Entrenchment and the United Kingdom constitution A discussion paper Dr. Andrew Blick December 2014 At present the constitution of the United Kingdom (UK) is the subject of pronounced disagreement and upheaval. Devolution is expanding, in an uneven fashion, and prompting fierce debate in the process. Opinion is divided over crucial issues such as the protection of human rights, membership of the European Union, and even the continued existence of the UK. It may be that a significant systemic recasting is necessary. If the new arrangement is to be satisfactory to different groups and parties, and to prove lasting, it may be necessary overtly to make its existence firmer than previous such settlements, or to ‘entrench’ it. But how might this quality be achieved in the UK context? Certain core traditional principles of the UK constitution involving the authority of Parliament have an important bearing upon the concept of constitutional entrenchment. The first is the idea that the Westminster legislature can – subject only to practical and moral constraints – do as it sees fit. Second is that no one law, whatever the relative importance of its substance, is of a different status to any other. Parliament can do or undo anything, so the theory runs, by exactly the same procedure, with a majority of one always enough. It follows from these two concepts that an Act of Parliament takes precedence over any other legal source, including even all previous Acts of Parliament. If one statute conflicts with another, it is the later Act of Parliament that must prevail. This latter rule – it is traditionally asserted – applies whether the later legislation expressly repeals or amends the earlier, or if it does so without specifically stating this purpose. This later form of implicit supersession is encapsulated in the so-called ‘doctrine of implied repeal’). As A. V. Dicey put it, if the if the Dentists Act 1878 had happened ‘unfortunately [to] contravene the terms of the Act of Union, the Act of Union would be pro tanto repealed, but no judge would dream of maintaining that the Dentists Act 1878, was thereby rendered invalid or unconstitutional.’1 The concept of entrenchment, the idea that some legal provisions should have a special position and be to some extent insulated from change, or only altered in accordance with a heightened procedure, might not seem to fit with these principles. Generally entrenchment is achieved internationally in written constitutions, subject to amendment only if special requirements such as legislative supermajorities or approval through referendum are met, and upheld by a judiciary that is able to invalidate actions and even primary legislation that conflict with the fundamental text. The UK has no written constitution. Yet entrenchment in some forms has had a part in UK constitutional conceptions. Moreover, in recent times this role has grown. Some precedent for supermajorities, for instance, has appeared through the provision in section 2 of the Fixed-term Parliaments Act 2011 for early general elections following support from two-thirds or more of MPs. Section 96 of the Enterprise and Regulatory Reform Act 2013 provides in effect for the establishment by Royal Charter of a body (intended in turn to perform the task of recognising one or more press 1 A. V. Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (Indianapolis, Liberty Fund, 1982) 78. 1 regulators) the alteration or abolition of which can, in the terms under which the body is set up, be made subject to parliamentary approval through a supermajority. In other words, ministers are able, supported by the 2013 Act, to use the Royal Prerogative to entrench an entity as they create it. The stipulations contained in these 2011 and 2013 Acts suggest that the idea of heightened requirements for certain forms of action, and entrenchment of a kind, is gaining currency. Further evidence of this new perception came with the ‘Vow’ to Scottish voters in advance of the independence referendum made by the Prime Minister, Deputy Prime Minister and the Leader of the Opposition. It guaranteed that the Scottish Parliament and its powers would, following a ‘no’ vote, take on a new ‘permanent’ status.2 This commitment – which the Smith Commission has stated will be given a basis in legislation by the UK Parliament 3 – appears incongruous within a constitutional tradition according to which the UK Parliament can undo anything it has done – including, presumably, the Scotland Act 1998, the statutory source for the Scottish Parliament. Against the background of these recent developments, the following note discusses existing forms of entrenchment, and speculates about other mechanisms that could appear in future, if they are deemed necessary. Conventions In some instances provisions may be entrenched by a very strong convention, not legally binding, that they are absolutely core to the political system and therefore that Parliament should not contemplate tampering with them. One legal stipulation obviously falling within this category is the general principle of universal adult suffrage, currently contained within the Representation of the People Act 1983. In this case, entrenchment is the product of