THE TRUTH OF OUR TIMES: Jung’s Liber Novus and the Psychological Difference John C. Woodcock 1 Introduction Psychology as the discipline of interiority (PDI) of course privileges interiority as its alpha and omega. The psychological difference is an equally crucial concept within the discipline because this concept is a living concept, i.e., the underlying logical life of our modern form of consciousness and, as such, is the psychological basis from which we can practice the discipline of psychology in the first place. Our modern structure of consciousness is a complex one in which the subjective psyche has not “caught up” with the logical life of the soul, in its historical self-transformations. There is thus a structural dissociation in place. I do not mean by this that there is a human failing somewhere. I sometimes wish it were that easy. No, by placing interiority at the centre, PDI is saying that the soul’s movements are determinative in our human lives. PDI is concerned with the background movements (negative reality) of our very existence as psychological beings. The soul undergoes a transformation in its logical life and we “suffer” the consequences, i.e., our existence alters accordingly, whether we like it or not. Thus our modern dissociated structure of consciousness is an outcome of some very complex moves within the logical life of the soul that have become “visible” through the historical development in the West. Perhaps it is germane here to note that such a consideration as the determining power of the soul was not always uncomfortable or even news. It was simply taken for granted that our ordinary existence was determined by “hidden powers” for millennia before our modern era with its emphasis on human freedom. Now it seems that, along with George Orwell, we must assert that restating the obvious is the first duty of intelligent men and women. We do have some responsibility in how we relate to the fact that our existence is determined by soul movements “occurring” in the background (negative reality). If PDI is a discipline that includes service to the soul in its ethic, then our responsibility lies in simply making what is real our truth. This human act releases the implicit background into explicitness, which, it seems, the soul intends—the soul “wants” to manifest in the world, though us in one form or another. This is another way of saying, “culture”! So, in our modern times, this ethical act would mean making our dissociated structure of consciousness explicit, which is possible only as the soul 1 John C. Woodcock is a practising Jungian Psychotherapist in Sydney Australia. He writes numerous essays and books as well which may be found at www.lighthousedownunder.com. This essay is excerpted from his latest book, Animal Soul (iUniverse). Page 1 of 9 becomes self-conscious, its “self” being the living unity of its own logic of dissociation. To this end, if we so choose to be of service, it becomes imperative to examine those habits of thought that perpetuate beliefs, prejudices, behaviours, and ideologies that lock us into identification with one side of our dissociated consciousness, thereby occluding the soul’s deeper movements altogether. Psychological phenomenology (the methodology of PDI) demands this selfdiscipline in the practitioner and the key to psychological phenomenology is the psychological difference! The most obdurate ideology that permeates our beliefs and prejudices our eye against the real (the logical life of the soul in the real) today has sprung up as an industry around C. G. Jung’s concept of the unconscious, hereafter called the Jungian unconscious. This essay will examine the Jungian unconscious, highlighting the singular importance of the psychological difference in understanding this significant habit of thought that at present prevents us from facing the truth of our times. Liber Novus or The Red Book Throughout Jung’s accounts of his psychic experiences, as recorded in the now published Liber Novus, as well as his autobiography, and other publications, his focus lies exclusively with his “spontaneous encounters” with real fantasies, i.e., fantasies that gained a substantial “body”, acted “autonomously”, and had a quality of “immediacy” and “compelling presence”. Subsequent generations of Jungian psychologists and beyond into the larger community of artists, poets, eco-psychologists and so on, have unquestioningly accepted Jung’s own account of his experiences as representing the true nature of the reality he was investigating—psychic reality, or the Jungian unconscious. 2 These qualities of the unconscious psyche were discovered by, at times, a shocked and even tormented Jung, during his confrontation of “some twenty years” with the unconscious, as recorded by him in Liber Novus. As Shamdasani demonstrates, there is a direct continuity between this “stream of lava” and the work of a lifetime for Jung. 3 4 These declared qualities of the Jungian unconscious made it possible for Jung and subsequent generations to preserve Meaning, as recapitulated in the human psyche, i.e., the Meaning that had been self-evidently present as the interiority of nature for millennia but which now appeared to be lost to our modern existence. 