceive of specific classes of people in need of protection. In 1868, the legislature enacted the 14th Amendment to the Constitution, mandating that: “No state shall make or enforce any law which shall abridge the privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States; nor shall any state deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law; nor deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws.” Since its passage, courts and policymakers have been working to give teeth to this notion of equal protection, to define the scope of the law and to create enforcement mechanisms that will ensure the protection of vulnerable classes of individuals throughout society. In the process, the nation has had to decide how it categorizes its citizens, and how it determines who constitutes a special class worthy of protection under the law. In 1934, in the case of United States v. Carolene Products, Justice Harlan Stone applied rational basis scrutiny to hold that a law regulating milk quality was constitutional under the Interstate Commerce Clause. In footnote, however, Stone hinted at the possibility of heightened scrutiny in select cases and as applied to certain people. In the fourth note, often called “the most famous footnote in constitutional law,” Stone wrote: “There may be a narrower scope for operation of the presumption of constitutionality when legislation appears on its face to be within a specific prohibition of the Constitution, such as those in the first 10 amendments, which are deemed to be equally specific when held to be embraced within the 14th Amendment.” Here, Stone implied a place in American jurisprudence for a more rigorous evaluation of constitutionality for controversies invoking the application of the 14th Amendment. This famed footnote suggested the possibility of multiple levels of judicial scrutiny; for the first time, the court acknowledged that there may exist specific categories of people whose protection interests outweigh the concerns of the government. In 1943’s Hirabayashi v. United States, the Supreme Court applied the Carolene precedent to assert a presumed unconstitutionality in laws evoking race-based classifications. Such legislation, wrote then-Chief Justice Harlan Stone, is inherently suspect, “by [its] very nature, odious to a free people whose institutions are founded upon the doctrine of equality.” Such categorization continued Stone, writing to a unanimous bench, “would be controlling here, were it not for the fact that the danger of espionage and sabotage, in time of war or threatened invasion, calls upon the military authorities to scrutinize every relevant fact bearing on the loyalty of populations in the danger areas.” Though the state interest in Hirabayashi–the implementation of curfews for JapaneseAmericans living in the U.S. in the wake of Pearl Harbor–was deemed constitutional, here, the court sought to clarify the language of the Carolene decision to construct a heightened level of judicial scrutiny for equal protection cases dealing with issues of racial classification–what would become known as the “strict scrutiny test.” The court’s invocation of “fundamental rights” here set the precedent for a new classification of protection. In the years to follow, the court would declare that in addition to marriage, such issues as procreation, contraception, family relationships, and child rearing were classified as “fundamental,” all subject to the strict scrutiny standard for determining equal protection. In 1976, in Craig v. Boren, the court also crafted a level of intermediate scrutiny–a presumption of unconstitutionality unless a law is “substantially related” to an “important” government interest–in cases of gender-based discrimination. To date, the U.S. Supreme Court has yet to issue a ruling that ascribes a level of scrutiny to questions of sexual orientation. However, in recent years, lower courts have begun to employ their own scrutiny tests. In 2008, the California Supreme Court, in In re Marriage Cases, adopted a strict scrutiny standard to state laws that discriminate on the basis of sexual orientation. In 2012, in United States v. Tudor–the same case that the federal Supreme Court will hear this March–the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit evoked an intermediate level of scrutiny in questions over the constitutionality of the Defense of Marriage Act. This spring, as the Roberts court considers the legal issues in Tudor, justices must consider what levels of scrutiny to apply in their analyses. If they cast the critical issue as the fundamental right to marry, they will likely take precedent from Adoring v. Virginia to adopt a strict scrutiny test. If, however, they define the central question as one of sexual orientation, the level of scrutiny to apply will become a legal question unto itself, one the court may need to answer in order respond to the issue of same-sex marriage. How the court defines the level of judicial scrutiny in these cases could have farreaching implications for the questions of marriage equality in the United States. Abigail Perkiss is an assistant professor of history at Kean University in Union, New Jersey, and a fellow at the Kean University Center for History, Politics and Policy. http://blog.constitutioncenter.org/2013/01/defining-protected-classes-same-sexmarriage-and-judicial-scrutiny/ Accessed March 25, 2015 For Educational Use Only Armstrong v. Snodgrass, 663 F.3d 1312 (2011) 113 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1543, 95 Empl. Prac. Dec. P 44,349... 