1 Spinozistic Moral Imperatives [draft of a draft of a draft] Michael LeBuffe Spinoza’s accounts of commands of reason (rationis dictamina) in the Ethics provide the resources for a distinctive and appealing theory of moral imperatives. The theory has two elements. First, it emphasizes the presence to mind of moral imperatives. They are associated closely with those features of the external world that we continuously regard as present in sense perception. Second, it emphasizes incrementalism. Imperatives vary incrementally in the extent to which they are known and in the kinds of circumstances in which they apply. To be a command of reason, on this theory, is not to be different in kind from all other moral imperatives but to occupy extremes of both ranges: moral imperatives are known to all agents and apply in all circumstances. In this essay, I present this theory of moral imperatives and advertise its appeal. The presentation emphasizes the theory’s two elements as they arise out of the account of reason in Part 2 of the Ethics. The Spinozistic theory of moral imperatives draws upon this account of reason more than Spinoza himself does, but it does so in a way—I will argue—that is consonant with the accounts of reason, the commands of reason, and other accounts of the value of action in the Ethics. In advertising the theory, I will describe the attractive and unusual accounts implicit in it of the universality of morality, of responsibility and cooperation, and of the relation between morality and motivation. 1. Reason and its Commands in the Ethics 2 Part Four of the Ethics includes several commands of reason. The most general of these may be found at 4p18s: Because reason demands nothing contrary to nature, it therefore demands this: that each person love himself; seek his own advantage, what is certainly to his advantage; want what certainly leads man to greater perfection; and, absolutely, that each person should strive, as far as it is in him, to preserve his own being.1 Other claims describing the guidance of reason, actions from reason, or human affects that agree with reason demand a short interpretative leap from description to prescription, but may probably be classified as commands of reason as well. For example, Spinoza argues at 4p65 that under the guidance of reason we follow the greater of two goods; at 4p66, that this is true regardless of time at which the goods might be obtained; at 4p63, that doing good in order to avoid evil is not an action from reason; and at 4p53 that humility does not arise from reason. It is a short leap to read into such descriptions a view on which reason commands that we pursue the greater of two goods; that we do so regardless of when the goods arise; that we not do good in order to avoid evil; and that we not fall under the influence of humility. 1 In this essay, I will frequently refer, as here, in an abbreviated form to the formal apparatus of the Ethics. For example, “4p18s” abbreviates Ethics, Part 4, Proposition 18, Scholium. I refer to passages in Spinoza’s work outside of the formal apparatus of his Ethics using the volume number, page number and line number of Carl Gebhardt, ed., Spinoza Opera (Heidelberg: Carl Winters, 1972). For example, “Spinoza 1972, II/222 1721” abbreviates volume II, page 222, lines 17 to 21 of Gebhardt. All translations in this essay are my own. 3 What these commands have in common is their source, reason (ratio), which unsurprisingly is for Spinoza a technical term. At 2p40s2 of the Ethics, Spinoza defines three varieties of cognition: imagination, reason, and intuition. Ideas of reason, he writes there, are “common notions and adequate ideas of the properties of things (2p38c, 2p39, 2p39c, and 2p40).” The use of ‘reason’ in the practical parts of the Ethics, Parts 4 and 5, and the 2p40s2 account is univocal. This is evident from the fact that in Parts 4 and 5 Spinoza frequently depends upon his claims about reason in general and especially upon his claims about the “common notions” at 2p38 and its corollary. Three examples of this connection, which is frequently overlooked in scholarly work on Spinoza, are notable. I introduce them here not to explicate them fully—the common notions will be the subject of much of the discussion below—but only to show that in the context of discussing the role of reason in human action, Spinoza continues to use ‘reason’ in the technical sense familiar from his epistemology and philosophy of mind. At 4p35, Spinoza argues that men necessarily agree in nature only to the extent that they live from the guidance of reason. The demonstration depends upon 3p3, a proposition fundamental to Spinoza’s intellectualism in which he associates a mind’s actions with its adequate ideas. The adequate ideas that Spinoza cites explicitly in the demonstration to 3p3 are, however, a particular kind of adequate idea: they are the common notions introduced at 2p38c. Where Spinoza writes about “men who live from the guidance of reason” at 4p35, then, he refers to reason as it is characterized in Part 2 and invoked at 3p3: to live under the guidance of reason is to be motivated by the common notions. 4 A second important example is 4p66, in which Spinoza argues that from the guidance of reason, we seek the greater future good before the lesser present one and the lesser present evil before the greater future one. This indifference to time derives from 2p44c2 (via 4p62), the claim that it is the nature of reason to perceive things from the standpoint of eternity. Spinoza defends 2p44c2 by referring to 2p38. Briefly his view is that because the properties understood in the common notions are always present in sensation time cannot be relevant to them. Finally, in describing the power that minds have to resist the influence of passion at 5p7 Spinoza argues that because ideas of reason are always present to mind they are pro tanto more powerful than other kinds of ideas, including passions, that may or may not be present. The demonstration depends upon 2p38 once again. It is the ideas discussed at 2p38 and later included among ideas of reason at 2p40s2 that are pro tanto more powerful than other ideas.2 The reason that demands certain actions and helps us to resist passion in Parts 4 and 5 of the Ethics, then, just is the reason that is introduced in Part 2 of the Ethics. The features that I take to be distinctive of Spinoza’s account of moral imperatives, presence to mind and incrementalism, have their source and frequently their clearest expression in that earlier, general discussion of ideas of reason. Here I will rely heavily upon Part 2 of the Ethics, then, in describing these features of reason and in building a Spinozistic theory of moral imperatives. 2 I offer a more detailed account of the relation between the second kind of knowledge and the commands of reason in, “Necessity and the Commands of Reason,” forthcoming in Andrew Youpa and Matthew Kisner, eds., Spinoza’s Moral Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press). 