1nc “USFG should” means the debate is about a policy established by governmental means Jon M. ERICSON, Dean Emeritus of the College of Liberal Arts – California Polytechnic U., et al., 3 [The Debater’s Guide, Third Edition, p. 4] The Proposition of Policy: Urging Future Action In policy propositions, each topic contains certain key elements, although they have slightly different functions from comparable elements of value-oriented propositions. 1. An agent doing the acting ---“The United States” in “The United States should adopt a policy of free trade.” Like the object of evaluation in a proposition of value, the agent is the subject of the sentence. 2. The verb should—the first part of a verb phrase that urges action. 3. An action verb to follow should in the should-verb combination. For example, should adopt here means to put a program or policy into action though governmental means. 4. A specification of directions or a limitation of the action desired. The phrase free trade, for example, gives direction and limits to the topic, which would, for example, eliminate consideration of increasing tariffs, discussing diplomatic recognition, or discussing interstate commerce. Propositions of policy deal with future action. Nothing has yet occurred. The entire debate is about whether something ought to occur. What you agree to do, then, when you accept the affirmative side in such a debate is to offer sufficient and compelling reasons for an audience to perform the future action that you propose. That means the affirmative has to affirm legalization in one or more of the topic areas. This is best for predictable limits – the only way to have a discussion in which all sides are prepared to debate is if we are all aware of what the terms of the debate will be. There are infinite criticisms that exist outside of the resolution that are overly specific and unpredictable. This means we can never be ready to engage in the specifics. The more their specific arguments are true, the more we need to be able to predict exactly what the affirmative is so we can go in depth on the subject and clash with the affirmative. Modest predictability of the resolution is worth potential substantive tradeoff. Topicality creates space for relevant debate. Toni M. MASSARO, Professor of Law, University of Florida, 89 [August, 1989, “Empathy, Legal Storytelling, and the Rule of Law: New Words, Old Wounds?” Michigan Law Review, 87 Mich. L. Rev. 2099, Lexis] Yet despite their acknowledgment that some ordering and rules are necessary, empathy proponents tend to approach the rule-of-law model as a villain. Moreover, they are hardly alone in their deep skepticism about the rule-of-law model. Most modern legal theorists question the value of procedural regularity when it denies substantive justice.52 Some even question the whole notion of justifying a legal decision by appealing to a rule of law, versus justifying the decision by reference to the facts of the case and the judges' own reason and expe-rience.53 I do not intend to enter this important jurisprudential de-bate, except to the limited extent that the "empathy" writings have suggested that the rule-of-law chills judges' empathic reactions. In this regard, I have several observations. My first thought is that the rule-of-law model is only a model. If the term means absolute separation of legal decision and "politics," then it surely is both unrealistic and undesirable.54 But our actual statutory and decisional "rules" rarely mandate a particular (unempathetic) response. Most of our rules are fairly open-ended. "Relevance," "the best interests of the child," "undue hardship," "negligence," or "freedom of speech" - to name only a few legal concepts hardly admit of precise definition or consistent, predictable application. Rather, they represent a weaker, but still constraining sense of the rule-of-law model. Most rules are guidelines that establish spheres of relevant conversation, not mathematical formulas. Moreover, legal training in a common law system emphasizes the indeterminate nature of rules and the significance of even subtle variations in facts. Our legal tradition stresses an inductive method of discovering legal principles. We are taught to distinguish different "stories," to arrive at "law" through experience with many stories, and to revise that law as future experience requires. Much of the effort of most first-year law professors is, I believe, devoted to debunking popular lay myths about "law" as clean-cut answers, and to illuminate law as a dynamic body of policy determinations constrained by certain guiding principles.55 As a practical matter, therefore, our rules often are ambiguous and fluid standards that offer substantial room for varying interpretations. The interpreter, usually a judge, may consult several sources to aid in decisionmaking. One important source necessarily will be the judge's own experiences -including the experiences that seem to determine a person's empathic capacity. In fact, much ink has been spilled to illuminate that our stated "rules" often do not dictate or explain our legal results. Some writers even have argued that a rule of law may be, at times, nothing more than a post hoc rationalization or attempted legitimization of results that may be better explained by extralegal (including, but not necessarily limited to, emotional) responses to the facts, the litigants, or the litigants' lawyers,56 all of which may go un-stated. The opportunity for contextual and empathic decisionmaking therefore already is very much a part of our adjudicatory law, despite our commitment to the rule-of-law ideal. Even when law is clear and relatively inflexible, however, it is not necessarily "unempathetic." The assumed antagonism of legality and empathy is belied by our experience in rape cases, to take one important example. In the past, judges construed the general, open-ended standard of "relevance" to include evidence about the alleged victim's prior sexual conduct, regardless of whether the conduct involved the defendant.57 The solution to this "empathy gap" was legislative action to make the law more specific - more formalized. Rape shield statutes were enacted that controlled judicial discretion and specifically defined relevance to exclude the prior sexual history of the woman, except in limited, justifiable situations.58 In this case, one can make a persuasive argument not only that the rule-of-law model does explain these later rulings, but also that obedience to that model resulted in a triumph for the human voice of the rape survivor. Without the rule, some judges likely would have continued to respond to other inclinations, and admit this testimony about rape survivors. The example thus shows that radical rule skepticism is inconsistent with at least some evidence of actual judicial behavior. It also suggests that the principle of legality is potentially most critical for people who are least understood by the decisionmakers - in this example, women - and hence most vulnerable to unempathetic ad hoc rulings. A final observation is that the principle of legality reflects a deeply ingrained, perhaps inescapable, cultural instinct. We value some procedural regularity - "law for law's sake" - because it lends stasis and structure to our often chaotic lives. Even within our most intimate relationships, we both establish "rules," and expect the other party to follow them.59 Breach of these unspoken agreements can destroy the relationship and hurt us deeply, regardless of the wisdom or "substantive fairness" of a particular rule. Our agreements create expectations, and their consistent application fulfills the expectations. The modest predictability that this sort of "formalism" provides actually may encourage human relationships.60 1nc The aff claims “spirituality grounds the political” in anti-colonialism. Gregor McLENNAN Sociology @ Bristol ‘7 “Towards Postsecular Sociology?” Sociology 41 (5) p. 859-866 To take these themes further, I want to indicate how the issue of secularism/ postsecularism has become pivotal to four different areas of social theory. In interpreting these developments, I challenge the ease with which some postsecularists move from observations on the social role of faith or spirituality to intellectual endorsements of faith-led perspectives on social life. From any generally naturalistic perspective on the idea of sociology (e.g. McLennan, 2006), the strains of fideism and obscurantism that surface in these literatures give cause for concern. Thus, when Burawoy rousingly announces that sociology today must show its public face by defending civil society and the interests of humanity against the tyrannies of the market and the state, it is becoming important to add … ‘and against the encroachments of religiosity too’. This does not mean that sociologists cannot be religious; it just means that their religiosity comes into play when, for whatever reason, their sociology ceases to provide the answers they seek. Expressions of Postsecularism: Poststructuralist Vitalism As with the term postmodern, the ‘post’ in postsecular need not automatically signal anti-secularism, or what comes after or instead of secularism. For many, the key postsecular move is simply to question and probe the concept of the secular, and to re-interrogate the whole ‘faith versus reason’ problematic that has so consistently punctuated modern thought. This probing seems timely, not least because under postpositivist lights, mainstream philosophical thought is now fairly comfortable about looking at modern science itself as a kind of ‘web of belief’. Accordingly, little is to be gained by harking back to rigidly scientistic models for sociological epistemology. Even so, it remains hard to see how sociology can be other than ‘on the side of science’, and the postsecular move to surpass the antinomy between (religious) faith and (naturalistic) reason turns out to be much easier said than done. Let me exemplify this claim by examining one ‘postmodernist’ expression of postsecularism, noting first that several prominent figures within poststructuralist social theory (Virilio, Kristeva, de Certeau, Agamben) have pointed to new forms of ‘re-enchantment’ in the world, or highlighted the sacred forms of‘bare life’, or insisted that the received view of modernity itself as being thoroughly disenchanted is plain mistaken (Bennett, 2001). Derrida (2001), for his part, has been developing something like ‘religion beyond religion’, while Rorty is trying to square his erstwhile secular postmodern pragmatism with Vattimo’s idea that secularization itself is our contemporary way of following the religious life (Rorty and Vattimo, 2005). Finally, Zizek (2003) has been arguing that in a secular world that is hardly ‘beyond belief’, the JudeoChristian heritage must be defended for the sake of Leninist politics. All these expressions of postsecular theory are interesting; but too complex and cryptic for our purposes. More amenable to summary treatment is political theorist William Connolly’s manifesto Why I am Not a Secularist (1999), which also reveals something of the current renaissance of vitalism. Connolly insists that the kinds of distinctions that are characteristic of secular social thought, such as that between public and private, and between reason, emotion and morality, have completely broken down. Secularists, he says, uphold such distinctions mainly in order to screen out any ‘metaphysics of the supersensible’, and so those distinctions themselves stand, precisely, as metaphysical commitments. And viewed in that light, secular philosophies can then be regarded, and pitied, as essentially ‘winter’ doctrines, formulae in search of an impossible moral stabilization and cognitive purity. But if instead we develop an ‘impious reverence for life’, embracing rather than disavowing desire, the visceral and the impure, and accepting wholeheartedly the mixedness of modes of apprehension whereby we grasp the ‘protean energies’ that flow through the organization of all things, then we are better placed to avoid the political exclusionism that necessarily results whenever the ‘irrational’ is intellectually stigmatized or empirically ignored. What then emerges is a more pluralistic, open, life-enhancing ethical stance, one that requires us to abjure altogether the traditional opposition of social science to religious worldviews. Instead, a conscious embrace of ‘multiple loyalties’ should be cultivated, a spiritual openness that might be regarded as nothing less than the very soul