Title Comparative political theory and the Cambridge School: An attempt at intra-disciplinary dialogue Author Lorna Bracewell Department of political science 234 Anderson Hall University of Florida Gainesville, FL 32611 lbracewell@ufl.edu 727.504.3344 Abstract In this article, my primary aim is to effect a rapprochement of sorts between two political theoretical projects that have often been figured as fundamentally at odds with one another: Comparative Political Theory (CPT) and the Cambridge School approach to the history of political thought. To this end, I argue that CPT and the Cambridge School are united by similar objectives: to spur the discipline of political theory beyond the boundaries of its traditional canon and to imbue it with a heightened awareness of the contingency and particularity of its own concepts and concerns. I further argue that the historical sensibilities of the Cambridge School would enhance “dialogical” approaches to CPT, particularly those along the lines Fred Dallmayr has envisaged, by chastening their problematic and, ultimately, self-undermining quest for universal moral consensus. Keywords comparative political theory, Cambridge School, Quentin Skinner, history of political thought, cosmopolitanism, universalism 1 Comparative political theory and the Cambridge School: An attempt at intradisciplinary dialogue In his introduction to Border Crossings: Toward a Comparative Political Theory, an edited volume published in 1999 with the ambition of inaugurating a new field, Fred Dallmayr accuses the discipline of political theory as it is practiced in most Western universities of amounting to little more than “the rehearsal of the ‘canon’ of Western political thought from Plato to Marx or Nietzsche.”i “Only rarely,” Dallmayr continues, “are practitioners of political thought willing (and professionally encouraged) to transgress the canon, and thereby the cultural boundaries of North America and Europe, in the direction of genuine comparative investigations.”ii Fifteen years later, despite the remarkable success Dallmayr and othersiii have had in garnering wider recognition for Comparative Political Theory (hereafter, “CPT”) within the subfield of political theory, Dallmayr’s critical observations remain apt: the discipline of political theory continues to exhibit a peculiar and, ultimately, limiting preoccupation with its “canon.” Despite my agreement with Dallmayr on this point concerning how political theory is practiced by most scholars within the Western academy, in this article, I resist Dallmayr’s dismissal of all or most theoretical engagements with the “canon” as mere “rehearsals” of a largely static and pre-existing body of authors and texts. Some of these engagements, I will argue, challenge (if not outright explode) traditional interpretations of canonical texts and even the boundaries of the canon itself, opening up a space for just the sort of comparative investigations Dallmayr and others have called for over the past two decades. I have in mind specifically scholarship produced by practitioners of what 2 has come to be known as the “Cambridge School” approach to the history of political thought, an approach most closely associated with Quentin Skinner.iv In the broadest sense, my aim in this article is to initiate what might be thought of as an intra-disciplinary dialogue between CPT and the Cambridge School. This aim will likely strike readers familiar with CPT as improbable or even ill-advised in light of the fact that some of CPT’s most prominent proponents and practitioners have rejected Cambridge School historicism as incompatible with the project of CPT.v However, as I will demonstrate, these rejections are premised on inaccurate or incomplete understandings of the Cambridge School’s method. Therefore, I will argue, the path remains open for a potentially fruitful and mutually beneficial alliance between CPT and the Cambridge School. To state my aim more specifically, in this article, I will argue that the Cambridge School approach to the history of political thought as set forth by one of its leading proponents, Quentin Skinner, might be understood as an ally rather than an adversary to at least one approach to CPT. This approach, pioneered by Fred Dallmayr and embraced widely within the field of CPT, takes the staging of “ethically transformative” encounters or “dialogues”vi across difference as one of its principal goals.vii This goal, in my view, presents an opportunity for conversation and collaboration between CPT and the Cambridge School, an opportunity that, unfortunately, has been largely overlooked. For, as I will show, just as “dialogical” approaches to CPT aim to “restore [to political theory] the sense of ‘wonder’ (thaumazein) that the ancients extolled as pivotal to philosophizing” viii by “opening mind and heart to the puzzling diversity of human 3 experiences and traditions – and also to the possibility of jeopardizing cherished preconceptions or beliefs,” ix so Skinner’s version of a Cambridge School approach aims to unsettle the regnant ideas of the present by bringing to light “the essential variety of viable moral assumptions and political commitments.”x By highlighting this shared goal, I hope to convince practitioners of CPT and the Cambridge School approach that their respective scholarly enterprises are not so far removed from one another, and, in fact, might benefit from collaborative exchanges. Additionally (and, perhaps, more ambitiously), I hope to persuade practitioners of CPT who, like Dallmayr, engage in cross-cultural inquiry with the further aim of deriving some set of universal moral principles to set this aim aside. If CPT is to allow for the invigorating and transformative encounters with and across difference that both Dallmayr and Skinner agree are the highest good cross-cultural and historical inquiry might bring about, then, I argue, CPT must forswear the pursuit of universal moral principles as a raison d’être. Fred Dallmayr’s dialogical approach to CPT Before taking up my article’s main objective – effecting a rapprochement of sorts between CPT and the Cambridge School – I would like to provide for my reader a brief introduction to the subfield of CPT, paying particular attention to where and how Fred Dallmayr’s distinctive and influential “dialogical” approach to CPT fits in vis-à-vis other leading approaches on offer in the subfield.xi From its earliest articulations in the mid-1990s, the defining objective of CPT has been to make political theory more global or non-Western in focus. However, while virtually all practitioners and proponents of CPT can be said to embrace this general aim, 4 they are far from agreement on what precisely it means or how it might best be accomplished. Roxanne Euben, for example, has argued that the best way to ensure “that ‘political theory’ is about human and not merely Western dilemmas” is “to introduce non-Western perspectives into [political theory’s] familiar debates about the problems of living together.” xii Because, in Euben’s view, thinkers working within non-Western traditions have grappled with the same “dilemmas and questions” that have long supplied the grist for political theory’s mills in the West, the task of CPT is, essentially, to treat the works these thinkers have produced as political theory.xiii Thus, Euben’s approach to CPT consists chiefly of bringing political theory’s fundamental questions “to bear across cultures”; questions such as “What is the good life? What is legitimate authority? What is the right relationship of the individual to society?”xiv “These questions,” Euben contends, “do not only arise from Western cultural experience,”xv and the attempts of non-Western thinkers to grapple with them merit the same consideration within the discipline of political theory as those of Western thinkers.xvi While largely sympathetic to Euben’s vision for CPT, Farah Godrej has attempted to deepen and strengthen it by imbuing the subfield with a degree of methodological selfconsciousness and sophistication she believes it lacks. For Godrej, CPT’s defining project of “articulating alternative ways of understanding the political world” in the terms provided by “the discourse of familiar theoretical conversations”xvii (or, as Euben puts it, bringing the questions of political theory “to bear across cultures” xviii) both more complex and more fraught than most practitioners of CPT let on. On one side, Godrej explains, CPT courts the danger of assimilating non-Western texts to its own inescapably 5 Western concepts and categories, and, in doing so, eliding the very “otherness” on which CPT’s comparative aspect depends.xix On the other side, Godrej continues, CPT risks setting up non-Western texts as so far removed from its own inescapably Western concepts and categories that, ironically, CPT ends up consigning these texts to the margins of the discipline where they are unable to “disturb or dislocate our familiar understandings of politics.”xx To ward off these twin dangers, Godrej calls on comparative political theorists to become one part anthropologist and ethnographer, “immersing themselves in the lived experience of the text” and acquiring the capacity to understand the text from “the perspective of adherence,” and another part “external observer and commentator, constructing cultural accounts in order to represent the experience of the text, and articulating how these insights may be used to illuminate our political life.”xxi By struggling “to balance the competing demands of scholarship and adherence” and hewing a middle-path between the assimilation and the ghettoization of non-Western texts and concepts, Godrej believes her approach to CPT will culminate in “a more genuinely cosmopolitan political theory” in which “complex encounters with otherness are increasingly available to provoke, dislocate, and challenge our settled understandings of political life.”xxii Godrej’s pronounced concern for preserving the “otherness” of non-Western texts and concepts in the context of cross-cultural inquiry is largely absent from the approach to CPT Andrew March has proposed.xxiii Dissatisfied with largely “rehabilitative” and “explanatory/interpretive” approaches to CPT such as Euben’s and Godrej’s, March calls on CPT to do more than salvage heretofore neglected non-Western texts from obscurity 6 or to draw on such texts in an effort to trouble political theory’s traditional concepts and categories. CPT as March envisions it will be, first and foremost, a “justificatory” project engaged in the “first-order evaluation of the implication of the contestations of norms, values, and principles between distinct and coherent doctrines of thought.”xxiv “Justificatory CPT,” March explains, “inherently includes and subsumes all of what is valuable” in other “weaker” approaches, “namely, the diagnostic element of examining the contours of disagreement between traditions and the appreciative element of demonstrating the diversity of other traditions.”xxv What it adds to these projects is a quest for what March describes as “reasonable conceptions of morality and justice free from the taint of imperialism” to which individuals immersed in radically divergent cultural traditions might assent.xxvi In other