5 1.1 Presence to Mind Ideas of reason inherit presence to mind from the first kind of knowledge, imagination. Ideas of imagination on Spinoza’s account include any ideas—including notably our sensory ideas, our passions, and our memories—that have partial causes external to the self. Ethics 2p17 and its scholium introduces these ideas together with presence to mind as a distinctive feature: 2p17: If the human body is affected with a mode that involves the nature of some external body, the mind will regard that same external body as actually existing, or as present to it, until the body is affected by a mode that precludes the existence, or presence, of that body. Scholium [excerpt]: The affections of the human body, the idea of which represent external bodies as though present to us, we shall call the images of things, even if they do not reproduce the figures of things. And when the mind regards bodies in this way, we shall say that it imagines. To take the paradigm case of sense perception, Spinoza takes the visual sensation of the sun to arise when the human body interacts with the sun in such a way that there is a change in the human body. This is the “mode that involves the nature” of the sun. When the human body changes, the mind does also: it now possesses an idea in which the external body, the sun, is thought to be present to it. 6 Ideas of reason represent their objects as present to mind just because they are components of ideas of imagination. This point is clearest in the demonstration to the proposition that introduces the common notions and that arises so frequently in discussions of reason later in the Ethics, 2p38: 2p38: Those things that are common to all and that are equally in the part and in the whole cannot be conceived except adequately. Dem.: Let A be a thing that is common to all bodies and is equally in the part and in the whole of each body. I say that A cannot be conceived except adequately. For its idea (2p7c) will necessarily be adequate in God, both to the extent that he has the idea of the human body and also to the extent that he has ideas of its affections, which (2p16, 2p25, 2p27) involve in part (ex parte involvunt) the nature both of the human body and also of the external bodies. That is (2p12, 2p13), the idea will necessarily be adequate in God to the extent that he constitutes the human mind or to the extent that he has the ideas that are in the human mind. The mind therefore (2p11C) necessarily perceives A adequately both to the extent that it perceives itself and also to the extent that it perceives its own or any external body, nor can A be perceived in any other way. 7 Cor.: From this it follows that there are certain ideas or notions common to all men. For (2l2) all bodies agree in certain things, which (2p38) must be perceived adequately, or clearly and distinctly, by all. As Spinoza notes in his definition of imagination at 2p17s, ideas of imagination may fail to “reproduce the figures of things”: we may not fully understand what we see and this failure can lead to error. Nevertheless, he argues at 2p38, if there is a property common to all bodies—including notably the human body and the external body with which it interacts—any imaginative idea that results will include an adequate understanding of that property in the external body. (Ideas of reason are therefore a principal source of our knowledge of the external world in Spinoza.) If the property in question is, for example, being either at motion or at rest, then a person looking at the sun, however much he might mistake the sun’s size or distance, will not mistake and indeed may be said to know in the experience that the object seen is either at motion or at rest. Such knowledge, as a component of an idea of imagination, will also be present to mind in the same way that the idea itself is present to mind. Because every external body and every human body have the common properties that are the objects of the common notions, moreover, knowledge of common properties will be continuously present to all human minds. Indeed, although Spinoza emphasizes human minds in Part 2, the argument of the Ethics suggests that because every body has these properties and there is an idea of every body, all minds whatever have this knowledge in this robustly conscious way.3 3 This unusual feature of Spinoza’s theory of mind has challenged sympathetic commentators. I return to it in my defense of the appeal of Spinozism in Section 2.4 below. 8 Spinoza’s discussion of reason at 5p7 shows both that he takes presence to mind to be an important feature of ideas of reason for human beings and also why he takes it to be so: 5p7: Affects that arise from or are intensified by reason are, if we take account of time, more powerful than those that are related to singular things that we consider to be absent. Dem.: We consider a thing to be absent not because of the affect by means of which we imagine it, but because of this, that our body is affected by another affect, that precludes the thing’s existence (2p17). Therefore an affect which is related (refertur) to a thing that we consider to be absent is not of such a nature that it surpasses the rest of a man’s actions and power (see 4p6); but, to the contrary, its nature is such that it can be checked in some way by those affections that preclude the existence of its external cause (4p9). An affect, however, that arises from reason, is related necessarily to the common properties of things (see the definition of reason in 2p40s2), which we also consider to be present (for there can be nothing that precludes their present existence) and which we always imagine in the same way (2p38). Therefore, such an affect will always remain the same, and consequently (5a1), affects that are opposed to it and that are not reinforced (foventur) by their external causes, must adapt 9 themselves more and more to it, until they are no longer opposed. To that extent, an affect that arises from reason is more powerful. An idea that is continuously present to mind, Spinoza argues here, is pro tanto more powerful than one that is not. Presence to mind is a kind of robust consciousness characteristic of sensation. Although other ideas may be present to mind from time to time, ideas of the common notions, just because they are ideas of properties possessed by all bodies, are present to mind continuously. As influences over a person’s activity, Spinoza argues at 5p7, ideas of the common notions are in virtue of their continuous presence to mind pro tanto more powerful motives than other ideas. 1.2 Incrementalism Incrementalism, the doctrine that important explanatory properties are pervasively present to greater or lesser degrees rather than being simply present or absent, is characteristic of Spinoza’s philosophy.4 It is most evident, perhaps, in his discussions of the place of human beings in nature. To insist that human beings are not a kingdom within a kingdom is for Spinoza to insist that we are not conscious, active, or passionate in ways that are different in kind from other things in nature. Instead we are—or tend to be—conscious, active, and passionate to a different degree from other things and from one another. 4 This definition of ‘incrementalism’ is adapted from Don Garrett, “Representation and Consciousness in Spinoza’s Naturalistic Theory of the Imagination,” in Interpreting Spinoza: Critical Essay, edited by Charlie Huenemann (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), 18. I am indebted to the same work for drawing my attention to the importance of incrementalism for Spinoza. 