of the ‘democratic adventure’ (Connolly, 1999: 24, 54, 88, 95). There are two main problems with this apparently refreshingly innocent outlook. The first is that this kind of discourse is characteristically expressive and philosophical rather than social scientific, and whilst many of us would insist that these two facets of social understanding are closely interwoven, they are not identical. One need not follow Goldthorpe (2004) in dismissing the kind of general debates that I listed at the head of this article, and no doubt this particular discussion of postsecularism too, as nothing but ‘pretend social science’ to grow weary of indeterminate reflexive speculation, untrammelled by empirical positivity and systematic propositional thinking. Thus, leaving aside the question of how good it is as philosophy, it is not obvious that Connolly’s freewheeling postsecularism could ground any public sociology as such, rather than serving as one kind of straw in the wind. But in any case, secondly, it remains unclear how deeply postsecular Connolly’s discourse actually is, and how far it is particularly encouraging of those who take their religious faith seriously. As one observant reviewer on an Islamicist web journal noted,1 the whole framework of argument that Connolly constructs, and the agonistic moral pose adopted, are ‘only intelligible within a secularist worldview’. Notably, he ‘does not deliver a single confessional reflection’, and exudes merely ‘a dogmatic claim of uncertainty’ that genuine believers can only experience as thoroughly disingenuous. This is germane, because the moralistic tone that is evident in Connolly’s discourse gains much of its strength from the implication that his ‘open’ perspective on the plenitude of social being would be something that the faithful would thank him for bringing to their attention. No wonder, then, that as his discussion wears on, Connolly spins his stance in rather different terms, naming it finally as one of ‘ironic evangelical atheism’, signalling a spirit of ‘nontheistic gratitude for the … plurivocity of being’ (1999: 159). Secularism may well be in question here, but it has hardly been negated. Transcendental Realism My second instance of postsecularism highlights the way in which authors within the critical realist movement have moved embark upon spiritually steadily away from their 1970s’ concern to be specifically ‘for science in the social sciences’ (Papineau, 1978) to transcendent quests. Critics always suspected realism of being overly metaphysical, proliferating theses about the nature and levels of being that were strictly surplus to investigative requirements. And realism, internally, was from the start somewhat divided between naturalist and anti-naturalist strands (Benton, 1981). But now Roy Bhaskar, its leading theorist over the years, has developed critical realism into a cosmic speculative philosophy that is increasingly dislocated from social science explanatory practice. Bhaskarian realism now claims directly to access, and to name, in a series of extravagant hypostatizations, the essential objects of understanding – ‘the transcendent’, the ‘ultimatum’, ‘the absolute simpliciter’, and ‘the categorical structure of the world’. This is no longer a project to establish the plain old truth, but an self-grounding ground of all being’, or, in simple terms, God (Bhaskar, 2000: 31). By way of such spiralling equations (man=God=unconditional love/joy=the cosmic envelope), all remnants of analytical precision and empirical constraint are thrown to the winds. But it gets worse, because a foolish piece of intellectual blackmail is thrown in for good measure: if you choose to be sceptical about all this, then you are ‘in denial’, victim of the ‘cardinal error of Western philosophy’, namely seeking and proposing a purely ‘positive’ account of being that falsely ‘absents’ the fundamental category of ‘absence’ itself (Bhaskar, 2000: 7–8). In trying to come immanent unveiling of what realists now call the ‘alethic’ truth, a kind of really true truth, sometimes rendered as ‘ the to terms with this inflated, reifying, entirely self-sustaining run of thought, Popper’s notion of falsifiability once again comes to mind as a useful criterion of assessment. The sociological theorist Margaret Archer can no longer quite follow Bhaskar in his ‘odyssey’, but she too increasingly seeks to find within both realism and sociology an essentially religious rationale. For Archer and her co-authors, the driving idea is to correct the previous secular bias within realist circles by establishing a ‘level playing field’ between atheistic realists and those who are believers (Archer et al., 2004: x). To that end, the argument is put forward that we can be realist ‘about God’ in just the same way that we can be realist about other deep-lying forces and powers, the exact nature of whose existence typically escapes the everchanging state of empirical knowledge. Realism, after all, enables us to hold our ontological commitments steady, even when a large degree of epistemic relativism is inescapable. God’s existence can therefore be rationally debated, and credible points can be made on both sides. Belief and disbelief in God are thus both held to be rational responses. It follows that ‘the objective arguments for and against God’s existence are equally strong, or weak’ (Archer et al., 2004: 3). But this train of argument is flawed. Realism, in the first place, is not, or at least should not be, the kind of philosophy that enjoins us to be realist ‘about’ anything in particular. Originally, the realist project was to give an ontological overview of the different levels of structure and appearance involved in any substantive process of knowledge, but the nature and identity of any specific existents and generative mechanisms were strictly the business of the specific sciences. What specific investigative practice, it needs to be asked, informs us of the nature and existence of God? Moreover, conclusions about what happens to exist, and in what relations to other forces, are arrived at within the special sciences only after painstaking, systematic, and publicly available empirical evidence and theoretical reasoning concerning generative mechanisms and developmental patterns. Yet the ‘knowledge’ that we have of God is accepted to be simply not of this kind, being chiefly a matter of revelation. In that sense, the contemporary ‘realist’ debate about God is no further forward than the one about the status of personal testimony concerning miracles that pitted David Hume against George Campbell 250 years ago. We have good grounds, then, to think that being realist ‘about’ God is not a viable or productive posture for (scientific) realists to adopt, or one that is in any tangible way related to questions of substantive social investigation. Notice, in addition, the conceptual slippage that marks Archer’s argument. People do indeed have reasons for believing in God, and in that sense there is no problem about thinking of the debate about God as ‘rational’ in a broad sense. But it does not follow from the holding of reasons on both sides, that belief and disbelief are equally rational responses. And even if they were considered equally rational responses, that would not justify the conclusion that equally objective arguments existed on both sides, nor would it mitigate the peculiarity of the idea that objective arguments come in various strengths, ranging from ‘weak’ to ‘strong’. Archer’s more sociological efforts to establish parity for religious consciousness are blocked by parallel non-sequiturs. In Being Human (2000) – much of which I find valuable – Archer specifies our ‘triune’ social environment as comprising the ‘practical order’, the ‘natural order’ and the ‘social order’, and each ofthese is said to possess a distinctive logic. Definitive of the practical order, Archer insists, is that its modes of knowledge and personal orientation are nothing like ‘applied’ rational understanding, nor can they be regarded as the consequences of sociality and solidarity per se. Rather, the logic of practice is a matter of embodied, experiential, ritualized, illuminated comprehension, and religious practice stands as the quintessential example of this (Archer, 2000: 184–6). As a sui generis form of practical action, this is deemed to be not (just) a matter of social routine, but of genuine knowledge, specifically religious knowledge, in which emotionality and understanding are too closely fused together, and too close to the lived discipline of ecstasy, to be analysed in a superficially ‘rational’ way. What is going on is a unique experience of, and formation of unity with, the divine. ‘Hence, the appropriate response to divinity is love, love of the Transcendent itself’. But this is not sociological thinking. As it develops, we move from an analytical stance that is poised between the inside and insider’s standpoint only. Nothing in Archer’s initially suggestive account of what people do and think and feel when they are involved in intense, dense, affective practical routines sanctions in any way her theologico-moralistic conclusion about what the divine requires by way of ‘appropriate response’. Similarly, nothing whatever can be reasoned about the existence of God or the divine or the transcendent from the (social) fact that people display astonishingly rich and varied ways of expressing their personal and collective commitments to such things. the outside of the phenomenon under examination, to an In similar manner, Philip Mellor in Religion, Realism and Social Theory turns on its head Durkheim’s definitively social understanding of what religious collective effervescence represents. From the perfectly proper, or at least interesting, sociological claim that religion can be seen as ‘a phenomenon that expresses, through actions and beliefs, a collective engagement with the possibility of transcendence emergent from the contingencies, potentialities and limitations of embodied human life’, the proposition is steadily contrived that society itself can be seen as ‘the creative force through which humanity realizes its deepest, most profound levels of being’, in particular ‘hyper-spirituality’ (Mellor, 2004: 19, 67 and passim). But clearly there is a mutation going on here, and an illegitimate one, such that religious hyper-spirituality, which stands as the explanandum of the first thought, becomes the veritable explanans in the second. From a collective engagement with the possibility of transcendence, we get transcendence itself working in and through collective strivings. This is straightforward religious essentialism, something that goes decisively beyond anything that can be taken even from appreciative analysts of religion like Durkheim or William James. Equating lack of spiritual grounding with colonialism and violence denies the legacy and virtue found in humanism. This totalizing picture writes off many members of our society as spiritually dead and ethically bankrupt. Linell CADY Religious Studies @ ASU ‘5 “Secularism, Secularizing, and Secularization: Reflections on Stout’s Democracy and Tradition” The Journal of the American Academy of Religion 73 (3) p.875-877 [Gender paraphrased – Turner] According to Stout’s retelling, American democratic life and its expression in the writings of some of its most seminal theorists reveal a developing tradition that is deeply attentive to the virtues and to moral and spiritual excellence. This tradition is by no means hostile to religion, although it does reflect a secularizing trajectory driven by the increasing religious pluralism of the nation. The secular liberal contractarians and its foremost theoretician, John Rawls, misconstrue this tradition, Stout argues, by seeking to translate the secularizing trajectory into an epistemological model that excludes religion in principle. Public reasoning, for Rawls means “being willing to accept a common basis for reasoning that others, similarly motivated, could not reasonably reject” (67). As Stout convincingly argues, however, this model is far too restrictive and, tellingly, “so contrary to the spirit of free expression that breathes life into democratic culture” (68). It suggests that figures like Abraham Lincoln and Martin Luther King, Jr. were deficient, judged in light of the ideal of public reason, rather than “paradigms of discursive excellence” in American democratic political life. The Rawlsian approach, Stout contends, suffers from its Kantian pursuit of universal norms and principles to ground