Lezione 2 Summary Deontological and Axiological Moral Theories. Actions and states of affairs. Norms or laws and goodness or value. Two ways of getting to something which is in itself or for its own sake morally praiseworthy: avoiding the regress of moral norms; setting a limit to the mind-dependence of values. Grundnorm and intrinsic value are two completely different ways of satisfying this requirement. (It is a requirement of realism; we are assuming moral realism.) The Development of Moore’s Metaethics (a) The Metaethical Innocence of Principia Ethica In Principia Ethica (PE) Moore holds (but this is a constant feature of his reflection on the foundations of ethics) that the subject matter of ethics consists of judgments that have the character of answers to the question: What kind of things ought to exist for their own sake? (PE 33) The substantive aim of ethics is to provide evidence or to give reasons for holding true certain of these judgments of intrinsic value. Intrinsic value thus is central to ethical enquiry. Ethics as a Systematic Science But it is important to individuate precisely its theoretical role within ethics as “the general enquiry into what is good” (PE 54). The structure of ethics as a “systematic science” (PE 58) can be specified in terms of three tasks. The first one is to give a logical (in Moore’s broad sense: concept- or meaningtheoretical) and metaphysical characterization of the predicate or property of Good. I will follow Moore in using "predicate" and "property" interchangeably, it must be clear from the outset that the enquiry into the meaning of the predicate Good is also and indissolubly an enquiry into the ontology of the property of goodness: What is the nature of that peculiar predicate, the relation of which to other things constitutes the object of all other ethical investigations? Or, in other words, What is meant by good? (PE 89) The second one is to determine what things have this property, or satisfy this predicate: To what things and in what degree does this predicate directly attach? What things are good in themselves? (PE 89) To have correct answers to these questions is, obviously, to have evidence for fundamental ethical judgments, judgments about what things ought to exist for their own sake or have intrinsic value. But ethics does not stop at judging what things are intrinsically good. Judgments of this kind (“So and so is good in itself”, “So and so ought to exist for its own sake”) are fundamental to ethics because they provide a halting point and a ground for all investigation and all judgments about what kinds of actions we ought to perform. This forms the third task of ethics: What kinds of actions ought we to perform? (PE 34) By what means shall we be able to make what exists in the world as good as possible? What causal relations hold between what is best in itself and other things? (PE 89) As it figures in Principia Ethica, the concept of intrinsic value finds its proper application in connection with the second task of ethics, that of establishing what things are ultimately, “directly” good; and with the third one, that of assessing the rightness of actions. The proper understanding of the notion of intrinsic value, that is, presupposes that the logic and metaphysics of the good have been appropriately articulated. It does not primarily and directly consist in framing the logic and metaphysics of the good itself. The Metaethical Agenda of Principia It is noticeable how few (if important) are the things Moore wants to say, in Principia Ethica, about the logical and metaphysical character of Good. Good is simple. This means that the property of goodness cannot be analyzed, resolved into simpler, independent components. The point is metaphysical: the reality of goodness does not consist in the obtaining, in the reality of any simpler and independent component. (Like, for instance, the reality of weight can be resolved in the simpler, independent components of mass and of location in a gravitational field.) The point is also logical: good is simple in that it cannot be defined in any interesting, informative way (as the concept horse can be); in that "it is not composed of any parts, which we can substitute for it in our minds when we are thinking of it" (PE 60). “Good is good, and that is the end of the matter” (PE 58): this, therefore, is not a refusal to take up the question of the composition and definition of good, but a full answer to it. Good is logically and metaphysically atomic and this is the ground for Moore's standing commitment to ethical propositions being all synthetic (PE 58). It is primarily in the sense of being non-analyzable and non-definable that Moore holds the Good to a property which is real in itself and a concept which has content and validity in itself. 