10 Ideas of reason also are present in different minds to different degrees. The ideas introduced at 2p38, the common notions, are ideas of properties common to all bodies. Such ideas meet the condition stipulated for the adequate knowledge of a property in the imagination of an external body—that the property in question be wholly in the human body and in the external body—in all cases. That is, every human body and every external body has the properties in question in the right way. As a result the ideas will be adequate in every mind or known to all. They will be true of all external objects. And, in any case of acquaintance in sensation, a mind will possess its understanding in the relevant way, as it applies to the external object with which the person interacts at the moment. As ideas of common properties, however, the common notions are an extreme, one end of a range of cases in which human minds might know external objects in sensation. If there are less abundant properties, properties common to some human bodies and some external objects, then those properties might be known in the imaginative ideas of some minds in the same way that the properties common to all bodies are known to all minds. At 2p39 Spinoza introduces this incrementalism. He argues that there are other properties that meet the stipulated condition in some cases; that is, there are properties that are common to some human bodies and some external bodies and so are known less perfectly and reflect truths that are less universal. The proposition, demonstration and corollary allow for the more or less frequent possession of shared properties that are otherwise similar to those described in 2p38. Spinoza’s incrementalism about reason emerges clearly in the corollary: 11 2p39: The idea of a thing, which is common to the human Body and external bodies that usually affect the human Body, and which is equally in the part and in the whole of each, will be adequate in the human Mind. Dem.: Let A be a thing that is common to and a property of the human body and certain external bodies and that is equally in the human body and in the same external bodies and, finally, that is equally in the part and in the whole of each external body. An adequate idea of A will be given in God (2p7c) both insofar as he has an idea of the human body and also insofar as he has ideas of those external bodies. Suppose now that the human body is affected by an external body through this that they have in common, that is, through A, the idea of this affection will involve the property, A (2p16), and therefore (2p7c) the idea of this affection insofar as it involves A will be adequate in God insofar as he is affected with the idea of the human body, that is, insofar as he constitutes the nature of the human mind (2p13). Therefore (2p11), this idea is also adequate in the human mind. Cor.: From this is follows that a mind whose body has more in common with other bodies is more able to perceive more things adequately. By 2p38, all minds at all times have robustly conscious, adequate ideas of properties common to all bodies in their ideas of the common notions. Moreover, by 2p39, some 12 minds have robustly conscious, adequate ideas of some other kinds of properties. The number and kind of such ideas that minds possess vary incrementally, depending upon the constitution of the human bodies and the abundance of the relevant properties in the external bodies with which the human bodies interact. The corollary to 2p39 indicates the importance of this result to Spinoza’s epistemology and moral philosophy: the existence of properties that are similar to but less abundant than common properties suggests that minds may take advantage of such properties to gain more knowledge of the external world. Where such ideas have affective components, such knowledge will also help a mind to master passions by means of ideas that possess the same pro tanto advantage, though to a lesser degree, as the common notions. Affects arising from the common notions, on the argument of 5p7, will be more powerful than any idea that is not present in all of a mind’s imaginations just insofar as they are continuously present. Similarly, any affects arising from the sorts of ideas described in 2p39 will be both present to mind and adequate, and they will be possess something close to the pro tanto advantage of affects arising from the common notions to the extent that the property in question is present in the external bodies with which the human body interacts. 1.3 Spinoza and Spinozism about Imperatives Spinoza does not explicitly identify the commands of reason with ideas of reason, and it is not clear in the Ethics what precisely the relation is. Perhaps the commands of reason require those actions that we perform when we are motivated by ideas of reason? Perhaps they are themselves ideas that we have that arise from ideas of reason but they are not 13 themselves ideas of reason. Perhaps they just are a variety of idea of reason. As an interpretative question, each option presents puzzles. I will not attempt to resolve the question here. That is one respect—there will be others—in which the theory here is not properly regarded as Spinoza’s own theory. I will consider it to be characteristic of Spinozistic moral imperatives that they are ideas similar to the common notions: adequate ideas that are powerfully present to mind in the same way that common notions are, that is, continuously and in ways appropriate to a particular situation. By “appropriate” I mean that, just as ideas of reason in sensation are knowledge of universally common properties as those properties occur in the objects of sensation, so the commands of reason include their own interpretations that are, in some sense, correct. If it is not clear that this is Spinoza’s own view, I think that it is nevertheless appropriate to find the view Spinozistic because of the emphasis that Spinoza puts on the presence of moral ideas in imagination. In addition to 5p7, this emphasis is clear in the scholium to 5p10, where Spinoza urges us to resist the influence of harmful passions by doing what we can to make commands of reason more robustly present in imagination: The best thing, therefore, that we can do while we do not have perfect knowledge of our affects is to conceive of…sure maxims of life, to commit them to memory, and to apply them continually to particular cases we frequently meet in life, so that our imagination will be affected by them extensively, and they will always be manifest (in promptu) to us. For example, we have asserted as a maxim of life (see 4p46 and 4p46s) that hate should be conquered by love, or nobility, not however by reciprocal 14 hatred. So that we may always have this rule of reason ready when it is needed, however, we should think and meditate often about common human wrong and how and in what way they may best be driven away by nobility. Thus, we will join the image of an injury to the imagination of this rule and (2p18) it will always be at hand when an injury is done to us... ...We should think about tenacity in the same way in order to set aside fear; that is, we should recount in detail and frequently imagine the common dangers of life, and how, by presence of mind and by strength of character they may best be avoided and overcome. This passage is not textual evidence one way or the other for the interpretative thesis that commands of reason are continuously present to mind in the same way that ideas of reason are. It might be taken to indicate that they are not continuously present to mind, and that this is the problem the moral sage ought to remedy. Or it might be taken to indicate that the moral sage can build on the advantage that the commands of reason already have by working to make their presence to the imagination still greater than it is already. On either reading, however, 5p10s does indicate that Spinoza associates robust awareness in imagination, the mental faculty that he associates with sensation, with the motivational influence of moral imperatives. That association justifies understanding moral imperatives that are present to mind in a manner similar to that in which minds know properties of objects in sensation to be Spinozistic moral imperatives. If commands of reason follow ideas of reason with respect to presence of mind, do they do so with respect to incrementalism as well? Spinoza does not offer commands 15 that are limited