words, March’s approach, more so than any of the others surveyed here, takes the engendering of moral consensus and the search for universal moral principles as its primary aim.xxvii Turning now to Fred Dallmayr’s “dialogical” approach to CPT, the approach that is the primary focus of this article, we can see that it shares something with each of the approaches outlined above. Like Euben’s, Dallmayr’s approach to CPT seeks to demonstrate the political theoretical significance of non-Western texts and concepts by employing them to illuminate some of political theory’s defining dilemmas.xxviii Like Godrej’s, Dallmayr’s approach strives to take into account the “otherness” of nonWestern texts and concepts in such a way as to ensure that they are still permitted entry into the heart of the discipline where they might call into question (or further illuminate) Western political theory’s principal concepts and categories.xxix And finally, like 7 March’s, Dallmayr’s approach counts among its aims the engendering of moral consensus or the discovery of what Dallmayr calls “truly universal principles or yardsticks of human conduct.”xxx xxxi In fact, what marks Dallmayr’s approach off as distinct from other approaches currently on offer in the subfield is its pluralism. In a contribution to the edited volume Western Political Thought in Dialogue With Asia (2009), Dallmayr spells out his vision for a pluralistic and multifaceted CPT aimed at the attainment of three hierarchically ranked ends or “goods.”xxxiiThe lowest good at which Dallmayr’s approach to CPT aims is a “pragmatic-utilitarian”xxxiii knowledge of diverse cultures and traditions. This type of knowledge, Dallmayr explains, is gained by way of strategies of cross-cultural inquiry “directed at subsuming or appropriating the ‘other’ in a unilateral fashion without reciprocity” and is of a kind with the inter-cultural knowledge pursued by “economists,” “business people,” and sometimes “even theorists or philosophers” who study other cultures “not for the sake of genuine learning, but for the purpose of gaining a strategic advantage or bolstering [their] own sense of superiority.”xxxiv “What has been termed ‘Orientalism,’” Dallmayr clarifies, “corresponded basically to such a policy of appropriation and domination on the part of Western intellectual elites.”xxxv In order to stave off such Orientalist possibilities and “to balance or calibrate selfinterest against the legitimate interests of others,” “comparative or cross-cultural inquiry,” Dallmayr writes, “may be placed in the service of another end or ‘good’: the good of finding truly universal principles of human conduct.”xxxvi In the context of pursuing this “‘moral-universal’ good,” Dallmayr explains, “the ‘other’ is studied not 8 primarily in his or her difference, but with a view toward what is common or shared in humanity,” such as a belief in “the so-called ‘golden rule’” or in the norms embodied in certain articles of modern international law “recognized as binding by the vast majority of states and peoples”xxxvii such as the Geneva Conventions and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights.xxxviii By placing CPT in the service of the pursuit of “truly universal principles of human conduct” rather than merely utilitarian or self-serving knowledge of other cultures, Dallmayr believes that the imperialist or Orientalist potential of CPT can be reigned in. However, if the moral universal good uncovered by way of comparative study is ever going to be brought to bear on the real world in a manner that does not reduce it to merely another tool of domination in the hands of already hegemonic Western powers, then, in Dallmayr’s view, a further step is required. CPT must move “beyond moral universalism” in the pursuit of a higher good, “an ‘ethical’ or ‘ethically transformative’ good” that culminates in “widespread ethical education and character formation.”xxxix In the pursuit of this last and highest good, Dallmayr explains, CPT’s focus shifts away from “what all cultures have in common” and toward “how and why they differ.”xl This shift makes the practitioner of CPT, in Dallmayr’s words, “aware of the limits of [her] own particular traditions” and “of the special character of [her] own customs and preferences.”xli Such awareness, Dallmayr continues, soon blossoms into “enhanced tolerance and a genuine recognition of others, including their traditions and aspirations” as the CPT practitioner “come[s] to appreciate the other no longer as a mere replica of [herself]” or as a “target of acquisition or abstract norm-regulation,” but as a richly 9 differentiated ‘persona,’ an authentic agent and perhaps friend.”xlii “It is on this level,” Dallmayr concludes, “that ‘dialogue’ in the proper sense can happen – where the term refers to a genuine mutual learning process proceeding through question and answer.”xliii As Dallmayr himself emphasizes, his pluralistic and multifaceted approach to CPT, which strives to balance the three competing goods of practical or utilitarian knowledge, universal moral consensus, and ethical education or transformation, is rife with tensions and paradoxes. Dallmayr captures nicely what he describes as the “agonal”xlivnature of his approach to CPT when he describes it as “deconstructive dialogue.” xlv Deconstructive dialogue, Dallmayr explains, struggles “to take otherness… seriously and hence to respect differences and distances that cannot simply be wished or talked away” xlvi while simultaneously insisting that the “recognition of difference is not equivalent to a counsel of despair”xlviiand that dialogue can be more than “the conduct of random chatter” without lapsing into “the enactment of a ready-made consensus (the subsumption of particulars under a universalist umbrella).”xlviii “Wedged between surrender and triumph,” Dallmayr writes, “dialogical exchange has an ‘agonal’ or tensional quality which cannot be fully stabilized,”xlix and it is this tension or competition between dialogue’s competing imperatives that, Dallmayr believes, makes the project of CPT interesting, significant, and worth pursuing. What we might think of as the agony of Dallmayr’s approach to CPT – its careful, almost anxious universalism, its insistence that difference be taken seriously and respected in the context of cross-cultural inquiry, and its faith in the ability of genuine encounters with and across difference to bring about profound ethical and political 10 transformations – make it, I believe, a particularly congenial dialogue partner, if you will, for the Cambridge School approach to the history of political thought. However, before I explore these affinities more deeply, I will provide for my reader a rough and ready summary of Quentin Skinner’s version of a Cambridge School approach. Once this summary is complete, the path will be clear for me to take up this article’s principal task of bringing CPT and the Cambridge School into fruitful conversation with one another. Quentin Skinner and the Cambridge School approach to the history of political thought Perhaps the most fitting way to introduce the Cambridge School approach to the history of political thought is to briefly sketch the intellectual context from which it emerged. Prior to Quentin Skinner’s transformational methodological interventions, the study of the history of political thought was dominated by two orthodoxies over and against which the Cambridge School would eventually come to define itself. The first of these orthodoxies is what one might generally describe as “perennialism” and is most famously associated with (though, as Skinner himself has persuasively shown, by no means confined to) scholars such as Arthur Lovejoy and Leo Strauss.l Adherents to the “perennialism” orthodoxy interpret certain historical texts deemed worthy, for various and often dubious reasons, of the designation “great books” as though they were contributions to a trans-historical, or, in some cases, timelessli conversation about a readily delineable and enduring set of topics that Lovejoy called “unit ideas”lii and that Strauss called “the political fundamentals.” liii Thus, when viewed from a “perennialist” perspective, writers as historically and culturally distant as, say, Plato and Thomas 11 Aquinas or Niccolò Machiavelli and Thomas Hobbes appear as contemporaries of a sort engaged in similar projects.liv Since the publication of what has proven to be his most influential methodological intervention, a bold and, at times, caustic essay originally entitled “The Unimportance of the Great Texts” but published, in 1969, under the markedly less pugnacious title “Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas,” Quentin Skinner has been a merciless critic of “perennialism.” To interpret historical texts in a “perennialist” manner, for example, to read Machiavelli’s Prince as though it was an effort to articulate a position vis-à-vis the same fundamental questions engaged by Thucydides in Book V of his History of the Peloponnesian War,lv is, in Skinner’s words, “unavoidably to run the perpetual danger of lapsing into various kinds of historical absurdity.”lvi Chief among these is the notion that there exists in history a select canon of writers spanning two continents and at least as many millennia who have all, in their turn, wrestled with the same enduring questions. This notion, Skinner insists, is a historical non-starter. “There simply are no perennial problems in philosophy,” he notoriously declares; “there are only individual answers to individual questions, with as many different answers as there are questions, and as many different questions as there are questioners.” lviiBecause “perennialists” do not concede this and are content to allow their own paradigm for the nature of political thought to determine the direction of their historical investigations, the interpretations they produce do not, in Skinner’s view, merit the name “histories” at all. Rather, Skinner insists, such interpretations are more properly understood as “mythologies” in which prolepsis (the crowding out of historical meaning by an 12 interpreter’s excessive concern with contemporary matters), parochialism (seeing something apparently familiar in the course of studying an alien culture, argument, or conceptual scheme and, in consequence, providing a misleadingly familiar-looking description), and outright anachronism run rampant. Ultimately, in Skinner’s view, interpretations produced in accord with the “perennialist” orthodoxy “can scarcely contain any genuinely historical reports about thoughts that were actually thought in the past” and risk reducing historical scholarship to nothing but “a pack of tricks we play on the dead.”lviii The second disciplinary orthodoxy over and against which the Cambridge School approach emerged is a perspective one might call “epiphenomenalism.” According to Skinner, “epiphenomenalists,” such as C.B. Macpherson, interpret historical texts as though they were the products of highly deterministic social, political, or economic structures, forces, or processes rather than mental activities bearing the mark of individual agency. In the “epiphenomenalist” view, ideas are incidental; they are the flotsam and jetsam adrift atop history’s surface, obscuring