1 Non-naturalness is a more complex matter. This is the thing Moore really wants to say about the Good. While he will end up being self-critical about the importance he ascribed to the simplicity of the Good, he never retreated from his commitment to its non-naturalness. However, Moore also never refrained from revising his conception of what is natural and non-natural; and it is precisely one of my tasks to outline a certain reading of the development of his views in this regard. In Principia Ethica Moore seems to suggest a dual criterion for identifying natural properties - in terms of possible independent existence in time and in terms of their constituting the substance of things. The two criteria (which sit uneasily together) are put forward almost in the same breath: Can we imagine ‘good’ as existing by itself in time, and not merely as a property of some natural object? For myself, I cannot so imagine it, whereas with the greater number of properties of objects – those which I call the natural properties - their existence does seem to me to be independent of the existence of those objects. They are, in fact, rather parts of which the object is made up than mere predicates which attach to it. If they were taken away, no object would be left, not even a bare substance: for they are in themselves substantial and give to the object all the substance it has (PE 93) I have quoted this text at length because it contains Moore’s most comprehensive distinction of natural and non-natural properties. While he later retreats from the idea that natural properties (as opposed to non-natural ones) can exist in time by themselves (RMC 581-582) and from identifying properties with parts, he modifies, but does not retract the idea that good can be distinguished from other, natural properties in reference to whether or not they constitute the nature of things or states of affairs. After Principia Moore abandons the idea that the substance of things consists of or is exhausted by their properties and adopts a more robust concept of individual substances which have natural properties as aspects or features of their intrinsic nature. Thus the reference to substantial nature remains constant; this is the sense of “natural” which will be fundamental for my discussion. In later texts, after having remarked that his previous attempts to define “natural property” were “hopelessly confused”, Moore introduces a different criterion for distinguishing natural and non natural properties: a natural property is a “property with which it is the business of the natural sciences or of Psychology to deal” (2PE 13). But he then (quite reasonably) complains that this criterion lacks precision, unless what it is meant by “natural science” is made more precise; and he doubts that this is an easy task For a sympathetic criticism of the Moorean view of the simplicity of goodness, see P. StrattonLake, “Introduction”, in Stratton-Lake (2002), pp. 12-3. 1 (2PE 15). As a modification of this view it has been suggested to identify natural properties in terms of their causal powers and causal roles (since it is arguable that natural sciences deal with their subjectmatters in terms of their causal interactions).2 There is something to this suggestion. But it has the flaw of failing to give justice to the comprehensive scope of Moore’s non-naturalism. Properties which are to kept distinct from the non-natural ones include not only empirical, but also metaphysical, supersensible properties. These latter cannot be captured in terms of causal powers; and considerations drawn on analogy (which Moore himself broaches, 2PE 13) are even less apt in regard of causation than in regard of the methods of natural science. By contrast, the most general concept of a natural property can well be captured in terms of forming the substance of empirical or of metaphysical things. This view of naturalness is the one which plays the most important role in the development of Moore’s metaethics. Intrinsic Value and What Things Are Good As it figures in Principia Ethica, the concept of intrinsic value does not primarily occur within the context of these logical and metaphysical considerations concerning Good. The distinction between intrinsic and non intrinsic value, against the background of the ontology of simple and non-natural goodness, has rather to do with what is for something (some substantial item or some state of affairs) to be good, to have that property. That is, what can intelligibly count as intrinsic is not the property of goodness as such (which is, of course, a thing in itself and of its own kind) but how or the way this property is possessed by a particular or a state of affairs (in time or outside time). Certain things (including states of affairs), not all things but only some of them, have finally and invariantly the (simple, non-natural) property of goodness. No matter what the circumstances are, no matter what we think of them or how we respond to them, they have goodness as a property; this mode of having goodness, not any feature of goodness as such, comes to expression in the