in scope in the same way that, at 2p39, he describes ideas of reason that represent properties shared by some but not all bodies. (Indeed even his invocation of ideas of reason at 5p7 does not refer to the ideas described at 2p39. The demonstration suggests that ‘reason’ ought to be understood to concern common properties alone.) I think, however, that there is again a good basis in the Ethics, for taking a Spinozistic theory of imperatives to include such commands. One reason to find the view Spinozistic is that Spinoza’s normative ethics tends to make action from knowledge a condition of reasonable and right action. For example, he argues at 4p63C that by a desire from reason, a person directly pursues the good and flees evil only indirectly. The implication of this view, since all forms of emotion arising from the apprehension of evil are harmful passions on Spinoza’s account, is that rational action does not arise from the apprehension of evil but from knowledge of the good. He goes on to illustrate his position in a scholium: “The sick man eats what disgusts him because he fears death; the healthy man, on the other hand, enjoys eating and so also enjoys life more than he would if he feared death and directly desired to avoid it.” The point is that eating healthy good from knowledge and positive love for it is a good action, but that the same action from an inadequate idea and the wrong passion is wrong. This position suggests that if there are ideas of reason that are known only by some minds and in some circumstances, those ideas might be the basis for right action in those circumstances alone: many moral imperatives we might devise on Spinoza’s behalf will have a scope limited by circumstances and, in particular, by the agent’s knowledge. A second reason for taking a Spinozistic theory of imperatives to incorporate the incrementalism of Spinoza’s account of reason is that Spinoza frequently does emphasize 16 the importance of particular situations—which minds contemplating which actions in what circumstances—for understanding the rightness and the rationality of action. At 4p59 he argues for something like this point, with respect to minds, generally: “To every action to which we are determined to act from a passion, we can be determined without it, from reason.” More important, perhaps, Spinoza’s infrequent, strong absolute recommendations of certain kinds of actions are best interpreted as diagnostic tools. Notably, he writes at 4p72 that the free man always acts honestly and never acts deceptively. This proposition is difficult to reconcile with Spinoza’s emphasis on selfpreservation if it is taken itself, after the fashion of a Kantian categorical imperative, as exceptionless. Scholars have found instead that the proposition describes what a free man does and so tells us whether we might be free in a particular situation, for example, if we have acted dishonestly, whether we have acted wholly freely.5 If general normative claims are to be used to diagnose what is good or not good to do in particular situations, though, that suggests that what is good or not good varies as particular situations vary. A localized view of right action such as this one is consonant with an account of practical reason that is sensitive to the particular states of agents and their surroundings and so can ground it. To take stock, the Spinozistic account of imperatives that I have presented here emphasizes presence to mind and incrementalism. The most basic imperatives, the limit case analogous to Spinoza’s commands of reason, are present to all minds continuously 5 For an influential account of 4p72, see Don Garrett, “ ‘A Free Man Always Acts Honestly, not Deceptively’: Freedom and the Good in Spinoza’s Ethics” in Spinoza: Issues and Directions, edited by Edwin Curley and Pierre-François Moreau (Leiden: Brill, 1990), 221-38. I have discussed this issue as well. See, “Spinoza’s Normative Ethics,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37:3 (2007), 371-392 and in From Bondage to Freedom: Spinoza on Human Excellence (New York: Oxford, 2010), 175-193. 17 and bind in all circumstances. They are a kind of common sense.6 Other imperatives are similar to the limit case in the way that they are known when they are known, but they are present only to some minds at some times and, because the relevant practical knowledge is a condition on right action, bind only in some circumstances. They are incrementally less common. Finally, there are imperatives similar to the imperatives of Part 5 of Ethics: know your passions! keep nobility present to mind! This last class of imperatives may indeed bind in all circumstances, but they are not related closely to reason and are not known in experience. They are not common sense, which we all share to a greater or lesser degree. Instead they are part of the wisdom of the sage. 2 Spinozism, Imperatives, and Morality Spinoza’s emphasis on the presence of practical reason in experience and his incremental naturalism are striking, distinctive, and appealing features of his account of imperatives. The attraction of Spinozism, generally, may be shown by a comparison to Kantian conceptions of practical reason and moral imperatives. Kant distinguishes sharply between the moral and the natural good whereas Spinoza identifies them. This contrast is most starkly evident, perhaps, in the philosophers’ accounts of the highest good. Spinoza closely associates the highest good, the knowledge of God, the highest degree of virtue, and the highest degree of human happiness, self-contentment.7 Kant, however, makes the highest good consist in virtue and happiness. That is, Kant takes the natural good of 6 [Cite common sense passage from the TTP.] Spinoza introduces the highest good at 4p28. Other important passages include 4p52, 4 Appendix 4, 5p15, and 5p20. One indication of Spinoza’s association of reason with imagination is his emphasis on knowledge of the third kind in discussions of the knowledge of God after 5p20, in the part of the Ethics concerning mind without imagination. Note LeBuffe and Rutherford. 7 18 human being to be something that can be added to the good that a person possesses as a moral and so extra-natural being.8 Turning to imperatives, Spinoza, as we have seen, places morality seamlessly in nature. He finds in our human bodies and the objects around us a source of obligation. Notably, facts about the world—properties that are common to our bodies and the external objects with which we interact and that are known in our experience of those objects—yield practical guidance. Kant, however, finds a source of obligation outside of and above nature. The ground of obligation in moral laws, he insists in the Preface to the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (44-45 or Akademie 4:389), “must not be sought in the nature of the human being or in the circumstances of the world in which he is placed, but a priori simply in the concepts of pure reason; [any] precept, which is based upon principles of mere experience—even if it is universal in a certain respect—insofar as it rests in the least part on empirical grounds, perhaps only in terms of a motive, can indeed be called a practical rule but never a moral law.” Experience can inform our deliberation about how to meet our obligations, but no fact about the world that is the least part empirical can for Kant be a ground of obligation. Thus stated in very general terms, and subject of course to a great deal of interpretation, Spinoza’s position simply looks better than Kant’s. Of course the way that the world and we happen to be and what we know about the world from experience is the source of knowledge of what we ought to do. Without doubt it is difficult to say precisely in what way nature and our knowledge of it inform practical reason. That difficulty does not change the fact that it is necessary for the praiseworthiness of an action that the world 8 See Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason in Practical Philosophy, edited and translated by Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 228-229 (or Volume 5, 110-111 of the Akademie edition). 