VIRTUAL RESEARCH ASSISTANT PROJECT RESEARCH BRIEF PROVIDED: It involved the question whether an unmarried father has any say or ought to be consulted in the adoption of his child. It is an opportunity to continue the discourse on permissible grounds of discrimination and an opportunity to revisit the reasoning in Mmusi and Others v Ramantele and Another, particularly the so called rule of practice that courts should be slow to determine issues on constitutional grounds when it is possible to do so on non-constitutional grounds. COUNTRY Botswana DATE COMPLETED 3 November 2014 CONTENTS I. Introduction ......................................................................................... 3 II. The Mey Case ....................................................................................... 4 III. Whether the applicant is entitled to the relief sought? ......................... 9 Unmarried Fathers in the 2009 Children’s Act ....................................... 10 The best interests of the child ................................................................ 25 Discrimination ....................................................................................... 30 Inhuman and degrading treatment ......................................................... 42 Right to a fair hearing ............................................................................ 44 IV. Non-constitutional grounds .............................................................. 47 The Mmusi/Ramantele Decisions .......................................................... 47 In the High Court - Mmusi .................................................................. 49 In the Court of Appeal - Ramantele ......... Error! Bookmark not defined. V. Concluding remarks ........................................................................... 55 2 I. INTRODUCTION To take the power of interrogating the Constitution away from the High Court (a superior court of record with unlimited original jurisdiction to hear and determine any criminal and civil cases under any law) is tantamount to leaving the people of a nation waiting for Superman to solve their very real problems. In this instance the applicant, Mr. Geofrey Khwarae is challenging section 4(2)(d)(i) of the Adoption of Children Act, insofar as it does not require his consent for the adoption of his child just because she was born out of wedlock. Mr Khwarae does not have time to wait for Superman, his daughter’s future lies in the balance and there is a very real possibility that the adoption process that may have been commenced without his consultation and/or consent could proceed and thereby permanently remove his hope to access his child. The applicant has framed his petition to the Court in terms of the Constitutionality of the section concerned and seeks to establish the rights of unmarried fathers to be granted equal recognition in the matter of consenting to the adoption of their children. Not all unmarried biological fathers will have a functional relationship with their child; but denying loving, functional fathers the opportunity to legally formalise their parental relationship is patently unfair to the children and men involved. “If an unwed father is ignored or given much less protection in the adoption process than other parents, his challenge to this treatment forces the Court to identify what elements in parent-child relationships make them worthy of constitutional protection. Only then can the Court 3 decide whether the unwed father's interests are entitled to protection.”1 In her analysis of court decisions on the issue, Buchanan summarised the prevailing tendency as follows: “unwed fathers who are presently exercising or have in the past exercised custodial responsibilities for their children have a constitutional interest in retaining the relationship established by their exercise of custody, and this interest is equivalent to the interests of other parents in their children.”2 II. THE MEY CASE In Mey v. July (the Mey case),3 the respondent Joshua July, the biological father of the little girl referred to as Angel, improperly obtained a High Court order declaring Angel to be a child in need of care when he discovered that her adoptive mother (a South African national) sought to leave the country with her. The child was removed from her home and placed amongst strangers at Child Line Botswana. The respondent was then given supervised access to the child, privileges that he had not previously enjoyed since he had no ongoing interaction with the child prior to that time. As a result of his appeals to the court, the little girl known as Angel was removed from her parents and her brother. Yet, as Lesetedi JA rightly pointed out: “it was never shown at any stage that these interim orders and the removal of Elizabeth Buchanan (1984) “The Constitutional Rights of Unwed Fathers Before and After Lehr v. Robertson” 45 Ohio State Law Journal 313, 318. 1 2 Buchanan, n1 above, 333. 3 CACGB-134-13, High Court Case No. UAHGB000072-12 (unreported). 4 the child from its legal parent or her guardian was in the best interest of the minor child.”[Para 47]. It is noteworthy that Lesetedi JA mentions the lack of a bond or relationship between the respondent and his biological daughter. “[I]t is evident from the respondent’s affidavit … that he had no bond with Angel who was now four years old. He had only seen the child once or twice in its first year of life but had not seen the child at any stage thereafter. … He had at no time assisted the appellant in any way in upbringing the child… he never took any legal steps to assert a right of access to the child until the last moment when he heard that the appellant was relocating from the jurisdiction.” [Para 13]. In terms of his application for the rescission of the adoption the court correctly pointed out that Mr July would have had to show that “he was a parent of the child as contemplated under Section 8(1)(a) of the [Adoption] Act and secondly, that the order of the adoption should not have been made without his consent. As pointed out earlier, the Adoption Act did not require his consent, so that the second requirement could not be shown. Since he based his rights on the Children’s Act No. 8 of 2009, he still had to show that he was a parent whose consent was required in terms of that Act.” [Para 60] The Court pointed out that: "Under section 121 of the current Children's Act, the repealed Act is deemed for those purposes to have been valid and to continue until the adoption was finalized. 5 Under the repealed Act there is no definition of a parent and in terms of the common law the consent of the father of a child born out of wedlock has no parental rights over that child. The new Children's Act No. 8 of 2009 does not in any of its provisions require the consent of the biological father of a child born out of wedlock to be a condition precedent to the adoption of the child. The Act gives such father greater rights of involvement in the child's upbringing and outlines in detail his duties. To that extent it does not conflict with or override the Adoption Act. What flows from the Children's Act of 2009 is that the father would now expect to be consulted if he had hitherto involved himself in the life of the child. His views and the nature and extent of his involvement in the child's welfare and upbringing would then be factors to be taken into account in deciding the totality of every relevant consideration whether the adoption would be in the child's best interests." [Para 61, emphasis added]. The court determined that the only recourse (aside from showing that he had locus standi in terms of law to bring the rescission of adoption application if his consent were necessary before the adoption order was made) would have been for the respondent to set out why the adoption was to the detriment of the child. None of these averments were made in the affidavits and for that reason alone he ought to have been non-suited to seek the reliefs he sought. The court ruled that in all matters involving the welfare of minor children “the court should always be astute to ensure that there are always compelling reasons, not mere unsupported allegations by a party to the litigation who has not yet established a prima facie right to custody of the child, advanced to interrupt the child’s present situation or circumstance. A 6 matter such as the present requires to be approached with caution to avoid the abuse of the judicial process by a litigant to gain an unfair advantage over another party for reasons which have little to do with the best interests of the minor child.” In closing the ruling the court referred once again to the lack of parental interest that the respondent had shown prior to launching the “purported appeal”: “for three years the respondent remained supine and made no attempt to assert his legal rights to have access to and bond with the minor child. This was the time at which the child was opening its eyes to the world, and for the respondent to later after the passage of several years seek to assert his rights on urgency, thereby disrupting the child’s ordered life for his own convenience without demonstrating that the child’s then situation was anything but well ordered and stable, was opportunistic and an abuse of judicial process.”[Para 78] In this way the Court of Appeal once more underscored the primacy of the best interests of the child. However, the Court also introduced the possibility for an unmarried father to assert and obtain recognition of his legal rights as a parent. In essence the Court relies upon the enhanced role awarded to fathers under the Children’s Act of 2009, which would not have been applicable to the respondent whose matter commenced prior to the Act. In its lieu the Court points to the lack of an effort to forge a relationship with his daughter. This view is suggestive of the approach that the American Courts have taken in establishing that where the unmarried father can show that there was a relationship with the child, there arises a right to parenthood that is worthy of constitutional protection. 7 “When unwed fathers have voluntarily failed to perform the custodial responsibilities that give rise to constitutional protection for parental rights, the state need not consider their interests because they are not of constitutional stature. Sometimes, however, the father does develop a relationship with his child that evidences a full commitment to all parental responsibilities, but cannot assume all of the responsibilities because the mother's interests conflict with his. Such a father cannot rely on a claim to equal treatment because his relationship with his child is not the same as that of other parents. Nevertheless, consideration of the values underlying constitutional protection for parent-child relationships leads to the conclusion that such a father's relationship is a protected one.”4 The key distinction between the Mey case and the Khwarae situation is that the adoption proceedings in the Mey case were commenced before the Children's Act of 2009 came into force. The respondent had attempted to rely upon the definition of parent provided in the 2009 Act as the grounds for seeking relief, in an attempt to show that his consent was required for the adoption to take place. The Court decreed that this approach was erroneous for two reasons: firstly that the adoption proceedings commenced in early 2009, before the commencement of the Children's Act on 19 June 2009; and secondly, under the Children's Act of 2009 he could be consulted if he was involved in the child's life but his consent was still not required. [Paras 61-62]. The Court reiterates the lack of the need for the unmarried father’s consent for an adoption to occur and avers that instead that the Children’s Act 4 Buchanan, n 1 above, 351. 