Wherein is Language Social, Burge 113 1. Language is social in two senses. a. interaction with others is necesary to learn a language. b. dialects of countries, cites, etc are shared. Shared, by social groups. 114 1. But, still, Burge notes that individuals do not often accord with public usage. 2. And if we want to have an individual psychology, perhaps 'there is some point is abstracting away from social or public patterns.' 3. But he notes that 'this view is limited.' 4. By, the fact that 'there is wide variation among people.' 5. For, after all 'peoples beliefs depend upon their experiences. 6. Hence, to account for all this, via Chomsky, 'there is a universal grammar, that is universal and individual.' 115 1. Chomsky develops a ideal speech community, where all people have the same linguistic capacities. 2. But, not just grammer, but 'relations to others enter into semantical kinds.' 116 1 1. Thought is individuated nonindividualistically. The 'nature of thoughts depends on the envirionment in which we interact.' 2. 'What information, say perceptions, we process' says Burge 'is dependent upon properties in the world which members of our species interact with perceptually.' 3. And, what 'empirical concepts' we think of is dependent upon external items. 4. We must distinguish what individuation is. a. our thoughts do not supervene on our bodies. b. actual thoughts depend upon nature of actual wide envirionment. c. now, can have the different thoughts, though body effects causally the same. d. the 'kind of thought that one thinks' thus 'is not supervenient on the body.' e. so 'thought kinds are individuated in a way that bears on relations to the envirionment.' 117 1. Failure of supervenience however does not cast doubt upon the fact that 'there are neural realizations of mental structures.' 2. Mental kinds depend on, cognitive function, obtaining information. 3. Likewise, a heart depends on its function in a body that it is in. 4. And, failure of supervenience 'does not entail that psychology must study, or make reference to the relations of individual and envirionment. 5. They, actually, are just presupposed; perhaps philosophy can study these. 118 2 1. Burge dilineates some of the aspects of the nonindividualism claim: a. it is that referents of a persons words could vary, though effects on body stay same. b. and, the referents are not themselves part of the individuals point of view. c. many of those aspects of seemingly personal meaning or thougt, are too nonindividualistically individuated. d. 'what a word means, even in an individuals ideolect, can be nonindividual' Note: In footnote five, Burge notes that the failure of local supervenience, hence nondindividualism, is a product of Kripke's work. on reference show 'the individual's proper He says that views names, kind terms demonstratives.... have definite referents.... even though the individual could not discriminate the referents.' Note: I think the point here is that no supervenience does not mean indefinateness of referent. The referent is still definite for us, though we do not know it. 119 1. In a sense some meanings in language is universal. 2. When we perceive things when we are very young, like early vision, this is independent of language. 3. But, this triggers innate responses, to edges, lines, etc. 4. So, because of biology, because of evolution, etc, such things are set. 5. And, such perceptual notions are nonindividualistically individuated. 6. Create a thouht experiment: 3 a. different optics b. different interactions with fellows. c. so different perceptions, different info. Now, d. but we can conceive of one of these beings, an individual whose by some strange fate, his perceptual notions like e. even if, by some chance, his body is like ours, his ours. 'meanings and senses for perceptual properties will be different.' 7. Burge notes Marr in footnote, that 'perceptual states are individuated by physical properties that bear appropriate relation to the envirion or our ancestors.' 8. Burge notes atop of next page that this is not social, 'the failure of individualism results entirely from the relation of the individual and physical envirionment.' 120 1. Burge says that he wants to show how nonsocial individualism underlies social individualism. 2. He notes that often there is a division of linguistic labor, which Chomsky picks on, and this does not mean that reference is ever indeterminate. 121 1. Deference to experts does not make reference more definate, just more clear. 2. Burge gives usual examples of this, helium, water, etc. does not change the referent, alter, but only clarify. 4 Learning more 3. Reference is not determined or dependent upon what the individual knows. 4. This means though that Chomsky's account is incomplete. Individuals 'explicational ability' does not suffice to 'fix the referent.' 5. In other words, I think, what is in the head, does not of itself fix referent. 6. Burge makes a group of distinctions between dictionary type meaning, and in the head type meaning. 7. On the public side, there is, a lexical item, a word, which has a concept. This public concept has what Burge calls 'translational meaning.' 8. On the head side, there is an head item, an entry for a word, as Burge says. This has an 'conceptual explication.' And, this has an 'explicational meaning.' Note: This seems just to be the difference of public and speaker concepts and meanings. Note: Burge notes that it is often assumed that explicational and translational meanings are interchangible. Well, it is not true. For two reasons. a. the referent plays a key role in individuating translational meaning. b. and, because of the role of nonexplicational abilities play in the individual's application of the concept. He says that he hopes to show the difference between lexical and explanational meaning. 122 1. All our words like mud, fish, walk, shadow, edge, bread, and the like, are not indexical. They do not depend on context time, or shift meaning with 5 context, time, etc. 2. The 'constancy of application' is a 'feature of the meaning' of such nonindexical words. 3. Now referent is a restraint here for 'a word has a different meaning if its constant referent, or, range of application, is different.' 123 1. Now, reference is not fixed by explicational meaning is substantiated: a. by the reference idea, that reference is definite, though you do not know it. b. and, considering the personal dialictic by which we arrive at conceptual explications, or lexical ones. 2. To support this latter, perceptually fixed examples typically determine the application of our words, like chair or water, before conceptual explications come along. 