concept of intrinsic value. We can also say that intrinsicalness forms part of a general and rather strong position of moral realism; but that it contributes to this position by investing the relation certain things or states of affairs stand into with goodness, their possession of goodness; not as a trait of the metaphysics of goodness itself; it is a property of the property of being good not of the property of goodness. We can accordingly distinguish two theses of realism about value in Principia Ethica. One is that goodness is a ‘thing in itself’, a simple, unique property. The other is a thesis about a way things can be good: in a necessary, final and invariant way, simply because of the things they are (PE 271). The two theses are independent: one might hold that value is a simple, unique, non-natural property and reject the idea of intrinsic value: for instance, natural and metaphysical things might be too remote from goodness for instantiating it except accidentally. (This would be a sort of radical Platonism or Neo-Platonism about value.) 2 See T. Baldwin, “Editor’s Introduction”, in Moore (1993), pp. xxii-xxiii. The Uses of Intrinsic Value in Principia What is striking is how non problematic the notion of intrinsic value seems to be in Principia Ethica, especially if we have present the amount of effort that Moore dedicates to detailing and defending the logic and the metaphysics of the Good. The concept of intrinsic value finds application mainly in two contexts. Firstly, it is employed to distinguish and set in order different forms of value possession and to prevent the confusion (prevalent in moral philosophy, PE, 271) between final value and value as a means. Good as a means and final good are distinct as different ways in which goodness can be said to be related to a thing: They may either assert that this unique property does always attach to the thing in question, or else they may assert only that the thing in question is a cause or necessary condition for the existence of other things to which this unique property does attach (PE 73) These two modes of value-possession, once the confusions have been dispelled, are perfectly consistent and ethics cannot do without either. Certain of our ethical judgments involve knowledge both of what has value in itself and of what has value for its causal connections with what has value in itself. The first is what has value as end, the second what has value as a necessary condition for the first. The first form of value-possession reformulates, in Principia Ethica, the Aristotelian concept of what is worth having for its own sake and is self-sufficiently good (PE 237).3 This form of value-possession is intrinsic, as it is made clear by the qualification that the “unique property” of goodness in this case “does always attach” to a thing. This form of value-possession is invariant because it is independent of contingent states of affairs involving the thing; in particular, it is independent of its causal relations (as value as means is obviously not). This is a plausible notion of intrinsicalness in terms of isolation: the intrinsically valuable thing would be valuable also if it were causally isolated from the rest of the world and in this way it is valuable as an end. It is important to observe that while this distinction between forms of value-possession is not merely pragmatic, still it is especially relevant in connection with the "practical questions" ethics has to deal with; it is appropriate primarily when we ask how what is valuable is connected with what we can do. This is of course an utterly important ethical consideration; but the point is that this practical question 3 See the Chapter "Intrinsic Value" in Moore (1912) especially pp. 144-155; and "The Nature of Moral Philosophy", in Moore (1922), pp. 323-327, for Moore's identification of intrinsic value with Aristotelian good. To be precise, the concept of final good is in Moore more exacting than that of good as end and of intrinsic value: all final good is good as end and intrinsic good, but not all good as end and intrinsic good is final value: a thing which is finally good must be intrinsically good through and through, must be without parts which are bad or indifferent. See Moore (1912), pp. 3032; and W. Rabinowicz and T. Rønnow-Rasmussen (2000), p.1 fn.2. is a perfectly familiar matter which we seem to have a conceptual mastery of, even though collecting the relevant information may be often difficult. Therefore, no hard metaethical question seems to be raised by this use of the notion of intrinsic value in Principia Ethica.4 The second area of discussion in Principia Ethica where the concept of intrinsic value finds particular and important application is that of the theory of organic unities and of the various forms of ideal - things that are good in themselves to a high degree. These are highly controversial issues and Moore is ready to recognize this. But it