Discussion Starter for Philosophers in Jesuit Education Meeting, 12/2013 Theistic Explanation in Natural and Moral Philosophy Mark C. Murphy, Georgetown University Theistic explanation The topic that I would like to discuss this evening is theistic explanation. I want to start my giving a brief account of what theistic explanation is, and what theistic explanations in natural and moral philosophy would be like before I turn to the questions for discussion. Here is a generic characterization of theistic explanation. A theistic explanation is, unsurprisingly, an explanation. An explanation relates facts: an explanation is a description of how some fact or thing makes, or contributes to making, some fact the case. That my children are uncontrollable explains why my living room is a mess, because my children’s being uncontrollable makes it the case that the living room is a mess. Theistic explanation is also, unsurprisingly, theistic. An explanation is theistic if the explaining fact, the explanans, is a fact about God. Note here the generality of the idea. To say that something has a theistic explanation leaves open a variety of questions about the sort of theistic explanation that it has. It leaves open the question, for example, whether the relevant theistic facts are facts about God that hold necessarily or facts about God that hold only contingently. It leaves open the question whether there is some particular aspect of God, e.g. the divine intellect or the divine will, that is doing the explaining. It leaves open whether the explanation is partial or complete, i.e. whether nontheistic facts may play an ineliminable role in the relevant explanation. It leaves open whether the explanation is mediated or immediate, i.e. whether the facts about God explain the relevant explanandum only by explaining some other nontheistic fact, or not. It leaves open whether the ‘making it the case’ that figures in explanation is causal (the activity of the bartender explains why there is a whiskey on the rocks in that glass) or constitutive (that there is whiskey in the glass and ice in the glass explains why there is a whiskey on the rocks in the glass). Here is an example of a putative theistic explanation in natural philosophy. There exists a world of finite beings subject to generation and corruption. That such a world exists is explained by the contingent willing of God. To say that God created the world is to give a theistic explanation of the world’s existence. Here is an example of a putative theistic explanation in moral philosophy. There exist requirements that give decisive reason for compliance to every rational creature and which have the same structure as the institutional requirements we 1 call obligations. That such moral requirements exist is explained by God’s having given the content of those requirements as commands to all created rational beings. Explanandum- and explanans-driven explanations When theistic explanation is invoked in natural and moral philosophy, the context is usually the following. There is some phenomenon, an explanandum, that calls for explanation. (This explanandum may be a contingent fact, but it need not be; it is possible for a necessary fact to itself call for explanation, if the necessary obtaining of that fact is not itself self-explanatory.) The only, or best available, explanation is an explanation that appeals to theistic facts. And so, driven by the demands set by the explanandum to be explained, we settle on theistic explanation as the best explanation. The question of when it is appropriate to offer theistic explanations because of explanandum-driven considerations such as these is a difficult and messy and worthwhile one, raising all of the standard concerns about God-of-the-gaps style reasoning along with other less-charged and equally-important questions. And I am happy for there to be discussion of it on this occasion. But my heart’s desire is to consider another way for theistic explanation to be desirable, one that is not occasioned by the need to explain some particular phenomenon in nature or morals but by reflection on the idea of God itself. Call an ‘explanans-driven’ explanation an explanation the quality of which as an explanation is promoted because it belongs to the very nature of the explanans to enter into explanations of that type. Every being that of necessity exercises some activity that tends to brings about certain results in the world is such as to enable some explanans-driven explanations. For every being is such that, by its nature, it makes things to be the case. To be a cat is to bring about a specific range of feline phenomena; to be a mushroom is to bring about a specific range of mushroomy phenomena, and so forth. If there is a cat in the room, and there is cat fur on the sofa, one thing that makes the explanation the cat shed its fur onto the sofa a good explanation of the presence of cat fur on the sofa is that that explanation accounts for the phenomenon; that is its explanandum-driven quality. But it is also made a good explanation because cats gotta shed fur. That’s what they do. So if you have a cat on the scene, then it needs to enter into such explanatory states of affairs. What sorts of explanans-driven theistic explanations should we aim to give? If every sort of existing being can potentially enter into explanans-driven explanations, then we might well wonder if there are theistic explanations that have some of their quality as explanations just from the fact that those explanations have God doing things that God’s just gotta do. Here is one that seems unproblematic. Though the standard view is that God creates contingently, here is an activity that God must engage in: if any contingent substance exists, God creates it. So, supposing God’s existence, for any contingent substance the existence of which calls for 2 explanation, there is something that counts in favor of a theistic explanation: it is an explanans-driven consideration that God is by nature a being the activity of which explains the existence of whatever contingent substances there are. So it is not just that contingent substances need explaining, and God fills the bill; given God’s existence, God is the sort of being that just has to do that sort of explanatory work. Here is an important question. What sorts of issues regarding sort of theistic explanation are answered, at least in part, by considering that some explanations are explanans-driven, and that it belongs to the divine nature to occupy a certain explanatory role? That is a bit of an abstract mouthful, but let me offer a couple of issues that we might address. Range. One thing worth puzzling over is the range of nontheistic facts that should be subject to theistic explanation. Theists have tended to be of one mind that the existence of a world of contingent material objects is