CSMN workshop on Adam Smith and Virtue CSMN, Oslo, Thursday and Friday, August 27/28, 2015 Workshop Venue: University of Oslo, Blindern Campus, Georg Morgenstiernes Hus, room 652 Adam Smith and Virtue Current debates on the nature of human morality have led to a revival of interest in neo-Aristotelian virtue ethics. However, it was not only in ancient times that thinking about the virtues was high on the agenda of moral philosophy. It also played an important part in the moral thought of the Scottish Enlightenment. CSMN is hosting a workshop in which participants explore Adam Smith’s moral thought and the role he attributes to the virtues. His virtue theory takes the shape of a kind of reflective sentimentalism and represents a contribution to our understanding of human morality that still deserves our interest. Organizers: Julia Annas and Christel Fricke ABSTRACTS (in order of presentation) Aaron Garrett (Boston): The Irregularity of Sentiments and the Goals of Moral Theorizing – Hume and Smith on Strength of Mind In this essay I will argue that Smith recognizes the errors of his predecessors Hutcheson and Hume in overstepping what a moral theory ought to do: They make questionable assumptions about providence and the moral sense that make for a coherent moral theory at the cost of a credible one. Smith adopts a different route, to restrict the goals of moral theorizing to moral psychology and to reject both meta-ethical theorizing and the ultimate unity of normative explanations. Hence the importance of the irregularity of the sentiments. Sveinung Sivertsen (Bergen): Love redirected: how the love of being praiseworthy can arise from the love of praise In his book Adam Smith and the Character of Virtue (2009), Ryan Patrick Hanley, like many other recent commentators on Smith’s The Theory of Moral Sentiments, points to Smith's statements about man being endowed, “not only with a desire of being approved of, but with a desire of being what ought to be approved of” (TMS III.2.7, 136), as an important piece in the puzzle of Smith's normative argument. But if it really is the case that the normative reading of Smith's model of moral judgement “rests on his postulation of a love of praiseworthiness both logically and temporally prior to a love of praise,” as Hanley puts it in connection with the distinction between being and seeming (2009, 140), then it appears that Smith is merely positing his way out of the worry that his model is merely descriptive or, if normative, relativistic. If one could avoid positing an original desire for being praiseworthy and show instead how such a desire can arise in moral development, this might be a way of strengthening the normative, non-relativistic reading of TMS. It is my aim in the present paper to show that this can be done, and it is my working hypothesis that one can combine this argument with Hanley's argument about the role of virtues in TMS. Christel Fricke (Oslo, CSMN): The Virtue of Impartiality – On the Nature of Adam Smith’s Moral Theory According to Smith, the moral judge is or should be an ‘impartial spectator’. ‘Impartiality’ can be understood both as a virtue and a character trait. But it is a character trait of a judge rather than that of an agent; it is manifest in proper moral judgments. These judgments are action guiding. But Smith’s account of these judgments is independent of whether or not there 1 any actual actions that are guided by them. Thus, Adam Smith’s moral theory is hybrid in kind: It combines elements of virtue theory (the conception of morality as an ideal and the account of moral motivation in terms of the search for a good life) with elements of modern moral theory such as deontology or utilitarianism (the focus on the moral judgment and the justification of its claims to universality). Adam Smith’s moral theory challenges the all too common categorical distinction between virtue theory on the one hand and modern moral theories on the other. Nir Ben-Moshe (University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign): Adam Smith and the Possibility of Universal Virtue In this paper, I examine the possibility of universal virtue in the context of a spectator-based account of moral judgment. In particular, I defend a novel account of Adam Smith's "impartial spectator" as the standard of correctness for moral judgment. I make use of a complexity in Smith’s conceptualization of the relations between sympathy and approbation, as well as a new interpretation of his use of reflective endorsement, in order to sketch an account of a modestly idealized, impartial standpoint which constitutes the appropriate conditions for moral judgments, making the objects of our patterns of approval approvable (worthy-ofapproval) and our moral judgments correct. In order to avoid circularity, I provide a developmental story that demonstrates how the standpoint of the impartial spectator is constructed from the bottom up, from agents’ sympathetic reactions and patterns of approval towards an impartial point of view. Once the standard is in place, these agents can also work from the top down, from their judgments of what is morally appropriate and inappropriate towards reshaping and broadening their sympathetic reactions. I conclude by explaining how the standpoint of the impartial spectator can determine virtue in a manner that transcends personal and societal points of view. Jack Russell Weinstein (North Dakota): Are Virtues Spontaneous? In Adam Smith's Pluralism (Yale UP, 2013), I argue that moral sentiments are rational, and