5 So, what’s the problem? We should all be grateful that Jung managed to make it possible for us all to find Meaning again, like our ancestors once did, 2 (Jung, 1965), (Jung, 1989), (Jung, 2009), (Tacey, 2010) (Jung, 1965, pp. 199-200) 4 (Jung, 2009). See Introduction by Shamdasani 5 For a full discussion of this problem, called Jung’s project, see: (Giegerich, 2010c, p. 189) 3 Page 2 of 9 shouldn’t we? The only difference is that, whereas our ancestors looked outward, finding nature’s interiority self-evidently right there, as the interiority of the world (naturally conceived only as world by our ancestors), we moderns only have to look within the human being to find it, as our interiority. There apparently is no problem, as we can see with the psychological culture that has sprung up around the Jungian unconscious for the last sixty years. And this “no problem” will therefore continue to harden into an inveterate habit of thought, occluding any access to the real (i.e., the real logical status of the soul today), as I said above. Have I claimed here that the Jungian unconscious is not real, i.e., is a human concept that does not reflect the living reality of soul today? Well, yes and no. To lead us into this more deeply, I want to compare Jung’s confrontation with the unconscious with an even more famous confrontation with fictional figures. Alice in Wonderland and the Psychological Difference When Alice drops into Wonderland, she leaves the categories of thought that belong to empirical reality behind and becomes fictional herself, evaluating this new reality within its own terms (remember her long conversations with the caterpillar and Humpty Dumpty, for example). 6 While she is inside the fiction, i.e., as the fictional “I”, each character opens up to its own interiority and depth, its own truth. Although Alice is amazed and perturbed by the various characters, she does not question their reality, using empirical categories. While she is in Wonderland, they are as real as she is, demanding that they be taken on their own terms, which Alice does willingly. When she shrinks and grows large, she is frightened, yes, but not doubtful or sceptical. She simply deals with each situation, as the situation itself demands. If an opiate-smoking caterpillar talks to her, she simply engages with it as best she can, trying to understand it entirely from within the fiction. She refrains from making the claim that the caterpillar, for example, could not exist because caterpillars do not smoke opium and cannot talk. When she does at the end finally employ an empirical category of thought, “O, you all are just a pack of cards!” she moves out of fictional reality back into empirical reality where she becomes a little girl once more. You could say that Alice’s employing that empirical category of thought is the very logical means by which she moves out of fictional reality back into empirical reality. We do the same every morning that we wake up out of a dream-state: “Whew, what a dream!” Now, the question arises, how am I able to say what I just said about Alice’s adventures in Wonderland? How am I able to speak about Alice’s fictional “I” and her empirical “I”, and her use or non-use of empirical categories of thought from 6 Lewis Carroll: Alice in Wonderland Page 3 of 9 within fictional reality? Alice does not talk in these terms at all and neither does the author, Lewis Carroll. I am able to approach Alice this way by virtue of the psychological difference operating in the background of my observations. Straightaway we can see that Giegerich’s formulation of the semantic-syntax difference within a soul phenomenon (here the text of Alice in Wonderland) comes alive through the background presence of the psychological difference. 7 I can thus pay attention not only to the content of the story but also to the background logical structure that forms the content in the first place. This “syntax” cannot be perceived but only thought. Once this implicit reality is “thought” (not thought “about” but “thought” in the sense of thinking its thinking), it can then be made explicit, as (what then becomes) reflected thought which communicates to others, who then may be able to “see” it too, when they next read Alice in Wonderland. This exercise in psychological phenomenology is only possible because the logical life of the soul “resides” today as the “syntax” of soul phenomena, not as the content or semantics. We have to learn how to read content as expressive of the syntax if we want to reach the soul of the real today. This is quite a mouthful and to arrive at such a conclusion regarding the logical status of soul today requires much study and effort. Yet, this conclusion lies at the heart of PDI. Everything else follows from this conclusion. It is not an article of faith. It is a conclusion! For now, let’s work from this conclusion for the purposes of this essay and once again turn to Liber Novus as a document of the soul. Liber Novus and the Psychological Difference Jung’s confrontation with the unconscious is obviously different