and constrain public reasoning in a pluralistic society. Advocating an Hegelian expressivism in its stead, Stout contends that norms and principles emerge in ongoing discursive exchange and rules for what is “reasonable” cannot be established in advance or for all time. That said, Stout makes room for the Rawlsian ideal of public reason that largely precludes religious language in public discourse. It is most appropriate as a “vague ideal” whose merit rests upon the respect for persons and commitment to exchanging reasons that characterize American democratic political life. In a religiously diverse nation public life generally fosters discourse and arguments that are not explicitly religious. So while not an epistemological rule, secularized public discourse can be understood as a matter of rhetorical prudence, etiquette, and even morality insofar as it arises from respect for others. But it does not abrogate one’s right to express one’s deepest convictions in public. Unless this is fully appreciated, we end up with “too much silence at precisely the points where more discussion is most badly needed” (90). Developing a more adequate picture of our secularized political culture is also essential to counter its religious despisers or, as Stout calls them, the ‘new traditionalists” such as John Milbank and Stanley Hauerwas. Exhibiting a similar “resentment of the secular,” their excessively negative picture of the “world” is aligned with an equally excessive, though exhalted, picture of “church.” Through his prolific and rhetorically powerful writings Hauerwas has done more than any other contemporary Christian thinker, Stout argues, to disparage democracy and our shared civic life. “ ‘Liberal society,’ ‘the secular,’ and ‘democracy’ are Hauerwas’ names for what the world has become in an age of fragmentation after the demise of virtue and tradition” (147). Against the moral bankruptcy of the broader society stands the “church,” a tradition of narratives and practices that nurture discipleship for the “peaceable kingdom.” Stout contends that the distinction between “church” and “world” has hardened into an undialectical opposition in the “new traditionalism,” dangerously undermining identification with civic life and progressive political coalitions. Stout engages in a sustained immanent critique of the “new traditionalism,” admirably modeling his theoretical commitment to a pluralistic public conversation that includes religion. Stout challenges Hauerwas’s dualistic take on both “church” and “world.” Although Hauerwas claims “to be speaking for the actual church of communion, homilies, Bible study, and potluck dinners,” Stout pointedly notes that “the actual church does not look very much like a community of virtue, when judged by pacifist standards” (160–161). He persuasively argues that Hauerwas and those attracted to his rhetoric of “church” harbor democratic sentiments that are left “unvoiced and unexplained” in their exaggerated critique of contemporary society. Stout insists that our shared democratic life is not as fragmented or as indifferent to the virtues as its new despisers claim. The charge reflects a narrow and authoritarian interpretation of tradition and virtue that implicitly serves to invalidate “a tradition dedicated to the project of loosening up that conception democratically and dialogically” (136). In this democratic model of tradition, the individual is not primarily viewed as a member of a bounded community with authoritative leaders and expositors controlling the parameters of the beliefs and practices of the tradition. To the contrary, a democratic tradition seeks to form individuals with “the practical wisdom to fashion a critical language for himself[themselves] out of materials borrowed from many sources” (138). The democratic shift means abandoning “an essentially deferential posture toward the past in spiritual affair” and developing a self-reliant piety that “holds, in contrast, that it is our own Although Stout clearly acknowledges the “horrors and injustices” (138) of our shared democratic life, he rightly refuses to paint it as a moral wasteland. He reminds us that the “most challenging democratic thinkers” have cared responsibility to imagine the sources on which we depend and to fashion lives worthy of our best imaginings” (37). deeply about questions of virtue and character. He goes so far as to insist, “What they want to promote in society generally and hope to exemplify in their own lives is excellence—and, if possible, spiritual greatness” (283). Stout is most effective at exposing the unfounded and insidious contrast between “church” and “world” that informs the new traditionalism. He rightly notes that this contrast is facilitated by the alignment of “world” to an ideology of secularism that is viewed as morally and spiritually vacuous. His insistence that “church” does not have a monopoly on virtues, character, and spiritual excellence—and constitutes a remarkable hubris to suggest otherwise—is absolutely critical. Asserting spiritual holism as the ground of politics justifies ritual scapegoating and sacrifice of secularists. Turns the case. Jeffrey STOUT Religion @ Princeton ‘4 Democracy and Tradition p.114-115 So there are reasons to be alarmed about the current condition of public discourse. But if I am right about the historical causes of secularization and the material conditions of contemporary fragmentation, the school of resentment in theology is actually making things worse. Theologies designed to articulate, defend, and reinforce resentment of the secular are symptoms of the disease they are meant to cure. They are the ideological expression of the enclave society. Their social function is to legitimate identification with the enclave as the primary social unit. The main means they employ to generate solidarity within the small group is the bashing of liberals, practiced as a form of ritual sacrifice. The ritual comes in two types, depending on whether the scapegoats are selected from inside or outside the enclave. The former type makes a negative example of believers, especially theologians, who have identified with movements of democratic reform in the broader society. The latter type holds up nonbelievers as symbolic representatives of the secularism that supposedly defines the broader society. In both cases, the boundary and discourage others from crossing it. effect of the exercise is to define the enclave You shouldn’t require that anti-colonialism grounds the political in the spiritual. Even if ethical relationships should respect spiritual, the propositional statement the 1AC makes equates spirituality with fulfillment and secular naturalism with alienation. This is not historically valid, and denigrates ethically committed humanists. Gregor McLENNAN Sociology @ Bristol ‘7 “Towards Postsecular Sociology?” Sociology 41 (5) p. 869 The result is that the faith/reason polarity is consistently presented as if all the humanity and richness and morality fall on the religion side, with nothing but alienation and depersonalization on the side of secularism/scientific naturalism. But my second objection is that this balance sheet is thoroughly distorted. Religion may well cultivate a range of social and moral goods, but it may equally well poison them too, and meanwhile many of the qualities supposedly distinctive of religion – collective morality, existential meaning, love, creativity and imagination, social energy, and spirituality – are readily encompassed and celebrated within a secular humanist outlook. Thirdly, we should question Habermas’s insistence that mutual respect and a common learning process between believers and non-believers must take an epistemic form. Indeed, this proposal strikes me as both implausible and undesirable. It is implausible because from within the perspective of secular sociological naturalism (broadly conceived), the question of the ‘truth content’ of claims about heaven and hell, God’s grace, salvation and the rest cannot really be entertained: these items are not candidates for truth and explanation. That is why the debating point sometimes scored by believers, to the effect that even if God’s existence cannot be proven, at least it cannot be disproved either, has no traction whatsoever. And the converse holds too: for a religious person whose worldview really is grounded on the notion of some ultimate Transcendent realm and an omnipotent, loving Spirit, then the explanation of life in terms of generative mechanisms, interlocking contingent material processes, and human agency can never be nearly enough. Habermas is thus backing the wrong horse when he seeks to base democratic dialogue on epistemological reflexivity. Generally over-rated as a source of self-correction, reflexivity is more effective in matters of ethics than of truth, and in relation to lifeaffecting events rather than propositions. Moreover, the power of common human morality in our appreciation of other people’s motivation and purpose should not itself be sold short. We can readily respond to, and value, people as people, partly through sociological imagination of their situation and plight, even if we are unlikely to share some of their presumptions about truth, existence and causality. 1nc The 1AC’s glorification of “indigenous knowledge” opposes “western” thought. This creates a power dynamic that always holds “indigenous” above “western” Gordon and Krech 12 [David M. Gordon is an associate professor of history at Bowdoin College. He is author of Nachituti’s Gift: Economy, Society, and Environment in Central Africa and numerous articles on African social, cultural, and environmental history.] [Shepard Krech III is a professor emeritus of anthropology at Brown University and a research associate in the Department of Anthropology, National Museum of Natural History, Smithsonian Institution. A trustee of the National Humanities Center, he is the author or editor of many essays and books, including The Ecological Indian and The Encyclopedia of World Environmental History, edited with John McNeill and Carolyn Merchant.] Indigenous Knowledge and the Environment “Indigenous knowledge ” excites and infuriates. One of its leading academic proponents and critics, Michael Dove, argues that its conceptual space has evolved from “innovative tool to hackneyed dichotomy.”1 Historians and anthropologists are uncomfortable at its mention— increasingly so, we sense, at the very moment that others press its birth as a discipline. After all, is not the notion of an impenetrable body of knowledge that belongs to an unchanging group of indigenes a romantic projection of our modern imaginations into the past? As newcomers—transients and immigrants—arrive in any particular place, some conquering, some settling, some exchanging genes and culture, and so on, with people already present, might not the notion of “indigenous” lack historical nuance? At the same time, however, indigenous knowledge holds political appeal and moral valence. It offers an alternative to a Western teleology of civilization (or development), even if the notion is a creation of the encounter between the West and the rest. It offers an alternative to the power-knowledge nexus of Western thought, and yet it introduces its own modalities of power. It unsettles stable categories of knowledge and fields of human agency, such as science and religion, and then tends to confirm the very same epistemological oppositions. This conceptual and political slipperiness is what makes “indigenous knowledge” such an academic apostasy, so essential and so interesting to study. This book investigates the historical constructions, the political uses, and the epistemological nuances of indigenous knowledges. Rather than claiming that indigenous knowledge stands in some kind of exterior relationship to Western conquest, colonialism, and science, we argue that the emergence of modern indigenous knowledges was intimately related to conquest and colonial rule. This is not to claim that people who are now termed indigenous—or who term themselves indigenous—did not have knowledge prior to contact with Europeans. Quite the opposite: the chapters in this volume detail such precolonial forms of knowledge. But they also show that during times of conquest and colonization, by Europeans and by others, attaching “indigenous” to “knowledge” often was, and often continues to be, a strategy entwined with acts of domination and resistance. Rather than an established body of knowledge that can be owned, written, and transmitted unchanged over time, we regard indigenous knowledges as claims, as strategic maneuvers that challenge the imposition of power and make claims to power. Most of all, we reveal modern indigenous knowledges as palimpsests upon which, if we look carefully and ask the right questions, we can detect the signs of past conflicts that scraped out notions of indigeneity. We are not the first to notice the conceptual and political inconsistencies of indigenous knowledge. In a seminal article that appeared just as indigenous knowledge became the catchphrase of environmental and developmental policymakers and activists, Arun Agrawal pointed to the fallacious oppositions that scholars and activists invoke between “Western science” and indigenous knowledge. Agrawal argued that the tendencies to try to “preserve” indigenous knowledges ex situ have not confronted the political and economic processes that marginalize people termed “indigenous.” 