and distracting from the truly significant structural phenomena churning deep below. Thus, for example, when viewed from an “epiphenomenalist” perspective, Edmund Burke necessarily becomes, as a consequence of his position in some version of a Marxist historical narrative concerning the inevitable emergence of capitalism, a laissez-faire liberal and an apologist for market society.lixlx That Burke’s intention in writing, say, Thoughts and Details on Scarcity could not possibly have been to proffer a conservative apology for the capitalist systemlxi is of 13 no consequence to the “epiphenomenalist” for whom authorial intentions are not decisive (or even necessarily relevant) when determining the meaning of a text. The problem, from a Skinnerian perspective, with interpretations guided by “epiphenomenalism” is that they fail to recognize that the intentions of the author whose work they are interpreting are more than merely incidental to the work’s meaning.lxii In other words, according to Skinner, “epiphenomenalists” commit a fundamental error: they disregard what, Skinner argues, is an undeniable “fact about language,” “that anyone issuing a serious utterance will always be doing something as well as saying something, and doing it in virtue of what is said.”lxiii In Skinner’s view (a view deeply indebted to Austin’s gloss on the Wittgenstenian insight that words, in addition to being words, are also deeds), if we wish to understand any serious utterance, we must “recover what the agent may have been doing in saying what was said,” that is, we must recover the agent’s “illocutionary intentions.”lxiv The recovery of these “illocutionary intentions” is crucial, Skinner believes, to answering the fundamental hermeneutic question “What does the writer mean by what he says in this work?”lxv However, Skinner is clear that efforts to get at these illocutionary intentions are not tantamount to the ridiculous and impossible task of popping open a long dead author’s head and peering inside. Nor, Skinner emphasizes, do such efforts preclude attending to the sort of broad historical, sociological, cultural, and contextual factors that figure so centrally in “epiphenomenalist” interpretations. This is because, in Skinner’s view, writers are normally engaged in intended acts of communication. Therefore, to be in a position to characterize what a writer was doing in writing a particular text, 14 interpreters must venture beyond the boundaries of the text itself and determine which conversations, arguments, or what Skinner frequently refers to as the linguistic “contexts” that particular text was intended by its author to intervene in or contribute to.lxvi In Skinner’s words, to grasp the context and, thus, the meaning (in one particular sense at least)lxvii of a given work, “we need to be prepared to take as our province nothing less than the whole of… the social imaginary, the complete range of the inherited symbols and representations that constitute the subjectivity of [the] age”lxviii in which the text was produced.lxix Barring such heroiclxx efforts, Skinner argues, we will never discern what a given text was intended to do, a crucial aspect, Skinner argues, of virtually any text’s meaning.lxxi The critiques Skinner proffers of both “perennialism” and “epiphenomenalism” are rooted in what I take to be the Cambridge School’s definitional methodological injunction: that historians of political thought treat the publication of a text and the utterance of its argument as acts performed in history, and, specifically, in the context of some ongoing discourse.lxxii The aim of Skinner’s method is not to pluck select past texts from the stream of history and restore them to the timeless resplendency proper to them, nor is it to peer behind the backs of the authors of past texts to discern what they, perhaps in spite of themselves, really mean. Rather, as Skinner has recently stated it, “the chief aspiration” of his proposed method is “to recover the historical identity of individual texts in the history of thought… to see such texts as contributions to particular discourses, and thereby to recognize the ways in which they followed or challenged or subverted the conventional terms of those discourses themselves.”lxxiii What Skinner describes as “the 15 nerve of [his] argument” is that “if we want a history of philosophy written in a genuinely historical spirit, we need to make it one of our principal tasks to situate the texts we study within such intellectual contexts as enable us to make sense of what their authors were doing in writing them.”lxxiv We must, Skinner continues, “use the ordinary techniques of historical enquiry to grasp their concepts, to follow their distinctions, to appreciate their beliefs and, so far as possible, to see things their way.”lxxv To critics who complain that such an approach “reduces the study of the history of thought to nothing more edifying than a conducted tour of a graveyard,”lxxvi Skinner responds that, in fact, studies of historical texts conducted in this manner and with these aims have the potential to impart important moral lessons.lxxvii “The classic texts, especially in social, ethical, and political thought,” Skinner wrote in his infamous 1969 polemic, “help to reveal – if we let them – not the essential sameness, but rather the essential variety of viable moral assumptions and political commitments.”lxxviii They call into question, Skinner would go on to argue several decades later, the validity of speaking in terms of “the vocabulary of politics” and reveal that “different societies may conceptualise [this domain] in different and possibly even incommensurable ways.”lxxix Such revelations, Skinner argues, help us to “stand back from our own assumptions and systems of belief, and thereby to situate ourselves in relation to other and very different forms of life” as merely “one tribe among others”lxxx Seeing ourselves in this way, Skinner continues, facilitates “a greater degree of understanding, and thereby a larger tolerance for elements of cultural diversity.”lxxxilxxxiiIt also, Skinner adds, helps us develop a certain capacity for self-criticism. Once we realize 16 that “our own society is no different from any other in having its own local beliefs and arrangements of social and political life” and that “those features of our own arrangements which we may be disposed to accept as traditional or even ‘timeless’ truths may in fact be the merest of contingencies of our peculiar history and social structure,” we can begin, Skinner explains, “to stand back from, and perhaps even to reappraise” those arrangements and features and, most importantly, cease to wield them as the yardstick against which we measure the world.lxxxiii “One of the present values of the past,” Skinner remarks in the concluding chapter of Liberty Before Liberalism, a text written (shall I dare say it?) with the intention to demonstrate the “practical use, here and now” of Skinner’s method, “is as a repository of values we no longer endorse, or questions we no longer ask.”lxxxiv “One corresponding role for the intellectual historian,” Skinner continues, “is that of acting as a kind of archaeologist, bringing buried intellectual treasure back to the surface, dusting it down and enabling us to reconsider what we think of it.”lxxxv In Skinner’s view, it is not solely or even predominantly the continuities between the past and the present that make the past of contemporary relevance, but the discontinuities whose excavation can, Skinner believes, “prevent us from becoming too readily bewitched” “into believing that the ways of thinking… bequeathed to us by the mainstream of our intellectual traditions must be the ways of thinking.” lxxxvi As Skinner memorably put it in 1969, “it is the very fact that the classic texts are concerned with their own quite alien problems, and not the presumption that they are somehow concerned with our own problems as well, which 17 [gives] not the lie but the key to the indispensable value of studying the history of ideas.”lxxxvii CPT and the Cambridge School: An attempt at rapprochement From the sketch of Skinner’s version of a Cambridge School approach to the history of political thought that I have just provided, one can begin to sense, I hope, the ways in which this approach might prove congenial to “dialogical” approaches to CPT such as those Dallmayr has championed. Much like Dallmayr (as well as most other practitioners of CPT), adherents to the Cambridge School have little patience for mere “rehearsals” of political theory’s canon. In fact, the oeuvres of the Cambridge School’s most prolific figures, Quentin Skinner and J.G.A. Pocock, are chock full of works that challenge both received wisdom regarding canonical thinkers as well as the boundaries of the canon itself. For instance, The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, Skinner’s famous two-volume study of European political thought from the late thirteenth to the late sixteenth century, does not address a procession “of so-called ‘classic texts’” and, consequently, does not concentrate “exclusively on leading theorists.”lxxxviiiInstead, Skinner considers “the more general social and intellectual matrix out of which [the socalled ‘classic texts’] arose” including the “more ephemeral contemporary contributions to social and political thought,”lxxxix works that may seem insignificant from the vantage point of the present but that figured prominently in the political thinking of canonical figures like Machiavelli, More, Luther, or Calvin. Skinner describes this procedure as “surround[ing]” the “classic texts” with “their appropriate ideological context” and insists that it is only by casting their gazes beyond the “canon” that “students of political 18 thought” can hope to arrive at a “history of political theory with a genuinely historical character.”xc Such an approach, as many critics of Skinner and the Cambridge School have pointed out,xci undermines the very notion that there exists in history a clearly defined canon of superlative texts from which we might draw transcendent political wisdom, and, thus, opens up for serious political theoretical consideration whole universes of forgotten or marginalized texts, authors, questions, and ideas. Such an opening up of political theory’s often-narrow vista seems deeply commensurate with Dallmayr’s expressed hopes for the practice of CPT. Another aspect of the Cambridge School approach to intellectual history that makes it a natural ally for comparative political theoretical projects akin to Dallmayr’s is its insistence on the potentiality that myriad and profound differences might inhere between the interpreter (in this case, the historian) and the interpreted (in this case, the historical text). As Conal Condren, a sympathetic critic of the Cambridge School, has remarked, the Cambridge School does not operate according to the maxim that, “If we shout loudly enough, Plato will have to reply in English.”xcii Rather, as I have demonstrated above, the maxim according to which the Cambridge School operates might be stated thusly: If we listen attentively, we will hear Plato speaking in his own language and, in doing so, we may come to appreciate not the essential sameness, but the essential