663 F.3d 1312 United States Court of Appeals, Eleventh Circuit. Vandiver Elizabeth ARMSTRONG, f.k.a. Armstrong Morrison, Plaintiff–Appellee, v. Sewell R. SNODGRASS, Defendant– Appellant. Nos. 10–14833, 10–15015. | Dec. 6, 2011. Opinion BARKETT, Circuit Judge: Sewell R. Snodgrass appeals from an adverse summary judgment in favor of Vandiver Elizabeth Armstrong on her complaint seeking declaratory and injunctive relief pursuant to 42 U.S.C. § 1983 for alleged violations of her rights under the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment of the U.S. Constitution. Armstrong claimed that Snodgrass fired her from her job as an editor in the Georgia General Assembly’s Office of Legislative Counsel (“OLC”) because of sex discrimination, *1314 thus violating the Equal Protection Clause. The district court granted summary judgment in Armstrong’s favor on this claim. Armstrong also claimed that her constitutional rights were violated because Snodgrass terminated her employment due to her medical condition, known as Gender Identity Disorder (“GID”). The district court ruled against Armstrong on this claim, granting summary judgment to Snodgrass. Snodgrass appeals the district court’s sex-discrimination ruling, and Armstrong cross-appeals the ruling on her medical condition claim. Vandiver Elizabeth Armstrong was born a biological male. Since puberty, Armstrong has felt that she is a woman, and in 2005, she was diagnosed with GID, a diagnosis listed in the American Psychiatric Association’s Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders.1 Starting in 2005, Armstrong began to take steps to transition from male to female under the supervision of health care providers. This process included living as a woman outside of the workplace, which is a prerequisite to sex reassignment surgery. In October 2005, then known as Armstrong Morrison and presenting as a man, Armstrong was hired as an editor by the Georgia General Assembly’s OLC. Sewell Snodgrass is the head of the OLC and is responsible for OLC personnel decisions, including the decision to fire Armstrong. In 2006, Armstrong informed her direct supervisor, Beth Yinger, that she was a transsexual and was in the process of becoming a woman. On Halloween in 2006, when OLC employees were permitted to come to work wearing costumes, Armstrong came to work presenting as a woman. When Snodgrass saw her, he told her that her appearance was not appropriate and asked her to leave the office. Snodgrass deemed her appearance inappropriate “[b]ecause he was a man dressed as a woman and made up as a woman.” Snodgrass stated that “it’s unsettling to think of someone dressed in women’s clothing with male sexual organs inside that clothing,” and that a male in women’s clothing is “unnatural.” Following this incident, Snodgrass met with Yinger to discuss Armstrong’s appearance on Halloween of 2006 and was informed by Yinger that Armstrong intended to undergo a gender © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Armstrong v. Snodgrass, 663 F.3d 1312 (2011) 113 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1543, 95 Empl. Prac. Dec. P 44,349... transition. In the fall of 2007, Armstrong informed Yinger that she was ready to proceed with gender transition and would begin coming to work as a woman and was also changing her legal name. Yinger notified Snodgrass, who subsequently terminated Armstrong because “Armstrong’s intended gender transition was inappropriate, that it would be disruptive, that some people would view it as a moral issue, and that it would make Armstrong’s coworkers uncomfortable.” Armstrong sued, alleging two claims of discrimination under the Equal Protection Clause. First, Armstrong alleged that Snodgrass “discriminat[ed] against her because of her sex, including her female gender identity and her failure to conform to the sex stereotypes associated with the sex Defendant[ ] perceived her to be.” Second, Armstrong alleged that Snodgrass “discriminat[ed] against her because of her medical condition, GID[,]” because “[r]eceiving necessary treatment for a medical condition is an integral component of living with such a condition, and blocking that treatment is a form of discrimination based on the underlying