Key Questions & Quotes on Wild-Type To What Extent Has There Been Continuity Between Nineteenth and Twentieth century Conceptions of Wild-Type? The Problem of Representation: How can Geneticists Justify Extrapolating from Laboratory Results to Natural Populations? If Laboratory Wild-Types ‘Stand In For’ Actual Wild Organisms, What do They Represent? Phenotypes, Genotypes, Epigenotypes? What is the Relationship Between Wild-Types and Their Environments? Does Wild-Type have a Place in Molecular Genetics? What is the Role of Wild-Types in Genetic Practice? Wild-Type – A Real or Instrumental Category? Linnaeus: “A variety is a plant changed by an accidental cause: climate, soil, temperature, winds, etc. A variety consequently reverts to its original condition when the soil is changed” (Mayr: pp. 640) Charles Darwin: “The doctrine of the origin of our several domestic races from several aboriginal stocks, has been carried to an absurd extreme by some authors. They believe that every race which breeds true… has had its wild prototype. At this rate there must have existed at least a score of species of wild cattle, as many sheep, and several goats in Europe alone” (pp. 27); “Now, in every one of the domestic breeds, taking thoroughly well-bred birds, all of the above marks [of Columbia livia]… sometimes concur perfectly developed. Moreover, when two birds belonging to two distinct breeds are crossed… the mongrel offspring are very apt suddenly to acquire these characters… We can understand these facts, on the well-known principle of reversion to ancestral characters, if all the domestic breeds have descended from the rock pigeon [alternative suggestions are not parsimonious]” (pp. 33) Fleeming Jenkin: “A given animal or plant appears to be contained, as it were, within a sphere of variation; one individual lies near one portion of the surface; another individual, of the same species, near another part of the surface; the average animal at the centre. Any individual may produce descendants varying in any direction, but is more likely to produce descendants varying towards the centre of the sphere, and the variations in that direction will be greater in amount than the variations towards the surface” (pp. 282) Alfred Russel Wallace: “Domestic varieties, when turned wild, must return to something near the type of the original wild stock, or become altogether extinct* [*That is, they will vary, and the variations which tend to adapt them to the wild state, and therefore approximate them to wild animals, will be preserved. Those individuals which do not vary sufficiently will perish]… [N]o inferences as to the permanence of varieties in a state of nature can be deduced from the observations of those occurring among domestic animals. The two are so much opposed to each other in every circumstance of their existence, that what applies to the one is almost sure not to apply to the other. Domestic animals are abnormal, irregular, artificial” (Contributions to the Theory of Natural Selection, Second Edition, WHS Corrections and Additions, Macmillan and Co., 1871, pp. 40-41) Ernst Haeckel: ‘Reversion to the Wild Form’: “When cultivated plants or domestic animals become wild, when they are withdrawn from the conditions of cultivated life, they experience changes which appear not only as adaptations to their new mode of life, but partially also as relapses into the ancient original form out of which the cultivated forms have been developed. Thus the different kinds of cabbage, which are exceedingly different in form, may be led back to the original form, by allowing them to grow wild. In like manner, dogs, horses, heifers, etc., when growing wild, often revert more or less to a long extinct generation. An immensely long succession of generations may pass away before this power of latent transmission becomes extinguished.” (The History of Creation: Or the Development of the Earth and Its Inhabitants by the Action of Natural Causes. A Popular Exposition of the Doctrine of Evolution in General, And Of That of Darwin, Goethe, and Lamarck in Particular. Vol. I, E. Ray Lankester (trans.), New York: D. Appleton and Company, 1887., pp. 209) Francis Galton: Galton: “The observed facts of Reversion enable us to prove that the latent elements must be greatly more varied than those that are personal or patent. The arguments are as follows:—(1) there must be room for very great variety, because a single strain of impure blood will reassert itself after more than eight generations; (2) an individual has 256 progenitors in the eighth degree, if there have been no ancestral intermarriages, while under the ordinary conditions of social and neighbourly life he will certainly have had a considerable, though a smaller number of them; (3) the gradual waning of the tendency to reversion as the generations increase conforms to what would occur if each fresh marriage contributed a competing element for the same place, thus diluting the impure strain until its relative importance was reduced to an insignificant amount” (pp. 395, ‘On Blood Relationship’, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Vol. 20, 1871-1872, pp. 394-402) Jean Gayon: “[Galton’s conception of] regression rapidly revealed itself to be a rehabilitation of the ‘doctrine of the constancy of races’ which had dominated the theory of breeding in the first half of the 19th century” (Darwinism’s Struggle for Survival: Heredity and the Hypothesis of Natural Selection, Matthew Cobb (trans.), Cambridge University Press, 1998, pp. 175) “It was Mendelism which cut the Gordian knot of selection. By