is remarkable that he does not individuate the source of the difficulties in the concept of intrinsic value. Rather, the problems seem to arise, on his own account, from the paradoxical character of the parts-whole relationship in organic unities (PE 79) and from the complex, asymmetric way in which "the Universe" satisfies the property of goodness (PE 270-271). The underlying concept of intrinsic value is, again, the basic one of value which is possessed invariantly; which things have across different circumstances. That there is such intrinsic possession of value is simply taken for granted. It is the background for the issue of the structure of organic unities even to possibly arise, since this issue presupposes that their constituents have values that are invariant across their figuring or not as parts of wholes (PE 81). Moore’s treatment of the ideals as well as the distinction between goods which are final in that they have no parts which are not goods themselves and goods which are not are, very simply, discussions of principles involved in the mereological determination of intrinsic value that is, intrinsic value-possession. These discussions assume that there is value-possession of this sort and that it is amenable to principles (and, for that matter, also to very detailed ones), it is clear that the concept of intrinsic value per se does not come at all in question, in regard of its metaethical warrant (PE 256). No Metaethical Drama 4 The interpretation of final value (value as end) as intrinsic value is controversial in the contemporary debate; in fact, it has been denied that final values must be intrinsic, since something might be valuable for its own sake because of its relational properties (like its uniqueness). The sharp distinction between final and intrinsic value has been introduced by Korsgaard (1983). I agree that the two concepts are different; but the difference I draw is different. Final value is a concept of theoretical ethics; it is a way of being valuable. Intrinsic value (post-Principia) is a concept of metaethics (and of metaphysics); it is what is for value to be. Notice therefore that the possibility that final value supervene on contingent properties has only ethical-theoretica, not metaethical or metaphysical import (this is remarked in passing by Rabinowicz and Rønnow-Rasmussen (2000), p. 16). It remains a possibility that final value is also necessarily intrinsic value, that finality and intrinsicalness are necessarily coinstantiated, at least for the case in which final value is nonderivative (see M.J. Zimmerman (2001b), pp.194-195). This might be right, although it raises complex questions about the bearers of final and intrinsic value. Still, the two properties, even if necessarily coinstantiated, are conceptually different. My conclusion is that, in Principia Ethica, the concept of intrinsic value belongs primarily not to metaethics but to theoretical ethics, in particular to the theory of value or axiology. It gives shape to the principles of the normatively significant application of the concept of the Good, not to its logic or metaphysics. There is a form of possession of value which is invariant or for its own sake. This form of possession is important, has a crucial, structural role for the whole space of value-properties and predicates. But the ontological commitments of this form of value possession are minimal and left unexplained: it is value of Good as it is possessed in isolation and which can be discovered by the method of “absolute isolation” (PE 142, 236). This is all there is to say about the ontology of intrinsic value. This concept is applied in raising and answering questions about what is for actions to be right or wrong and about what is for complex states of affairs to have value dependently on the values of their parts. But it is not discussed in terms of its own possibility and metaphysical structure. It would be exaggerated, mistaken in fact, to interpret Principia Ethica as putting forward only a first-order, substantive-normative understanding of intrinsic value. There is such an understanding; it is perfectly legitimate; and it is pro tanto common ground to moral realists and antirealists. But this is not Moore’s only way of addressing intrinsic value in Principia Ethica. I think that there is room for realistic axiology as a form of theoretical understanding of value-concepts which addresses the structure of their contents and their general roles and conditions of application and which places us midway in moral realism between the recognition and defence of substantive values (normative ethics) and the logic and metaphysics of value (metaethics). This is anyway how things are with Principia. In this work there is no metaphysical or metaethical drama about intrinsic value; even though it has an important theoretical role and is framed in terms that anticipate those in which will become metaethically problematic. Ultimately, the