19 in which one acts is a certain way rather than some other way. Kant, I think, does not do enough to acknowledge the strength of his rejection of this position. He does famously concede that the categorical imperative will require us to tell the truth even the circumstances of the world in some case are such that doing so will have disastrous consequences. The position of the Preface, however, requires much more: we should do what the categorical imperative requires of us even if all circumstances are such that disastrous consequences always follow. This separation of practical reason from experience is as mistaken as it could be. Spinoza, by contrast, has a very appealing general conception of the relationship between experience and practical reason: we ought to do just what we know from experience to do. Some conclusions about what to do will be general because they are known in all experience; others, just as important perhaps, will fall short of perfect generality because they are known in and so ought to be done in only some circumstances.9 In this section, I will try to build on the appeal of Spinoza’s view for some fundamental questions about morality. 2.1 Universality and Morality An imperative of morality is frequently thought to be universal in at least two senses, applying to agents and to circumstances: everybody should heed it and in all cases. Kant’s categorical imperatives, for example, clearly have both senses and perhaps are stronger still: all possible agents should follow them in all possible circumstances. An imperative of morality is sometimes thought to be universal in a third, epistemic sense as 9 [Soften the criticism of Kant by noting the consequentialist stuff from other writings. But emphasize the basic structure of Kant’s commitments and the importance to contemporary ethics, to Kantianism, of the Groundwork.] 20 well: everybody might know any genuine moral imperative, that is, it is available to reason. Kant guarantees this kind of access to the content of morality as well, I think, making it something like a condition of agency.10 In defending more modest theories of moral imperatives, for example theories of morality on which moral imperatives are hypothetical imperatives of a certain sort, authors typically seek to show that the imperatives they find really are moral just by showing that they are universal in something like these senses. J.W.N. Watkins, for example, defended an influential interpretation of Hobbes on which Hobbesian moral imperatives were hypothetical but universal in the sense that they described universal means to ends that are universally desired: We all want to survive; and keeping covenant is the best means to survival; therefore we all ought always to keep our covenants.11 It is not emphasized in Watkins’s account, but the third sense of universality is clearly present in this interpretation of Hobbes as well. The imperatives under discussion Hobbes clearly takes to be known by all rational men. They are the laws of nature, “of which no man, that pretends but reason enough to govern his private family, ought to be ignorant.”12 Universality is a feature of morality for Spinoza as well. Indeed a prominent commentator has defended an interpretation of Spinoza’s commands of reason under which their universality is like that of Watkins’s Hobbesian laws of nature.13 I think, however, that the place of universality in Spinozism is different and, although all three types of universality contribute to the important functions of imperatives that have them, 10 [ Cite a passage or two in Kant. And Locke and Hobbes] [Cite Watkins] 12 Hobbes, Leviathan, edited by Noel Malcolm (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2012) 3: 1139, ll 3-4. 13 [Curley—and say why I disagree and cite my own discussion of Curley.] 11 21 none is necessary to morality. Genuine moral imperatives may fail to be universal in any of the three senses. Under Spinozism, the commands of reason, those imperatives that arise from the common notions, are indeed universal in the sense that they bind us all in all cases. The scholium to 4p18 suggests, for example, that all of us ought to seek perseverance in being in all circumstances. It is also clear from Spinoza’s account of the source of such commands in the common notions that the commands are readily known in a way that is distinctive of reason, that is, they are known by all in all experience. Incrementalism in Spinoza suggests, however, that none of these three sorts of universality are distinctive of moral imperatives. There are, for example, imperatives that are not known through reason and that belong only to the sage who has attained an unusual degree of mastery of the passions. There are also acts that we ought to do from those of our ideas of reason that are related to properties shared by our bodies and some but not all other bodies. Only those who know such imperatives and only the circumstances in which they are known have the kind of obligation that the commands of reason always carry. So universality in Spinozistic ethics is a kind of limit case. An important set of imperatives, the commands of reason, are universal in the agent, circumstantial, and epistemic senses. Perhaps in the best circumstances—in which bodies were maximally powerful and Spinoza was maximally successful in the project with which his begins the Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect, of bringing “as many people as possible, as easily and securely as possible” to the greatest happiness and the best understanding of nature—the other imperatives of reason would be known by and applicable to all and everyone would have the sage’s wisdom robustly present to mind just as the commands 22 of reason are. In actual circumstances, however, genuine imperatives, although similar in kind to the commands of reason in some ways, nevertheless fall short of universality in one or more of the three senses. 2.2 Local Imperatives of Reason The Spinozistic distinction between those ideas that are known to all and apply in all circumstances and those that are not universally known or applicable is important for what it is not: a distinction between imperatives that require the pursuit of ends without qualification or for its own sake and imperatives that require the pursuit of an end for the sake of some further end. The common notions give rise to commands, the commands of reason, that are known to all in all circumstances and so apply in all circumstances. Supposing that ideas of reason present in some but not all minds give rise to commands as well, the knowledge in which those commands consist is not different in kind from the knowledge that is a common notion. As Spinoza would say of an idea of the sort described at 2p39, it is still an idea of reason. It is simply less common. So local imperatives need not differ in kind from universal imperatives. Just as I must without qualification pursue the greater of two goods if that is a command arising from a common notion, so I must without qualification keep left if that is a command arising from a less common idea of reason. The result, I think, is a strong and interesting account of etiquette. Two familiar views about