the sort of thing that requires a theistic explanation, and they would be skeptical of a view on which there is a mass of material that is simply part of the given that God has to work with, much the way Plato’s demiurge works with refractory material. In other words, it is not just that material beings need a theistic explanation; it is that God must account for their being. But some philosophers have wondered about the existence of other sorts of facts, or things, in ways that either expressly assert or seem implicitly to endorse a limitation on theistic explanation. Some philosophers have suggested that the realm of abstract objects — properties, propositions, etc. — is a realm of necessarily existing beings that does not require theistic explanation. (This view was defended by Wolterstorff in On Universals, and more recently by van Inwagen in “God and Other Uncreated Things.”) Do explanans-driven considerations give us reason to think that such objects must be theistically explained or necessarily nonexistent, even if explanandum-driven considerations do not force us in that direction? Here is another range issue. Leftow has argued that the very range of what is possible should be seen, pace Leibniz, as being theistically explained. The argument is perspicuous: it is that God would be greater if God were conceived as the explainer of modal truth than if these were part of the ‘given’ within which God’s activity must take place. Do explanans-driven considerations give us reason to think that the shape of the modal itself is theistically explained? Immediacy. Put to the side the range issue for a moment. One relevant dimension along which would-be theistic explanations differ is the dimension of immediacy. The divine willing that explains creation is related immediately to the fact of creaturely existence; God uses no instrument to create, and so creation is a matter of immediate theistic explanation. One key question is whether this feature of theistic explanation of creation should be taken to be a feature of the theistic explanation of every phenomenon. Should we take every nondivine fact to have an immediate theistic explanation? 3 Here is a case study. Mere conservationism is the view that God creates and conserves creatures and their causal powers, but the creatures exercise those powers unaided by God; what happens between creatures, so to speak, stays between creatures. Concurrentism is the view that creatures exercise their causal powers only through divine cooperation, divine concurrence, so that in every effect in the natural order there is a theistic explanation that exhibits immediacy. Though facts about the creaturely nature enter ineliminably and immediately into the explanations of all that happens in the natural order, facts about God ineliminably and immediately enter into all that happens as well. Suárez, a defender of the concurrentist view, considers a variety of reasons for thinking that the action of creatures requires divine cooperation. Some of these arguments hold that it is arbitrary or incoherent to hold that God conserves effects in existence while rejecting that God concurs in the bringing about of those effects. Some make appeals to Scripture, either to direct descriptions of divine cooperation with the action of creatures or to reports that seem best explained on a concurrentist theory of divine action in nature (e.g. the miraculous non-incineration of Shadrach, Meschach, and Abednego in the fiery furnace, which Suárez interprets to be a case in which God miraculously withheld concurrence from the fire while leaving the fire’s nature intact). But he saves what he calls his “best argument” for last: This manner of acting [i.e. divine concurrence in the ordinary course of nature] in and with all agents pertains to the breadth of divine power, and on God’s part it presupposes a perfection untainted by imperfection; and even though it does bespeak an imperfection on the part of the creature, … this imperfection is nonetheless endemic to the very concept of a creature or participated being as such. … For the rest, there is in this way a perfect and essential ordering between the First Cause and the secondary cause, and there is nothing impossible here… therefore, this general influence should not be denied to God (Disputationes Metaphysicae, disputations 20-22 trans. Alfred Freddoso as On Creation, Conservation, and Concurrence (St. Augustine’s Press, 2002), 22, 1, 13.). I understand Suarez here to be making an argument from the perfection of the divine nature — an explanans-driven consideration — to the concurrentist account of divine action in nature. It befits the perfection of the divine nature to be involved in this intimate way in the bringing about of events in the natural order. And as nothing precludes this relationship between God and creature in the bringing about of events in the natural order, then, that relationship ought to be affirmed. Suárez’s “best argument” appeals primarily to God’s nature — it speaks to the “breadth of divine power” and is possible only for a being whose “perfection is untainted by imperfection.” And so we should take God’s involvement in nature to be the more 4 extensive concurrentist account rather than the less extensive conservationist account. Is Suarez’s argument cogent, the sort of thing that can be used to assess rival explanations? Should we take it that every nondivine fact has a theistic explanation that exhibits immediacy? Are there any facts that just preclude this understanding? Completeness. While I obviously have some enthusiasm for Suárez’s argument, my enthusiasm is tempered by the fact that it looks like one could wield it as an argument that theistic explanation of nondivine facts is not just immediate, but complete. Yikes. If you wield that argument in natural philosophy, you get occasionalism. If you wield it in moral philosophy, you get raging theological voluntarism. Suppose for the sake of argument that both of these are bad things. Is there a way of making a relevant distinction, so that even if Suárez’s best argument gives a strong basis for preferring theistic explanations that exhibit immediacy, that argument does not give a strong basis for preferring theistic explanations that exhibit completeness? (Suárez is very clear that God’s contribution is not typically complete (except in the case of miracles, say), but that it is not complete is treated as just an obvious point, and we aren’t given a diagnosis of why the form of the argument for divine immediacy does not also yield an argument for divine completeness.) The general question that gathers together the various particular queries raised above is: What implications does theism itself have for the sort of theistic explanations we affirm? I am much looking forward to y’all’s guidance for how to think through this question. 5