intrinsicalness of value-possession is only introduced, non-problematically, as the background of invariance and for-its-own-sakeness; these latter are what matters philosophically. It is true that in order to grasp these concepts and that of intrinsic valuepossession we must know something about the property, value, which is intrinsically possessed. But this is not to say that being intrinsic is something that characterizes Good in itself, on a par with simplicity or non-naturalness.5 This difference of the theoretical levels which the two notions of Good and of intrinsic value belong to is in its turn connected to other differences in their structure or ‘logic’ and in the nature of their contents: 5 As Peter Geach famously pointed out, one might suspect that keeping apart goodness as simple and non-natural from the intrinsic value of things betrays a misunderstanding of the attributive, rather that predicative, role of “good”; see Baldwin (1990), pp. 73-4; but see also Zimmerman (2001), pp. 21-26, who rejects this criticism (at least in general terms). In any case, Moore is aware of the issue (“all things which are good are also something else”, PE 62); but does not regard it as contradicting the simplicity and non-naturalness of the Good. (a) Rightly in the sense in which Good is considered by Moore to be indefinable (“it is not composed of any parts, which we can substitute for it in our minds when we are thinking of it”, PE 60) intrinsic value is definable (it is composed of goodness and of intrinsicalness); (b) While Good is a content which is primarily the object of a single act of thought, intrinsic value is a content which is only apt to be expressed in the mode of a judgment (PE 72-73 and passim). Therefore, the two notions seem to be perfectly distinct in themselves, apart from their figuring at different levels in the argument of Principia Ethica. There are (at least) two sources of possible confusions here. One is mistaking the idea that of goodness being in itself (which according to Moore is a simple, non-natural property) with that of goodness being intrinsic (which is a way for such property to be possessed). This suggests a third difference (c) Being in itself is a second-order property of the property of goodness; being intrinsic is a second order property of the relation of value-possession. The other source of confusion is mistaking: it is necessary that, if Good is instantiated, something is intrinsically good, with: it is necessary that, if Good is, something is intrinsically good. The first claim is true and the second one is false in the theory of Principia Ethica: nothing would instantiate goodness unless something intrinsically instantiated goodness; but goodness would be also if nothing existed which were intrinsically good (this includes goodness itself, which is real but not as a natural or metaphysical existent, while only such an existent can be intrinsically good). That is, a world where no good thing or state existed would still be a world which included goodness, Good in itself. What one can thus say is that Good is intrinsic in the sense that it would be itself also if nothing at all existed; but since (as we will see presently) Good is not an existent, this is intrinsicalness merely by equivocation. Once these thoughts are kept apart, the inclination to regard intrinsicalness as the ontological, realistic mark of goodness or value simply wanes. 6 6 Therefore, in reporting Moore's views, we should be wary of how we are using expressions like “intrinsic value” or "bearers of intrinsic value". Moore occasionally refers to the simple Good or goodness as “intrinsic value” (PE 109, 222). But overall there is no intrinsic Good in the sense in which there is simple, non-natural Good; and to bear intrinsic value is not to bear a certain kind of value or value under a certain aspect; but to bear it in a certain way. Only natural or metaphysical things can intrinsically bear value by standing into a relation of intrinsic possession with non-natural simple goodness. Even careful interpreters occasionally slip in this respect, see Baldwin (1990), p. 69 (“Moore, of course, takes goodness to be the fundamental value (he standardly calls it ‘intrinsic value’)”); Baldwin (1993), p. xxii (where apparently nonnaturalness is discussed in connection with intrinsic value); Zimmerman (2001), pp.18-21, while recognizing that Moore distinguishes between the question: “What is good?” and “What is intrinsically good?”, does not regard this as an important distinction – while (at least for understanding Principia Ethica) it certainly is. Appendix Bibliographical References Works by G.E. Moore PE: Principia Ethica, T. Baldwin ed., Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1993 Moore (1912): Ethics [****] CIV: “The Conception of Intrinsic Value” (1922), in PE, 281-298 2 PE: “Preface to The Second edition of Principia Ethica” (1922) in PE, 2-27 Moore (1922): Philosophical