from Alice’s encounters in Wonderland on the level of semantics, or content. What is not so obvious is that it is also entirely different on the level of syntax. The text of Alice’s adventures, when seen as a soul phenomenon, displays a structure of consciousness in which the empirical/fictional separation is maintained. This historically determined separation emerged with the scientific revolution, empirical reality being privileged as reality, and imaginal reality being downgraded to, well, fiction! The text (when viewed as a document of the soul) of Jung’s confrontation with the unconscious, on the other hand, shows something very strange happening— historically unheard-of. “Jung’s account” is the account given by an ego that from the start is logically exterior to the fictional images and thus could call them psychic facts, a description only possible to a consciousness for which empirical reality is the 7 (Giegerich, 2008, p. 30). This form of the psychological difference appears throughout Giegerich’s works. Page 4 of 9 privileged reality. So far, Jung is on the same level of logical structure as Lewis Carroll. The difference emerges when we note how Alice enters the fictional world by passively falling down the rabbit hole (she falls asleep), leaving the empirical world behind. Jung, on the other hand, in a deliberate and programmatic move, forces his way into the fictional, while leaving his categories of empirical reality intact. 8 I devised such a boring method [i.e. tunnelling] by fantasizing that I was digging a hole, and by accepting this fantasy as perfectly real. This is naturally somewhat difficult to do—to believe so thoroughly in a fantasy that it leads you into further fantasy, just as if you were digging a real hole… And: 9 Then a most disagreeable thing happened. Salome… began to worship me. I said, “Why do you worship me?” She replied, “You are Christ.” In spite of my objections she maintained this. I said, “This is madness,” and became filled with sceptical resistance. Alice moves smoothly between empirical and fictional reality, as we do when we fall asleep and dream. Like Alice, we normally do not need to persuade ourselves about the reality of the dream while we are dreaming. 10 Jung’s approach to fictional reality however requires his “having to accept it as real”, i.e., he has to convince himself, and it is difficult to do so. There is a doubt in place throughout. We can also see that, while Jung is engaging as one image to another, as might happen in a dream, he at the same time is also evaluating or interpreting the image “from the outside”, i.e., as an empirical ego would. The unheard-of move by Jung is that he employs empirical categories of thought while remaining, by an act of will, within the imaginal state. “Disagreeable”, “madness”, “sceptical resistance” are all evaluations that can be made only by an ego that has attained a form of consciousness we know as positivistic today, i.e., the modern empirical ego. 11 This is only one example and I recommend Giegerich’s analysis of The Red Book, for a conclusive discussion of this complex psychology at work. 12 8 (Jung, 1989, p. 47) Ibid: p. 96 10 I am aware of lucid dreaming having a different logic to normal dreaming. See footnote 11. 11 To gain a sustained, unremitting experience of this procedural move of Jung’s, see the movie, Inception (2009). 12 (Giegerich, 2010b, pp. 402-403) 9 Page 5 of 9 Jung enters his fantasies with the categories of external reflection, namely with the distinction between fantasy and reality. Inside his fantasies, he views them from the outside and doubts the reality of their figures. It is as if a novel tried to pull the rug out from under its characters as only imagined, or as if we, while dreaming, turned around to the wild animal or to the murderous criminal chasing us and said to them, “you are only symbols”. When approaching the text of Liber Novus as a soul phenomenon, as informed by the psychological difference, we thus get a startlingly different understanding of the nature of the Jungian unconscious. Far from recapitulating the qualities of soul life belonging to former times, as hoped for by subsequent generations of “Jungians”, the Jungian unconscious has the logical structure of a return to metaphysics under modern conditions of positivity: 13 The question emerges for us how and why the unconscious did come to be conceived as a natural object (thereby opening up the project of rescuing god or Meaning). The precondition was the great revolution from the metaphysical to the positivistic, scientistic stance at the beginning of the 19th century… the unconscious is the return… of the memory of and longing for metaphysics under the conditions of positivity [our modern form of consciousness—my insert]. This is a very complex structure of consciousness indeed but complexity should not lead to naive bids for simplicity. Instead, as psychologists of the soul, we should familiarize ourselves, with it, rise up to its demands, acquire the comprehension of it for ourselves, and learn to think its thinking. Consciousness of our Dissociated Structure We can see from a psychological