2 Others, including Dove, Roy Ellen, and Paul Sillitoe, have followed Agrawal with significant contributions to the debate that we join in this collection.3 This creates a notion of a superior “indigenous people” that should reorder the world, creating a new set of elites Gordon and Krech 12 [David M. Gordon is an associate professor of history at Bowdoin College. He is author of Nachituti’s Gift: Economy, Society, and Environment in Central Africa and numerous articles on African social, cultural, and environmental history.] [Shepard Krech III is a professor emeritus of anthropology at Brown University and a research associate in the Department of Anthropology, National Museum of Natural History, Smithsonian Institution. A trustee of the National Humanities Center, he is the author or editor of many essays and books, including The Ecological Indian and The Encyclopedia of World Environmental History, edited with John McNeill and Carolyn Merchant.] Indigenous Knowledge and the Environment Despite the instrumental, moral, and ideological qualities of indigeneity, some still insist on viewing it in biological terms. Early twentiethcentury racial theories remain inscribed in theories of indigenous belonging. This biological— or “blood”—understanding of indigeneity emerges from legal formulations that insist on proof of belonging. Blood seems to offer such convincing proof. In addition, outside of institutional, state, and legal arrangements, blood kinship models still inspire models of wider corporate group membership. For these reasons, even while this volume—along with a range of scholarship—emphasizes the historical model of the indigenous belonging, the biological blood model of indigenous belonging prevails in quotidian, and even some academic understandings. The notion of “indigenous people” may even “provide ideological ammunition to those who would reorder the world according to blood and soil,” as André Béteille points out.19 Yet, as analyses in this volume and elsewhere make clear, lurking beneath the surface of blood is always power: power, exercised by the state or by the people of indigenous status themselves, to determine that indigeneity depends on descent from an ancestor on a particular historical list; on descent from a man but not a woman or a woman but not a man; on descent from a person free but not from one enslaved; on comportment; on culture—the vexed tradition; on membership in a group of a certain size; or on myriad other historical and cultural factors. In its emphasis on an unchanging body of knowledge and in its opposition to modernity, indigenous knowledges share a conceptual relationship with “tradition.” Like “tradition,” “indigenous” implies something ancient, even primordial. In their influential work The Invention of Tradition, Eric Hobsbawm and Terence Ranger argue that while tradition disguises itself as unchanging, it is dynamic and invented according to political and ideological exigencies.20 In their view, tradition is often conservative, involving cultural artifacts that legitimize established elites —thus the need for historians to lay bare its invention. Tradition is also typically modern in its nostalgia for a lost past. The idea of indigenous knowledge has comparable qualities (indeed, indigenous knowledge is often referred to as “traditional environmental knowledge,” or TEK). Indigenous knowledges conceal their dynamism under the appearance of a timeless body of knowledge. They share a nostalgia for a culturally particular form of knowledge and an imagined past, which makes them an adept tool to resist ostensibly scientific and universal discourses. (Unlike “traditions,” however, indigenous knowledges are often thought to be a tool of the disempowered and dispossessed, rather than of the elite.) Indigenous knowledges invoke their conceptual power by claims of timelessness, even while their ability to respond to contemporary articulations of power demands flexibility. Like tradition, indigenous knowledges have hidden and often repressed histories. Over time, cultural (including indigenous) knowledge is unevenly produced, unevenly shared, and unevenly distributed. And society is rarely, if ever, insular, tightly bounded, and exclusionary. It rarely remains homogeneous in its membership and composition. What this means is obvious: No assumption should be made that indigenous knowledges are closed to external influence or history, that they do not incorporate or reflect originally nonindigenous conception or perception, or that what one or several people might think or perceive is held universally in that society. That creates widespread Occidentalist violence Baber 02 Zaheer BABER Sociology @ Saskatchewan ‘2 The European Legacy 7 (6) p. 748-749 Despite the highly mediated nature of the diverse networks of intellectual influences, there is no doubt that residues of the European legacy of colonial conquest and rule continue to influence certain dominant strands of social scientific discourses. One of the intellectual responses to the situation has been the project of “indigenization,” an attempt to exorcise the remnants of the Eurocentric elements of the European legacy from academic discourse. The task at hand for scholars associated with this project is to provide a corrective to what is perceived to be the valorization of the experience of “Western” societies as the yardstick for measuring “Other” societies and cultures. At the extreme end of the spectrum is the Indian scholar Claude Alvares, who yearns for a radically anti-modern era that would be in tune with “our own distinctive eastern traditions.” In a recent book, Science, Development and Violence: the Revolt Against Modernity, Alvares makes the dramatic announcement that he has cut off connections with all institutions.6 Presumably, with the exception of Oxford University Press (his publisher), all institutions are compromised products of Eurocentric modernity. The degree of commitment of other intellectuals to the project of indigenization is variable, depending on the issues at hand. Vandana Shiva, for example, whose contribution to the critical literature on biotechnology, patents and development has been insightful and important, unnecessarily conjures up visions of a kinder and gentler science based on a highly romanticized “feminine principle.” Determined not to make any concessions to heterogeneity, ambivalence, contradictory formations or even a Shiva categorically rejects “Western” categories, science and knowledge with the objective of constructing a friendlier, decidedly non-strategic essentialist model derived from “non-Western” worldviews, because, as she puts it, “most nonWestern cultures have been based on the democracy of all life.”7 The attractions of replacing presumably Eurocentric discourses and institutions are all also all too evident in anthropologist T. N. Madan’s nod to the Spivakian “strategic use of positive essentialism,” confident dismissal of the state policy of secularism in India. He has no doubts about the fact that in the Indian context, the policy of secularism exhibits “moral arrogance” since it constitutes an “alien cultural ideology … a gift of Christianity … an impossible credo of life … the dream of a minority (secularists) which wants to shape the majority in its own image.”8 Not to be outdone, Ashis Nandy who in some of his earlier writings has steered away from Manichean dichotomies, ratchets up the temperature of the polemical game by quite a few degrees. As he puts it, secularism is quite obviously a “Western concept … introduced into Indian public life to subvert and discredit” Indian society. The policy of secularism for him constitutes the archetypical Eurocentric project if ever there was one, peddled by individuals who are obviously “intellectually crippled and morally awed … senile … seduced and brainwashed … anaemic” and who have “taken over the white man’s burden in this part of the world.”9 However, not all intellectual encounters with the legacy of Europe in postcolonial societies and theories inevitably traverse the path that leads to a categorical rejection of “alien” epistemologies and knowledge. Nor do all proponents of what has come to be known as the “indigenization” project seek concepts that are sui generis, untainted, and unalloyed by non-indigenous influences. A nuanced variation on the indigenization theme is the promotion of a universalism based on intellectual titration that would replace parochialism masquerading as universalism.10 As formulated by Alatas, the driving force behind this movement is the “idea that social scientific theories, concepts, and methodologies can be derived from the histories and cultures of the various nonWestern civilizations” with the ultimate objective of explaining and interpreting “the whole world from various non-Western vantage points.”11 Arguing that the “culture-specific situation of a society determines, at least in part, the concepts, theories and methodologies that arise from tackling specifically indigenous problems,” the ultimate objective of the movement is the construction of “systematized bodies of knowledge … that are based on the indigenous cultures in the same way that Western social science is based on Western historical experiences and cultural practices.”12 While Alatas has been careful to emphasize that as he conceives of it, the move to indigenize the social sciences should not and must not end up being a form of “nativism” or “occidentalism and orientalism in reverse,” not all scholars have been as cautious as seeking to contest the dominance of Eurocentric ideas in the social sciences, some scholars have ironically and perhaps unwittingly reinforced the very paternalistic Orientalism that they claim to be contesting. In more ways than one, some proponents of this project variously known as “indigenization,” “ethnosociology” and “alternative discourses” have succeeded in unintentionally inflicting heavy doses of conceptual violence on the very idea of social science and knowledge. Little wonder that Edward Said, who is frequently saddled with the responsibility of contributing to the construction of such unreflexive nativism, has been highly critical of this gesture.13 The claims of two scholars gone native with a vengeance are discussed him. In below in some detail, but these two do not by any means exhaust the laundry list. This Occidentalist view turns the case – flips the power binary and allows the destruction of humanity Buruma and Margalit 04 Ian Buruma is a Dutch writer and academic. Much of his work focuses on the culture of Asia, particularly that of China and 20th-century Japan and Avishai Margalit, is an Israeli George F. Kennan Professor at the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton, and Professor Emeritus in Philosophy at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem “Occidentalism: The West in the Eyes of Its Enemies” P. 10-11 There are, of course, perfectly valid reasons to be critical of many elements that go into the venomous brew we call Occidentalism. Not all the critiques of the Enlightenment lead to intolerance or dangerous irrationalism. The belief in universal progress, driven by business and industry, is certainly open to criticism. Blind faith in the market is a self-serving and often damaging dogma. American society us far from ideal, and U.S. policies are often disastrous. Western colonialism has much to answer for. And the revolt of the logical against claims of the global can be legitimate, even necessary. But criticism of the West, harsh as it may be, is not the issue here. The view of the West in Occidentalism is like