Studies [****] RCM: “A reply to My Critics” (1942): The Philosophy of G.E. Moore, P.A.Schilpp, Open Court, La Salle (Ill.) 1942, vol. 2, 535-627 Other Works T. Baldwin (1990): G.E. Moore, Routledge, London and New York T. Baldwin (1993): “Editor’s Introduction”, in Moore (1993) S. Blackburn (1993): Essays in Quasi-Realism [****] S. Blackburn (1998): Ruling Passions [****] J. Broome (1999): “Normative Requirements” [****] D.J. Chalmers (2005): “The Foundations of Two-Dimensional Semantics”, in M. Garcia-Carpintero (2006), 55-140 R. Chisholm (1981): “Defining Intrinsic Value”, in Rønnow-Rasmussen and Zimmerman (2005), 15-16 J. Dancy (2000): “The Particularist Progress”, in Rønnow-Rasmussen and Zimmerman (2005), 325-347 S. Darwall, A. Gibbard, P. Railton (1997): Moral Discourse and Practice [****] S. Darwall (2003): ‘Moore, Normativity, and Intrinsic Value”, in Ethics [****] M. Davies & I.L. Humberstone (1980): “Two Notions of Necessity”, in Philosophical Studies, 38, 1-30 M. Davies (2004): “Reference, Contingency, and the Two-Dimensional Framework,” in Philosophical Studies, 118, 83-131 (Taking and adapting a different clue from Zimmerman, we might say that goodness in itself is virtually intrinsic value, meaning by this that it existence is entailed by the existence of a state with actual intrinsic value, see M.J. Zimmerman (1999), p. 407; but this is a very loose sense in which something is intrinsic.) That intrinsicalness is not a property of properties (a fortiori of an abstract property of value) but of exemplications of properties of value is well grasped by N.M. Lemos (2005b), p. 184. D. A. Denby (2006): “The Distinction between Intrinsic and Extrinsic Properties”, Mind, 115, 1-17 J. Dreier (2006): “Was Moore a Moorean?” [***] J.M. Dunn (1990): “Relevant Predication 2: Intrinsic Properties and Internal Relations”, in Philosophical Studies, 60, 177-206 F. Feldman (1998): “Hyperventilating about Intrinsic Value”, in Rømmow & Zimmerman (2005), 45-58 M. Garcia-Capintero (2006): [***] A. Gibbard (2003a):“Normative Properties”, in Horgan & Timmons (2003), 319-337 A. Gibbard (2003b): Thinking How to Live, Harvard University Press, Cambridge (Mass.)-London T. Horgan & M. Timmons edd (2003): Metaethics After Moore, Clarendon Press, Oxford I.L. Humberstone (1996): “Intrinsic/Extrinsic”, Synthese, 108 [****] F. Jackson (1998), From Metaphysics to Ethics, Clarendon Press, Oxford S. Kagan [***] C. Korsgaard (1983): ‘Two Distinctions of Goodness” [****] S.Kripke (1980): Naming and Necessity, Harvard University Press, Cambridge (Mass.) R. Langton and D. Lewis (1998): “Defining ‘Intrinsic’”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58, 333-345 N.M. Lemos (1994a): “The Concept of Intrinsic Value”, in Rømmow & Zimmerman (2005), 17-31 N.M. Lemos (1994b): “The Bearers of Intrinsic Value” (1994b), Rømmow & Zimmerman (2005), 181190 M.J. Loux & D.W Zimmerman edds (2003): The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, Oxford University Press, Oxford E.J. Lowe (2003): “Individuation”, in Loux & Zimmerman (2003), 75-95 J. Mackie (1977): Ethics. Inventing Right and Wrong [****] A. Miller (2005): An Introduction to Contemporary Metaethics [****] F. Orsi (2006): Reasons and Values. A Study, PhD Dissertation, The University of Reading C. Peacocke (2004): The Realm of Reason, Clarendon Press, Oxford W.Rabinowicz and T. Rønnow-Rasmussen (2000): “A Distinction in Value: Intrinsic and For Its Own Sake”, in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society [****] W.Rabinowicz and T. Rønnow-Rasmussen (2003): “Tropic of Value”, in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 389-403 W. Rabinowicz and T. Rønnow-Rasmussen (2004): “The Strike of the Demon: On fitting Pro-attitudes and Value”, in Ethics, 391-423 T. Rønnow-Rasmussen and M. Zimmerman, edd. (2005): Recent Work on Intrinsic Value, Springer, Dordrecht W. D. Ross (1930): The Right and the Good [****] T. Scanlon (1998): What We Owe To Each Other, Harvard University Press, Cambridge(Mass.)-London R. Shafer Landau (2003): Moral Realism. A Defence [****] S. Soames (2005): Reference and Description, Princeton University Press, Princeton and Oxford R.S. Stalnaker (2004): “Assertion Revisited: On the Interpretation of Two-Dimensional Modal Semantics”, in Philosophical Studies, 118, 299-322 The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: “Intrinsic vs. Extrinsic Properties”; “Supervenience” P. Stratton-Lake (2002): “Introduction”, in P. Stratton-Lake ed. Ethical Intuitionism [****] P. Stratton Lake and B. Hooker (2006): “Scanlon versus Moore on Goodness” [****] J.J. Thomson (2006): “The Legacy of Principia” [****] M.J. Zimmerman (2001a): The Nature of Intrinsic Value M.J. Zimmerman, “Virtual Intrinsic Value and the Principle of Organic Unities” (1999), in RønnowRasmussen and Zimmerman (2005) 401-413 M.J. Zimmerman, “Intrinsic Value and Individual Worth” (2001b), in Rønnow-Rasmussen and Zimmerman (2005) 191-201