variety of viable moral assumptions and political commitments. Such revelations, such exposures to what Skinner has called “the fact of historical difference,”xciii are, as one perceptive commentator has noted, “character forming,”xciv and the character they form shares much with the character that Dallmayr hopes exercises 19 in CPT will inculcate: one that possesses the capacity to “move from the habitually familiar toward the unfamiliar,”xcv and to recognize “the limits of our own particular traditions” and “the special character of our own customs and preferences.”xcvi Such a character is as integral to the sort of “inter-civilizational dialogue” for which Dallmayr has called – a dialogue that “proceeds ‘by way of question and answer,’ with an accent on the primacy of questioning” and in which “one [partner in the dialogue] does not try to argue the other down but… genuinely weighs the other’s perspective”xcvii – as it is to the sort of interpretive method advocated by Skinner and the Cambridge School.xcviii The Cambridge School historian’s distinctive determination to interpret the text she is studying in light of the context(s) in and for which it was composed and to resist the everpresent temptation to assimilate it to her own present is matched by the determination of the participants in Dallmayr’s “genuine civilizational encounter” to proceed “modestly and soberly… taking their departure… from their own distinct perspective… while simultaneously guarding against any form of cultural or self-enclosure,” including facile imputations of identity (or what Dallmayr calls “strateg[ies] of appropriation”)xcix which obscure, silence and deny the very other one is supposed to be encountering. As tempting as it is to conclude this article on such dulcet notes, I must concede that all is not agreement and concord between the Cambridge School approach to the history of political thought and CPT. In fact, several leading practitioners of CPT have expressly dismissed the interpretive methods of the Cambridge School as inadequate for the purposes of CPT. However, as I will demonstrate, more often than not, these dismissals are premised on misunderstandings of the Cambridge School’s method and, 20 therefore, pose no real impediments to the rapprochement between CPT and the Cambridge School I am proposing here. Perhaps the most prominent of the Cambridge School’s detractors in the CPT literature is Farah Godrej. In her well-known contribution to the ongoing methodological discussion in CPT, “Towards a Cosmopolitan Political Thought: The Hermeneutics of Interpreting the Other,” Godrej argues that the Cambridge School method does not allow “for the sort of challenge and dislocation that the existential – and, ultimately, theoreticalencounter with alterity should bring forth” and, therefore, does not contain “the resources for a cosmopolitan re-envisioning of the task of political theory.”c Godrej bases this judgment on her view that, for the Cambridge School, all texts, including non-western ones, “are interesting only as historical or cultural relics, with no relevance for our time and place.”ci Godrej is not the first (and likely will not be the last) critic to accuse the Cambridge School of cordoning off the past from the present and reducing the study of historical texts to a purely antiquarian and utterly un- (or even anti-) theoretical endeavor.cii In fact, this accusation is nearly as old as the Cambridge School itself,ciii and, for as long as critics have been putting it forward, the Cambridge School’s leading lights have been taking pains to defend against it. For example, in Liberty Before Liberalism, Quentin Skinner explicitly intervenes in contemporary political theoretical controversies over how we might best understand the ideas of political and individual freedom. In Godrej’s view, such an excursion into the domain of contemporary political theoretical concerns is inconsistent with Skinner’s 21 historicist premises; however, as Skinner himself explains, this accusation hinges on a misreading of those very premises. In fact, one of Skinner’s central concerns in Liberty Before Liberalism is to refute “the accusation of antiquarianism” – an accusation that, he admits, “troubles [him] deeply” - by demonstrating, through the deployment of his method, “the practical use, here and now”civ of his historical studies. To this end, Skinner offers a compelling argument as to why seeing “philosophical reflection as in its essence a kind of historical activity”cv is indispensable to contemporary political theorizing. As I have already highlighted in my discussion of Skinner’s method in the preceding section, in Skinner’s view, attentiveness to the historical character of works of political philosophy or theory is beneficial to political theorists in the present because it can, in his words, “prevent us from becoming too readily bewitched” into believing that our political present is a necessary rather than a contingent product, and can show us that “the values embodied in our present way of life, and our present ways of thinking about those values, reflect a series of choices made at different times between different possible worlds.”cvi By confronting us with the contingent character of our present values and convictions, historical study can enable us to, in Skinner’s words, “stand back from the intellectual commitments we have inherited and ask ourselves in a new spirit of enquiry what we should think of them.”cvii This makes Cambridge School historicism not inimical to the provocative, dislocating, and challenging enterprise of CPT, as Godrej would have it, but, rather, vital to it. And, one need look no further than the extensive literature on the “neo-Roman” ideal of freedom as “non-domination” (understood as a possible contemporary alternative to liberal conceptions of positive and negative liberty) to see 22 that Skinner’s historical method has inaugurated a veritable cottage industry of critical political theoretical reflection on our contemporary understandings of political life.cviii Of course, Godrej’s has not been the only voice in the CPT literature critical of the Cambridge School. Chris Goto-Jones, for one, has recently accused contemporary scholarship in the history of political thought of exhibiting a “defensive ethnocentricity” attributable in large part, he argues, to the disciplinary ascendancy of the Cambridge School.cix “[C]ontext,” Goto-Jones writes, “has unfortunately become a buzzword for intellectual conservatism and ethnocentricity in the history of political thought.”cx “[O]f all the contexts that might be of interest to historians of political philosophy,” Goto-Jones continues, “none of them appear to be found outside the geohistorical spaces of Europe and the United States.cxi I find this particular criticism of the Cambridge School misdirected for two reasons. First, at least one leading Cambridge School scholar, J.G.A Pocock, has explicitly encouraged scholars possessing the requisite language skills and historical expertise to employ the Cambridge School method in contexts beyond the European and the North American.cxii In fact, in an essay originally published in 1964 and republished as the second chapter of Politics, Language, and Time, Pocock, despite his lack of the requisite skills and expertise, tentatively undertakes a bit of comparative political theory himself as he examines several philosophical texts from China’s heroic age.cxiii More recently, Skinner has echoed Pocock’s call for intellectual historians to venture beyond Europe’s borders. In an address delivered in 1997, Skinner voiced concern over what he described as a “form of parochialism… on the rise in Europe,”cxiv 23 brought about, he suggested, as an unintended consequence of the rise of a certain and, in Skinner’s view, misbegotten variant of multiculturalism. European intellectuals, Skinner told the audience, have become so absorbed with “local questions” such as “try[ing] to do justice to the complex subcultures out of which… our so-called national identities were… very loosely formed” that “other intellectual traditions appear less relevant, and perhaps less interesting.”cxv If such a trend continues, Skinner warned, “I foresee a risk of our becoming less interested in each other, and in each other’s political arrangements and philosophies.”cxvi Such a development would be “regret[table]” in Skinner’s view, “partly because an exclusive interest in our own origins and identities strikes me,” Skinner explained, “as boringly self-absorbed, but also because,” he continued, “a more demanding but more rewarding form of multiculturalism is available to us.”cxviiThis form of multiculturalism is exemplified by scholars such as Albert Hirschman and Clifford Geertz who, in Skinner’s view, “continue to move between different cultures, different languages, different continents” without “embracing the Hegelian heresy that some nations are worldhistorical while others are not” and who remain “internationalist in outlook while dedicating themselves at the same time to the uncovering of local knowledge.”cxviiiThe “more strenuous and inclusive form of multiculturalism”cxix informing the work of scholars like Hirschman and Geertz is just the stuff that Skinner hopes will inform the work of scholars in his own discipline in the years to come. These remarks, coupled with Pocock’s repeated calls for qualified historians to explore texts and thinkers that he lacks the linguistic and historical wherewithal to adequately explore himself, are powerful 24 evidence that the Cambridge School approach to intellectual history is capable of traveling beyond “the West.” The second reason I have for finding Goto-Jones’ allegations of the Cambridge School’s “defensive ethnocentricity” somewhat wide of the mark is that Goto-Jones himself concedes that it is not the Cambridge School’s method that is ethnocentric, but its application. According to Goto-Jones, the Cambridge School approach has been “incidentally rather than necessarily ethnocentric” and, in his view, “still holds promise as an appropriate method… to construct a worldly history of political thought.”cxx Thus, while it must be admitted that the concerns of the Cambridge School’s leading lights have been predominantly (though, as Pocock’s 1964 essay evidences, not exclusively) Euro-American, I believe it is mistaken to attribute this to the purported ethnocentrism of the Cambridge School’s method. The Euro-American focus of the Cambridge School seems to me, rather, a contingent result of the particular intellectual interests, specializations and competencies of the scholars who developed it. Now, indisputably, the fact that Quentin Skinner and J.G.A Pocock are interested primarily in Euro-American texts and authors, trained specialists in early-modern and modern European history, and competent in only Romance languages is attributable, at least in part, to a set of cultural and disciplinary background conditions and institutions that one might aptly describe as ethnocentric.cxxi However, acknowledging this does not necessarily entail endorsing an indictment of the Cambridge School’s method as ethnocentric. Despite the fact that the Cambridge School’s method was developed by scholars who were, perhaps, constrained