etiquette—both of which are strengthened by the identification of moral imperatives with categorical imperatives and imperatives of etiquette with hypothetical imperatives—are suspicious: the requirements of etiquette can never provide an equal or 23 stronger reason for action than the requirements of morality; and etiquette and morality can sometimes conflict. If we identify the common notions as the source of moral imperatives and the ideas of reason described in 2p39 as the source of imperatives of etiquette, Spinozism provides strong responses to both views. First, because ideas of the same sort—adequate ideas—are the source of both morality and etiquette, it will not be the case that the commands of morality always provide a stronger reason for action than the commands of etiquette. Morality requires honesty, suppose, and etiquette requires keeping left. We may view the demands of etiquette as quite as strong as the demands of morality for cases like this one: surely some instances failing to keep left are worse than some instances of dishonesty. Spinozism vindicates that insight by making morality’s commands and the commands of etiquette similar in kind. Second, some social conventions that are known as etiquette might indeed seem to conflict with morality. In Central Texas, conventions of diet might seem suggest that, by etiquette, a person should eat one hundred pounds of meat every year. If animal suffering, self-abuse, and environmental degradation are morally wrong, though, morality may seem under this assumption to conflict with etiquette in this case: morally speaking, a person should eat less meat, perhaps none. Spinozism suggests a different and more appealing way of presenting the example. Etiquette is similar in kind to morality in its basis and the strength of its demands and different only in the extent to which it is present in minds. We may therefore draw on familiar arguments for the impossibility of moral conflict to undermine supposed examples, like this one, of the conflict between etiquette 24 and morality.14 In the terminology of the Ethics, we should say that all adequate ideas are consistent, and that the common notions (introduced at 2p38), therefore, are consistent with other, local truths of reason (introduced at 2p39). Likewise, commands of reason will not conflict with local commands. Undoubtedly there is a localized convention that meat should be eaten in Central Texas. If that convention conflicts with morality, Spinozism suggests, that is an indication that it is not genuine and respectable etiquette there, as perhaps keeping right is. In short, because etiquette is rational under it, Spinozism has the resources to distinguish between valuable and respectable social conventions—genuine etiquette—and those that are not valuable and may perhaps be against reason. A true, if local, demand of reason would not conflict with a universal imperative. Of course these features of Spinozism are related. One reason to think that the commands of reason are stronger than the commands of etiquette is that, in cases of conflict between morality and etiquette, it seems clear that morality should prevail: it offers a better reason, and, in the case of well-adjusted person, a stronger motive. Once we identify etiquette with local commands of reason and therefore give ourselves a means of distinguishing genuine etiquette from valueless or harmful convention, which is not rational, this basis for drawing a distinction in kind between morality and etiquette also vanishes. Genuine etiquette may offer reasons and motives just as strong as or stronger than those supplied by morality. It is part of morality, even if it lacks universality. Since etiquette and morality do not conflict, however, this fact never implies that the less moral action is sometimes best. 14 Note literature on moral conflict, perhaps Brink. 25 2.3 Responsibility and Cooperation There is good reason to conceive of the distinction between the commands associated with the common notions and commands that arise from the ideas of reason described in 2p39 as a distinction between moral imperatives and genuine imperatives of etiquette. As we have seen, the former have and the latter lack much of the universality that is usually taken to be characteristic of morality. Because the common notions belong to all minds whatever the commands of reason are universal in the familiar sense of binding all rational beings in all circumstances.15 Commands arising from localized ideas of reason are not and so do not. Although local commands—the commands of etiquette—might be quite as binding as universal commands in the sense that they are rational requirements to just the same extent, the presence of reason to imagination gives universal commands, the commands of reason, a much greater social importance, which may be understood in terms of responsibility and social cooperation. Supposing that we take a person to be responsible for wrongdoing whenever she violates a known requirement of reason, the presence of reason in imagination suggests that persons are always responsible for 15 Understanding which beings are rational beings in this sense, that is, which beings are capable of practical deliberation under Spinozism, is difficult. Spinoza does offer a restrictive sense of action—causing something as an adequate cause—which one might hope could serve as a basis for an account of agency. Making the capacity to act in this sense of action a necessary condition on agency may be too strong. The argument of Ethics 5pp7-10 suggests that those deeply influenced by passion are bound by but regularly fail to follow the commands of reason. That is, they are regulated by commands that in some sense they cannot follow. On the other hand, it seems clear that the capacity for action in the narrow sense is sufficient for agency on Spinoza’s own account. We might say, for example, that an elephant or a computer is an agent if it ever does act as an adequate cause. Indeed, in some passages, Spinoza also suggests that this condition is sufficient for being a genuine thing [CITE]. 26 violations of the commands of reason. The commands of reason follow from the common notions, ideas of reason present in all minds. So we may be sure that an agent violating a command of reason knew consciously at the time of action that she was doing so. Any violation of them may be understood to be a product of conscious deliberation in which the moral rule was considered and the decision to violate it explicit. Supposing that it would be just as wrong, in a given circumstance, to fail to keep left as to act dishonestly, then, there remains a difference between the two wrongs: the person who fails to drive on the left may truthfully claim not to know that she should have done so but the person who fails to act honestly cannot make such a claim. The familiar conviction that moral violations are worse than violations of etiquette—one sense of which we have already discredited—can be recast, then, in epistemological terms: moral violations are those in which the law breaker certainly acted in the knowledge that the action was wrong; violations of etiquette may or may not be instances of knowingly doing wrong. Of course, just as ideas of reason that are not ideas of common properties vary incrementally, so commands that are not moral imperatives may approach universality more or less closely, such that judgments about responsibility in violating norms of etiquette may likewise vary. The universal presence in imagination of moral imperatives, in Spinoza’s account, also serves to justify our expectations that others will be moral. It is likely that a great number of laws and other