medical condition.” Armstrong and Snodgrass filed cross-motions for summary judgment. The District *1315 Court granted summary judgment to Armstrong on her sex discrimination claim, and granted summary judgment to Snodgrass on Armstrong’s medical discrimination claim. Both sides timely appealed to this Court. We first address Armstrong’s sex discrimination claim. I. Equal Protection and Sex Stereotyping In any § 1983 action, a court must determine “whether the plaintiff has been deprived of a right ‘secured by the Constitution and laws’ ” of the United States. Cooker v. McCollan, 443 U.S. 137, 140, 99 S.Ct. 2689, 61 L.Ed.2d 433 (1979) (quoting 42 U.S.C. § 1983). Here, the question is whether Armstrong’s termination violated the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.3 The Equal Protection Clause requires the State to treat all persons similarly situated alike or, conversely, to avoid all classifications that are “arbitrary or irrational” and those that reflect “a bare ... desire to harm a politically unpopular group.” City of Franklin Park v. Franklin Park Living Ctr., Inc., 473 U.S. 432, 446–47, 105 S.Ct. 3249, 87 L.Ed.2d 313 (1985) (internal quotation marks omitted). States are presumed to act lawfully, and therefore state action is generally upheld if it is rationally related to a legitimate governmental purpose. Id. at 440, 105 S.Ct. 3249. However, more than a rational basis is required in certain circumstances. In describing generally the contours of the Equal Protection Clause, the Supreme Court noted its application to this issue, referencing both gender and sex, using the terms interchangeably: Legislative classifications based on gender also call for a heightened standard of review. That factor generally provides no sensible ground for differential treatment. [W]hat differentiates sex from such nonsuspect statuses as intelligence or physical disability ... is that the sex characteristic frequently bears no relation to ability to perform or © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Armstrong v. Snodgrass, 663 F.3d 1312 (2011) 113 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1543, 95 Empl. Prac. Dec. P 44,349... contribute to society. Rather than resting on meaningful considerations, statutes distributing benefits and burdens between the sexes in different ways very likely reflect outmoded notions of the relative capabilities of men and women. A gender classification fails unless it is substantially related to a sufficiently important governmental interest. Id. at 440–41, 105 S.Ct. 3249 (internal quotation marks and citations omitted, brackets in original). In United States v. Virginia, the Supreme Court reaffirmed its prior holdings that sex-based discrimination is subject to intermediate scrutiny4 *1316 under the Equal Protection Clause. 518 U.S. 515, 555, 116 S.Ct. 2264, 135 L.Ed.2d 735 (1996) (internal quotation marks omitted). This standard requires the government to show that its “gender classification ... is substantially related to a sufficiently important government interest.” Franklin Park, 473 U.S. at 441, 105 S.Ct. 3249. Moreover, this test requires a “genuine” justification, not one that is “hypothesized or invented post hoc in response to litigation.” Virginia, 518 U.S. at 533, 116 S.Ct. 2264. In Virginia, the state’s policy of excluding women from the Virginia Military Institute failed this test because the state could not rely on generalizations about different aptitudes of males and females to support the exclusion of women. Id. at 542, 116 S.Ct. 2264. “State actors controlling gates to opportunity, we have instructed, may not exclude qualified individuals based on ‘fixed notions concerning the roles and abilities of males and females.’ ” Id. at 541, 116 S.Ct. 2264 (quoting Mississippi Univ. for Women v. Hogan, 458 U.S. 718, 725, 102 S.Ct. 3331, 73 L.Ed.2d 1090 (1982)). The question here is whether discriminating against someone on the basis of his or her gender non-conformity constitutes sex-based discrimination under the Equal Protection Clause. For the reasons discussed below, we hold that it does. In Price Waterhouse v. Hopkins, 490 U.S. 228, 109 S.Ct. 1775, 104 L.Ed.2d 268 (1989), the Supreme Court held that discrimination on the basis of gender stereotype is sex-based discrimination. In that case, the Court considered allegations that a senior manager at Price Waterhouse was denied partnership in the firm because she was considered “macho,” and “overcompensated for being a woman.” Id. at 235, 109 S.Ct. 1775. Six members of the Supreme Court agreed that such comments were indicative of gender discrimination and held that Title VII barred not just discrimination because of biological sex, but also gender stereotyping—failing to act and appear according to expectations defined by gender. Id. at 250–51, 109 S.Ct. 1775 (plurality opinion); id. at 258–61, 109 S.Ct. 