8 confers a right to have been consulted where the father was involved in the child’s life. It is this second point that has been raised by the Attorney General. It is opined that the Court’s position highlights the existence of due process rights that are established under the provisions, objectives and spirit of the Children’s Act. The nature and the scope of the father’s right to be consulted must be explored. Even when the minimum acceptable standard is consultation, this consultation must be in good faith and with the intention of substantially addressing the concerns of the unmarried father whose child’s future is at issue.5 III. WHETHER THE APPLICANT IS ENTITLED TO THE RELIEF SOUGHT? The applicant is challenging Section 4(2)(d)(i) of the Adoption of Children Act, insofar as it does not require his consent for the adoption of his child just because she was born out of wedlock. In his arguments, the applicant seeks to rely upon three constitutional protections – freedom from discrimination (section 15); freedom from inhuman and degrading treatment under (section 7); and, the right to a fair hearing (section 10(9)). His second argument is that section 4(2)(d)(i) of the Adoption Act conflicts with the Children’s Act of 2009 and based on the terms of the Children’s Act, Section Internationally Courts have debated the right to consultation within the context of Aboriginal lands and have held that the right to be consulted may in some cases require the full consent of the Aboriginal peoples whose lands are at issue (see Delgamuukw v. British Columbia [1997] 3 S.C.R. 1010; Sonia Lawrence & Patrick Mackelm (2000) “From consultation to reconciliation: Aboriginal rights and the Crown’s duty to consult” 79 Canadian Bar Review 252) 5 9 4(2)(d)(i) should require the father’s consent to adoption subject to the best interest of the child. UNMARRIED FATHERS IN THE 2009 CHILDREN’S ACT The progressive drafting of the Children's Act of 2009 recognises the unmarried father as a parent and accedes that there is a relationship between him and his offspring - with the exception of those children sired through rape or incest. The current Children’s Act with its enhanced acknowledgment of the parental role of unmarried biological fathers would seem to suggest that some biological fathers hold protected rights regarding the parent-child relationship. Especially as seen from the perspective of the child and their best interests which are to be considered paramount in all decisions concerning children. The Children’s Act defines the parent to include biological parents (no distinction is made on the basis of marital status) with the exception of those biological fathers whose children were sired through an act of rape or incest with the biological mother. The stated objectives of the Act include acknowledgement of the “primary responsibility of parents … to care for and protect children, and to support and assist them in carrying out that responsibility.” 6 The issue of discrimination arises in the context of the child, the guiding principles of the Children’s Act prohibit decisions or actions whose result or likelihood is to discriminate against the child on the basis of their parents or any other status – this prohibition feasibly extends 6 Section 4(d). 10 to discrimination upon the basis of so-called illegitimacy. The guiding principles also vest the primary responsibility for safeguarding and promoting the child’s wellbeing in the hands of the parents.7 The Act contains a Bill of Child Rights to supplement the rights set out in Chapter II of the Constitution. These rights include the right to a birth certificate indicating the name and particulars of the biological father “whether the child is born in or out of wedlock.”8 Most powerful in relation to Mr Khwarae is the right enshrined in section 13 of the Children’s Act: the child’s right to know and be cared for by both biological parents; and the corresponding duties that the Act places upon the biological parents under section 27: the primary duty being to care for and maintain a child. Section 28 goes further and outlines the rights of every parent, including those of the unmarried father, these rights (subject to the best interests of the child) include the right to: have the child live with them; be involved in the child’s upbringing; and to participate in court and other proceedings relating to his child. The Children’s Act has established that the unmarried father may no longer be categorically excluded from the legal definitions of "parent" and thus must participate in legal proceedings concerning the future of his child. Although there has been some speculation as to the relevance of comparative case law in deciding local cases, there is much to be learned 7 Sections 7(a) & 7(c). 8 Section 12(4) 11 from the ways in which Courts around the world have grappled with similar judicial cases. Whilst keeping clear consideration of the local context within which the facts of the case arise. Currently, unmarried fathers in England receive protection only when they embrace fatherhood or express commitment to their children’s mothers. The general rule is that where a family tie exists between parent and child, then the state must act in a manner that allows that tie to be developed. Failure to do so will amount to a breach of article 8 of the European Convention on Human Rights (the European Convention). Article 8 of the European Convention recognises the right to respect for family life. The European Court of Human Rights (ECHR) has interpreted the fundamental right of Article 8 to be access of a family member to children, opining that “the mutual enjoyment by parent and child, as well as by grandparent and child, of each other’s company constitutes a fundamental element of family life, and domestic measures hindering such enjoyment amount to an interference with the right protected by Article 8 of the Convention.” In other words, Article 8, incorporated into English law, protects parents’ and grandparents’ access to children.9 There are a number of cases that illustrate the point in relation to unmarried fathers and adoption. In Keegan v Ireland10 an unmarried couple living together planned to have a child. Shortly after the child was conceived Maragaret Ryznar (2009) “Two to tango, one in limbo: A comparative analysis of fathers’rights in infant adoptions” 47 Duquesne Law Review 89, 102. 9 10 (1994) 18 EHRR 342. 12 the relationship broke down. The father saw his baby once. The child was placed for adoption without his knowledge or consent. He applied to be appointed the child’s guardian, but by the time his application came to be decided the child had formed bonds with the prospective adopters and could not be moved without damage to her welfare. The ECHR considered that the relationship between the parents, and hence between the father and child had the hallmark of family life. The state was required to act in a manner calculated to enable the tie between parent and child to be developed. Legal safeguards were required to render possible the child’s integration with her family. The Court held that secret placement of a child for adoption amounted to an interference with the father’s right to respect for family life. No reasons relevant to the welfare of the child had been advanced to justify such a departure from the principles that governed respect for family ties. S. v The Adoption Board:11 the Court held that in establishing whether family life exists as between a natural father and his child it is apparent that the Court will adopt a pragmatic approach in identifying the necessary personal ties. If this relationship exists, a very high threshold must be reached to demonstrate that those ties have been extinguished by subsequent events. If a natural father who enjoys family life with his child is deprived of any participation in adoption proceedings this may or may not result in a finding of a breach of Article 8. It will have to be established, in the context of the specific case, whether such a decision to exclude him was “in accordance with the law”, pursued a “legitimate aim” and whether it was “necessary in a 11 [2009] IEHC 429. 13 democratic society”, in the sense of being a proportionate measure in the circumstances. It is clear that a child’s interests may override that of a natural parent. It appears that in the U.K. a high threshold must be met before the participation of a natural father is ruled out. The first step is to determine whether family life under Article 8 of the Convention exists as between the father and the child. A balancing exercise is then undertaken weighing the rights of the mother, father and the child or children of that relationship. It is clear that there may be instances where it would be inappropriate to notify him or to join him to the proceedings. However, these instances appear to be extreme cases. 12 In Re H; Re G (Adoption: Consultation of Unmarried Fathers),13 in the first case, the parents had had a relationship, including cohabitation, which had lasted for several years and the father had shown continuing commitment to the elder child. The father was therefore entitled to respect for a family life with the child under Art 8(1) of the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms 1950. The court held that to place the child for adoption without notice to the father would prima facie be in breach of this right, and in accordance with Art 6(1) and under r 15(3) of the Adoption Rules 1984, the father should be given notice and made a respondent with the opportunity to be heard. In contrast, in the second case, the facts were less strong. The parents had never cohabited and their 12 13 S. v The Adoption Board [2009] IEHC 429, para 8.14 [2001] 1 FLR 646. 14 relationship did not have sufficient constancy to show de facto family ties. Consequently, the relationship did not come within the concept of family life within Art 8 and the father therefore had no right to respect for family life. It was not necessary for him to be given notice or joined as a respondent to the proceedings. The English Courts placed significance on the relationship between the parents to establish the existence of family ties. The United States Supreme Court has protected fathers’ legal rights mostly through the Equal Protection and Due Process Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment. Although the parent-child relationship is therefore recognised to merit protection, this protection is conditioned on certain specific circumstances that trigger it.14 The legislative response to the conundrum has been to establish putative father registries, state-specific databases that allow men to register the names of their sexual partners so as to receive notification if these women both become pregnant and place their babies for adoption.15 Generally in the USA, the father's status as the biological parent of the child is not enough to grant him a protected parental interest. He must also have displayed, at the earliest possible moment, an interest in taking responsibility for his child, and he must have acted upon that interest in a timely manner. Essentially, he must have established a relationship with the child to the greatest extent possible under the 14 Ryznar, n 9 above, 90. 