the worst aspects of its counterpart, Orientalism, which strips its human targets of their humanity . Some Orientalist prejudices made non-Western people seem less than fully adult human beings; they had the minds of children, and could thus be treated as lesser breads. Occidentalism is at least as reductive; its bigotry simply turns the Orientalist view upside down. To diminish an entire society or a civilization to a mass of soulless, decadent, money-grubbing, rootless, faithless, unfeeling parasites is a form of intellectual destruction. Once again, if this were merely a matter of distaste or prejudice, it would not be of great interest. Prejudices are part of the human condition. But when the idea of others as less than human gathers revolutionary force, it leads to the destruction of human beings. Our alternative: Recognize that the epistemology diversity and density of native communities. Epistemological investigation should emphasize density not absolute difference because Western epistemes assist everyday struggles against resource exploitation. Andersen 09 Chris ANDERSEN Michif (Métis) from western Canada. He is an associate professor in the Faculty of Native Studies @ Alberta ‘9 “critical indigenous studies From Difference to Density” Cultural Studies Review 15 (2) p.95-96 By way of conclusion, let me offer some thoughts on where my removal of difference—a central pillar of studies—leaves us with respect to fashioning a discipline which can honour our past complexity while accounting for its contemporary and future manifestations.68 Champagne spends much of his analytical time arguing that Western concepts and disciplines are of only limited use to Indigenous studies because they fail to account for the distinctive needs, aspirations and epistemologies of Indigenous communities. A proper Indigenous studies discipline must thus produce: points of view and conceptualizations drawing on the everyday Champagne’s Native strategies and conceptions of American Indian communities that require mainstream academics and policy makers to rethink and extend the views of indigenous groups, as a means to include their views and socio-cultural actions outside the use of class, ethnicity, race, and even nationality. Native American Studies, and more generally indigenous studies, calls for conceptualizations and strategies that encompass issues, rights, and strategies of political, cultural, and territorial survival.69 He thus positions Native studies (a position familiar to Native studies practitioners) as a dog on the leash for Indigenous communities and nations . Such a position offers little in the way of analysis about the complexity of academic/community relations but it certainly feels good to say. He doesn’t appear to realise the extent to which analysing such a relationship necessarily requires sliding into disciplinary territory long claimed by other disciplines. If his point is that as Indigenous studies practitioners we need to claim this territory as our own, I am in full agreement. My point is merely that staking such a claim requires none of the epistemological baggage he wants to pack for the journey, and indeed raises troubling issues that require us to carefully unpack what he proposes to bring. Two of these are worth unpacking here. First, the community/academic relationship which appears to anchor Champagne’s formulation is problematic in that it ignores the ways that whiteness in the academy shapes the boundaries of its knowledge production in ways which do not necessarily subscribe to the regimes under which community knowledges are produced: Moreton-Robinson contends quite rightly that such representations ‘may not reflect the same knowledges about authenticity that are created and deployed within and by Indigenous communities and as such they may not be acceptable’.70 In ignoring this complexity, how on earth is Champagne to deal with the conflicts that inevitably arise? It does little good to acquiesce to one discourse or the other (though more often than not academic representations are given the nod), nor can we pretend that such differences are always reconcilable. These conflicts arise in situations pertaining to fundamentally irreconcilable positions on precisely the relationships between humans and nature (as Champagne points to) but they can also arise in more mundane situations, such as how to provide honorariums for elders involved in research projects in ways which don’t claw back from their monthly social assistance cheques. Second, even (or especially) if Indigenous studies is a dog on the leash for Indigenous communities and nations, why does this necessarily require an entirely new set of theoretical or methodological precepts that differ from those of mainstream disciplines? I agree with the broad strokes of Champagne’s argument about constructing a specific niche for ourselves in the academic, as do many other Native studies practitioners. But many of us have been involved in situations in which an Indigenous community has approached our department to ask for research assistance for mundane issues about collecting data on telephone or internet use in their community; proper application of census documents to produce the robust statistical profiles through which they interface with government funders; water purity samples to make determinations of water safety; or even archival documents to assist them in legal battles over hunting, fishing and other resource extraction questions. Although the disciplines of sociology, biological sciences, history or anthropology could and have undertaken this assistance, so can many existing Indigenous studies departments. It seems inherently strange to call for a theoretical and methodological orientation—and thus, according to Champagne, a discipline—which possessed none of this capability. His model presupposes the difference of Indigenous communities and in doing so slams the shutters closed on forms of expertise which might nonetheless prove of central concern to the communities. Champagne contends that ‘the issues confronting indigenous peoples are not reducible to race, class, ethnicity or other common analytical dimensions in use within mainstream disciplines’.71 The problem, from an epistemological standpoint, is that no issues of any peoples can be reduced to these factors. Concepts—all concepts—are by definition schematic and as such are laughably simplistic in the face of the enormous complexity of human life. This complexity requires us to acknowledge that Indigenous communities are—and have been for centuries—more than the ‘holistic, institutionally nondifferentiated’ entities in which ‘knowledge is inherently integrated with community, culture, and political and economic relations’72 painted by Champagne. Thus, although not fully captured by terms like race, ethnicity or class, such terms nonetheless assist greatly in reflecting upon the relationships between our communities and the various nation-states, and not only because they possess symbolic power in dominant society. The real irony of Champagne’s model of Indigenous studies is that his choices of analytical focus require none of the theoretical or methodological prescriptions he begs of them. For example, his most prominent critique of Indigenous studies—that a ‘cacophony’ of theoretical and methodological tools will ‘doom’ it to institutional marginality73—is usually emphasised as a disciplinary strength. Thus, Indigenous studies scholar Jace Weaver writes that: in dealing with the totalizing systems that we know as Native cultures, each view from traditional disciplines is limited and partial, NAS must draw together the various disciplines and their methods in order to achieve something approaching a complete picture of Natives, their cultures and experiences.74 This isn’t an issue for Champagne, apparently, since his positioning of Indigenous communities strips them of any of the epistemological complexity that would require us to intrude on others’ disciplinary turf. He sees this as his model’s strength but in fact it becomes its Achilles heel. By beginning with the assumption that Indigenous communities are epistemologically dense (rather than just different), however, Weaver’s appeal for interdisciplinarity becomes vital. Indeed, failure to account, interdisciplinarily, for this density elevates the danger of producing a naive, substantialist and ultimately parochial Indigenous studies. Case Humanist ideas have the possibility of being helpful or hurtful, however, their ideas have helped critique imperialism Sankar MUTHU Poli Sci @ Chicago ‘3 Enlightenment Against Empire p. 266-271 Universal Dignity, Cultural Agency, and Moral Incommensurability Do commitments to the idea of a shared humanity, to human dignity, to cross-cultural universal moral principles, and to cross-cultural standards of justice rest upon assumptions and values that unavoidably denigrate, or that disturbingly undermine respect for, cultural pluralism, that is, the wide array of human institutions and practices in the world?16 Are they imperialistic either explicitly, to justify Europe's political, military, and commercial subjugation of the non-European world, or implicitly, by indicating a rank ordering of superior and inferior peoples, which could then be used to justify a more indirect, quasi-imperial 'civilizing' process? The aforementioned commitments are sometimes collectively gathered under the term 'Enlightenment universalism' and, as we have seen, they are sometimes considered to constitute the core of 'the Enlightenment project'. I have suggested already that such assertions mask and distort a complex reality. In this case, they obscure the multiplicity of universalisms across eighteenth-century European political thought, each with distinct foundational claims, varying relationships to conceptualizations of human diversity and to humanity (which themselves differ from thinker to thinker, and even from text to text), and different political orientations toward the nature and limits of state power in theory and in practice. These philosophical sensibilities and approaches can yield remarkably dif-ferent political arguments toward foreign peoples, international justice, and imperialism. Thus, rather than ask whether 'the Enlightenment project' and 'Enlightenment universalism' are compatible with an appreciation of cultural pluralism or whether they are at bottom imperializing ideologies, it is more constructive to pose more precise and historically accurate versions of such questions with regard to particular texts and thinkers. In this book, I have studied a distinctive variant of Enlightenment writings against empire, one which includes the philosophical and political arguments of Diderot, Kant, and Herder. While there is no such thing as 'Enlightenment universalism' as such, let alone a larger 'Enlightenment project', there is nonetheless an identifiable set of philosophical and political arguments, assumptions, and tendencies about the relationship between universal and pluralistic concepts that animates the strand of Enlightenment political thought under study here. With this in mind, one can more meaningfully ask what the relationship is between universalism, pluralism, and incommensurability in such political philosophies, and how precisely they yield anti-imperialist political commitments. Answers to these more circumscribed questions can be given by better understanding the core elements of Diderot's, Kant's, and Herder's political philosophies, and how they differ from earlier (and, indeed, from many later) understandings and judgements of empire. Immanuel Kant remarks pointedly in Toward Perpetual Peace that the Europeans who landed and eventually settled in the New World often denied indigenous peoples any moral status. When America, the Negro countries, the Spice Islands, the Cape, and so forth were discovered, they were, to them [to Europeans], countries belonging to no one [die keinem angehorten], since they counted the inhabitants as nothing. (8:358, emphasis added) What philosophical concepts and arguments were necessary for New World peoples to be counted finally as something and especially to be considered as equals, as they were eventually in some crucial respects, by anti-imperialist political thinkers in the Enlightenment era? In this section, I focus on what I have taken in this book to be the philosophically most robust strand of Enlightenment anti-imperialist political thought. 