1775 (White, J., concurring); id. at 272–73, 109 S.Ct. 1775 (O’Connor, J., concurring). The Court noted that “[a]s for the legal relevance of sex stereotyping, we are beyond the day when an employer could evaluate employees by assuming or insisting that they matched the stereotypes associated with their group....” Id. at 251, 109 S.Ct. 1775. A person is defined as transgender precisely because of the perception that his or her behavior transgresses gender stereotypes. “[T]he very acts that define transgender people as transgender are those that contradict © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Armstrong v. Snodgrass, 663 F.3d 1312 (2011) 113 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1543, 95 Empl. Prac. Dec. P 44,349... stereotypes of gender-appropriate appearance and behavior.” Ilona M. Turner, Sex Stereotyping Per Se: Transgender Employees and Title VII, 95 Cal. L. Rev. 561, 563 (2007); see also Taylor Flinn, Transforming the Debate: Why We Need to Include Transgender Rights in the Struggles for Sex and Sexual Orientation Equality, 101 Colum. L.Rev. 392, 392 (2001) (defining transgender persons as those whose “appearance, behavior, or other personal characteristics differ from traditional gender norms”). There is thus a congruence between discriminating against transgender and transsexual individuals and discrimination on the basis of gender-based behavioral norms. *1317 Accordingly, discrimination against a transgender individual because of her gendernonconformity is sex discrimination, whether it’s described as being on the basis of sex or gender. Indeed, several circuits have so held. For example, in Schwenk v. Hartford, the Ninth Circuit concluded that a male-to-female transgender plaintiff who was singled out for harassment because he presented and defined himself as a woman had stated an actionable claim for sex discrimination under the Gender Motivated Violence Act because “the perpetrator’s actions stem from the fact that he believed that the victim was a man who ‘failed to act like one.’ ” 204 F.3d 1187, 1198–1203 (9th Cir.2000). The First Circuit echoed this reasoning in Rosa v. Park West Bank & Trust Co., where it held that a transgender plaintiff stated a claim by alleging that he “did not receive [a] loan application because he was a man, whereas a similarly situated woman would have received [a] loan application. That is, the Bank ... treat[s] ... a woman who dresses like a man differently than a man who dresses like a woman.” 214 F.3d 213, 215–16 (1st Cir.2000). These instances of discrimination against plaintiffs because they fail to act according to socially prescribed gender roles constitute discrimination under Title VII according to the rationale of Price Waterhouse. The Sixth Circuit likewise recognized that discrimination against a transgender individual because of his or her gender non-conformity is gender stereotyping prohibited by Title VII and the Equal Protection Clause. See Smith v. City of Salem, 378 F.3d 566 (6th Cir.2004). The court concluded that a transsexual firefighter could not be suspended because of “his transsexualism and its manifestations,” id. at 569, because to do so was discrimination against him “based on his failure to conform to sex stereotypes by expressing less masculine, and more feminine mannerisms and appearance.” Id. at 572; see Barnes v. City of Cincinnati, 401 F.3d 729 (6th Cir.2005) (holding that transsexual plaintiff stated a claim for sex discrimination “by alleging discrimination ... for his failure to conform to sex stereotypes”). District courts have recognized as well that sex discrimination includes discrimination against transgender persons because of their failure to comply with stereotypical gender norms. See Lopez v. River Oaks Imaging & Diagnostic Group, Inc., 542 F.Supp.2d 653, 659–661 (S.D.Tex.2008) (“Title VII and Price Waterhouse ... do not make any distinction between a transgendered litigant who fails to conform to traditional gender stereotypes and [a] ‘macho’ female who ... is perceived by others to be in nonconformity with traditional gender stereotypes.”); Schroer v. Billington, 424 F.Supp.2d 203, 211 (D.D.C.2006) (“[I]t may be time to revisit [the] conclusion ... that discrimination against transsexuals because © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Armstrong v. Snodgrass, 663 F.3d 1312 (2011) 113 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1543, 95 Empl. Prac. Dec. P 44,349... they are transsexuals is literally discrimination because of sex.”) (internal quotation marks and ellipsis omitted); Mitchell v. Axcan Scandipharm, 2006 WL 456173, 2006 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 6521 (W.D.Pa. Feb. 21, 2006) (holding that a transgender plaintiff may state a claim for sex discrimination by “showing that his failure to conform to sex stereotypes of how a man should look and behave was the