in various ways by the ethnocentrism of their 25 discipline, one can imagine a reformed or, to borrow Leigh Jenco’s language, “recentered” discipline of political theory producing scholars equipped with the inclinations, knowledge, and skill sets necessary to undertake the study of the history of, say, Japanese political thought in accord with something along the lines of the Cambridge School’s method. Having diffused several of the most prominent critiques of the Cambridge School presently afoot in the CPT literature, I would now like to address what is, in my view, a much less easily resolved tension between the Cambridge School approach to the history of political thought and the project of CPT as some scholars have envisioned it. As I explained in the first section of this article, one aim characteristic of Fred Dallmayr’s influential approach to CPT is to move “beyond the spurious ‘universality’ traditionally claimed by the Western canon and by some recent intellectual movements” and toward “a more genuine universalism”cxxii that will enable us to discern “truly universal principles or yardsticks of human conduct.”cxxiii As I have also already explained, many practitioners of CPT, Dallmayr included, are keenly alert to the perils of universalism. Specifically, Dallmayr calls attention to and criticizes the tendency of universalist projects to efface or occlude difference through various (and often violent) strategies of appropriation or assimilation and radical distancing or “othering.” However, rather than compelling him to set aside the pursuit of “truly universal principles or yardsticks of human conduct,” Dallmayr’s insight into universalism’s darker side leads him to attempt to mitigate its harmful effects by subordinating the pursuit of universal morality to another aim or good: the engendering of ethically transformative encounters or 26 “dialogues” with and across difference. Such dialogues, Dallmayr believes, will bring about heightened tolerance, respect, and even friendship amongst their participants, effectively curbing the risks associated with the universalist aspects of his approach. Despite his attentiveness to universalism’s more troubling implications and his attempt to counteract them, any adherent to the Cambridge School approach to intellectual history would, I believe, look upon Dallmayr’s efforts to justify comparative political theoretical scholarship by reference to its promise to yield “a more genuine universalism” or “truly universal principles” with grave suspicion. To undertake comparative scholarship, be it historical, inter-cultural, or, as is more often than not the case, some combination of both, with even the most qualified of universalistic aspirations in mind is, a Cambridge School adherent would insist, to risk working at cross-purposes with oneself. Recall that, in Skinner’s view, the chief reason we have beyond “natural curiosity”cxxiv for studying historical texts is that they help us to “stand back from our own assumptions and systems of belief, and thereby to situate ourselves in relation to other and very different forms of life” as merely “one tribe among others.”cxxv This is a goal that, I have argued, the Cambridge School approach shares with those comparative political theoretical projects which, like Dallmayr’s, count among their aims the cultivation of “attentive[ness] to diverse traditions or life-forms,” the “valoriz[ation of] difference and ‘otherness,’” “genuine civilizational encounter,” and “exploring others and immersing ourselves in their distinct life-worlds.”cxxvi From a Skinnerian Cambridge School perspective – and at times it would seem Dallmayr’s – the most edifying lessons that can be learned from the comparative historical study of cultural “others” are to be 27 learned through the very experience of difference itself. However, what practitioners of CPT like Dallmayr have perhaps failed to fully recognize is the extent to which their pursuit of synthetic unity, convergence, or universality may jeopardize their simultaneous pursuit of other vital goals and occlude what a Skinnerian would regard as most beneficial about the comparative study of non-Western political thought, namely, that it creates a space in which the “other” can instruct “us” by opening up worlds of questions and answers “we” have not pondered.cxxvii Megan C. Thomas has drawn attention to the potentially troubling implications of Dallmayr’s aspiration to discern shared universal principles beneath the ostensibly variegated tapestry of global religious, philosophical, and intellectual traditions by drawing parallels between contemporary comparative political theory and Orientalist scholarship of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. Not unlike many contemporary practitioners of comparative political theory, Thomas argues, Victorian Orientalists such as Max Müller and Friedrich Schlegel often emphasized and celebrated commonalities between Europe and the Orient.cxxviiiResisting Edward Said’s famous description of “Orientalism” as a strategy of imperial domination that operated primarily through epistemological “othering,” Thomas draws attention to the fact that certain Orientalists portrayed Europe as intimately “related to parts of the Asian world, rather than always in contrast with or other to them” and that such epistemological appropriation proved as potent an imperial strategy as that identified by Said.cxxix The implications of Thomas’s observations for contemporary comparative political theory are clear: “Comparative political theory cannot distance itself from Orientalism,” Thomas writes, “simply by 28 denouncing Eurocentrism, and recognizing value of non-Western traditions for political theory more generally.”cxxx For Thomas “the epistemological imperialism and authority of Orientalism was enabled by finding value in ‘the East,’ as much as from a presumption of Western superiority.”cxxxi Thomas’ account of the history of Orientalism as an academic and political practice raises the troublesome possibility that in endeavoring to discover and celebrate points of agreement or overlap between “the East” and “the West” contemporary comparative political theorists may be reenacting the infamously imperialist gestures of the Victorian Orientalists. My purpose in making these observations is, of course, not to discredit the project of CPT in general or its more Dallmayrian varieties in particular. It is, in fact, just the opposite: I hope to strengthen “dialogical” approaches to CPT by chastening their dangerous desire for universalism. Even a circumspect and qualified quest for moral universals such as the one Dallmayr proposes runs the risk of perpetrating reductive and assimilative gestures that efface difference, reduce cross-cultural dialogue from the status of an end worthy in itself to a mere means in the service of the attainment of a set of universally agreeable moral precepts, and render the sort of genuine cross-cultural encounter or dialogue that Dallmayr so compellingly describes unlikely, if not impossible.cxxxii Put another way, the agon or contest between the pursuit of a universal morality and the engendering of ethically transformative encounters with and across difference that Dallmayr places at the heart of his approach to CPT cannot be perpetually maintained. Difference cannot be recognized as itself or valued for itself at the same time that it is conscripted into another project that, as Dallmayr himself recognizes, is 29 historically deleterious.cxxxiii If difference is to be given its due and the dialogical project that, on Dallmayr’s own account, is CPT’s highest aim is to be effectively pursued, then practitioners of CPT must chasten their universalistic ambitions and concentrate instead on an admittedly less glamorous task: ascertaining the meaning (in a Skinnerian sense) of the texts and traditions they are interpreting. As Dallmayr himself has wisely noted, “genuine dialogue cannot operate on an abstractly postulated universal level or be supervised from ‘on high’ (a ‘view from nowhere’), but can only function and take wings through an initial attentiveness to the historical and geographical location of participants.”cxxxiv My central aim in this article has been to suggest that the methodological insights of the Cambridge School might prove useful to practitioners of CPT as they strive to achieve this attentiveness to historical specificity in their own work. For over forty years now, Skinner and other Cambridge School theorists have insisted that “we have no a priori reason for expecting previous political thinkers to reveal any interest in or awareness of our ‘basic’ issues.”cxxxv In a similar spirit, I would insist that we have no a priori reason for expecting previous or present political thinkers from other “cultures” or “civilizations,” to use Dallmayr’s language, to reveal any interest in or awareness of what Dallmayr (or anyone) portrays as the basic issues confronting the “global village.”cxxxvi Nor do we, it should be emphasized, have any a priori reason for expecting previous or present political thinkers from other “cultures” or “civilizations” to be uninterested in or unaware of “our” basic issues. While Skinner’s own work has focused overwhelmingly on historical discontinuities,cxxxviiPocock’s work attests to the fact that historical inquiry conducted in accord with the strictures of the Cambridge 30 School may very well uncover extensive continuities between the past and the present.cxxxviiiI should not, therefore, be construed as suggesting that universalism’s great desideratum is eo ipso impossible. Such a suggestion would be as ahistorical as the opposite. Some sort of empirically derived universalism, perhaps along the lines of the “unforced consensus”cxxxix Charles Taylor has described, is certainly possible and discoverable by way of the method described and practiced by Skinner and the Cambridge School. What I am suggesting is that the pursuit of universal moral principles be set aside as a reason, motive, or justification for engaging in cross-cultural or historical inquiry. If we fail to do so, we risk cutting ourselves off from the invigorating and transformative encounters with and across difference that both Dallmayr and Skinner agree are the highest goods cross-cultural and historical inquiry stand to bring about. By way of conclusion, let me underscore the fact that, in suggesting that CPT relinquish the universalist dimension of its project, I do not mean to cut the legs out from under CPT. This subfield is gaining much deserved momentum and attention both within political theory and beyond. But, just as Skinner does not believe that the admission that there may be no perennial questions in philosophy deprives intellectual history of its raison d’être, neither do I believe that the admission that there may be no globally acceptable moral principles immobilizes the project of CPT. In fact, in the radical (in this regard, at least) spirit of the Cambridge School, I would suggest that acknowledging the possibility that there are no such principles is the only place from which genuine intercultural dialogue might begin. 