15 Ryznar, n 9 above, 95. 15 circumstances. It is this parent-child bond and nothing less that, according to the Court, deserves constitutional protection.16 The Courts in the United States have grappled with the question of the rights of putative fathers. In the 1972 case of Stanley v. Illinois, 17 Joan Stanley lived with Peter Stanley intermittently for 18 years, during which time they had three children. When Joan Stanley died, Peter Stanley lost not only her but also his children. Under Illinois law, the children of unwed fathers become wards of the State upon the death of the mother. Accordingly, upon Joan Stanley's death, in a dependency proceeding instituted by the State of Illinois, Stanley's children were declared wards of the State and placed with court-appointed guardians. Stanley appealed, claiming that he had never been shown to be an unfit parent and that since married fathers and unwed mothers could not be deprived of their children without such a showing, he had been deprived of the equal protection of the laws guaranteed him by the Fourteenth Amendment. The Supreme Court held that the State of Illinois was barred, as a matter of both due process and equal protection, from taking custody of the children of an unwed father, absent a hearing and a particularised finding that the father was an unfit parent. The Court concluded, on the one hand, that a father's interest in the "companionship, care, custody, and management" of his children is "cognizable and substantial," at 651-652, and, on the other hand, that the State's interest in caring for the children is "de minimis" if the father is in Karin Dwelle (2002) “Adoption without consent: How Idaho is treading on the constitutional rights of unwed fathers. Comment” 39 Idaho Law Review 207, 215. 16 17 405 U.S. 645 (1972). 16 fact a fit parent, at 657-658.18 Stanley’s primary role in the upbringing of the three children in question was a crucial component in establishing the existence of a protected interest. Thus highlighting the importance, in the Court's estimation, of the already established parent-child relationship.19 In another key US case on the matter, Quilloin v. Walcott the issue was the constitutionality of Georgia's adoption laws as applied to deny an unwed father authority to prevent adoption of his illegitimate child. The child was born in December 1964 and had been in the custody and control of his mother, appellee Ardell Williams Walcott, for his entire life. The mother and the child's natural father, appellant Leon Webster Quilloin, never married each other or established a home together, and in September 1967 the mother married appellee Randall Walcott. In March 1976, she consented to adoption of the child by her husband, who immediately filed a petition for adoption. Appellant attempted to block the adoption and to secure visitation rights, but he did not seek custody or object to the child's continuing to live with appellees. Although appellant was not found to be an unfit parent, the adoption was granted over his objection. The Appellant contended that even if he was not entitled to prevail as a matter of due process, principles of equal protection required that his authority to veto an adoption be measured by the same standard that would In Stanley the dissenting judgement of Mr Chief Justice Burger pointed out that the Supreme Court had decided the case on an issue that was never raised in the lower courts “No due process issue was raised in the state courts; and no due process issue was decided by any state court” at 659. 18 19 Dwelle, n 16 above, 215. 17 have been applied to a married father. In particular, appellant asserted that his interests were indistinguishable from those of a married father who is separated or divorced from the mother and is no longer living with his child, and therefore the State acted impermissibly in treating his case differently. The Supreme Court held that ... the appellant's interests are readily distinguishable from those of a separated or divorced father, and accordingly believe that the State could permissibly give appellant less veto authority than it provides to a married father. Although appellant was subject, for the years prior to these proceedings, to essentially the same child-support obligation as a married father would have had, compare § 74-202 with § 74-105 and § 30-301, he has never exercised actual or legal custody over his child, and thus has never shouldered any significant responsibility with respect to the daily supervision, education, protection, or care of the child. Appellant does not complain of his exemption from these responsibilities and, indeed, he does not even now seek custody of his child. In contrast, legal custody of children is, of course, a central aspect of the marital relationship, and even a father whose marriage has broken apart will have borne full responsibility for the rearing of his children during the period of the marriage. Under any standard of review, the State was not foreclosed from recognizing this difference in the extent of commitment to the welfare of the child. For these reasons, the court concluded that the relevant laws, as applied in this case, did not deprive appellant of his asserted rights under the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses. 18 In the case of Caban v. Mohammed, 20 the appellant, Abdiel Caban, challenged the constitutionality of § 111 of the New York Domestic Relations Law (McKinney 1977), under which two of his natural children were adopted by their natural mother and stepfather without his consent. Section 111 of the N. Y. Dom. Rel. Law (McKinney 1977) provides in part that "consent to adoption shall be required as follows: . . . (b) Of the parents or surviving parent, whether adult or infant, of a child born in wedlock; [and] (c) Of the mother, whether adult or infant, of a child born out of wedlock. . . ." The statute makes parental consent unnecessary, however, in certain cases, including those where the parent has abandoned or relinquished his or her rights in the child or has been adjudicated incompetent to care for the child. Absent one of these circumstances, an unwed mother has the authority under New York law to block the adoption of her child simply by withholding consent. The unwed father has no similar control over the fate of his child, even when his parental relationship is substantial—as in this case. He may prevent the termination of his parental rights only by showing that the best interests of the child would not permit the child's adoption by the petitioning couple. The Supreme Court found the statute to be unconstitutional, as the distinction it invariably makes between the rights of unmarried mothers and the rights of unmarried fathers has not been shown to be substantially related to an important state interest. The court took the view that genderbased distinctions "must serve important governmental objectives and must 20 441 US 380 - Supreme Court 1979. 19 be substantially related to achievement of those objectives" in order to withstand judicial scrutiny under the Equal Protection Clause. “Even if unwed mothers as a class were closer than unwed fathers to their newborn infants, this generalization concerning parent-child relations would become less acceptable as a basis for legislative distinctions as the age of the child increased. The present case demonstrates that an unwed father may have a relationship with his children fully comparable to that of the mother. Appellant Caban, appellee Maria Mohammed, and their two children lived together as a natural family for several years. As members of this family, both mother and father participated in the care and support of their children.[7] There is no reason to believe that the Caban children—aged 4 and 6 at the time of the adoption proceedings—had a relationship with their mother unrivaled by the affection and concern of their father. We reject, therefore, the claim that the broad, gender-based distinction of § 111 is required by any universal difference between maternal and paternal relations at every phase of a child's development.” At 389. The Supreme Court held that the effect of New York's classification was to discriminate against unwed fathers even when their identity was known and they had manifested a significant paternal interest in the child. “The facts of this case illustrate the harshness of classifying unwed fathers as being invariably less qualified and entitled than mothers to exercise a concerned judgment as to the fate of their children. Section 111 both excludes some loving fathers from full participation in the decision whether their children will be adopted and, at the same time, enables some alienated mothers arbitrarily to cut off the paternal rights of fathers. We conclude that this undifferentiated distinction between unwed mothers and unwed fathers, 20 applicable in all circumstances where adoption of a child of theirs is at issue, does not bear a substantial relationship to the State's asserted interests.” At 394. In Lehr v. Robertson,21 the question presented was whether New York has sufficiently protected an unmarried father's inchoate relationship with a child whom he has never supported and rarely seen in the two years since her birth. The appellant, Jonathan Lehr, claimed that the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment, as interpreted in Stanley v. Illinois, and Caban v. Mohammed, gave him an absolute right to notice and an opportunity to be heard before the child may be adopted. The Court disagreed. The State of New York maintains a "putative father registry."22 The court took the view that a man who files with that registry demonstrates his intent to claim paternity of a child born out of wedlock and is therefore entitled to receive notice of any proceeding to adopt that child. Before entering Jessica's adoption order, the Ulster County Family Court 21 463 US 248 - Supreme Court 1983. The putative father registry is a state level legal option for unmarried males to document through a notary public any female they engage with in intercourse, for the purpose of retaining parental rights for any child they may father. “Despite how reasonable this system might sound, the putative father registry has a number of significant flaws. First of all, few men are actually aware that such registries even exist and are, thus, unlikely to avail themselves to the “protection” they afford. More problematic, however, is the fact that the registries are state specific. Thus, to adequately protect himself, the putative father must know not the state in which the mother resides but the state where the she plans to give the child up for adoption. As discussed below, a mother can simply flee her state of residence and travel to another state to surrender her child for adoption. Unless the putative father actually registered in that specific state, he will not be entitled to notice of any adoptions concerning the child. Additionally, any ability he might have had to challenge the adoption is now permanently foreclosed.” Michael J Higdon (2014) “Marginalized fathers and demonized mothers: A feminist look at the reproductive freedom of unmarried men” Legal Studies Research Paper Series, Research Paper #234, 20. 