17 Despite the many differences in the ethnographic sources that Diderot, Kant, and Herder consulted, the philosophical languages that these thinkers employed, and the particular concepts they drew upon to attack European empires, their anti-imperialist arguments intriguingly overlap in important respects. Thus, in this section, I identify and elucidate the family resemblances that exist among their philosophical arguments and rhetorical strategies, and discuss the underlying assumptions, ideas, and intellectual dispositions that make their version of anti-imperialist political thinking conceptually possible. In contrast to what is effectively the premiss of the kinds of familiar questions asked at the opening of this section, the commitments of Diderot, Kant, and Herder to moral universalism, cultural diversity, partial incommensurability, and the delegitimization of empire are not fundamentally in tension but rather reinforce one another. Overall, there are three principal philosophical sources of Enlightenment anti-imperialism. The first and most basic idea is that human beings deserve some modicum of moral and political respect simply because of the fact that they are human. This humanistic moral principle alone, however, was far from sufficient for engendering an anti-imperialist politics. The whole modern tradition_Qf natural right and social contract theory held this view in some form. Moreover, Amerindians inparticurar: were explicitly described by such thinkers as the pure, natural humans of the state of nature. Yet much of this tradition of modern political thought, from Grotius onward, was either agnostic about imperialism or lent philosophical support to European empires. Not every understanding of what it means fundamentally to be a human fosters the philosophical materials necessary to build a more inclusive and pluralistic political theory that could serve as the basis of anti-imperialist arguments. Indeed, as I will argue, some understandings of humanity that are manifestly egalitarian can nevertheless impede such a development. Second, therefore, these anti-imperialist arguments rested upon the view that human beings are fundamentally cultural beings. Diderot, Kant, and Herder all contend that the category of the human is necessarily marked by cultural difference; in this view, humanity is cultural agency. This thicker, particularized view of the human subject, paradoxically, helped to engender a more inclusive and meaningful moral universalism. Third, a fairly robust account of moral incommensurability and relativity was also necessary for the rise of anti-imperialist political thought. The anti-imperialist arguments offered by Diderot, Kant, and Herder all partly rest upon the view that peoples as a whole are incommensurable. From this perspective, entire peoples cannot be judged as superior or inferior along a universal scale of value. Moreover, in distinct but closely related ways, these thinkers argue that our cultural freedom produces a wide variety of individual and collective practices and beliefs that are incommensurable, given their view that many practices and beliefs lie outside the bounds of a categorical judgement or universal standard. When these three conceptual developments were brought together, the strand of Enlightenment anti-imperialist political theory that I have identified became philosophically possible. I want to reiterate here that this framework is not meant to elucidate all of the anti-imperialist arguments that one can find in the philosophical writings of the Enlightenment era. Moreover, the distinctive intellectual dispositions, personal idiosyncrasies, and domestic political commitments of Enlightenment-era thinkers significantly shaped their particular arguments on the issue of empire. Still, as I will show, these three philosophical ideas play a crucial role in enabling the development of a rich strand of anti-imperialist political theory in the late eighteenth century. In discussing the development of a more inclusive and anti-imperialist political theory, my focus in this section (as it has been generally in this book) is on Europeans' political attitudes toward non-Europeans. Many thinkers in nonEuropean societies clearly operated with similarly self-centred conceptions, but my emphasis throughout is on Europeans' intellectual responses to the fact of cultural difference and imperial politics, not with non-European peoples' understandings of each other or of their ac-counfsofEuropean peoples. Nor do I examine here the variety of intra-European distinctions between allegedly superior and inferior groups, those, for instance, involving linguistic, geographical, class, religious, and gender differences, which of course historically also legitimated differential treatment within European societies. Thus, I do not intend to argue that Enlightenment anti-imperialist political philosophies are inclusive as such, for their underlying principles do not necessarily (and, in the eighteenth century, they manifestly did not) support egalitarian arguments against every form of exclusion. As I have noted, the first idea that enables Enlightenment anti-imperialism- first both historically and analytically-is that foreigners are human beings and, consequently, that they deserve moral respect, however understood. The development, in other words, of some variant of a humanistic moral universalism ensured that the shared humanity of both Europeans and non-Europeans would be acknowledged and given some due. The philosophical and political legacy with which Enlightenment anti-imperialist thinkers struggled, as they themselves understood, was one of exclusion. As they often noted, ethical principles of respect and reciprocity had been limited almost always to (some) members of one's own tribe, polis, nation, religion, or civilization. Accordingly, the distinction between one's own society, however defined, and the barbaroi (others, foreigners), whether justified outright or tacitly assumed, influenced not only the anthropological conceptions of, and popular understandings about, foreign peoples, but also legitimated the often brutally differential treatment of various groups. It is along these lines that Kant expresses dismay, in a lecture on moral philosophy, at what he calls the "error that the [ancient] Greeks displayed, in that they evinced no goodwill towards extranei [outsiders, or foreigners], but included them all, rather, sub voce hastes = barbari [under the name of enemies, or barbarians]". (27:674) In the long history of imperial exploits, actions that in at least some contexts might have provoked outrage in one's own land not only gainedlegitimacy on foreign soil but were deemed praiseworthy, noble, and even morally obligatory abroad. While European imperialists in the New World, writes Diderot, "faithfully observe their own laws, they will violate the rights of other nations in order to increase their power. That is what the Romans did."lB Enlightenment antiimperialists recognized that such Janus-faced practices constituted the very core of imperial activity from the empires of the ancient world to the imperial conquests and commercial voyages of their day. The fact of difference itself lay at the heart of such inconsistent behaviour from Europeans' initial encounters with Amerindians onward, as Diderot notes: "[t]he Spaniard, the first to be thrown up by the waves onto the shores of the New World, thought he had no duty to people who did not share his colour, customs, or religi6n~" 19 Not wanting to single out tlie Spanish, Diderot suggests further that the Portuguese, Dutch, English, French, and Danes all followed in precisely the same spirit of exclusion and injustice. From an anthropological viewpoint, such discoveries of non-European peoples no doubt played a role in Europeans' changing conceptions of humanity. From Herodotus onward, of course, travel narratives played a central role in contemplating what it might mean to be, in some fundamental sense, a human being. Given that theorizations of human nature relate, in complicated ways, to changing understandings of the range and characteristics of human societies, institutions, and practices, the European discovery of 'new' lands and peoples accordingly generated further, and at times more complex, theorizations of humanity.2o Moreover, from the sixteenth century onward, thinkers were particularly keen to consult and appropriate the latest ethnographic reports. In part, the heightened interest no doubt complemented, and may in part have resulted from, what is often described as the intellectual revolution in 'natural philosophy' and the resulting emphasis on experimentation, empirical study, and inductive reasoning in fields such as astronomy, but also (especially from the mid-seventeenth century onward) in the study of human anatomy, physiology, and psychology. Although many of Hume's contemporaries did not share his hope of introducing "the experimental method" to moral philosophy, there was nonetheless a widespread presumption that an understanding of the human condition needed to take account, in some manner, of the growing anthropological literature that detailed the vast range of human experiences, customs, and practices throughout the globe.21 This turn toward what Georges Gusdorf has called 'human science', however, requires a stable referent for what counts as 'human' while also upsetting the stability of the term by focusing attention increasingly on human difference.22 In this sense, the attempt at identifying the most salient features of humanity was often an erratic and inherentlyconflicted task, as John Locke argued it would have to be, given the very nature of our self-knowledge. Anti-colonialism doesn’t require a break from our existing political vocabulary. The tools of institutional engagement, the language of rights, freedom and citizenship provide important resources for antiimperialism. The aff’s method risks self-marginalization. James TULLY Poli Sci @ Victoria (Canada) ‘8 Public Philosophy in a New Key Vol. 1 p. 3-11 Public Philosophy in a New Key is a new approach to the study of politics. The role of a public philosophy is to address public affairs. This civic task can be done in many different ways. The type of public philosophy I practise carries on this task by trying to enter into the dialogues with citizens engaged in struggles against various forms of injustice and oppression. The aim is to establish pedagogical relationships of reciprocal elucidation between academic research and the civic activities of fellow citizens. The specific role of this public philosophy is to throw a critical light on the field of practices in which civic struggles take place and the practices of civic freedom available to change them. It does this by means of historical and critical studies of the field and the given theoretical forms of representation of it. Reciprocally, this critical ethos learns from citizens and the successes and failures of their civic activities how to improve the historical and critical studies and begin again. In the studies that follow, I use the term 'citizen' to refer to a person who is subject to a relationship of governance (that is to say, governed) and, simultaneously and primarily, is an active agent in the field of a governance relationship. While this includes the official sense of 'citizen' as a recognised member of a state, it is obviously broader and deeper, and more appropriate and effective for that reason. By a 'relationship of governance', I refer not only to the official sense of the institutional governments of states, but to the broad sense of any relationship of knowledge, power and subjection that governs the conduct of those subject to it, from the local to the global. Governance relationships in this ordinary sense range from the complex ways individuals and groups are governed in their producing and consuming activities to the ways peoples and subalternised states are subject to global imperial relationships of inequality, dependency and exploitation. They comprise the relationships of normativity, power and subjectivity in which humans find themselves constrained to recognise themselves and each other, coordinate interaction, distribute goods, act on the environment and relate to the spiritual realm. 