31 Notes i Fred Dallmayr, Border Crossings (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 1999), 2. Dallmayr, Border Crossings, 2. iii Of course, Fred Dallmayr has not been alone in his quest to press political theory beyond its traditional Euro-American boundaries and establish CPT as a subfield within political theory. See, for instance, Brooke Ackerly (2005) “Is Liberalism the Only Way Toward Democracy?: Confucianism and Democracy,” Political Theory 33: 547576; Roxanne Euben (1997) “Comparative Political Theory: An Islamic Fundamentalist Critique of Rationalism,” The Journal of Politics 59: 28-55; Roxanne Euben (1999) Enemy in the Mirror: Islamic Fundamentalism and the Limits of Modern Rationalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press; Roxanne Euben (2002); Roxanne Euben (2006) Journeys to the Other Shore: Muslim and Western Travelers in Search of Knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press; Michael Freeden and Andrew Vincent eds. (2013) Comparative Political Thought: Theorizing Practices. New York, NY: Routledge; Farah Godrej (2009) “Towards a Cosmopolitan Political Thought: The Hermeneutics of Interpreting the Other,” Polity 41: 135-165; Leigh Jenco (2007) “‘What Does Heaven Ever Say?’ A Methods-centered Approach to Cross-cultural Engagement,” American Political Science Review 101: 741-755; Leigh Jenco, (2010) Making the Political. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010; Leigh Jenco (2011) “Recentering Political Theory: The Promise of Mobile Locality,” Cultural Critique 79: 27-59; Andrew March (2009) “What is Comparative Political Theory?”, The Review of Politics 71: 531-565. See also The Review of Politics 70, (Winter 2008), a special issue devoted entirely to CPT with articles by Jürgen Gebhardt, Anthony Black, Anthony Parel, Richard Bernstein and Takashi Shogimen. iv John Dunn and J.G.A. Pocock are also frequently identified as pioneers and leading practitioners of the Cambridge School approach. Nevertheless, in this essay, I focus exclusively on Skinner for two reasons: First, while both Pocock and Dunn have reflected considerably on questions concerning method, neither scholar has published as extensively on these matters as Skinner, and, second, the methodological writings of Pocock and Dunn, despite their originality and depth, have not served as flashpoints for scholarly controversy to the degree that Skinner’s methodological writings have. Despite the fact that Dunn, Pocock, and Skinner all share, in Pocock’s words, “an understanding of ‘political thought’ as a multiplicity of language acts performed by language users in historical contexts,” Pocock notes that it is Skinner who has borne the brunt of the criticism this particular understanding has elicited from historians, philosophers, and political theorists alike (Pocock, 2009, viii). One might also add that while many scholars lump Cambridge School approaches into a monolithic whole, there are quite significant differences among these approaches as well. For those interested in exploring these differences, Pocock’s most significant methodological essays have now been published together in Political Thought and History: Essays on Theory and Method (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009). See also his Politics, Language, and Time (Chicago: ii 32 University of Chicago Press, 1989). Many of Dunn’s most significant methodological reflections have been included in The History of Political Theory and Other Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995). v I survey the criticisms various CPT scholars have offered of the Cambridge School in this article’s final section. vi Fred Dallmayr, “Comparative Political Theory: What is it Good For?” in Western Political Thought in Dialogue with Asia, eds. Takashi Shogimen and Cary J. Nederman (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2009), 18-19. vii The widespread influence of Dallmayr and his “dialogical” approach in the field of CPT is often noted. See, for instance, Leigh Jenco (2007) “‘What Does Heaven Ever Say?’ A Methods-centered Approach to Cross-cultural Engagement,” American Political Science Review 101: 741-755; Andrew March (2009) “What is Comparative Political Theory?,” The Review of Politics 71: 531-565. Melissa S. Williams and Mark E. Warren (2013) “A Democratic Case for Comparative Political Theory,” Political Theory 42(1): 26-57. viii Fred Dallmayr, “Beyond Monologue: Toward A Comparative Political Theory,” Perspectives on Politics 2, (June 2004): 249-257. ix Dallmayr, Border Crossings, 2. x Quentin Skinner, “Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas,” History and Theory 8 (No. 1, 1969), 52. xi The brief introduction to the subfield of CPT I offer here is meant to be just that. For a more comprehensive overview of this flourishing and diverse subfield, see Michael Freeden and Andrew Vincent eds. (2013) Comparative Political Thought: Theorizing Practices. New York: Routledge, 2013. xii Roxanne Euben, “Comparative Political Theory: An Islamic Fundamentalist Critique of Rationalism,” The Journal of Politics 59, (February 1997): 28-55, 32. xiii Euben, “Comparative Political Theory,” 32. xiv Euben, “Comparative Political Theory,” 32. xv Euben, “Comparative Political Theory,” 32. xvi Euben articulates a similar conception of CPT in her path breaking book, Enemy in the Mirror: Islamic Fundamentalism and the Limits of Modern Rationalism (1999) where she writes that there “is a tension between, on the one hand, political theorists’ aspirations to engage questions about the nature and value of politics that, if not universal, are at least pressing to a broad range of peoples and cultures and, on the other, a political theory canon almost exclusively devoted to Western texts” (Euben, 1999, xi) “My central argument,” Euben continues, “is that this tension can recall students of politics to the promise contained in an older, yet never quite lost, understanding of theory as inherently comparative, one defined by certain questions about living together, rather than particular answers” (Euben, 1999, xi). In her more recent work, particularly Journeys to the other Shore: Muslim and Western Travellers in Search of Knowledge (2006), Euben does not explicitly break with this conception of CPT, but she does broaden it. In this work, Euben stresses the capacity of comparative political theorizing, 33 to, in her phrasing, “enact dislocating mediations between the familiar and the unfamiliar,” thereby “enabling imagination of and reflection on modes of life other than [one’s] own” (Euben, 2006, 18). Here, CPT is not so much concerned with “enlarg[ing] the domain of political theory to include a range of human, and not merely Western thought, practice, and experience” as it is with drawing political theory beyond its “domain” through transformative encounters with “the strange and estranging” akin to those experienced by individuals during physical travel (Euben, 1999, 158; Euben, 2006, 12). This latter approach to CPT, which seeks to blur rather than bolster political theory’s traditional boundaries, shares much with what I find admirable in Dallmayr’s approach. xvii Godrej, “Towards a Cosmopolitan Political Thought,” 159. xviii Euben, “Comparative Political Theory,” 32. xix Godrej, “Towards a Cosmopolitan Political Thought,” 160. xx Godrej, “Towards a Cosmopolitan Political Thought,” 138. xxi Godrej, “Towards a Cosmopolitan Political Thought,”164; 148 xxii Godrej, “Towards a Cosmopolitan Political Thought,” 160, 164. xxiii Godrej notes this important difference between her approach and that proposed by March in Godrej (2009) “Response to ‘What Is Comparative Political Theory?’” The Review of Politics 71: 567-582. xxiv Andrew March, “What Is Comparative Political Theory?”, The Review of Politics 71 (September 2009), 560-562. xxv March, “What Is Comparative Political Theory?,” 561. xxvi March, “What Is Comparative Political Theory?,” 561. xxvii Readers well versed in the literature of CPT will realize that I have omitted Leigh Jenco’s approach to cross-cultural inquiry from my summary of the various approaches currently on offer in the field of CPT. I have made this omission for two reasons. First, Jenco herself has explicitly resisted the label of CPT to describe her work. (See Leigh Jenco, Making the Political:Founding and Action in the Political Theory of Zhang Shizhao. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010). Second, in my view, Jenco’s project differs so fundamentally from those of the other theorists I have discussed here that it can fairly be said to exceed the framework of CPT. For Jenco, the goal of cross-cultural inquiry is expressly not to make political theory more global or nonWestern in focus or, in her words, to merely add “culturally diverse voices to established parochial debates” (Jenco, 2007, 741-742). Rather, Jenco’s aim is “to ask new questions through alternative frames of reference” (Jenco, 2007, 741-742). Moreover, in Jenco’s view, the “fundamental question of cross-cultural theorization” is not “how to overcome intersubjective barriers to cultural understanding,” but how to trade “dominant Western scholarly practices” for “alternative modes of inquiry that produce and are informed by particular concerns and texts” (Jenco, 2007, 741-742). In other words, Jenco is not interested in how political theorists might best approach and study non-Western texts as political theorists, but how political theory itself might be, in her words, “recentered,” that is, how “alternative sites of knowledge” might “come to replace the academic conventions and commitments that originally marked the identity of both political theory, 34 and, perhaps, ‘theory’ as such” (Jenco, 2011, 28-29). By arguing for a rapprochement between CPT and the Cambridge School, I hope to urge both CPT and the Camrbridge School in the direction indicated by Jenco’s work. xxviii This is evident, for example, in a chapter from Dallmayr’s Dialogue Among Civilizations entitled “Freedom East and West.” Here, Dallmayr draws on classical Indian and Buddhist conceptions of freedom to, first, counter-act the trope of “Oriental despotism” long employed to denigrate non-Western cultures and justify imperialist and colonialist projects in the West, and, second, underscore the limited nature of a freedom conceived in “cognitive-propositional terms,” an insight, Dallmayr argues, that can also be found in the Western tradition in the works of Heidegger and Gadamer (Dallmayr, 2002, 201; 210-211). xxix Dallmayr describes the delicate balancing of difference and similarity that he believes CPT must effect in the following manner: “‘[C]onversation of human kind,’” Dallmayr writes, “has to steer a difficult path between a hegemonically imposed universalism, governed by one idiom or voice, and an array of self-enclosed, ethnocentric particularisms where no voice would be willing or able to listen to others” (Dallmayr, 2002, 32). “Civilizational dialogue,” Dallmayr notes elsewhere, “has to take otherness… seriously and hence to respect differences and distances that cannot simply be wished or talked away,” but it must do this without eliciting from its participants “gesture[s] of selfabandonment [that would] cancel the pre-judgments stimulating dialogue” (Dallmayr, 2002, 4; 28). xxx Fred Dallmayr, “What is it Good For?”, 13-24. xxxi “The