22 21 had the putative father registry examined. Although appellant claimed to be Jessica's natural father, he had not entered his name in the registry. In addition to the persons whose names are listed on the putative father registry, New York law requires that notice of an adoption proceeding be given to several other classes of possible fathers of children born out of wedlock — those who have been adjudicated to be the father, those who have been identified as the father on the child's birth certificate, those who live openly with the child and the child's mother and who hold themselves out to be the father, those who have been identified as the father by the mother in a sworn written statement, and those who were married to the child's mother before the child was six months old. Appellant admittedly was not a member of any of those classes. He had lived with appellee prior to Jessica's birth and visited her in the hospital when Jessica was born, but his name does not appear on Jessica's birth certificate. He did not live with appellee or Jessica after Jessica's birth, he has never provided them with any financial support, and he has never offered to marry appellee. The court took a strong position upon this lack of parental interest: The difference between the developed parent-child relationship that was implicated in Stanley and Caban, and the potential relationship involved in Quilloin and this case, is both clear and significant. When an unwed father demonstrates a full commitment to the responsibilities of parenthood by "com[ing] forward to participate in the rearing of his child," Caban, 441 U. S., at 392, his interest in personal contact with his child acquires substantial protection under the Due Process Clause. At that point it may be said that he "act[s] as a father toward his children." Id., at 389, n. 7. But the mere existence of a biological link does not merit equivalent constitutional protection. The actions of judges neither create nor sever 22 genetic bonds. "[T]he importance of the familial relationship, to the individuals involved and to the society, stems from the emotional attachments that derive from the intimacy of daily association, and from the role it plays in `promot[ing] a way of life' through the instruction of children . . . as well as from the fact of blood relationship." Smith v. Organization of Foster Families for Equality and Reform, 431 U. S. 816, 844 (1977) (quoting Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U. S. 205, 231-233 (1972)). The significance of the biological connection is that it offers the natural father an opportunity that no other male possesses to develop a relationship with his offspring. If he grasps that opportunity and accepts some measure of responsibility for the child's future, he may enjoy the blessings of the parent-child relationship and make uniquely valuable contributions to the child's development. If he fails to do so, the Federal Constitution will not automatically compel a State to listen to his opinion of where the child's best interests lie. At 261-263. In this case, the Court clarified that it was not assessing the constitutional adequacy of New York's procedures for terminating a developed relationship. Appellant had never had any significant custodial, personal, or financial relationship with Jessica, and he did not seek to establish a legal tie until after she was two years old. Instead they were concerned only with whether New York has adequately protected his opportunity to form such a relationship. The existence or nonexistence of a substantial relationship between parent and child is a relevant criterion in evaluating both the rights of the parent and the best interests of the child. Because the appellant, like the father in Quilloin, had never established a substantial relationship with his daughter, the New York statutes at issue in this case did not operate to deny appellant equal protection. 23 In the US jurisprudence, “Constitutional protection for a parent's right to maintain a relationship with his or her child does not derive from some kind of parental possessory right existing in a vacuum. Rather, the protection is inextricably entwined with the parent's constant responsibility to care for the child.” 23 In each of these cases, the father's status as the biological parent of the child was not enough to grant him a protected parental interest. He must also have displayed, at the earliest possible moment, an interest in taking responsibility for his child, and he must have acted upon that interest in a timely manner. Essentially, he must establish a relationship with the child to the greatest extent possible under the circumstances. It is this parent-child bond and nothing less that, according to the Court, deserves constitutional protection.24 The parent's constitutional right to be with, provide for, and control their child is closely linked to the parent's duty to provide for the child's physical and emotional needs. According to Buchanan, the term "custody" has been used to describe this intermingling of rights and duties. In her analysis, she concludes: “that the Constitution particularly protects the custodial rights of biological parents who perform custodial responsibilities has been stated as a fact and explained in terms of tradition and natural right. That the Constitution continues to protect parent-child relationships even when parents no longer perform custodial responsibilities also has been stated as a fact and has been explained as a recognition that the emotional 23 Buchanan, n 1 above, 319. 24 Dwelle, n 19 above, 215. 24 attachments that arise during a custodial relationship are worthy of protection even when the custodial aspect of the relationship no longer exists. Thus, parents who live with, provide for, and form emotional attachments with their children perform the social function of caring for children, and their interests are worth protecting. Under this analysis, unwed fathers who have custodial relationships with their children are parents whose interests are worth protecting.”25 ... argues that the Supreme Court was correct to ground parental rights in a combination of biology and nurture. In order to determine whether an unmarried biological father has the right to consent to the adoption of his offspring, the law should look at his actions with respect to both the potential child and the mother during her pregnancy as well as after the birth. Parental rights cannot be decided without considering the complex web of relationships involved in procreative activity.26 THE BEST INTERESTS OF THE CHILD The supremacy of this standard has been clearly established in the legislation and in judicial decisions concerning children, including those born out of wedlock. In Macheme v Ndlovu 27 the Appeal Court upheld the judgement of Dingake J dated 6 October 2008 finding the respondent entitled to certain periods of access to Lorako Macheme, a male child born on 10 April 2003, of whom the appellant was the mother and the respondent 25 Buchanan, n 1 above, 323. Mary L Shanley (1995) “Unwed fathers’ rights, adoption and sex equality: GenderNeutrality and the Perpetuation of Patriarchy” 95(1) Columbia Law Review 60, 77. 26 27 (CACLB 035/08) [2009] BWCA 49. 25 is the father. Lord Coulsfield JA (with Tebbutt JP and Foxcroft JA concurring) held that "the primary standard to be applied in all questions of guardianship of or access to children, whether their parents are married or unmarried, is that of the best interests of the child." In Mfundisi v. Kabelo,28 Chatikobo J held: "The predominant approach, shared by all the cases, seems to be that the illegitimacy of the child is not the compelling reason for denying access by its father. Rather it is the interest of the child which must predominate. See also S v. S 1993 (2) S.A. 200 (W) A and B v. S 1993 (2) S.A. 211 (W). In my view, the mere fact that a person is the natural father of his illegitimate child creates sufficiently close kindredship such as should make it highly desirable that the father be granted access to the child to enable a bond of affinity to develop. Any notion of such a father being regarded as a stranger to his own child is anachronistic and detrimental to the interests of the child." The Children’s Act stipulates guiding principles to be used in determining the best interests of the child. These principles include taking into account the capacity of the child’s parents to care for and protect the child; and, the importance of stability and the likely effect on the child of any change or disruption in the child’s circumstances. 29 Furthermore, no decision or action shall be taken that would result in the discrimination against any child on any status, including family; and, the parents of a child have the 28 2003 (2) BLR 129 (HC). 29 Section 6. 26 primary responsibility of safeguarding and promoting the child’s wellbeing.30 In South Africa, the Children’s Act 38 of 2005 contains an extensive list of factors to be considered when determining the best interests of the child, including: the nature of the personal relationship between the child and the parent; the attitude of the parents or specific parent towards the child and their exercise of parental responsibilities and rights in respect of the child; and, the likely effect on the child of any separation from either of the parents. 31 “Section 21 of the Children’s Act awards parental rights and responsibilities to (in essence) two groups of unmarried fathers as of right. The first are fathers who were living with the mother at the time of the child’s birth. The second are those who were not living with the mother, but who fulfil specified criteria: the father must have consented or successfully applied to be identified as the child’s father or paid damages under customary law (which have the effect of identifying him as the child’s father); he must have contributed or attempted in good faith to contribute to the child’s upbringing for a reasonable period; and he must have contributed or attempted in good faith to contribute towards the maintenance of the child for a reasonable period.”32 30 Section 7. 