an historical process creating an assumption so deep and widely shared that it generally goes unstated. It is unthinkable in the foreseeable future that Parliament would seek in a serious way to override this value, though in theory it could do so (however, it might in the process violate European law and the European Convention on Human Rights [ECHR] as presently incorporated under the Human Rights Act 1998). In this instance, convention serves to protect a principle, rather than the particular legislation that expresses it. Other features of the constitution seemingly embedded by convention include the devolved institutions (with Scotland seemingly shortly to receive legislative recognition of its entrenchment, whatever the legal impact of this measure might be). It would probably be difficult to reverse the establishment of the UK Supreme Court. However, other constitutional statutes, such as the Human Rights Act 1998 and the Fixed-term Parliaments Act 2011, seem far more susceptible to change and do not enjoy the protection of convention. Finally, there is a broad convention that certain legislative acts should be subject to approval by referendum, either across the whole UK or in a particular territory. No comprehensive list exists however. In some cases, it is widely accepted that decisions previously endorsed by referendum, involving devolution and continued European Economic Community (now EU) membership, are only reversible if a similar vote For the text of the ‘Vow’, see Daily Record, 16 September 2014. The Smith Commission, Report of the Smith Commission for further devolution of powers to the Scottish Parliament (Edinburgh, The Smith Commission, 2014), 13. 2 3 2 takes place. Some hold that other decisions, such as the abolition of the monarchy or the House of Lords, would need to involve a referendum.4 The courts and entrenchment The courts can play a part in entrenching certain features of the constitution. This practice can take place when they carry out judicial review, assessing the legality of ministerial actions under primary legislation. In doing so they may apply principles that could be regarded as constitutional – such as the need for adherence to proper procedure – thereby ensuring that these values are to some extent entrenched. Courts also carry out human rights review under the Human Rights Act 1998. The Act requires them to read acts – whether passed before or after the 1998 Act – as far as possible as to render them compatible with the ECHR. The judiciary can in the process potentially wield a high degree of discretion in the interpretation it applies. If despite its best efforts the courts are unable to make the Act fit with the Convention, then they make a declaration of incompatibility. The offending Act remains in force, but so does the 1998 Act, which is consequently immune to implied repeal and in this sense entrenched. It is left to ministers and Parliament to resolve the discrepancy, though a convention is arguably emerging that they should in such circumstances accept the judgement of the courts and respond in the spirit of it. Another statute entrenched through immunity to implied repeal is the European Communities Act 1972. It has a harder status than the Human Rights Act in that the courts can, under the 1972 Act, disapply Acts – including those passed after it – in as far as they are not compatible with European law. Both the Human Rights and European Communities Act represent a challenge to view presented by Dicey of parliamentary sovereignty as rendering legal entrenchment impossible. Some members of the judiciary have expressed the view that parliamentary ‘sovereignty’ itself derives its force from common law. Consequently, according to this ‘common law constitutionalism’ school, the courts are the source of parliamentary authority, and are therefore able to place limits upon it, or perhaps reject it altogether. For instance they may decide that certain enactments are of a constitutional nature and should be subject only to express as opposed to implied amendment or repeal. In other words, the courts – so this theory runs – could decide that Parliament must make its intention positively clear if it is to alter certain earlier statutes it has produced, even if these previous Acts do not specify that they are protected in this way.5 Perhaps legislation providing for devolution might fall within this category of statute that was not on the surface immune to implied repeal, but which a judge could decide a later Parliament could only change using precise terms. This theory, were it put into practice, would seem to imply the courts reading an implicit intention into some legislation that prevented it from inferring another implied purpose from later Acts. A variant on this theory might hold that amendment and repeal of statutes deemed constitution might not require express words, but would at least need to make the conclusion that such alteration was needed hard to avoid. Legislative barriers 4 See: House of Lords Select Committee on the Constitution, Referendums in the United Kingdom HL 99 (Stationery Office: London, 2010) 27. 