point of comparative political theory,” Dallmayr has written, “… is… to move toward a more genuine universalism, and beyond the spurious ‘universality’ traditionally claimed by the Western canon and by some recent intellectual movements” (Dallmayr, 2004, 253). xxxii Dallmayr, “What is it Good For?,” 13. xxxiii Dallmayr, “What is it Good For?,” 18. xxxiv Dallmayr, “What is it Good For?,” 18. xxxv Dallmayr, “What is it Good For?,” 18. xxxvi Dallmayr, “What is it Good For?,” 18. xxxvii Dallmayr, “What is it Good For?,” 18-19. xxxviii It is important to note that the variety of moral universalism Dallmayr believes might be attainable via CPT, a variety that he, at one point, describes as “lateral universalism,” is not “a facile consensualism,” “a bland assimilationism or a melting-pot cosmopolitanism” that minimizes or entirely neglects cultural differences or “prevailing global inequalities” (Dallmayr, 1996, xxii, 203; Dallmayr, 2002, 6). “Despite a complacent sense of moral ‘superiority’ in the West,” Dallmayr reminds us, “universalist ambitions are far from blameless, having often entailed violent or destructive consequences – a fact amply documented by the Spanish conquest [of the Americas]” (Dallmayr, 1996, 203). While Dallmayr is keenly aware of universalism’s perilous history, he holds out hope that a “lateral universalism… where universal principles are no 35 longer found beyond concrete differences but in the heart of the local or particular itself, that is, in the distinct topography of the world” will avoid these pitfalls (Dallmayr, 1996, 222). xxxix Dallmayr, “What is it Good For?,” 19. xl Dallmayr, “What is it Good For?,”19-20. xli Dallmayr, “What is it Good For?,” 20. xlii Dallmayr, “What is it Good For?,” 20. xliii Dallmayr, “What is it Good For?,” 20. xliv Fred Dallmayr, Beyond Orientalism, (Albany, NY: University of New York Press, 1996), xi. xlv Dallmayr, Beyond Orientalism, xviii. xlvi Fred Dallmayr, Dialogue Among Civilizations (New York, NY: PalgraveMacMillan, 2002), 28. xlvii Dallmayr, Beyond Orientalism, 42. xlviii Dallmayr, Beyond Orientalism, xviii. xlix Dallmayr, Beyond Orientalism, xviii; 134 l . Skinner, “Meaning and Understanding,” 5. Leo Strauss, “What Is Political Philosophy?” in An Introduction to Political Philosophy: Ten Essays, ed. Hilail Gildin. (Detroit, MI: Wayne State University Press, 1989), 3-57. li Leo Strauss, for instance, defines political philosophy as “the attempt to truly know both the nature of political things and the right or the good political order” and insists that political philosophy’s “meaning and meaningful character is evident today as it always has been since the time when political philosophy came to light in Athens” (Strauss, 1988, 6; 3). lii Arthur Lovejoy, The Great Chain of Being (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,1936), 3. liii Leo Strauss , Persecution and the Art of Writing (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1988), 6. liv I am alluding to the argument about the birth and subsequent decline of the doctrine of natural law laid out by Leo Strauss in Strauss (1953) Natural Right and History. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. lv I refer here to the interpretation of Machiavelli’s writings proffered by Leo Strauss in Strauss (1978) Thoughts on Machiavelli. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. lvi Skinner, Meaning and Understanding, 7. lvii Skinner, Meaning and Understanding, 50. lviii Skinner, Meaning and Understanding, 22; 14. lix C.B. Macpherson, Burke (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1980). lx While the assumptions underlying Namierite historiography are obviously very different from those held by Marxists, Skinner and other members of the Cambridge School have been equally critical of the Namierite dismissal of the historical relevance of ideas. 36 This could not have been Burke’s intention because these terms and concepts were simply not available, or, at the very least, did not bear the resonances and meanings that they bear today, in the late-eighteenth-century European context in which Burke lived and wrote. On this point, see, for instance, Donald Winch (1996) Riches and Poverty: An Intellectual History of Political Economy in Britain (1750-1834). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. lxii John Dunn provides a pithy statement of the problematic aspects of the “epiphenomenalism” orthodoxy from the perspective of the Cambridge School. Adherents to this orthodoxy, Dunn writes, “[pay] only the most perfunctory (or insincere) attention to the concerns of the author, and [stress] instead the aspects of the historical society in which the text was composed, of which its author might well have been imperfectly aware but which, nevertheless, prompted him or her to think and express themselves as they did” (Dunn, 1996, 19). lxiii Skinner, Visions, 106. lxiv Skinner, Visions, 99. lxv Skinner, Visions, 100; 113. lxvi Skinner, Visions, 114-116. lxvii Skinner delineates three distinctive types of “meaning” that an interpreter might pursue via various methods and stipulates that his method is intended to get at only one of these types, “Meaning3” (Skinner, 1972, 93). “Meaning3,” Skinner explains, is the meaning one is after when one asks, “What does the writer mean by what he says in this work?” or, phrased in the idiom of Austin’s analysis, “What was the agent doing in issuing that particular utterance?” or “What were the agent’s primary intentions in issuing that particular utterance?” (Skinner, 1972, 93). Meaning3 is not, in Skinner’s view, the only meaning a text can rightly be said to have. “Any text will normally include an intended meaning,” Skinner writes, “and the recovery of that meaning certainly constitutes a precondition of understanding what its author may have meant” (Skinner, 2002, 113). ”But,” Skinner continues, “any text of any complexity will always contain far more in the way of meaning than even the most vigilant and imaginative author could possibly have intended to put into it” (Skinner, 2002, 113). lxviii Skinner, Visions, 105; 100; 98; 102. lxix In “Meaning and Understanding,” Skinner makes a similar injunction. “[W]e must study all the various situations,” Skinner writes, “which may change in complex ways, in which the given form of words can logically be used – all the functions they can serve, all the various things that can be done with them” (Skinner, 1969, 37). J.G.A. Pocock similarly insists that the historian of ideas practice a sort of archaeology, “uncovering the presence of various language contexts in which discourse has from time to time been conducted” (Pocock, 1987, 23). lxx Skinner admits that there are limits to what an interpreter of historical texts can hope to accomplish. “Some utterances,” Skinner writes as a concession to a criticism of his method made by Jacques Derrida, “are completely lacking in the sorts of context from which we can hope to infer the intentions with which they were uttered. We may well be lxi 37 obliged to concede in such cases that we can never hope to arrive at even a plausible hypothesis about how the utterance in question should be understood” (Skinner, 2002, 121). Moreover, Skinner continues, due to the nature of “the hermeneutic enterprise,” its “outcome… can never be anything resembling the attainment of a final, self-evident or indubitable set of truths about any text or other utterance whatsoever” (Skinner, 2002, 121). “To look for complete intelligibility,” Skinner suggests elsewhere, “is to adopt an unduly optimistic view of what we can hope to bring back from the foreign lands of the past” (Skinner, 2002, 56). lxxi It must be emphasized that Skinner does not identify the meanings of texts with the intentions of their authors. “Where a text says something other than what its author intended to say,” Skinner writes, “we are bound to concede that this is nevertheless what the text says, and thus that it bears a meaning other than the one intended by its author” (Skinner, 2002, 110). What Skinner identifies with authorial intentions are not the meanings of texts per se but “only what their authors meant by them” (Skinner, 2002, 113-114). Of course, this question of what an author meant by a particular work, phrase, or even word is one that detains a great many readers and on which a great many interpretive controversies hinge. As Richard Ashcraft has noted, scholarly disputes about the infamous “turfs passage” in John Locke’s Second Treatise are a case in point of this (Ashcraft, 1992, 716-723). lxxii J.G.A. Pocock phrases the bedrock methodological principle underlying the Cambridge School approach in this way: “What we have all been doing is insisting that a certain branch of the study of politics be perceived as a history of activity and be conducted within the discipline of history” (Pocock, 2004, 538). lxxiii Skinner, Visions, 125. lxxiv Skinner, Visions, 3. lxxv Skinner, Visions, 3; emphasis added. lxxvi See, for instance, John Gunnell (1982) “Interpretation and the History of Political Theory: Apology and Epistemology,” The American Political Science Review, 76: 317-327; Charles Tarlton (1973) “Historicity, Meaning, and Revisionism in the Study of Political Thought,” History and Theory, 12: 307-328. lxxvii See, for instance, John Gunnell’s 1982 article “Interpretation and the History of Political Theory: Apology and Epistemology” or Charles Tarlton’s 1973 article “Historicity, Meaning, and Revisionism in the Study of Political Thought.” lxxviii Skinner, Meaning and Understanding, 52. lxxix Skinner, Visions, 175-176. lxxx Skinner, Visions, 125. lxxxi Skinner, Visions, 125. lxxxii In a lecture delivered in 1997, Skinner argues that his proposed interpretive method entails a commitment to a “most wholehearted multiculturalism, to the fullest attempt to deconstruct hegemonal ideologies and make it possible for those with different cognitive as well as social allegiances to be heard with equal respect” (quoted in Scott and Kates, 2001, 22). 