31 Section 7, “Best interests of the child standard.” Julia Sloth-Nielsen & Belinda Van Heerden (2014) “The ‘Constitutional Family’: Developments in South African child and family law 2003-2013” International Journal of Law, Policy and The Family 1, 14. With regards to adoption proceedings, the consent of the unmarried biological father of a child is generally required with the exception of situations where the father: 32 27 The ultimate test for each of the decisions that are taken concerning the minor child in this and in every matter will be her best interests. The Court and every decision-making body tasked with her matter must weigh all choices against this standard. Furthermore, the standard is context-specific and the court will be influenced to a large extent by the social, political and economic conditions of Botswana. There is a danger that in using this standard any rights that Khwarae and other unmarried biological fathers may seek to rely upon will be defeated by the socio-economic benefits and stability that adoption might proffer a child. However, this danger is mitigated by the reinforced message in the Children’s Act that the parent is to be supported and assisted in their efforts to care for the wellbeing of their child – this includes granting them primacy in the queue for custodial relationship with their children. 1. Is incompetent to give consent due to mental illness; 2. Has abandoned the child; 3. Has abused or deliberately neglected the child; 4. Has consistently failed to fulfil his parental duties during the last twelve months; 5. Has been divested of his right to consent by an order of the court; or, 6. Has failed to respond to the notice of adoption within 30 days of service of the notice. In the exceptions as laid out in section 236(1) of the Act, his consent is not required (where the child was born from rape or an incestuous relationship and) unless he has acknowledged that he is the father of the child. There are four ways whereby a person can acknowledge that he is the biological father of a child: 1. By giving written acknowledgment that he is the biological father of the child either to the mother or the clerk of the children’s court before the child reaches the age of six months; 2. By voluntarily paying maintenance in respect of the child; 3. By paying damages in terms of customary law; or 4. By causing particulars of himself to be entered into the registration of birth of the child in terms of the relevant sections of the Births and Deaths Registration Act, 1992 28 The Children’s Act recognises a child as an individual and a member of a family and a community, with rights and responsibilities appropriate to his or her age and stage of development. The question of custody and access affects the future of the child; it therefore seems logical that the views of children should also be considered in these matters. However, the court should obviously be able to distinguish between those cases in which the cchildren of more mature age have shown decided opinions of their own about where they should live, and those in which one parent is indulging and encouraging them in the role in which they have been cast, as adversaries of the other parent in court battles.33 There have been various approaches used to involve the child’s voice in the decision-making process: family reports by social workers; reports from child experts (psychologists or therapists); judicial interview with the presiding judge in chambers; and in rare instances calling upon the child to give testimony in open court. In giving meaning to the principle of the best interests of the child, the court may wish to consider eliciting input from the child involved: bearing in mind that contemporary understanding of children’s psychological, emotional and cognitive development should inform the ways in which judges elicit and evaluate children’s perspectives.34 Even if a child is not considered to have a clear preference about custody or the adoption process, the child may have perspectives about family relations that may assist the court in its decision- Frans Mashilo Mahlobogwane (2010) “Determining the best interests of the child in custody battles: should a child's voice be considered?” 31(2) Obiter 232, 237. 33 34 Mahlobogwane, n 33 above, 241. 29 making. 35 In this instance the court may be able to gain clarity on the bond/relationship between Khwarae and his daughter, and that between the child and the suggested adoptive parent, as seen from her perspective. DISCRIMINATION The question that falls to be determined is whether section 15 of the Constitution allows discrimination on the ground of marital status. Khwarae contends that the Adoption Act discriminates between him on the basis of marital status. He is essentially attempting to overcome the marital presumption that awards parenthood and the rights and the related responsibilities to married men automatically. Khwarae has assumed parental duties and held himself out as the child’s father but is precluded from establishing his legal paternity because he is unable to rebut the marital presumption. The marital presumption—that the husband of a child’s mother is the child’s legal father, regardless of whether he is the child’s biological father—has its roots in old English common law:36 The purpose of the marital presumption is to preserve familial integrity by ignoring an out of wedlock dalliance. From an efficiency perspective, the marital presumption has merit, because the child’s legal father is readily identified. Unfortunately, a strict application of the presumption may render some loving, biological and functional fathers as legal strangers to their children.37 35 Ibid, 244. Melanie B Jacobs (2012) “Overcoming the marital presumption” 50(2) Family Court Review 289, 290. 36 37 Jacobs, n 36 above, 290. 30 According to Jacobs, strict adherence to the marital presumption that does not permit a biological (and, more importantly, a functional) father the opportunity to rebut the presumption represents one piece of what she calls the paternity riddle: some willing, ready, and able fathers are denied the opportunity to legally establish and/or preserve their parental relationship because of an outdated doctrine. Rather than emphasising parentage by marriage or parentage by genetics, she proposes that we should emphasise parentage by function and intention. She suggests that integrating these newer doctrines within the old paradigm will yield better results for children and their parents.38 There is need to closely examine the possible impact of the marital presumption throughout the legislation. Times are changing and with those changes are marked shifts in the traditional configuration of families. Many young couples are living together responsibly without being legally married. It is no longer so shameful in most communities for an unmarried woman to show her pregnancy or keep her child: “In so complex a society, it is more difficult, but no less essential, that democratic values prevail. The primary value is the worth of the human person. It is consistent with this value that the rights of one person may not be overruled without a hearing, even in the interests of one more needful. Thus, it follows that the father of the child born out of wedlock should be considered as a concerned individual.” 39 38 Jacobs, n 36 above, 295. Rita Dukette & Nicholas Stevenson (1973) “The Legal Rights of Unmarried Fathers: The Impact of Recent Court Decisions” 47(1) Social Service Review 1, 14. 39 31 The position of the Attorney General is that Section 15(3) is not violated because the applicant is simply complaining that he is being discriminated by virtue of being unmarried as opposed to a married man. Consequently, it is argued that he cannot complain that he is being discriminated on the basis of sex. However, the underlying feature in section 15 of the Constitution of Botswana is the failure to treat all persons equally where no reasonable distinction can be found between those favoured and those not favoured.40 “The crucial part of this is subsection 3 ... [i]t apparently lists a fixed category of proscribed distinctions, made with reference to 'race, tribe, place of origin, political opinions, colour or creed . . .' ... the weakness with this fixed category approach is that it puts pressure on the courts, in cases of groups marginally outside the fixed categories, to stretch their powers of statutory interpretation to its limits.” 41 However the courts have made it clear that neither the categories nor the derogations contained in section 15 are immutable. In Attorney-General v Dow42 Amissah JP suggests general guidelines for expanding these categories: If the categories of groups or classes mentioned in section 15(3) are but examples, where does one draw the line as to the categories to be included? Of course, treatment to different sexes based on biological differences cannot be taken as discrimination in the sense that section 15(3) proscribes. With regard to the classes which are protected, it would be wrong to lay down any hard and fast rules. The vulnerable classes identified in sections 3 Charles Manga Fombad (2004) “The Constitutional Protection against Discrimination in Botswana” 53(1) The International and Comparative Law Quarterly 139, 141. 40 41 Fombad, n 40 above 143. 42 Appeal Court, 1994 (6) BCLR 1. 32 and 15 are well known. I would add that not only the classes mentioned in the definition in section 15(3), but, for example, the class also mentioned in subsection (4)(d), where it speaks of “community” in addition to “race” and “tribe” have to be taken as vulnerable. Civilised society requires that different treatment should not be given to people wholly or mainly on the ground of membership of the designated classes or groups.... The only general criterion which could be put forward to identify the classes or groups is what to the right thinking man is outrageous treatment only or mainly because of membership of that class or group and what the comity of nations has come to adopt as unacceptable behaviour. If these guidelines are adopted then it would require examining the differentiation between married and unmarried men in light of the provisions of the Adoption Act and determining whether the laws as they stand represent outrageous treatment or treatment that has been deemed unacceptable internationally. In this analysis however, the court would need to be cautious and cognitive of the very real differences that exist in the lived realities of women and men as parents. Granting formal equality to unmarried men that expands their role over the decision-making process concerning their biological children would have to be achieved in such a manner as to avoid further burdening women who in practicality bear the brunt of child-rearing duties. Allowing a blanket differentiation that applies to unmarried biological fathers would appear to be unacceptable in terms of the progressive realisation of equality rights for all: it is suggested that the answer lies in a case-by-case evaluation of the intentional or functional unmarried fathers and an 33 interpretation of the Children’s Act that ensures a bona fide participatory role in decision making. An argument has been raised on the grounds of the differentiation between biological mothers and biological fathers in the relevant laws. It was essentially brought to the pleadings by the Attorney General who sought to rely upon the terms of customary law, whereby a child born out of wedlock belongs to the mother’s family and argued that this is a position that was