conventions in a given society will be a matter of etiquette, and a person can understand those conventions more or less comprehensively. A complete stranger, however, can be confident both that others will—if not always act on the commands of reason—at least know them, be generally guided by them and also that 27 others will expect that her own actions will be similarly governed. So understood the commands of reason are core social values. Every society will include them, and, just because of their importance to responsibility, they might be expected hold a special status in each society. They do not guarantee cooperation because we do not always act rationally. They do, however, describe what cooperation in society should be. Spinoza himself defends these points at 4p37s2: If men lived under the guidance of reason, each might hold [the right of nature] without any harm to another (4p35c1). However because they are vulnerable to affects (4p4c), which far surpass human power, or virtue (4p6), they are often drawn in different directions (4p33) and oppose one another (4p34) even while they stand in need of each other’s aid (4p35s).16 Just as one may distinguish between genuine etiquette and mere convention by reference to the consistency of local imperatives and moral imperatives, one may also distinguish different spheres and subspheres of society by reference to different imperatives of etiquette characteristic of them. Our attributions of responsibility and expectations for conformity to etiquette will vary to the extent that we understand each sphere and take others to belong or not to belong to a given sphere. 2.4 Morality and Motivation 16 A similar passage opens the Theological Political Treatise: “It is far from true that everyone can always be led under the guidance of reason alone. For each is drawn by his own delight, and the mind is so often filled with avarice, ambition, envy, anger and so on that no place remains for reason” (Spinoza 1972, 3/193 1-4). 28 Spinoza’s intellectualism incorporates a close association between activity and belief. In each adequate idea that a mind has, it is also active; each inadequate idea in a mind reflects in part the activity of external things on the mind, and a mind may be less active to the extent that the activity of external things opposes its own activity. Because of this close association, the contribution of Spinoza to the question of the relation between morality and motivation may seem to fall largely outside of the main lines of debate.17 Many of the philosophers debating the question, calling themselves Humean, distinguish sharply between belief and desire and so do not consider a position like Spinoza’s to contribute to the debate.18 Such a conclusion would be hasty. Presence to mind in Spinoza’s theory of moral imperatives is a positive account of motivation associated with morality that is available to Humeans and anti-Humeans alike. It suggests, following 5p7, that moral convictions are pro tanto more powerful than other motives because and to the extent that they are more robustly conscious. Even supposing that belief and desire are different, it is clear that belief can contribute to motivation, that is, to the production of action. Beliefs arising in sensation are especially good candidates because they are prominent in consciousness in the right way. For example, suppose that I have two desires that are equally strong: I want to fold my clothes and I want to read the latest issue of the journal. Suppose also that I have forgotten about both desires. Neither is strong enough to be gripping. Pacing with little to 17 For a defense of the importance of Spinoza’s close association of activity and belief, see Don Garrett, “Spinoza’s Ethical Theory,” in The Cambridge Companion to Spinoza (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 295-297. 18 For a classic, accessible discussion of the various positions that one might take on the relation between morality and motivation, see Michael Smith, The Moral Problem (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), 4-13. Smith might characterize Spinoza, with some good company, as an anti-Humean theorist of motivation, 12-13. 29 do one afternoon, I come across a sticky note: “Fold your clothes!” Although, other things being equal, my desires are equally likely to produce action, this experience tips the balance. I fold my clothes. Presence to mind in Spinozism suggests that experience is full of similar reminders to actions. Elements of what I sense remind me continuously of my projects, interests, likes, and dislikes. The reminders may be construed as solely cognitive and not desires themselves. (Spinoza does not construe the relevant ideas of reason in this way.) Under such a conception they still contribute to my activity. Spinoza’s universal moral imperatives, the commands of reason, are particularly prominent in experience. Wherever I turn my attention, 2p38 suggests, an element of experience serves as a sticky note saying, “a lesser good now is not as valuable as a greater good later.” As a result of their prominence in experience, as Spinoza argues at 5p7, motives that I have to act on the commands of reason will be systematically more efficacious than other motives. It can happen that we fail to act on the commands of reason, but we can never fail to know them in acting. Imperatives of etiquette, as presented in 2.3, are not universally present in experience. In some regions, however, they may be quite prominent. The account of the sticky note is not a metaphor. It is an example.19 Other examples may include signs; the behavior of others, and regional instances of properties that have practical consequences just as the common notions are universal properties that have the same practical consequences everywhere. The Spinozistic view on which the motivation characteristic of morality is a function of the prominence of reminders to moral behavior in ongoing experience is 19 The close association of etiquette and public signs may be clearer in French. ‘Étiquette’means both etiquette and, more commonly, label. 30 consistent with many varieties of internalism, the conception of the relation between morality and motivation on which whenever I understand an action to be morally required I also have a motive (on some strong versions, an overriding motive) to perform that action. However, this element of Spinozism is perhaps more important to externalists, those who deny that such understanding always includes a motive. For externalists widely hold that we usually have motives to do what we think right and that there are some circumstances in which we nevertheless lack such motives. The presence to mind of moral imperatives both explains why moral motives are typically very strong and also describes the circumstances in which we might fail to be guided by them. We typically have a strong motive to act morally because a moral command is reinforced in experience whereas other potential motives—desires, perhaps, of which we are not currently aware—are not. Commands of reason, notably, are always reinforced in experience. When we fail to act on the commands of reason, a strong reading of 5p7 suggests, it is because our other desires are reinforced in a similar way. Present temptation belongs to experience, although perhaps only to present experience, in the same way that a moral command does. A weaker reading of 5p7 suggests that we may have desires that are not moral and not reinforced in experience but are nevertheless very strong and can override the desire to act well. On either interpretation of 5p7, Spinoza holds that our motivation to act on imperatives of reason will retain a pro tanto greater strength than other motives in virtue of its presence in experience. The moral knowledge that is practical reason in Spinoza is occurrent knowledge. Spinoza’s association of presence to mind with the motivation to act well at 5p7 makes a valuable point about publicity. The publication of law clearly has the benefits of 31 responsibility and cooperation: only if a law is known can we hold law breakers responsible and expect to gain the benefits of cooperation. If the law is a good one, Spinoza’s argument at 5p7 establishes that publication also makes citizens better. The presence to mind of a good law typically contributes to the motivation to follow that law and therefore makes knowledge of the rule more robust (contributing to a person’s character) and action more frequently right. 