5 The most celebrated expression of this view came in obiter comments made by Lord Justice Laws in the Thoburn or ‘Metric Martyrs’ case. [2002] EWHC 195 (Admin) para. 102. 3 The above forms of entrenchment do not prevent a resolute Parliament from achieving particular objectives, especially if it is willing to do so using express terms, which could overturn even the Human Rights Act and European Communities Act. However, further obstacles exist, potentially creating difficulties for Parliament if it sought to produce certain types of statute or achieve particular objectives. The Parliament Act 1911, as amended by the Parliament Act 1949, provides for a form of entrenchment. It made it easier for Parliament to legislate in most possible ways through creating a mechanism (used on seven occasions to date) for the House of Commons ultimately to have the last word in a dispute with the House of Lords, circumventing the second chamber and presenting a bill for Royal Assent notwithstanding resistance from the second chamber. The 1911 Act also ended any Lords powers whatsoever over money bills. This system utilises certification by the Speaker of the House of Commons. But certain bills are exempt from the Parliament Act bypass procedure, most notably those that have the effect of extending the life of a Parliament beyond five years (section 2 [1]). In this sense, the maximum duration of a Parliament is entrenched, since it is subject to the same protection of a potential Lords veto that once applied to all legislation. The European Union Act 2011 creates a whole class of parliamentary action – in relation to the pooling of powers at EU level – which is subject to approval by referendum (part I). However, it seems that Parliament could amend or repeal this Act using normal legislative processes, ending this requirement for a plebiscite, without first holding a referendum. Stipulations surrounding the possible departure of Northern Ireland from the UK, involving a referendum, are also provided for in statute, the Northern Ireland Act 1998 (section 1 and schedule 1). While Parliament could repeal this Act, to do so unilaterally would seem to entail violation of a treaty, the Belfast (or ‘Good Friday’) Agreement, of which the 1998 Act is an expression. In this sense, this particular provision, or at least the content it contains, is entrenched under international law. Judicial non-recognition An extreme form of the ‘common law constitutionalism’ model discussed above, that holds judicial decisions to be the source of the authority of Parliament, proposes that there are certain constitutional principles so fundamental that a court should refuse to recognise as law any attempt by Parliament to abrogate them.6 Such proscribed measures might include the abolition of judicial review or the mandating of torture, the prohibition of which is a principle that long predates the existence of the ECHR. It is also possible that a court might not recognise an attempt to bypass the Parliament Act precaution against extensions in the duration of a Parliament, through first using the Parliament Act to force through a bill removing this protection, then – having abolished the prohibition – using the same power to prolong a Parliament. These projected scenarios would amount to a major clash between ministers and Parliament on the one hand and judiciary on the other hand, meriting the label ‘constitutional crisis’. There are some other types of legislation that would certainly fail to receive judicial recognition, this time by courts outside the UK. Parliament might try, if it chose, to 6 See: Jackson and others (appellants) v. Her Majesty’s Attorney General (Respondent), [2005] UKHL. 4 amend or repeal Acts of Parliament providing for the autonomy of former colonies, such as the Canada Act 1982, which included the Canadian constitution as a schedule and pronounced the ‘Termination of power to legislate for Canada’ for the UK Parliament (section 2). A Canadian court would surely not accept any unilateral effort by the Westminster Parliament in this direction. Here, then, is a class of entrenched legislation. One interpretation of the reason for this special status is that a new consensus has emerged across different branches of government in the territories concerned. Where once the accepted ‘rule of recognition’ was that an Act of Parliament had supremacy over all other law, the new common understanding is that the written constitution is the ultimate source of authority.7 The Union: a fundamental provision? The Treaty and Acts of Union between Scotland and England of 1706-7 provide further perspectives on the concept of entrenchment. First, the text appears to seek to be self-entrenching, repeatedly describing itself as permanent through the use of terms such as ‘forever after’ (see eg: article I). Furthermore, and perhaps more importantly, since the union provided for the existence of a new Parliament of Great Britain, (article III), how can a Parliament interfere with an instrument in which its own authority is founded? However, Parliament has since successfully altered some of the perhaps less central terms of the union through regular legislative procedures. Whether a more substantial amendment or repeal is possible through this means has remained a subject of