disassociating the operational notion ‘heredity’ from those of descent and ancestrality, Mendelism forced the science of heredity away from the contemplation of genealogy and imposed a representation of heredity as a structure. Furthermore, the extrapolation of Mendelian calculations to the population level destroyed once and for all the representations of heredity as a force of return... Heredity could no longer be viewed as... a biological analogy of momentum – it was stripped of any reference to its effects in terms of ‘force’ or ‘energy’” (Darwinism’s Struggle for Survival: Heredity and the Hypothesis of Natural Selection, Matthew Cobb (trans.), Cambridge University Press, 1998, pp. 404) Bateson: “For the first time Variation and Reversion have a concrete, palpable meaning. Hitherto they have stood by in all evolutionary debates, convenient genii, ready to perform as little or as much as might be desired by the conjuror. That vaporous stage of their existence is over; and we see Variation shaping itself as a definite, physiological event, the addition or omission of one or more definite elements; and Reversion as that particular addition or subtraction which brings the total of the elements back to something it had been before in the history of the race.” (pp. 48, The Methods and Scope of Genetics) William Castle: “I have shown that the agouti, or wild type of coat of the guinea-pig, results from the simultaneous presence of three factors, which are separately heritable unit characters, namely, black pigment, yellow pigment and a factor causing the two pigments to be disposed in bands. In uniformly colored (or self) varieties of the guinea-pig, at least one of these three factors is wanting. If the lacking factor is supplied by a cross with a variety which possesses it, then reversion is obtained, that is a return to the wild type of coat” (pp. 287, Color Variations of the Rabbit & Other Rodents (1907)); “Knowing the unit-characters borne by each variety (its gametic formula), one can readily predict the result of crosses between the several varieties. Any cross which brings together the three factors, B, Y and A, will give reversion, i. e., a return to the wild type of coat, gray” (pp. 288, Color Variations of the Rabbit & Other Rodents (1907)) Raphael Falk (see diagram below): “Unfortunately, Morgan soon realized that extending his notation based on multiple developmental steps beyond the simple case of two factors acting independently on a character, actually led to an impossible situation with regard to the use of factors… Morgan soon realized that it was not only the nomenclature, but also empirical considerations that required him to abandon efforts to reconcile his embryological top-down conceptions with Mendelian bottom-up research. It was ‘with much reluctance’ that he suggested a change of his nomenclature. ‘The change is not one of any theoretical importance, but a practical necessity for cases of this kind’… He conceded that the name of a new character stands merely as its symbol… [As Castle however observed] the new nomenclature… was not ‘simply starting the facts’. It was strongly implying exactly what Morgan wished to avoid, namely a ‘genocentric’ notion of genes being for traits” (Genetic Analysis: A History of Genetic Thinking, Cambridge University Press, 2009, pp. 233-4) From: Raphael Falk, Genetic Analysis: A History of Genetic Thinking, Cambridge University Press, 2009, pp. 232 TH Morgan, Sturtevant, Muller & Bridges: “In most cases different genetic types produce different results in any ordinary environment. The environment, being common to the two, may therefore in such cases be ignored, or rather taken for granted. There are other cases, however, in which a particular genetic type appears different from another one only in a special environment. Where this environment is not the normal one, its discovery is an essential element of the experiment” (The Mechanism of Mendelian Inheritance, 1915, pp. 38) TH Morgan: “What bearing has the appearance of these new types of Drosophila on the theory of evolution may be asked. The objection has been raised in fact that in the breeding work with Drosophila we are dealing with artificial and unnatural conditions. It has been more than implied that results obtained from the breeding pen, the seed pan, the flower pot and the milk bottle do not apply to evolution in the "open", nature "at large" or to "wild" types. To be consistent, this same objection should be extended to the use of the spectroscope in the study of the evolution of the stars, to the use of the test tube and the balance by the chemist, of the galvanometer by the physicist. All these are unnatural instruments used to torture Nature's secrets from her. I venture to think that the real antithesis is not between unnatural and natural treatment of Nature, but rather between controlled or verifiable data on the one hand, and unrestrained generalization on the other” (A Critique of the Theory of Evolution (1916), pp. 84-5) R.A. Fisher: “The two alternative statements, that the mutant type is generally recessive, or that the wild type is generally dominant, are formally equivalent; nevertheless, the latter statement is to be preferred, in view of the behavior of series of multiple allelomorphs, of which Drosophila furnishes several examples, which have been admirably paralleled in the albino series in rodents. In these cases it is found that while the wild type is clearly dominant to the mutant allelomorphs, yet the heterozygote of two mutant allelomorphs is intermediate between them. The