also applicable under common law with parental rights and responsibilities over a child being acquired by birth in lawful wedlock.43 According to Louw, various reasons can be found for the law's preferential treatment of mothers as legal parents: (a) It promotes legal certainty. Since, unlike paternity, maternity could always be established with certainty, it made sense to allocate parental responsibilities and rights to the biological mother. In this way, the legal parentage of the child could, at least as far as the mother was concerned, be determined whatever the marital status of The Attorney General argues that in terms of Botswana customary law, a child born out of wedlock belongs to the mother’s family. The child of an unmarried woman belongs to her mother’s home. This is a position that reflects the common law, whereby the father of an illegitimate child had no rights regarding his offspring, and the child lacked the rights normally bestowed upon a legitimate child, such as the right to inherit from his parents. The development of customary law came into focus in the Mmusi case, and the present case presents another opportunity for the court to examine the intent and content of customary laws. Amissah JP in the Dow case: 43 “Our attention has been drawn to the patrilineal customs and traditions of the Botswana people to show, I believe, that it was proper for Parliament to legislate to preserve or advance such customs and traditions. Custom and tradition have never been static. Even then, they have always yielded to express legislation. Custom and tradition must a fortiori, and from what I have already said about the pre-eminence of the Constitution, yield to the Constitution of Botswana. A constitutional guarantee cannot be overridden by custom. Of course, the custom will as far as possible be read so as to conform with the Constitution. But where this is impossible, it is custom not the Constitution which must go.” 34 the child's parents. Paternity, as well as legal paternity, could then be determined with reference to a certain objectively determinable fact – maternity. (b) It gives effect to the importance of the mother's contribution to the child who, in the opinion of the Constitutional Court in Fraser v Children's Court, Pretoria North: ... has a biological relationship with the child whom she nurtures during the pregnancy and often breast-feeds after birth. She gives succour and support to the new life which is very direct and not comparable to that of a father. (c) Lastly, the automatic allocation of parental responsibilities and rights to the unmarried mother affords the mother, as primary caregiver, a certain degree of autonomy as far as decisions regarding her child are concerned. This protects her (and, as a consequence, presumably also the children born out of wedlock) from the unwarranted and sporadic interference by "irresponsible" fathers of such children44 She points out that in this manner mothers are entrusted with full rights and responsibilities because they can give birth whilst fathers are subjected to a screening process where they have to show necessary commitment to either the mother or the child. Then and only then will the law accept and expect them to assume legal rights and responsibilities. Louw argues that despite the fact that the automatic allocation of parental responsibilities and rights to all mothers serves a rational purpose, the unfair impact of such an allocation may still result in unfair discrimination.45 Anne Louw (2010) “The constitutionality of a biological father’s recognition as a parent” 13(3) PER/PELJ 156, 164. 44 45 Louw, n 44 above, 165. 35 On the other hand, some authors contend that the arguments for unmarried biological fathers to invoke the principle of gender-neutrality are deeply flawed since they mask a form of male domination under the language of equality rights. Whilst on the other hand, arguments that privilege maternal autonomy that rest upon the unmarried mother and fathers different biological and social relationship to the foetus during pregnancy may produce unfair results in some cases and enhance the empowerment of women at the cost of reinforcing gender roles that vest the primary caregiving role for children only with the woman. It is important to bear in mind that formal equality, as far as parental roles are concerned, will not create substantive equality for women who may suffer even more if fathers are automatically given parental responsibilities and rights. The focus of this argument is on the mother's diminished autonomy as a result of having to share parental responsibilities and rights with the father of the child. The concern is that while mothers will still deal with the daily task of parenting, fathers will acquire the right to interfere with the parenting decisions.46 Shanley concludes that in order to have a right to consent to the adoption of his child, the unmarried biological father must have acted to assume responsibility for the child from the earliest possible moment. 47 For Shanley what is crucial is that parental rights be grounded in specific manifestations of care, and of demonstrations of parental responsibility.48 Buchanan argues 46 Louw, n 44 above, 166. 47 Shanley, n 26 above, 77. 48 Shanley, n 26 above, 90. 36 for the rights of unmarried fathers but rights that “do not depend on claims by unwed fathers for equal treatment with other parents whom the state may favor. The rights derive, rather, from an independent consideration of the fundamental rights of all parents in their relationships with their children.”49 Such rights would be recognisable in Botswana, regardless of the provisions of sections 3 and 15 of the Constitution. These rights are conferred by the Children’s Act in its expansion of the Constitution. The articulated goals of the Children’s Act include promoting the wellbeing of children, families and communities in Botswana; and, acknowledging the primary responsibility of parents and families to care for and protect children AND to support and assist them in carrying out that responsibility.50 In the South African case of Fraser v. Children's Court Pretoria North and Others51 the question of the constitutionality of S 18(4)(d) of the Child Care Act 74 of 1983 was referred for determination to the Constitutional Court in terms of s 102(1) of the Constitution. S 18(4)(d) of the Child Care Act 74 of 1983 provided that a children’s court to which application for an order of adoption is made shall not grant the application unless it is satisfied that consent to the adoption has been given by both parents of the child, or, if the child is illegitimate, by the mother of the child only. The Court held that the discrimination entailed by the section could not be justified. It unfairly 49 Buchanan, n 1 above, 382 50 Section 4. 51 [1997] ZACC 1. 37 discriminated against the fathers of certain children on the basis of their gender or their marital status. Every mother was given an automatic right to withhold her consent to the adoption of the child while this right was denied to every unmarried father. An order declaring the section unconstitutional was made whereas order was made to allow the section to survive pending correction by parliament. Mahomed DP pointed out that: The effect of section 18(4)(d) of the Act is that the consent of the father would, subject to section 19, be necessary in every case where he is or has been married to the mother of the child and never necessary in the case of fathers who have not been so married. In the context of certain laws there would often be some historical and logical justification for discriminating between married and unmarried persons and the protection of the institution of marriage is a legitimate area for the law to concern itself with. But in the context of an adoption statute where the real concern of the law is whether an order for the adoption of the child is justified, a right to veto the adoption based on the marital status of the parent could lead to very unfair anomalies. The consent of a father, who after his formal marriage to the mother of the child concerned, has shown not the slightest interest in the development and support of the child would, subject to section 19, always be necessary. Conversely a father who has not concluded a formal ceremony of marriage with the mother of the child but who has been involved in a stable relationship with the mother over a decade and has shown a real interest in the nurturing and development of the child, would not be entitled to insist that his consent to the adoption of the child is necessary. The consent of the mother only would, subject to section 19, be necessary even if the only reason why the relationship between the 38 couple has not been solemnised through a marriage is that the mother refuses to go through such a ceremony, either on the ground that she has some principled objection to formal marriages or on some other ground. [Para 26]. … A child born out of a union which has never been formalised by marriage often falls into the broad area between the two extremes expressed by the case where he or she is so young as to make the interests of the mother and the child in the bonding relationship obvious and a child who is so old and mature and whose relationship with the father is so close and bonded as to make protection of the father-child relationship equally obvious. There is a vast area between such anomalies which needs to be addressed by a nuanced and balanced consideration of a society in which the factual demographic picture and parental relationships are often quite different from those upon which “first world” western societies are premised; by having regard to the fact that the interest of the child is not a separate interest which can realistically be separated from the parental right to develop and enjoy close relationships with a child and by the societal interest in recognising and seeking to accommodate both.[Para 29] In addition section 15(4) contains a claw back clause specifying that the protections of section 15 do not extend to any law that makes provision with respect to adoption or other matters of personal law. The Attorney General argues that in this instance, we are dealing with adoption, one of those instances specifically prohibited by Section 15 (4) (c). However, the derogations listed in section 15 are not beyond reproach and have to be tested against the parameters set out in the umbrella provision of section 3. 39 Lesetedi JA reiterated the holding in Dow that a derogation as contained in section 15(4) does not permit unchecked discrimination which is not consistent with the core values of the constitution, stating: “Where there is a derogation the Court must closely scrutinize it, give it a strict and narrow interpretation and test whether such discrimination is justifiable having regard to the exceptions contained in Section 3 of the Constitution. It is only when the Court is satisfied that a discrimination passes that test that the Court can find that the derogation is constitutionally permissible. ... the derogations contained in Section 15(4) of the Constitution are not unchecked. They must be rational and justifiable either as being intended to ensure that the rights and freedoms of any individual do not prejudice the rights and freedoms of others or as being in the public interest.” 