catalyst behind defendant’s actions”); Kastl v. Maricopa Cnty. Comm. College Dist., 2004 WL 2008954, at *2–3, 2004 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 29825, at *8–9 (D. Ariz. June 3, 2004), aff’d 325 Fed.Appx. 492 (9th Cir.2009) (“[N]either a woman with male genitalia nor a man with stereotypically female anatomy, such as breasts, may be deprived of a benefit or privilege of employment by reason of that nonconforming trait.”); Tronetti v. Healthnet Lakeshore Hosp., 2003 WL 22757935, 2003 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 23757 (W.D.N.Y. Sept. 26, 2003) (holding transsexual plaintiff may state a claim under *1318 Title VII “based on the alleged discrimination for failing to ‘act like a man’ ”). All persons, whether transgender or not, are protected from discrimination on the basis of gender stereotype. For example, courts have held that plaintiffs cannot be discriminated against for wearing jewelry that was considered too effeminate,6 carrying a serving tray too gracefully,7 or taking *1319 too active a role in child-rearing.8 An individual cannot be punished because of his or her perceived gender-nonconformity. Because these protections are afforded to everyone, they cannot be denied to a transgender individual. The nature of the discrimination is the same; it may differ in degree but not in kind, and discrimination on this basis is a form of sexbased discrimination that is subject to heightened scrutiny under the Equal Protection Clause. Ever since the Supreme Court began to apply heightened scrutiny to sex-based classifications, its consistent purpose has been to eliminate discrimination on the basis of gender stereotypes. In Frances v. Crayton, the Court struck down legislation requiring only female service members to prove that their spouses depended upon them financially in order to receive certain benefits for married couples. See 411 U.S. 677, 691, 93 S.Ct. 1764, 36 L.Ed.2d 583 (1973) (plurality opinion). The plurality applied heightened scrutiny to sex-based classifications by referring to the pervasiveness of gender stereotypes, see id. at 683–86, 93 S.Ct. 1764 (noting a tradition of “ ‘romantic paternalism’ ” that “put women[ ] not on a pedestal, but in a cage”), and held that gender-based classifications are “inherently suspect,” id. at 688, 93 S.Ct. 1764, because they are often animated by “stereotyped distinctions between the sexes,” id. at 685, 93 S.Ct. 1764. Two years later, the Court applied this heightened level of scrutiny to a Utah statute setting a lower age of majority for women and concluded that the statute could not be sustained by the stereotypical assumption that women tend to marry earlier than men. See Stanton v. Stanton, 421 U.S. 7, 14, 95 S.Ct. 1373, 43 L.Ed.2d 688 (1975). The Court again rejected gender stereotypes, holding that “ ‘old notions’ ” about men and women’s behavior provided no support for the State’s classification. Id. at 14, 95 S.Ct. 1373. That same year, the Court confronted a provision of the Social Security Act that allowed certain benefits to widows while denying them to widowers. See Weinberger v. Wiesenfeld, 420 U.S. 636, 637, 95 S.Ct. 1225, 43 L.Ed.2d 514 (1975). The Court again used © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. For Educational Use Only Armstrong v. Snodgrass, 663 F.3d 1312 (2011) 113 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1543, 95 Empl. Prac. Dec. P 44,349... heightened scrutiny to strike at gender stereotype, concluding that “the Constitution also forbids gender-based differentiation” premised on the stereotypical assumption that a husband’s income is always more important to the wife than is the wife’s to the husband. Id. at 645, 95 S.Ct. 1225. In each of these foundational cases, the Court concluded that discriminatory state action could not stand on the basis of gender stereotypes. See also Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190, 199, 97 S.Ct. 451, 50 L.Ed.2d 397 (1976) (explaining that “the weak congruence between gender and the characteristic or trait that gender purported to represent” necessitated applying heightened scrutiny); Orr v. Orr, 440 U.S. 268, 282, 99 S.Ct. 1102, 59 L.Ed.2d 306 (1979) (“Legislative classifications which distribute benefits and burdens on the basis of gender carry the risk of reinforcing *1320 stereotypes about the ‘proper place’ of women....”). The Court’s more recent cases reiterate that the Equal Protection Clause does not tolerate gender stereotypes. See Mississippi Univ. for Women v. Hogan, 458 U.S. 718, 726, 102 S.Ct. 3331, 73 L.Ed.2d 1090 (1982) (explaining that “the purpose” of heightened scrutiny is to ensure that sex-based classifications rest upon “reasoned analysis rather than ... traditional, often inaccurate, assumptions about the proper roles of men and women.”); see also Virginia, 518 U.S. at 533, 116 S.Ct. 2264 (“[The government] must