mutant allelomorphs show little or no dominance inter se, although it has been demonstrated that one can arise as a mutation from another. This group of observations suggests, therefore, that it is rather a peculiarity of the wild type to be generally dominant than a peculiarity of the mutant to be recessive to the type from which it arose” (‘The Possible Modification of the Response of the Wild Type to Recurrent Mutations’, The American Naturalist, Vol. 62, No. 679, 1928, pp. 115-6) C.R. Plunkett (from: 1932, 1932, ‘Temperature as a Tool of Research in Phenogenetics: Methods and Results’, Proceedings of the 6TH International Congress of Genetics, Ithaca 2, 158–169.): “The usual difference . . . between wild-type and mutant characters, in respect to the effects of temperature, are ascribed, on the basis of this theory, to differences in the distance of the developmental process from its asymptote at the time it ends: processes controlled by wild-type genes usually closely approach their asymptotes, while those modified by mutant genes may be terminated by the effects of other developmental processes while still very incomplete. This conception is applicable... also to other usual differences between wild-type and mutant characters, in respect to variability in general and in respect to dominance, which is merely a special case of interaction of factors affecting the same phenotypic character. This peculiarity in the physico-chemical kinetics of “wild-type” developmental processes is a result of natural selection, which tends, in general, to favor a genotype which produces a relatively uniform phenotype” (In: Falk, Raphael, ‘The rise and fall of dominance’, Biology and Philosophy, Vol. 16, pp. 285-323, 2001, pp. 310) Theodosius Dobzhansky “The ability of the gene complexes carried in second chromosomes of wild Drosophila pseudoobscura to produce, through recombination, a great variety of new gene complexes disrupts the notion of ‘normal’ or ‘wild type’ chromosome, genotype, or phenotype. In general, these notions only exist because of the reluctance of the human mind to abandon the idea of a finite number of static prototypes underlying the unmanageable… multiformity of the living nature… it is, nevertheless, [in non-polymorphic species] convenient for descriptive purposes to contrast mutant or aberrant individuals or strains with normal or wild type ones” (‘Genetics of natural populations. XIII. Recombination and variability in populations of Drosophila pseudoobscura’, 1945) A. R. Cordeiro and Theodosius Dobzhansky: “Except in polymorphic species, individuals which occur in natural populations of most organisms are sufficiently uniform in phenotype to be described simply as "normal," or representing the "wild-type" of their respective species or races. It is legitimate to use the concept of "norm" to facilitate the description of mutants and of genetical and environmentally induced aberrations that occur from time to time. Unfortunately, some biologists have gone beyond this, and came to regard the "norm" as a sort of ideal prototype of which the actually existing individuals are imperfect copies. This typological thinking, the roots of which go down to the Platonic philosophy, is basically anti-evolutionistic, and has produced much confusion in biological though” (‘Combining Ability of Certain Chromosomes in Drosophila Willistoni and Invalidation of the "Wild-Type" Concept’, The American Naturalist, Vol. 88, No. 839, 1954, pp. 83) Rachel Ankeny: “For C elegans, the wild type worm is from a certain strain (Bristol) and has been genetically purebred since its adoption by Brenner in the 1960s; however, the selection of this variant as the wild type was relatively arbitrary and dependent not on its typicality (e.g., later use of the Bergerac strain allowed detection of transposons; see Anderson et al. 1992) as much as on the ease of its experimental manipulability” (‘Fashioning Descriptive Models in Biology: Of Worms and Wiring Diagrams’, Philosophy of Science, Vol. 67, Supplement. Proceedings of the 1998 Biennial Meetingsof the Philosophy of Science Association. Part II: Symposia Papers (Sep., 2000 pp. S265) “[T]he first step in the underlying strategy [of classical genetics] is to select and establish a “wild type” for the organism (taken as a standard from among other possible wild types available in nature) against which other genetic variants or abnormal types can be compared. Despite its name, the wild type may not be the most common, frequent, or even a “normal” version of the organism; sometimes it is simply the first strain that was discovered on which subsequent research has been based, but is oftentimes the easiest to manipulate experimentally. These experimental organisms of course are “natural”, inasmuch as they are still actual, living, concrete organisms, and have been “selected from nature’s very own workshop”. However, the carefully selected wild type is, in this sense, an idealized model of actual organisms in nature, since oftentimes they end up differing considerably from those highly rarefied beasts that remain isolated in the laboratory, particularly as a model organism comes to be more widely used. Thus modelling occurs in most obviously in the establishment of the wild type, which is an essential first step to establishing and using something on an ongoing basis as a model organism. Without this, it is not possible to have a “norm” against which “abnormal” (or more precisely, that which is variant) can be compared, in terms of genetics, developmental lineages, and so on” (‘Wormy Logic’, 2006, pp. 8)