debate, which the judiciary has been careful to leave open.8 This issue received surprisingly little attention in the period prior to the Scottish independence referendum of September 2014. Yet it would have been reasonable to ask whether, in the event of Scotland voting ‘yes’, Parliament would have had the strict legal authority to put this decision into effect. An aggrieved party might well have brought litigation to probe this area of uncertainty. It is notable that it is generally accepted that a referendum is required for a break-up of the union, perhaps a tacit acknowledgment that full repeal of the Treaty and Acts of Union requires, for practical even if not legal reasons, something more than a normal Act of Parliament. If, however, the Treaty and Acts of Union have failed to achieve entrenchment simply through statements to this effect, it is reasonable to ask whether this course of action, seemingly envisaged by The Smith Commission, will be any more successful with respect to the Scottish Parliament and Government. Options The options for entrenchment of constitutional provisions or principles, therefore, would seem to be: The attempted establishment of a convention around the permanence or semipermanence of given measures or values, perhaps through a joint declaration agreed by multiple parties. However, it could always in theory be overridden by an Act of Parliament, with probably only political rather than legal consequences. 7 See: Jeffrey Goldsworthy, Parliamentary Sovereignty: Contemporary Debates (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2010). 8 See eg: N. MacCormick, ‘Does the United Kingdom have a Constitution? Reflections on MacCormick v. Lord Advocate (1978) 29 1 Northern Ireland Law Quarterly; T B Smith, ‘The Union of 1707 as Fundamental Law’ (1957) 99 Public Law. 5 New processes whereby Parliament can identify for itself legislation of constitutional significance and apply procedures it deems appropriate to it. The courts might then take into account the view of Parliament that a particular Act is constitutionally important when deciding whether or not it is subject to implied repeal by a subsequent piece of primary legislation.9 Inclusion of additional protected provisions in the Parliament Act, or in a similar statute. This method may be vulnerable to reversal by a determined House of Commons, and intervention from the courts might prove necessary to seek to prevent such action. Protection from implied repeal, using the Human Rights Act or the European Communities Act as a model, with the judiciary playing an enforcement role. Self-entrenchment of the type the Treaty and Acts of Union apparently seek to achieve, though perhaps not successfully, by simply stating that they are in force forever. To seek more security, an Act might impose a super-majority or referendum requirement upon amendments to itself, or an Act might stipulate similar procedures for the amendment or repeal of another Act or Acts. In another territory without a written constitution, New Zealand, the Electoral Act 1993 (section 268) makes certain provisions in the Constitution Act 1986, involving elections, subject to heightened procedures. A UK entrenchment measure might also provide for a body created under other powers, such as the recognition body referred to in the Enterprise and Regulatory Reform Act, that can in turn contain in its own terms of incorporation protection through supermajority or perhaps referendum. Yet it remains possible that Parliament could repeal the provision for such protections using ordinary legislative processes. The courts may, once more, become the adjudicator in such circumstances. To rely on common law protections. This course of action seemingly leaves excessive discretion to the judiciary in defining what are the entrenched provisions, and perhaps invites destabilising constitutional conflict. The final option is to seek to establish a new ‘rule of recognition’, such as that which has arguably taken hold in former UK colonies. This could make possible the entrenchment of one or more constitutional provisions that were no longer subject to alteration, either express or implicit, by Act of Parliament, at least using its regular processes. Amendment might require a legislative supermajority, referendum, or perhaps approval from a specified number of nations and regions of the UK. Achieving this fundamental status would require a process commanding such legitimacy that it would be able to create a ‘rule of recognition’ supplanting notions of parliamentary ‘sovereignty.’ A constitutional convention, separate from Parliament but incorporating parliamentarians, alongside representatives of the regions and nations of the UK, as well as members of the public possibly chosen at random, might be an 9 See: Andrew Blick, David Howarth and Nat le Roux, Distinguishing Constitutional Legislation: A modest proposal (London, The Constitution Society, 2014). 6 appropriate vehicle for achieving such an outcome. Its end product would resemble at least to some extent a written constitution for the UK. Andrew Blick Lecturer in Politics and Contemporary British History Institute of Contemporary British History King’s College London 7