52 If the distinction between men based upon their marital status is determined to be discriminatory then it falls to interrogate whether the derogation concerning adoption is rational and justifiable. The Children’s Act changes the distinction made between married and unmarried men as suggested in the relevant section of the Adoption Act because it allows for consultation of the biological father, especially where the father in question has taken on the rights and duties that accord to a parent. The Children’s Act reverses the traditional common law and even the customary law position that considered the unmarried mother as the 52 Ramantele case, paras 71-72. 40 sole responsible parent, and establishes the requirement that the unmarried father be involved in any decision-making processes regarding his children. In the words of Mahomed DP in the Fraser case: “What is evident from the modern legislative and judicial responses to the problems associated with adoption is the recognition of the fact that in determining the rights of fathers to withhold their consent to the adoption of their children it may be too simplistic merely to draw a distinction between married and unmarried fathers, and it may equally be too simplistic to discriminate between the mothers and fathers of children born in consequence of a union not formalized by marriage. Unmarried fathers, by the acceptance of their paternity and parental responsibility, may often be qualified to make the most active inputs into the desirability of such an adoption order and in certain circumstances they may legitimately wish to withhold their consent to such an adoption order. It is equally evident that not all unmarried fathers are indifferent to the welfare of their children and that in modern society stable relationships between unmarried parents are no longer exceptional. The statutory and judicial responses to these problems are therefore nuanced having regard to the duration of the relationship between the parents of the children born out-of-wedlock, the age of the child sought to be given up for adoption, the stability of the relationship between the parents, the intensity or otherwise of the bonds between the father and the child in these circumstances, the legitimate needs of the parents, the reasons why the relationship between the parents has not been formalised 41 by a marriage ceremony and generally what the best interests of the child are.” [Para 43]. The Court is now tasked with striking a balance between recognising those unmarried fathers who wished to assume an active role as parents yet not giving rights to others who had not shown such commitment. If a protected right arises based upon genetics alone then it would confer significant power to even a sperm donor, there ought to be more to it than that. Protecting the substantive rights of women would meet the test of section 3 of the Constitution as advanced by Amissah JP in the Dow case and reinforced in the more recent decision by the Appeal Court in the Ramantele ruling for upholding the applicable derogation under section 15. INHUMAN AND DEGRADING TREATMENT Generally used to capture levels of human suffering that do not amount to torture, treatment or punishment amounts to cruel, inhuman and degrading treatment (CIDT) when it involves mental and physical ill-treatment that has been intentionally inflicted by, or with the consent or acquiescence of, the state authorities. CIDT refers to “ill-treatment that does not have to be inflicted for a specific purpose, but there does have to be intent to expose individuals to the conditions which amount to or result in the ill-treatment. Exposing a person to conditions reasonably believed to constitute illtreatment will entail responsibility for its infliction. Degrading treatment may involve pain or suffering less severe than for torture or cruel or inhuman treatment and will usually involve humiliation and debasement of 42 the victim. The essential elements which constitute ill-treatment not amounting to torture would therefore be reduced to: Intentional exposure to significant mental or physical pain or suffering; By or with the consent or acquiescence of the state authorities It is often difficult to identify the exact boundaries between the different forms of ill-treatment as this requires an assessment about degrees of suffering that may depend on the particular circumstances of the case and the characteristics of the particular victim. In some cases, certain forms of ill-treatment or certain aspects of detention which would not constitute torture on their own may do so in combination with each other. Ill-treatment is, however, prohibited under international law and even where the treatment does not have the purposive element or, as far as degrading treatment is concerned, is not considered severe enough (in legal terms) to amount to torture, it may still amount to prohibited ill-treatment.”53 The Courts in Botswana have dealt with cases on this ground, mainly within the context of imprisonment and the death penalty, and it has been established that: “what constitutes inhuman and degrading punishment has been defined as punishment which though not necessarily cruel, does not Physicians for Human Rights (2010) “PHR Toolkits: Cruel Inhuman & Degrading Treatment & Punishment (CID)” <http://phrtoolkits.org/toolkits/istanbul-protocol-modelmedical-curriculum/module-1-international-legal-standards-overview/torture/cruelinhuman-degrading-treatment-punishment-cid/> (accessed 29 October 2014). 53 43 accord with human dignity.”54 As to the gravitas of the proscribed actions, the Court stressed that the “... elements of torture, and inhuman or degrading punishment or other treatment are pregnant with meaning and are powerful concepts reaching down to the very depths of a person’s humanity and to his right not to be treated in a manner which robs him of his human dignity and worth.”55 In order to show that he has been made to suffer “inhuman or degrading punishment or other such treatment,” Khwarae would have to show that he was intentionally exposed to mental or physical suffering and that this intentional exposure was committed by or with the acquiescence of state authorities. Failing which, his prayer under section 7 ought to be unsuccessful. RIGHT TO A FAIR HEARING Khwarae further contends that that Section 10 (9) of the Constitution has been violated by permitting the adoption to proceed, while he has a court order permitting him visitation and other privileges and that this would tantamount to taking away those rights without giving him a fair hearing. The scope of a natural father’s right to be heard and to be notified in respect of the adoption of his child must be explored. It is arguable that the right of an unmarried father to be consulted in the event of adoption implies and amounts to a right to the opportunity to be heard. Since a biological father is legislatively entitled to be consulted before the proceeding that will result Per Lesetedi AJA in Motlhabane and Another v S (CLCLB-107-09) [2010] BWCA 27 (28 January 2010) para 12. 54 55 S v Ndou (CLCLB-029-08 ) [2008] BWCA 60 (24 July 2008) para 59. 44 in the termination of his relationship with his child, the state may not completely disregard the father's interest. At the least, the state must take into account the father's argument that it would not be in the child's best interests to terminate his relationship with the child, and the state may terminate the relationship only on a finding that it would be in the child's best interests to do so.56 The biological connection between the unmarried father and the child, whilst not creating automatic parenthood, provides the opportunity for men to step forward and father their children. The legislature in recognition of the changing implications of parenthood has expanded the laws to formally recognise the unmarried father as a parent and to support him in fulfilling this role. In the words of Justice White in Lehr v. Robertson “The intangible fibers that connect parent and child have infinite variety. They are woven throughout the fabric of our society, providing it with strength, beauty, and flexibility. It is self-evident that they are sufficiently vital to merit constitutional protection in appropriate cases.”57 Furthermore, under the Children’s Act, the parents shall be given an opportunity to participate in decision-making processes under the Act that are likely to have a significant impact on the child’s life, processes such as adoption, and are to be given adequate information as well as complaint or 56 Buchanan, n 1 above 346. 57 See n 21 above, para 256. 45 review procedures.58 In McMichael v UK59 Scotland encountered difficulties under the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms when it did not afford an unmarried father access to documents before the children’s hearing. This was held to be a breach of article 8 (respect for family life) because it did not allow him to be involved in the decision-making process to a degree sufficient to protect his interest. The current provisions of section 4(1)(d)(i) of the Adoption Act have serious consequences for the unmarried biological father alone. The Court must clearly and unequivocally elaborate the meaning of consultation as provided for under the 2009 Children’s Act: does consultation entail the opportunity to withhold consent? If not then it does not qualify as a meaningful involvement in the decision-making process and instead becomes an empty provision that does nothing to alleviate the potential consequences for the unmarried father and his biological child. It is further suggested that consultation in some cases may even require that the father grants his consent to the adoption proceedings. The deciding factor will be the best interests of the child, and the prior established relationship or bond between the two would necessarily be relevant and ought to be factored in to the decision making process. The consultation requirement ought to be calibrated accordingly. That leaves the Court in the Khwarae decision with 58 Sections 7(e) & 7(f). 59 (1995) 20 EHRR 205. 46 an opportunity to flesh out broad parameters of this requirement, including practicalities relating to the who, when and how of consultation.60 On the presented facts, Khwarae has established the existence of a relationship between him and his child that entitled him to be consulted before the commencement of adoption proceedings. The Children’s Act and the Constitution both protect and provide him with the right to have an opportunity to be heard. The Attorney General contends that the applicant is permitted and should correctly approach the court for an appropriate order where section 10(9) of the Constitution is applicable. However, it is unclear why the present court is not able to be seized with the matter? The right to be given adequate information as well as complaint or review procedures is encompassed in the Children’s Act and in the constitutional provision that the applicant seeks to rely upon. IV. THE MMUSI/RAMANTELE DECISIONS The High Court decision in the Mmusi case was broadly lauded as a landmark decision in advancing women's rights in Botswana. Jonas suggests that the Mmusi decision takes over from where Dow left off in “pushing back the frontiers of emancipation for the women of Botswana, Africa and the world.” 