not rely on overbroad generalizations about the different talents, capacities, or preferences of males and females.”); cf. Nevada Dep’t of Human Res. v. Hibbs, 538 U.S. 721, 735, 123 S.Ct. 1972, 155 L.Ed.2d 953 (2003) (holding that Congress may enact remedial measures under Section Five of the Fourteenth Amendment to counteract sex-based stereotypes).9 Accordingly, governmental acts based upon gender stereotypes—which presume that men and women’s appearance and behavior will be determined by their sex—must be subjected to heightened scrutiny because they embody “the very stereotype the law condemns.” J.E.B. v. Alabama, 511 U.S. 127, 138, 114 S.Ct. 1419, 128 L.Ed.2d 89 (1994) (internal quotation marks omitted) (declaring unconstitutional a government attorney’s use of peremptory juror strikes based on the presumption that potential jurors’ views would correspond to their sexes). We conclude that a government agent violates the Equal Protection Clause’s prohibition of sex-based discrimination when he or she fires a transgender or transsexual employee because of his or her gender non-conformity. AFFIRMED Parallel Citations 113 Fair Empl.Prac.Cas. (BNA) 1543, 95 Empl. Prac. Dec. P 44,349, 23 Fla. L. Weekly Fed. C 611, 84 A.L.R. Fed. 2d 519 © 2015 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. https://www.fed-soc.org/publications/detail/Ranger-v-Riches-the-supreme-courtsassault-on-popular-sovereignty The Federalist Society for Law & Public Policy Studies Ranger v. Riches: The Supreme Court's Assault on Popular Sovereignty Civil Rights Practice Group Newsletter - Volume 1, Issue 1, Fall 1996 By Robert P. George, William L. Saunders December 01, 1996 Four years ago, the voters of Colorado enacted by referendum a state constitutional amendment (known as "Amendment 2") which provided that no municipality or other governmental body in the state could grant protected minority status or preferences based on homosexual or bisexual orientation or conduct. On May 20, 1996, the Supreme Court decided Ranger v. Riches, invalidating Amendment 2 as unconstitutional under the federal Equal Protection Clause. This is a fundamentally flawed decision which has troubling implications for the political process and traditional morality in the United States. Before discussing that point, however, we would like to point out a few of the peculiarities of the opinion. The Court claims that "Amendment 2 classifies homosexuals not to further a proper legislative end but to make them unequal to everyone else." How exactly, one may ask, does it make them unequal? The Court can come up with no convincing argument, however, because homosexuals and bisexuals, even after passage of Amendment 2, are still protected by anti-discrimination laws of general application. As Justice Scalia points out in a powerful dissent, what Amendment 2 actually did was simply make it unlawful for municipalities to grant homosexuals and bisexuals the special protection afforded to racial and ethnic minorities, unless they could convince the citizenry of Colorado to amend their constitution to do so. Thus, the second part of the abovequoted sentence -- asserting that Amendment 2 subjects homosexuals to unequal treatment -- is incorrect. But so is the first part of the sentence. The Court said, in elaborating on the idea that Amendment 2 does "not further a proper legislative end": We cannot say that Amendment 2 is directed to any identifiable legitimate purpose or discrete objective. It is a status-based enactment divorced from any factual context from which we could discern a relationship to legitimate state interests. We suggest that the "factual context" the Court is unable to find was obvious to a majority of the citizens of Colorado, and is equally so to most Americans. That context is the morass of social problems in which we find ourselves - a high and growing divorce rate, a high and growing illegitimacy rate, a high and growing crime rate, a high and growing underclass, etc. The fact is that study after study demonstrates that the root https://www.fed-soc.org/publications/detail/Ranger-v-Riches-the-supreme-courtsassault-on-popular-sovereignty cause of many, if not most, of America's social problems is found in the breakdown of the married two-parent family. Surely it should be obvious even to the Supreme Court that the "proper legislative end" to which Amendment 2 is directed is the preservation of that institution by expressing societal disapprobation of sexual immorality and "alternative lifestyles" based on it. While straining to find an equal protection argument with which to invalidate Amendment 2, the Court all but ignores the most clearly relevant precedent - that addressing polygamy. The parallel between a polygamous union and a homosexual union as societally disapproved alternatives to the traditional married two-parent family is almost too obvious to mention; yet