3. Conceptual explications are 'typically inferences from these perceptual examples.' 4. When refining conceptual explanation, first, recognizes perceptual examples as veridical, and then one tries to make sure one's inferences fit them. 5. So, perceptual examples come first, 'they do not derive from conception explications.' Note: Burge gives chair and water examples, where, even when we learn that stools are also chairs, compositions of water, learn something new, still, such revisions are but improvements upon a reference that is already fixed. Note: As he says 'in such cases, it remains possible for me to have thoughts 6 about water as water.' Knowning 'that there may be other similar liquids I cannot discriminate, and will confuse with water.' 6. So, 'there is a sense in which the translational meaning of the word stays the same, even though the expicational meaning changes.' 124 1. Yet, from this view, we cannot infer that correct explications are tacitly in our heads. 2. Nor, that tacit conceptual explications exaust our concepts in general. 3. First, 'we have the materials in our mental repetoirs' to form 'a better conception.' But that does not mean the meanings themselves are already there. 4. The claim is just that 'mental structures for deriving recognition' are in place. So, ideally, in situation 'will lead to recognition.' 5. Second, we have perceptual storehouses. These are nonconceptual. Thus materials are put together, and worked up into conceptual explications. 6. The claim again, is not that these deep down percepts are knowledge. They are not. Note: Burge intends the two above reason to apply to the tacitly in our heads view. The next two are about exausting concepts. 125 1. Third, erceptual ability to dicriminate leads to explicational concepts in home world. 2. Say the ability to discriminate any and all types of sofas round here. 3. Yet, say on other worlds such concepts might have an application. 7 4. But, we might not be able to discriminate look alikes there. 5. So, explicational ability does not exaust the concepts we have. Note: This argument requires a case where discriminative ability of x's works here, but not there. Yet, the concept of x is applicible in both places. a concept seems to conflict with anti individualism though. Such It seems it would be a molinium, or crackdow. 6. Fourth, then we get our references fixed, the relation to examples is perceptual. 7. Of course perception is often wrong. 8. When we get to conception, we inherit this fallability. 9. Yet, such wrong seeings, and thinkings, are still genuine instances of the concepts. 10. Explicational abilites, thus, do not exaust the concepts they explicate. Note: I assume this argument is that after explicational abilities, including errors, are layed out of 'water,' there is a stable, residual, concept of 'water,' that we still have, which is not accounted for by such abilities. This too seems problematic. Note: The problem is that once we admit that we get perception wrong, and conception wrong, in what sense do we have the concept which is stable, residual. It seems that we do not have that concept at all. 126 1. We want to get examples right. So we defer to someone else's linguistic authority. 2. For the authority is 'better placed,' has 'has superior empirical insight' 8 3. Burge notes that we all have access generally to the same stuff. We all live in a world with, and want to talk about chairs, contracts, water, and fish. 4. And, a 'persons access to such examples' often, 'is through others.' It is through the testimony of others that we get concepts fixed. Note: That is, we all talk about the same subjects, but experts often know them better. 127 1. Such dependence on others for access to examples grows as one learns more. 2. In other words we 'rely on their experience to suppliment out own.' 3. And, this is key 'we accept correction because they have better access to the examples that determine the nature of our concepts.' 4. And, 'if experts had provided different examples... we would have different concepts.' Note: Burge is here talking about translational meaning. meaning is dependent upon interaction with others.' referents. 'Translational He is talking about And, how others let us see them. 128 1. Burge says he will summarize the argument, that 'an individual's ideolect cannot be understood... without others.' a. numerous empirical words are nonindexical. b. they have different translational meanings. e. our explicational meanings do not fix the referents of these. d. our explicational abilities do not fix our translational meanings. 9 e. our conceptual explications and lexical meanings require much correction, to insure their accuracy. f. we cannot do this correction for our cognitive relations to referents is fallable. g. so, others are in a better position to do this for they have better access to the referent. 1. for, we all speak of same stuff. 2. and other have access we do not. h. since translational meaning is dependent upon referent, since others get to the referent, if others told you and about different referents, you would have different translational meanings. Note: Burge makes a rather odd extention in a footnote. view. It seems to bely his He says that from difference in referent, you get difference in concept. But, he says, the difference first might just be in communal standards or access. Then, you might also have different concepts. Note: The reason that this is odd is that it goes against the object fixing concept idea. The idea that the extension makes a difference is no more. I think that perhaps this was a bit of a slip. 129 1. Burge says this argument makes it plausible that 'people share translational meanings,' and this 'regardless of their beliefs about the world.' 2. The applicable concepts like shoe, fish, house, etc are fixed by. a. experienced references, others references, and/or produced by evolution of species. b. rudamentally conceptualizations of said examples. 10 references c. preconceptual perceptual abilities, and kind forming assume this would include visual processes, abilities. I etc. 3. Burge notes that, thus, there is an element of meaning which is shared. Translational meaning. Thus surely is not narrow however. 130 1. The two senses of social, thus, are: a. people defer to others in explanation b. individuation of concepts is access. 11 often dependent upon others