2.5 Aspirational Morality Several aspects of Spinoza’s discussions of the commands of reason characterize them in ways that may place them out of reach. First (from 1.1), Spinoza’s initial presentation of the common notions in the Ethics suggests that they are present in the experience of all minds whatever, not only the minds of human agents, and for Spinoza it is probably correct to say that all singular things have minds. Because the commands of reason arise from the common notions, this point suggests, wildly, that all singular things are bound by the commands of reason and know them continually in experience.20 Second (from 2.1), incrementalism in Spinozistic accounts of imperatives suggest that the universality of the commands of reason is a limit case. A wide range of imperatives are known only to some minds, are robustly conscious only in some minds, and applicable only in some cases. The commands of reason, on the other hand, are few, and their derivation from the 20 I think that this is the most pressing problem for the attribution to Spinoza of an interesting theory of consciousness. Invocations of incrementalism (of power or complexity) typically help sympathetic readers to argue that, in a sense, pears and frying pans “think” about their surroundings; because they are so simply, they are just very badly confused and the thinking that they do is primitive. Ideas of reason, however, are adequate in all minds just as the common properties are present in all bodies. Pears and frying pans have adequate ideas of the common properties, then, and they know them and regard them as present in any bodies with which they interact. 32 common notions is not clear. Third (from 2.3 and 2.4), although it does seem right that responsibility and cooperation in society depend upon the assumption that others know what is required in some circumstances of action, the rosy picture of universal, occurrent knowledge may seem overly optimistic; moral requirements are known more or less widely and robustly, but none are known universally and in all sensation, even by human agents. These points suggest that there are not any imperatives known to all and binding to all in all circumstances, whatever Spinoza himself might argue. It is not clear, however, that this is a problem for Spinozism, however, and it may be a strength. The independent rational authority of local imperatives in Spinoza, together with his incrementalism, suggests that there need not be imperatives like the commands of reason described in the Ethics. Sometimes local imperatives of morality are thought to depend upon imperatives that are universal in two or all three senses for their rational authority. Kant is perhaps best understood in this way: the addition of empirically learned considerations yields hypothetical imperatives recommending the means to an end derived from pure practical reason.21 Such a view requires universal imperatives, then, if there are to be any moral imperatives at all. The independent rational authority of local imperatives (from 2.2) in Spinozism avoids this requirement. Local imperatives have the same basis in Spinoza’s account of reason as that possessed by the commands of reason. If it is true, then, that despite Spinoza’s own arguments on behalf of commands of reason there are not any, that does not mean that local imperatives lack authority. The Spinozist 21 The interpretation of Kant’s hypothetical imperatives remains a vexed question. In recommending this account, I follow Mark Schroeder, “The Hypothetical Imperative,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 83 (2005): 357-372. 33 may hold that there are only local imperatives and may make use of the resources of coherentism to understand their justification and structure.22 We might nevertheless want to work towards universality in our imperatives. One important reason for doing so is social. In the spirit of Spinoza remarks at 4p37s2, the more frequently we can understand each other’s motives and predict each other’s actions, the better we can cooperate. Perfect cooperation, as Spinoza admits, is beyond reach in any case; we are too often moved to act against what we know to be best. The admission that there are in fact no fully universal commands of reason reveals another barrier between the ideal of perfect cooperation and the actual world. We will cooperate reliably only insofar as we are rational, and rationality has only local bases, which we must expand in order to realize the benefits of society more fully. Another reason for working toward universality is a consideration of the good of each person. Any step toward universality in the agent sense contributes to the practical rationality of those who are brought under the scope of a local moral imperative. Despite being local, such an imperative will be adequate (that is, it will be rational to act on it) and be present to mind in those who possess it. So, like all ideas of reason, it will help that person both to resist irrational motives and also to be better. The independence of local moral imperatives in Spinozism permits a shift in our understanding of the universal in morality from a kind of ground of practical reason to an aspiration. As I have acknowledged, this is a departure from Spinoza’s own conception of reason in human practice. Spinoza derives commands of reason solely from the common 22 David Brink, Moral Realism and Foundation of Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), Chapter 5 informs this discussion. Brink defends a coherentist account of justification in his argument for moral realism. 34 notions, universal truths of reason, and he does not derive any commands of reason from the local truths of reason described at 2p39. Nevertheless, I think that it is a small departure. Spinoza himself does not offer many commands of reason and they are not central to the moral themes of the Ethics. Incrementalism and presence to mind, however, resonate with both Spinoza’s emphasis on situational ethics and his accounts of cooperation in society. The project of building local moral imperatives towards universality lends a clear and specific sense to the project, which is pursued throughout his writing but stated most elegantly perhaps in the Treatise on the Emendation of Intellect: I aim, therefore, at this end: to acquire such a nature and to strive that many others might acquire it with me. It is for my happiness that I work so that many others will understand in the same way that I do, so that their intellects and desires unite harmoniously with my intellect and desire. So that this might happen, it is necessary to understand as much about nature as is necessary for the attainment of such a nature, and, next, to form a society of the desired kind, so that as many people as possible, as easily and securely as possible, may attain it. (Spinoza 1972, 2/8 28-2/9 3)