phenomenological approach to Liber Novus that the background logical movements of soul life had determined the entire ordeal that Jung underwent as a sustained torture to the point of madness for many years. We must not forget that, in any evaluation we may make “from the armchair”, as it were, of Jung’s efforts, he was serving the interests of the soul from start to finish. But we are now in a position to inquire more deeply about what those soul interests were, rather than simply taking Jung’s word for it (Jung’s project). My own formulation of the soul movement involved in Jung’s confrontation with the unconscious is this: In thinking the semantic-syntactical structure of Liber Novus, we can comprehend two soul movements. One movement aims at recovering a lost past but in such a way that it needs to convince itself, thereby demonstrating that all along, it does not really believe in what it is doing. The 13 (Giegerich, 2004, p. 209) Page 6 of 9 other movement is a further development in the soul movement that Giegerich has elsewhere called the Christian moment in history. 14 This development may also be discerned in the same fear that gave rise to a longing for the return of metaphysics in the first place. The soul has distilled out of the reality that once could be best articulated by metaphysics. We human beings experience this shift as a loss of Meaning, the very Meaning that Jung, under the neurotic regressive pull of the soul itself, sought to recover in his particular conception of the unconscious psyche. Giegerich comments on this shift and our reaction to it: 15 With the disappearance of the metaphysical concept and definition of the soul the soul itself did not also disappear. It entered a different logical status. It is a positivistic fallacy to think that the negation of the metaphysical soul led simply to nothing at all.… The “dissolution into thin air” of the soul is a naturalistic picture of the soul’s transformation into a reality status that no longer is reflected in any substantial form at all (natural object, thing, even image-as-object—all these are metaphysical in their logic). The soul today is occluded or hidden in the very form of consciousness that we are today. We can apprehend its movements only “within” that form of consciousness, i.e., the realm of living thought. When kept in consciousness, the metaphysical return to “substance”, under conditions of positivity, along with the distillation of soul-life beyond substantiality altogether, constitute our modern structure of consciousness, as exemplified in the text of Liber Novus, when viewed as a document of the soul. The semantic-syntactical formulation demonstrates a very complex concept of modern soul-life. It takes some getting used to but it is possible to get used to it and even to live soulfully from within the living concept of the psychological difference. It is us, in our definition! We may begin for example, by paying attention to those habits of thought— conscious beliefs, ideals, etc. about ourselves and our modern age (freedom to choose, dignity of the human self, self-directedness, human rights, etc.) while, at the same time comprehending how they are immediately undermined by another, dissociated logical structure, at every turn, showing their unreality (the global economy, exploitation, oppression, surveillance, etc.) We could also give some attention to our unthinking allegiance to the Jungian unconscious and ask if Jung’s interpretation of his confrontation with the unconscious is the same thing as the logical structure (living logic, as which the 14 15 (Giegerich, 2007b) (Giegerich, 2012, p. 20) Page 7 of 9 phenomenon exists) of the text of The Red Book, when seen as a document of the soul. Nietzsche’s true greatness as a mouthpiece of his and our age can be found in his simple statement God is Dead, in which the content is undermined by the syntax just as quickly as it is said, demonstrating in one move the complexity of our modern consciousness and as well, the psychological difference. 16 16 See Giegerich’s essay: Saban’s Alternative: An Alternative? (2012), pp. 8-9 Page 8 of 9 Works Cited Giegerich, W. (2004). After Shamdasani. Spring 71, 193-213. ____________ (2007b). Collected English Papers Volume II: Technology and the Soul. New Orleans: Spring Journal Books. ____________ (2008). Collected English Papers Volume III: Soul Violence. New Orleans: Spring Journal Inc. ____________ (2010b). Liber Novis, that is, The New Bible, A First Analysis of C. G. Jung's Red Book. Spring 83, 361-413. ____________ (2010c). The Soul Always Thinks. New Orleans: Spring. ____________ (2012). What is Soul? New Orleans: Spring Journal Books. Jung, C. G. (1965). Memories, Dreams, Reflections. New York: Random House. __________ (1989). Analytical Psychology: Notes on the seminar given in 1925. (W. McGuire, Ed.) Princeton: Princeton University Press. __________ (2009). The Red Book. (S. Shamdasani, Ed., S. Shamdasani, M. Kyburz, & J. Peck, Trans.) New York: W.W. and Norton & Company. Tacey, D. (2010). Ecopsychology and the Sacred: The Psychological Basis of the Environmental Crisis. Spring 83, 329-353. Page 9 of 9