38 lxxxiii Skinner, Meaning and Understanding, 52-53. Quentin Skinner, Liberty Before Liberalism (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 112. lxxxiv Skinner, Liberty, 107; 112. lxxxv Skinner, Liberty, 112. lxxxvi Skinner, Liberty, 111; 116. lxxxvii Skinner, Meaning and Understanding, 52. lxxxviii Quentin Skinner, The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, vol. 1 (Cambridge, UK: Camrbridge University Press, 1978), x. lxxxix Skinner, Foundations, x-xi. xc Skinner, Foundations, xi. xci In an early (1973) critique of Skinner’s method, Bhikhu Parekh and R.N. Berki accuse Skinner of conflating what they characterize as three distinct levels of abstraction, generality, and seriousness “at which thinkers concerned with political problems can be said to have been operating” (Parekh and Berki, 1973, 172). In effect, Parekh and Berki argue, Skinner’s method “reduces everything to [the lowest] level” of “mere political pamphleteering,” a level that, Parekh and Berki imply, is best ignored by those possessing “a genuine feeling for political thought” and an interest in what they characterize as the perennial questions of political life (Parekh and Berki, 1973, 173; 174175; 179). xcii Conal Condren, The Status and Appraisal of Classic Texts (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985), 50. xciii Skinner, Meaning and Understanding, 52. xciv David Runciman, “History of Political Thought: The State of the Discipline,” British Journal of Politics and International Relations 3 (April 2001): 84-104. xcv Dallmayr, “Beyond Monologue,” 254. xcvi Dallmayr, “What is it Good For?,” 20. xcvii Dallmayr, Dialogue Among Civilizations, 27. It should be noted that Dallmayr’s notion of dialogue owes much to Gadamer’s, especially as it was developed and refined after the publication of Truth and Method. For more on the relationship between Dallmayr’s and Gadamer’s understandings of dialogue, see Dallmayr’s Beyond Orientalism, especially the second chapter entitled “Gadamer, Derrida, and the Hermeneutics of Difference.” xcviii It should be noted that Dallmayr’s notion of dialogue owes much to Gadamer’s, especially as it was developed and refined after the publication of Truth and Method. For more on the relationship between Dallmayr’s and Gadamer’s understandings of dialogue, see Dallmayr’s Beyond Orientalism, especially the second chapter entitled “Gadamer, Derrida, and the Hermeneutics of Difference.” xcix Dallmayr, Dialogue Among Civilizations, 17; 4. c Godrej, “Towards a Cosmopolitan Political Thought,” 162. ci Godrej, “Towards a Cosmopolitan Political Thought,” 162. cii For instance, Andrew March has written of the Cambridge School that “it is hard to imagine a less engaged approach to the history of political thought, one which 39 risks reducing political theory to [‘a banal and trivial] wisdom literature,’ as [Judith] Shklar warned” (March, 2009, 549). I would be remiss to fail to point out here that the Judith Shklar quote March employs here to buttress his critique of the Cambridge School comes from Shklar’s overwhelmingly positive review of one of the most well-known pieces of scholarship the Cambridge School has ever produced, Quentin Skinner’s Foundations of Modern Political Thought. In this review, Shklar praises Skinner’s method for doing precisely what March accuses it of not doing, namely, putting the politics back into political theory by striving to restore canonical works of political theory to their original political contexts. “One can easily sympathize with this aim,” Shklar writes, adding the observation that March would later tear from its original context and contort into a critique of the Cambridge School: “Political theories wholly removed from the controversies of their world become a banal and trivial ‘wisdom’ literature” (Shklar, 549). ciii See, for instance, Margaret Leslie (1970) “In Defense of Anachronism,” Political Studies 18: 433-447 and Bikhu Parekh and R.N. Berki (1973) “The History of Political Ideas: A Critique of Q. Skinner’s Methodology,” Journal of the History of Ideas 34: 163-184. civ Skinner, Liberty, 106-108. cv Richard Tuck, “History” in A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, ed. Robert E. Goodin, Philip Pettit, and Thomas Pogge (Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell Publishing, 2012), 80. cvi Skinner, Liberty, 116-117. cvii Skinner, Liberty, 117. cviii I have focused here on an example taken from Skinner’s work because he is the representative Cambridge School theorist I have chosen to focus on in this article. However, since Godrej does not aim her critique at Skinner alone but at the Cambridge School more generally, it is worth noting that the accusation that a Cambridge School theorist such as J.G.A. Pocock is somehow unconcerned with the relationship between past and present is even less convincing than in the case of Skinner. Whereas Skinner, much like Michel Foucault, has tended to focus on conceptual ruptures and breaks between political discourses, Pocock has focused on the long continuity and influence of certain ideas (as well as the institutions they help create) in historical time. Indeed, it would be virtually impossible to think about contemporary “republican” institutions, let alone about how to act with political efficacy in the present either to support or overturn them, without grappling with their history. For that understanding, we are indebted more to Pocock than any other single scholar. cix Chris Goto-Jones, “The Kyoto School, the Cambridge School, and the History of Political Philosphy in Wartime Japan,” Positions 17 (Spring 2009): 14. cx Goto-Jones, “The Kyoto School,” 14. cxi Goto-Jones, “The Kyoto School,” 14. cxii Pocock’s 1964 essay “Ritual, Language and Power: An Essay on the Apparent Meanings of Ancient Chinese Philosophy,” proposes what Pocock later describes as “an 40 enterprise that I still wish scholars better equipped than I would take up: the writing of histories of East Asian political thought comparable with those which we have for the classical and postclassical West” (Pocock, 1989, x). “To have history written with an Eastern and a Western face,” Pocock remarked in a reflection on this 1964 essay written in 1989, “will be very important and necessary in times to come” (Pocock, 1989, x). cxiii “This essay,” in Pocock’s words, “records the attempts of a historian and political theorist who is no Oriental scholar, and knows no Chinese, to discover a pattern of meanings in the ideas about government and society expressed in the heroic age of Chinese thought… and to present them in such a way as to aid his understanding both of political society and of the character and problems of thought about it” (Pocock, 1989, 42). Pocock is clear that, in the essay, he is “framing hypotheses about a realm of meaning which may have been present and operative” rather than describing a realm of meaning that, as a matter of historical fact, was. Such hypotheses, Pocock believes, can form an invaluable part of historical study because they provide historians, if they need them, places to begin their empirical investigations. For a detailed discussion of this relationship, see Pocock (1989) Politics, Language and Time: Essays on Political Thought and History. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press. cxiv Joan Scott and Debra Kates, eds. Schools of Thought: Twenty-Five Years of Interpretive Social Science (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001), 23. cxv Scott and Kates, Schools of Thought, 23-24. cxvi Scott and Kates, Schools of Thought, 23. cxvii Scott and Kates, Schools of Thought, 24. cxviii Scott and Kates, Schools of Thought, 24. cxix Scott and Kates, Schools of Thought, 24. cxx Goto-Jones, “The Kyoto School,” 38. cxxi Leigh Jenco makes this point, though not specifically in relation to the Cambridge School. In sounding her call for a “recentering” of political theory, Jenco points to the obvious but often neglected fact that “knowledge production is tied more closely to contingent structures of power, inclination, and commitment than to inevitably overpowering cultural background conditions” (Jenco, 2011, 44). In light of this fact, Jenco challenges political theory as a discipline to reform and reorganize itself in order to “facilitate access, by way of linguistic and other forms of training, to diverse fields of interconnected knowledge and schools of thought abiding in particular locales” (Jenco, 2011, 44-45). Absent such reforms, Jenco rightly notes, virtually all political theorists, well-intentioned historians of political thought and practitioners of CPT alike, will continue to be shunted into Eurocentric topics and traditions of inquiry. cxxii Dallmayr, “Beyond Monologue,” 253. cxxiii Dallmayr, “What is it Good For?,” 18. cxxiv Skinner, Liberty, 107. cxxv Skinner, Visions, 125. cxxvi Dallmayr, “Beyond Monologue,” 253-254; Dallmayr, Dialogue Among Civilizations, 17; Dallmayr, “What is it Good For?,” 20. 41 William Connolly has registered similar concerns regarding Dallmayr’s pursuit of universality or “convergence” through dialogue (Connolly, 2001, 351). In Connolly’s view, Dallmayr’s tendency to link difference to fragmentation belies his “residual commitment to a concentric image of political culture” in which “progressively enlarged circles of family, neighborhood, community, nation, civilization, and universal norms resonate with each other” and “minorities in each of these domains are… defined as satellites ranged around the national center, either to be tolerated or persecuted” (Connolly, 2001, 350-351). For Connolly, such an ideal ought not be the primary or exclusive desideratum of dialogue across difference. “A political culture of multidimensional diversity,” Connolly explains, “will also be one in which the quest for convergence often gives ground to the pursuit of multiple connections of respect across persisting differences, issuing in what might be called a political culture of positive connections through relations of agonistic respect” (Connolly, 2001, 351). Dallmayr’s conflation of difference with fragmentation prevents him from envisioning such an alternative dialogical outcome, in Connolly’s view. cxxviii Megan C. Thomas, “Orientalism and Comparative Political Theory,” The Review of Politics 72 (Fall 2010): 656. cxxix “The significant revelation of Orientalism,” Thomas writes, “was… that modern Europe… derived most fundamentally from India, rather than Greece or Rome” (Thomas, 2010, 668). “Just as the Greek and Roman patrimony was thought to ‘belong’ to nineteenth-century (northern) Europe (rather than contemporary Greeks and Romans),” Thomas continues, “so ancient India, too, ‘belonged’ to contemporary European men of letters” (Thomas, 2010, 668). “In this respect,” Thomas shrewdly notes, “’Orientalism’ [as a strategy of colonial domination] was largely about identifying value in its subject, rather than denigrating or dismissing it,” a fact that “while suggested by Said, is stifled by his own emphasis on how Orientalist views denigrated the East” (Thomas, 2010, 668669). cxxx Thomas, “Orientalism,” 674. cxxxi Thomas, “Orientalism,” 674. cxxxii In Comparative Political Thought: Theorizing Practices (2013), Michael Freeden and Andrew Vincent sound a similar note of caution regarding the universalist aspirations of many variants of CPT. “Attempts to draw different cultures together and to forge a common normative discourse and a universal register are not merely utopian exercises in impossibility,” Freeden and Vincent write, “but underplay the desirable diversity of the human mind, its languages and practices.” cxxxiii See, for instance, the first chapter of Dallmayr’s Beyond Orientalism, in which Dallmayr details “the ‘conquest’ of the Americas by European powers,” paying special attention to the role played by a specifically Christian variant of moral universalism in the “domination, exploitation, and extermination” of the native peoples of south, central, and north America. cxxvii 42 cxxxiv Dallmayr, Dialogue Among Civilizations, 2. . Condren, Status and Appraisal, 49. cxxxvi . Dallmayr, “Beyond Monologue,” 249. cxxxvii . Skinner, Liberty, 111. cxxxviii . J.G.A. Pocock, “Languages and their Implications: The Transformation of the Study of Political Thought” in Politics, Language, and Time: Essays on Political Thought and History (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press), 3-41. cxxxix . Charles Taylor, “A World Consensus on Human Rights?,” Dissent 43 (Summer 1996), 15-21. cxxxv 43