'Practices of civic freedom' comprise the vast repertoire of ways of citizens acting together on the field of governance relationships and against the oppressive and unjust dimensions of them. These range from ways of 'acting otherwise' within the space of governance relationships to contesting, negotiating, confronting and seeking to transform them. The general aim of these diverse civic activities is to bring oppressive and unjust governance relationships under the on-going shared authority of the citizenry subject to them; namely, to civicise and democratise them from below. What is distinctively 'democratic' about public philosophy in a new key is that it does not enter into dialogues with fellow citizens under the horizon of a political theory that frames the exchange and places the theorist above the demos. It rejects this traditional approach. Rather, it enters into the relationships of normativity and power in which academic researchers and civic citizens find themselves, and it works historically and critically on bringing them into the light of public scrutiny with the particular academic skills available to the researchers. Every reflective and engaged citizen is a public philosopher in this sense, and every academic public philosopher is a fellow citizen working within the same broad dialogue with his or her specific skills. Studies in public philosophy are thus specific toolkits offered to civic activist and civic-minded academics working on the pressing political problems of our times. I first developed this approach in Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an Age of Diversity. By means of a series of historical studies, I argued that constitutional democracies could respond to contemporary struggles over recognition by reconceiving constitutions as open to continuing contestation and negotiation by those subject to them. This would be a transition from constitutional democracy (where the constitution is conceived as founding and standing behind democratic activity) to democratic constitutionalism (where the constitution and the democratic negotiation of it are conceived as equally basic). In the decade since it was published, I have come to see that this approach can be improved and applied to a broader range of contemporary struggles: over diverse forms of recognition, social justice, the environment and imperialism. These two volumes explore this complex landscape. Volume I, Part r sets out this public philosophy, its employment of historical studies, its relation to contemporary political struggles and its orientation to the civic freedom of citizens. Chapter r is a sketch of my approach, the tradition from which it derives, the contemporary authors from whom I have learned this approach, and a contrast with the dominant theory-building approach. Chapters 2 and 3 provide the groundwork of public philosophy through an interpretation and adaptation of the works of Wittgenstein, Foucault and the Cambridge school. These chapters provide the methods that are employed in the case studies that follow in both volumes. Volume I, Part 2 consists of three applications to the democratic struggles over the appropriate forms of recognition of diverse, multicultural and multinational citizens in contemporary societies. Chapter 4 locates the approach relative to trends in political philosophy over the last thirty years and sketches out the general field of relations of power and the freedom of citizens that is studied in detail in the following chapters. Chapter 5 is a study of ways to democratise various types of contemporary recognition struggles while generating appropriate civic bonds of solidarity among diverse citizens. Chapter 6 is a study of democratic forms of recognition in political associations that are not only multicultural but also multinational, based on the work of an international team of social scientists from the European Union and Canada. This is a comprehensive yet defeasible analysis of the actual legal and political practices of democratic constitutionalism for multinational associations. Volume I, Part 3 consists of two studies of the struggles of Indigenous peoples for recognition in modern states and under international law. The first sets out a normative framework for the bi-civilisational negotiation of decolonisation and reconciliation of the rights of Indigenous peoples to govern themselves in their own ways over their territories and the rights of states that have colonised them over the last half millennium. It is based on my work for the Canadian Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples (1991-5). Chapter 8 addresses the prevailing discursive and practical obstacles to the negotiation of reconciliation proposed in Chapter 7 and the practices of freedom available to Indigenous peoples and their supporters to overcome the obstacles and initiate negotiations. Chapter 9 concludes Volume I, setting out this new approach to recognition and distribution struggles developed in the course of these studies and the ways in which contemporary societies are beginning to adopt this democratic approach in their legal and political institutions. I show how this approach represents a fundamental transformation of the manner in which struggles over recognition are standardly conceptualised today in the dominant schools of thought. It recommends a transition from the orientation to discrete and dyadic struggles for the just and definitive form of legal recognition in a state to multiple and interrelated negotiations over the always-imperfect prevailing norms of mutual recognition of members of any form of association. This modest democratic approach has a much better chance of bringing peace to the deeply diverse world of the twentyfirst century than the standard approaches. Volume II applies public philosophy in a new key to global politics. It consists of historical and critical studies of global relationships of horrendous inequality, dependency, exploitation and environmental damage, and of the corresponding practices of civic freedom of global and local citizens to transform them into democratic relationships. The transition to Volume II does not only mark a broadening of the field of public philosophy to the global. More emphasis is also placed on specific locales of civic struggles, the diversity of governance relationships and the range of ways of acting otherwise in them, provincialising Eurocenrric traditions and bringing in more non-Western voices and perspectives. Volume II, Part I consists of studies of global relationships and practices of civic freedom available from the perspectives of the dominant schools of globalisation. Chapter I critically examines the tradition of international relations' and global justice associated with Kant's theoty of a world federation of identical nation-states. Chapter 2 examines the theories of globalisation, global governance and cosmopolitan democracy. Chapter 3 examines the activities of environmental movements from the perspective of civic freedom and advances a democratic ethic of ecological politics. Chapter 4 is the most comprehensive. It is an immanent critique of the dominant and agonistic approaches to global justice and international law. The critique leads step by step to the conclusion that only a more historical and contextual approach, related to the actual practices of freedom on the ground, can illuminate the unequal global relationships and the possibilities for their transformation. The conclusion I draw from these four studies is that these approaches, while illuminating and useful, are nevertheless limited and inadequate because they overlook the historically persisting imperial character of the global relationships they analyse. This provides the transition to Part 2. Volume II, Part 2 consists in studies of global relationships under the description of them as a network of vastly unequal imperial relationships between the North and global South (the I20 former colonies that comprise the majority of the world's population). The three chapters show how different aspects of the contemporary global order continue to be structured by imperial relationships inherited from five hundred years of Western imperialism. These relationships survived decolonisation in the twentieth century in a new phase of imperialism, standardly called post-colonial or informal imperialism. Chapter 5 sets out this argument in historical detail and shows how each of the major approaches to globalisation and international relations overlooks the imperial dimensions of the present in different ways and marginalises other approaches that study globalisation under the category of imperialism. Even some of the approaches that claim to take into account informal imperialism misrepresent the contemporary form of imperialism. With this disclosure of the field of globalisation as the continuation of Western imperialism by informal means and through institutions of global governance, Chapter 6 turns to the networkisation and communications revolution of the last twenty years. I show that this revolution, which is often portrayed as democratising globalisation, has been Janus-faced: helping global citizens to organise effectively at the local and global levels, yet also helping institutions of global governance, multinational corporations and the US military to network and govern informally the global relationships of inequality they inherited from the period of colonial imperialism. Chapter 7 shows how the imperial spread of the modular form of modern, Western-style constitutional nation-states and international law by colonisation, indirect rule and informal rule over the last three hundred years has not freed the non-West from imperialism. Quite the opposite: it has been and continues to be the political, legal and economic form in which relationships of inequality, dependency and exploitation have been extended and intensified around the world. Volume II concludes by asking the crucial question: what can citizens who are subject to these imperial relationships (in both the North and global South) do to transform them into non-imperial, democratic relationships by bringing them under their shared authority? T he general answer is the exercise of civic freedom by citizens in the North and global South and the exercise of academic research in networks of reciprocal learning with these global/local citizen movements: namely, a new public philosophy for a de-imperialising age. Chapter 8 takes the citizenry of the European Union as an example. I argue that European citizens are already taking the lead in improvising new forms of democratising civic activities with respect to immigration, alternative economics and relationships with the global South. Chapter 9 is the conclusion to Public Philosophy in a New Key. It draws together the strands of argument throughout the two volumes and weaves them into a sketch of a new kind of local and global citizenship I call 'glocal' citizenship. This mode of citizenship has the capacity to overcome the imperialism of the present age and bring a democratic world into being from the local to the global. Since it is the conclusion to the two volumes, I will provide a brief synopsis at the outset to give a preliminary indication of where the chapters lead. The first part of the chapter summarises the imperial character of the present global order and the dominant modular form of citizenship (modern citizenship) that has been spread by Western expansion. Far from offering a challenge to imperialism, it actually serves in a number of ways to extend it, in both its national (civil) and its global (cosmopolitan) forms. The second part argues that there is another mode of citizenship (diverse citizenship) that also developed historically in both the West and nonWest. It provides the democratic means to challenge and transform imperial relationships in both its local (civic) and local/global (glocal) forms. I set out the main features of the traditions of diverse civic citizenship historically and conceptually, and then apply it to global struggles of deimperialisation and democratisation. It is a form of citizenship that is grounded in local civic practices yet extended globally by democratic networks. The chapter thus brings together the three themes of the two volumes: public philosophy, practices of civic freedom and the countless ways they work together to negotiate and transform oppressive relationships. This is not only possible but what millions of citizens, nongovernmental organisations, networks and social movements are doing today. The chapter ends with a view of Gandhi's life as a civic citizen contra imperialism; it stands as an exemplar of civic citizenship and engaged public philosophy. There are many public philosophers from whom I have drawn inspiration. John Locke, Mary Wollstonecraft, Emma Goldmann, Antonio