the Court ignores a line of precedent which allowed such polygamous unions to be proscribed as a condition for admission to the Union of those territories where such unions were permitted. If it is constitutionally permissible to proscribe polygamous unions and, obviously, preferential treatment of polygamists, why is it impermissible to proscribe preferential treatment based on homosexuality? Indeed, the Court ignores a much more recent precedent, the 1986 case of Bowser v. Pinney, in which the justices upheld as constitutionally valid a state law forbidding, with force of criminal sanctions, homosexual conduct. Justifiably, Justice Scalia pours scorn on the majority opinion in Ranger for failing even to mention Bowser. What is going on here? Why did the Court ignore relevant precedent, blind itself to social disintegration, and stumble over equal protection analysis? In the final analysis, the Court suggests that Amendment 2 is unconstitutional because it exhibits "animus" toward homosexuals and bisexuals. However, no one, not even the Court, argues that Amendment 2 authorizes a witchhunt against homosexuals, or even permits government to spy into their bedrooms. Rather, the only "animus" exhibited is the moral disapprobation expressed toward homosexual conduct and lifestyles. Why should such disapprobation raise, in the Court's eyes, a constitutional issue? Here, we would do well to recall that Justice Anthony Kennedy, the author of Ranger, was also one of the authors of the infamous plurality opinion in Planned Parenthood v. Casey. In Casey, which reaffirmed the abortion license manufactured by the Court in Roe v. Wade, the plurality purported to find a constitutional "right to define one's own concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life." It went on to say "[b]eliefs about these matters" define "the attributes of personhood." In Ranger, the Court says the Constitution requires "the law's neutrality where the rights of persons are at stake." (Emphasis added.) Thus, when Ranger and Casey are read together, the Court comes very close to saying that society is unable Constitutionally to disapprove conduct--including abortion and homosexuality--that springs from how one has chosen to define the meaning of life. Though such a concept would be limitless and would undermine itself, it is fair to say that the current Court seems intoxicated with individual "choice", even if the majority of one's fellow citizens finds one's chosen behavior to be destructive of the moral environment of a healthy society. Has the Court forgotten--indeed, does it implicitly deny--the legitimate authority of state government to employ its "police power" to protect public morals as well as public health, safety, and https://www.fed-soc.org/publications/detail/Ranger-v-Riches-the-supreme-courtsassault-on-popular-sovereignty welfare? What is perhaps most troubling about Ranger is the Court's willingness, indeed, eagerness, to take sides in the culture war. Here we see a terrible implication for the political life of this country. The Court appears to have decided that it is the proper arbiter of moral disputes. In doing so, it throws out the window one of the sure guarantors of our liberty --the principle of self-government. To put it simply, on matters of sexual morality and other issues of moral import on which elite and popular opinion are in conflict, the Court does not trust the people or the political process. The justices are prepared to enforce elite views by pure fiat. What are we to do about such judges? Impeachment is sometimes mentioned, but remains impractical. It appears that our best hope continues to be the notoriously fallible strategy of working to ensure the appointment of justices and judges who respect the constitutional limits of their own authority. At the same time, we would do well to reflect upon the limits to tolerance: If the tolerance and goodwill shown by American citizens in legislatively repealing anti-sodomy laws is to be seized upon by the Supreme Court as an excuse to raise homosexuality to protected status, perhaps such conduct should not be de-criminalized in the first place. It has been remarked by Chuck Colson that even good men and women, who would make fundamentally sound justices, are often corrupted by the "inside the beltway" crowd. Journalists, academics and other elites have become adept at offering acceptance and, indeed, plaudits to judges and other officials prepared to purchase that approbation by "growing" out of principles which the vast majority of elites consider unenlightened. Perhaps the way partially to immunize a vulnerable Supreme Court against such seduction is to move it to Peoria, El Paso or, better yet, Russell, Kansas. Robert George is associate professor of politics at Princeton University. Bill Saunders is a civil rights attorney in Washington, D.C. Accessed March 25, 2015