subject to critical thinking and revision. Rational sentiments allow a deeper connection between the moral actor and the community while still preserving moral independence. They also support a moral progressivism that leads to historical improvement. In response, Craig Smith argues that my account is "troubling" because it suggests that "for Smith the rules of morality are not spontaneous." In this paper, I seek to examine his objection, calling into doubt the role of spontaneous order in Smith's corpus. The paper will be divided into two sections. The first will look at the coherence of spontaneous order itself, contrasting it with natural law, constitutional governance, and Smith's stadial approach to history. The second will ask how deep spontaneity must go to integrate it into Smith's moral theory. In the process, I will examine what spontaneous order might mean for the virtues and the moral sentiments.Sveinung Sivertsen (Bergen): Love redirected: how the love of being praiseworthy can arise from the love of praise Ryan Hanley (Marquette): Adam Smith on Self-Command That Adam Smith held the virtue of self-command in high regard is well known. Less well understood is why Smith held self-command in such high regard. This paper argues that Smith’s interest in self-command derives from his recognition of its unique capacity to further three related yet discrete elements of his ethical project: utility, dignity, and sympathy. First, self-command plays an indispensible role in promoting the individual’s self-interested efforts to maximize her utility. In part, these utility-maximizing 2 efforts aim at material goods. But Smith also thinks that self-command plays a key role in maximizing our pursuits of other non-material external goods, such as esteem and tranquility. Second, Smith values self-command for the opportunities it provides to individuals to exercise their capacities as dignified beings. In this sense, self-command plays a crucial role both in Smith’s substantive concept of dignity and in his concern to develop mechanisms whereby individuals can pursue the realization of their authentic selves – a side of Smith’s moral psychology that has not been often emphasized. Third, Smith values self-command for its capacity to support the bonds of a society built on sympathy and dedicated to equality. In this sense, self-command not only promotes individual well-being but also plays a social and political role. And herein lies one of the most interesting sides of Smithean self-command. Where classical theories of self-command often emphasize insensibility to all passions, including sentiments towards others, Smithean self-command discriminates between sentiments. One of Smith’s key claims on this front is that self-command properly understood is capable of encouraging at once insensibility to self as well as sensibility to others – a capacity of self-command that renders it particularly suited to modern polities committed to equality. Reconsidering Smithean self-command through these three lenses of utility, dignity, and sympathy can help us better understand Smith’s reasons for so highly admiring selfcommand, even within the context of the modern commercial state. Lisa Hill (Adelaide): The Poor Man’s Son and the Corruption of Our Moral Sentiments: Commerce, Virtue and Happiness in Adam Smith In this paper I respond to the view that, contrary to the popular perception, Adam Smith was sceptical about the value of material acquisition. I also explore whether he believed that the pursuit of virtue –especially beneficence--offers a superior route to happiness than the commercial world of materialist acquisition. I approach these issues partly by considering the role of beneficence in Smith’s system but primarily by analysing the story of the poor man’s son related in Book IV of The Theory of Moral Sentiments. As he narrates this story, Smith seems highly critical of the unrelenting drive for worldly success. But what is the real moral of the story? Should people contain their ambitions for recognition and material success and pursue virtue instead? By way of answering this question I suggest that Smith does not really go this far; nevertheless, his discussion in and around the story of the poor man’s son points to a significant tension between his personal ideal of happiness and his observations and recommendations as a social scientist. Smith seems to be suggesting that, while society may be able to thrive without classical virtue, individual agents fare less happily in its absence. But whether this resolves the tension adequately is unclear. Aino Lahdenranta (Boston/Jyväskylä): Smith’s solution to Hume’s puzzle concerning justice There is a large debate about the relevant motive in Hume’s account of artificial virtue. Is it enlightened self-love, blind rule-following, or sense of moral duty that motivates just acts and gains our approval? In this paper, I examine Smith’s answer to the same question. For Smith, vicarious resentment provides a completely natural foundation for the norms of justice but the question of motive remains. I claim that with respect to motivation justice turns out to be more artificial than the other virtues. Namely, fear of blame-worthiness must play a direct motivational role in the uniform observance of justice whereas living up to the other virtues is bound to be a matter of cultivating natural passions. I also argue that defining justice in negative terms is the key move that allows Smith to stay true to a sentimentalist understanding of virtue and vice. 3