Gramsci, Sojourner Truth, Paulo Friere, Bertrand Russell, Maude Barlow, Edward Said, Noam Chomsky, Vandana Shiva, Boaventura de Sousa Santos, Iris Marion Young and Gandhi are exemplary. And, as I mentioned, every engaged and reflective citizen is an inspirational public philosopher in this democratic sense. But I have always questioned why more political philosophers and political theorists are not also public philosophers. What stops many of them from seeing their work as a discussion with their fellow citizens as equals? I think the answer is that many tend to enter into a relationship with citizens under the horizon of a political theory that sets them above the situated civic discourses of the societies in which they live. This presumptive elevation is standardly based on four types of assumption. The first assumption is that there are causal processes of historical development (globalisation) that act behind the backs of citizens and determine their field of activity. It is the role of the theorist of modernisation to study these conditions of possibility of civic activity. The second is that there are universal normative principles that determine how citizens ought to act. It is the role of the theorist of global justice to study these unchanging principles that prescribe the limits of democracy. The third is that there are background norms and goods implicit within democratic practices that constrain and enable the field of democratic activity of citizens in the foreground. It is the role of the interpretative and phenomenological theorists to make these background conditions explicit. The fourth is that there are canonical institutional preconditions that provide the foundations of democratic activity, and it is the role of political scientists to study these legal and political institutions. In each of these four cases, the theorist is elevated above the demos by the assumption that there are background conditions of possibility of democracy that are separate from democratic activity and it is his or her role to study them, not what takes places within them. In the course of the studies in the two volumes, each pillar of elite political theory falls to the ground. Each of the four conditions of possibility is shown to be internally related to and reciprocally shaped by the everyday activities of democratic citizens, not separate from and determinative of their field of freedom. It is this revolutionary discovery that brings political philosophy 'down' into the world of the demos and renders it a situated public philosophy in conversation with fellow citizens. Equally important, it enables us to see that we are much freer and our problems more tractable than the grand theories of the four pillars make it seem. For while we are still entangled in conditions that constrain and enable, and are difficult to change, we are no longer entrapped in background conditions that determine the limits of our foreground activities, for none is permanently off limits. I associate this revolutionary insight with the late Richard Rorty (Volume I, Chapter 4). Others will associate it with other writers and their own experiences of human freedom and agency where they were told it was impossible. I would like to say a few words about the phrase 'in a new key' . Just as a jazz musician plays a composition in a new key relative to the classic performances of it, so too a specific public philosopher plays the role in his or her own new style in relation to the classic public philosophers in his or her field. The style of these studies is a new key in that it combines historical studies and a reciprocal civic relationship (MARKED) in what I hope is a distinctive way. Jazz musicians play in a new key in the course of improvising with other musicians and in dialogue with classic performances and present audiences. Analogously, public philosophers improvise in dialogues with contemporary theorists, the classics, engaged citizens and in response to the political problems that confront and move them. This is the situated freedom of a public philosopher. I see the studies in these volumes as improvisations in this sense.1 Finally, I would like to respond to a common objection to this style of public philosophy. Radical critics often say, given the radical character of your particular public philosophy, why do you engage in the 'mainstream' academic debates and use the conservative language of citizenship, public philosophy, governance, democracy and civic freedom? Your work will be co-opted by the mainstream you disagree with and alienated from the civic activists you hope to reach. You should write in a language of radical politics. I acknowledge that my views are somewhat radical relative to much of the literature I discuss. However, there are three reasons for the approach I take. Firstly, the alternative language of radical politics often involves a kind of self-marginalisation and an attitude of self-righteousness that I find incompatible with a democratic ethos. Moreover, there are already many excellent public philosophers, such as Chomsky, who write directly to civic activists and bypass the theoretical debates, and they too write in the same plain and simple language of citizens, public goods and freedom. Secondly, the economic, political and military elites and their ideologists have inherited not only much of the earth and its resources but also many of its languages, including the manipulable language of citizenship, democracy, civic goods and freedom. Yet, it is precisely this ordinary language that the oppressed and exploited of the world have always used to express their outrage at the injustices of the present and their hopes and dreams of another world. Like Edward Said, I refuse to surrender it to our adversaries without a fight and abandon the repository of the history of struggles from which we derive. 2 Moreover, the fall of the four pillars of the ancien regime also brings down the fiction of an alternative, pure language of freedom (radical or otherwise) that stands above the fray of politics and is impervious to unpredictable redescription by one's fellow adversaries. Thirdly, I have deep respect for the elaborate Western and non-Western traditions of critical political reflection, the great yet partial insights they can bring, and the people who carry them on today in this public language. While I disagree with the dominant theories that legitimate the status quo in these terms, engagement with them forces dissenters like myself constantly to test our own views against them and, in so doing, to try to move the academic debate in another direction. As we will see, I am far from the first or only one to take this agonistic stance. Furthermore, is it not presumptuous to assume that these debates are alien and of no interest to citizens? T he following chapters were written in conversations with engaged citizens. Academic debates are not as far from and unrelated to the public debates as they are often portrayed from the perspectives of the four pillars. They are a historically integral part of the complex field of practical discourses on which public philosophy is inescapably thrown and in which it can find its voice and make a distinctive difference. Except for the concluding chapter of Volume II, all chapters are based on works published previously over the last eight years and then rewritten to bring them together in the sustained argument of these rwo volumes. The concluding chapter of Volume II was written for the rwo volumes and to bring their themes together in a portrait of global/local civic freedom and public philosophy contra imperialism. Their totalizing system for understanding sovereignty as nothing but domination, control and the production of bare life is politically counter-productive. Ernesto LACLAU Political Theory @ Essex ‘7 in Giorgio Agamben: Sovereignty and Life eds. Matthew Calarco and Steven DeCaroli p. 21-22 Needless to say, we fully reject Agamben's third thesis, according to which the concentration camp is the nomos or fundamental biopolitical paradigm of the West. He asserts: The birth of the camp in our time appears as an event that decisively signals the political space of modernity itself. It is produced at the point at which the political system of the modern nation-state, which was founded on the functional nexus between a determinate localization (land) and a determinate order (the State) and mediated by automatic rules for the inscription of life (birth or the nation), enters into a lasting crisis, and the State decides to assume directly the care of the nation's biological life as one of its proper tasks. . . . Something can no longer function within the traditional mechanisms that regulated this inscription, and the camp is the new, hidden regulator of the inscription of life in the order—or, rather, the sign of the system's inability to function without being transformed into a lethal machine. (HS, 174-75) This series of wild statements would only hold if the following set of rather dubious premises were accepted: I. That the crisis of the functional nexus between land, State, and the automatic rules for the inscription of life has freed an entity called "biological—or bare—life" That the regulation of that freed entity has been assumed by a single and unified entity called the State That the inner logic of that entity necessarily leads it to treat the freed entities as entirely malleable objects whose archetypical form would be the ban Needless to say, none of these presuppositions can be accepted as they stand. Agamben, who has presented a rather compelling analysis of the way in which an ontology of potentiality should be structured, closes his argument, however, with a naïve teleologism, in which potentiality appears as entirely subordinated to a pre-given actuality. This teleologism is, as a matter of fact, the symmetrical pendant of the "ethymologism" we have referred to at the beginning of this essay. Their combined effect is to divert Agamben's attention from the really relevant question, which is the system of structural possibilities that each new situation opens. The most summary examination of that system would have revealed that: (1) the crisis of the "automatic rules for the inscription of life" has freed many more entities than "bare life," and that the reduction of the latter to the former takes place only in some extreme circumstances that cannot in the least be considered as a hidden pattern of modernity; (z) that the process of social regulation to which the dissolution of the "automatic rules of inscription" opens the way involved a plurality of instances that were far from unified in a single unity called "the State"; (3) that the process of State building in modernity has involved a far more complex dialectic between homogeneity and heterogeneity than the one that Agamben's ‘`camp-based" paradigm reflects. By unifying the whole process of modern political construction around the extreme and absurd paradigm of the concentration camp, Agamben does more than present a distorted history: he blocks any possible exploration of the emancipatory possibilities opened by our modern heritage. Let me conclude with a reference to the question of the future as it can be thought from Agamben's perspective. He asserts: "Only if it is possible to think the Being of abandonment beyond every idea of law (even that of the empty form of laws being in force without significance) will we have moved out of the paradox of sovereignty towards a politics freed from every ban. A pure form of law is only the empty form of relation. Yet the empty form of relation is no longer a law but a zone of indistinguishability between law and life, which is to say, a state of exception" (HS, 59). We are not told anything about what a movement out of the paradox of sovereignty and "towards a politics freed from every ban" would imply. But we do not need to be told: the formulation of the problem already involves its own answer. To be beyond any ban and any sovereignty means, simply, to be beyond politics. The myth of a fully reconciled society is what governs the (non-)political discourse of Agamben. And it is also what allows him to dismiss all political options in our societies and to unify them in the concentration camp as their secret destiny. Instead of deconstructing the logic of political institutions, showing areas in which forms of struggle and resistance are possible, he closes them beforehand through an essentialist unification. Political nihilism is his ultimate message.