61 The main critique levelled against the Mmusi decision is that there was no satisfactory discussion and resolution of the 60 Lawrence & Patrick, n 5 above, 258. Obonye Jonas (2013) "Gender equality in Botswana: The case of Mmusi and Others v Ramantele and Others" 13 African Human Rights Law Journal 229, 230. 61 47 tension between sections 3 and 15 of the Constitution. The second critique is the position that the court erred in opining that there is no room for public opinion in constitutional interpretation.62 In contrast, Fombad takes issue with the attempt to strike down a rule of customary law, suggesting instead that "... courts, when interpreting a rule of customary law, should, where it appears to conflict with – or actually conflicts with – the fundamental rights provisions in the constitution, strive to interpret and develop rather than strike down the rule of customary law." 63 Fombad's discussion of the Mmusi decisions is not as relevant to the present case since his primary train of thought revolves around the role that the courts ought to play in the development of customary laws. Whatever the criticism levelled against the High Court judge for his handling of the Mmusi decision, the judicial activism that he exhibited in his handling of the case shone a powerful beam on the way that custom can be misappropriated to thwart the advancement of equality rights in society. The case opened the gate for engaging and enhanced interrogation of the role that the Constitution can play in shifting women’s lived realities. Furthermore, the inclusion of international case law and legislation in the discussion only served to strengthen the position that no country is an island free from the changes that occur in the international community within which it exists. 62Jonas, n 61 above; Chiara Van Ingen & Tshegofatso Phala (2014) " Homophobia in African law" Without Prejudice 54; Charles Manga Fombad (2014) "Gender equality in African customary law: has the male ultimogeniture rule any future in Botswana?" 52:03 The Journal of Modern African Studies 475, 483. 63 48 In the High Court decision of the Mmusi case, the court took a firm stance upon the necessity for the courts of law, as the conscience and voice of contemporary society, to do their part towards the achievement of gender parity. The learned judge opined that the justices of the court must “assume the role of judicial midwives and assist in the birth of a new world struggling to be born, a world of equality between men and women as envisioned by the framers of the Constitution.” [Para 217]. It was held that the right to protection of the law contained in section 3 of the Constitution leads to the principle that all laws must treat all people equally save as may legitimately be excepted by the constitution; and that section 3 is a standalone provision from section 15: “I am conscious of the argument advanced by the respondents that I must apply section 15 to the dispute and not section 3(a) of the Constitution. I am unable to understand the logic of such argument. Section 3(a) is a substantive section that confers rights. It is distinct from section 15. If a litigant, as in this case, chooses to proceed in terms of section 3(a), and succeeds to meet the requirements of the said section, then his/her challenge is entitled to succeed.” This decision was deemed problematic both in the higher court and in the literature that has since developed on the famous case. Jonas observes that: “It appears that the Constitution of Botswana gives a right with one hand and takes it away with the other. Whereas the Constitution prohibits discrimination in some of its clauses, it entrenches discrimination in other provisions. Thus, a conflict arose in the case. This tension can only be 49 settled by the application of the doctrine of harmonisation, which requires that the provisions of the Constitution must be interpreted in a manner that ensures their peaceful coexistence.”64 Lekgowe refers to the unresolved and continuing tension as a missed opportunity, the High Court having “failed to interrogate the purpose of and the distinction between Section 3 and Section 15: “If not improbable, it is extremely unlikely that the framers of the Constitution would have framed two provisions, put them separately, in the same Constitution, dealing with the same subject matter, the other one, simply being a perfect reflection of the other. Interrogating the purpose of and distinction between Section 3 and Section 15 would had the benefit of, if not making sound the reasoning of the Court, then at least revealing the reasons why the Court chose to apply Section 3(a) and not Section 15(1). Simply because the Applicant elected to proceed under Section 3, such an election was neither a hindrance nor a bar to the Court probing its legitimacy. 65 Lekgowe then suggests an alternative interpretation of the relationship between the contentious sections: “It is submitted that the difference between Section 3 and Section 15(1) is that Section 15(1) guarantees the right to non-discrimination and Section 3 guarantees fundamental rights, without discrimination, or equality with regard to the rights and freedoms set forth in the Constitution. Any inequality with regard to anything that is not a 64 Jonas, n 61 above, 238. Gosego Rockfall Lekgowe (2012) "Mmusi & Ors v Ramantele & Another: An opportunity missed to begin the burial of Attorney General v Unity Dow?" 15 University of Botswana Law Journal 81, 83. 65 50 fundamental right cannot be considered a violation of Section 3. In terms of Section 3, even the right to nondiscrimination is conferred on every person in Botswana without discrimination. To come under Section 3, a litigant must allege that he or she is being denied one of the fundamental rights and that it is being done in a discriminatory manner that is, based on more or one of the stipulated descriptions. Unlike a complaint under Section 15(1), a complaint under Section 3 need not be based on a discriminatory law. It will then be open to the opposing party to plead that the case is affected by the limitations of that right such as to allege that such denial is in the public interest or it is being done for the purposes of respecting the rights and freedoms of others.”66 Furthermore, the court rejected outright “any suggestion, no matter how remote, that the court must take into account the mood of society in determining whether there is a violation of constitutional rights as this undermines the very purposes for which the courts were established.”67 Lastly, authors such as Fombad have been extremely critical of the use of comparative foreign legislation and case law to assist in the adjudication of Mmusi case. Although the author took more issue with how the cases/constitutions were cited as opposed to whether or not there is a role for “comparative human rights jurisprudence and international human rights law in the determination of the claim.”68 In deciding Ramantele, The Court of Appeal took issue with the lack of adequate evidence leading to a ruling on the constitutionality of a 66 ibid, 87. 67 Para 197. This is a position of the court that invited severe criticism from scholars. 68 Citing Jonas, n 61 above 229. 51 Customary Law and more generally with the judge’s method of deciding the case on a constitutional ground: “a court should not be too quick to consider the constitutionality of a Customary Law unless it is possessed of sufficient evidence regarding the existence and content of such custom, its application and the rationale thereof. Should a court do so, it is likely to find itself making decisions which have got no contextual and factual foundation, yet with far-reaching consequences. ... The constitutional question did not advance the determination of the case in any way. ... The wheels of justice must not be mired and slowed by philosophical and theoretical issues which do not advance the dispute resolution process, nor by uncalled for piece-meal determination of litigation. ... [W]here it is possible to decide a case before the court without having to decide a constitutional question, the court must follow that approach.” [Para 37-40]. Yet, the court proceeded to set out the “proper constitutional analytical process merely for guidance.” [Paras 51 & 58]. With specific reference to the relationship between sections 3 and 15 of the Constitution, Lesetedi JA rejected the High Court’s finding that section 3 provided rights separate from section 15 and thus was not limited by the exemptions outlined under section 15(4). Instead, Lesetedi JA held that section 3 was an umbrella provision under which section 15 was subordinate.69 Furthermore, Lesetedi JA noted that any limitations outlined in section 15, among others, would themselves be limited by those outlined in section 3. Thus, a court must assess whether the particular limitation on 69 Para 65. 52 a specific right under the Constitution is justifiable in that it either prejudices the freedoms of others or is in the public interest. In particular he stated that: “the derogations contained in Section 15(4) of the Constitution are not unchecked. They must be rational and justifiable either as being intended to ensure that the rights and freedoms of any individual do not prejudice the rights and freedoms of others or as being in the public interest.” [Para 72]. The Court also admonished the High Court judge for “traversing” issues that do not directly arise from the case being dealt with, declaring that “[n]o rebirth was called for in this case.” In conclusion the High Court decision was set aside and replaced but its outcome retained. It was suggested that in opting to deal with section 15 as a standalone provision that the learned judge erred in his interpretation of the Constitution. However, the interpretative method used in the Mmusi case was reversed in the Appeal Court decision and replaced with an approach that merely reiterated previous decisions on the issue without suggesting new or varied ways of construing the relationship between sections 3 and 15 of the Constitution. The question that then arises is whether such an effort is actually relevant to the decision in the Khwarae matter? If decided only on the basis of section 15 as pleaded, the case would still implicate the protection afforded by section 3 of the Constitution since a “piece-meal” rendition of the protected liberties is not feasible in actuality – human rights are interdependent and interrelated. Thus the section 15 right to be 53 protected from discrimination of necessity implicates the section 3 rights to protection of the law. V. NON-CONSTITUTIONAL GROUNDS In Ramantele the Court of Appeal admonished the learned judge for dealing with the Mmusi decision on constitutional grounds when there were nonconstitutional remedies available to dispose of the matter. The Court must not actively avoid the constitutional issues that are brought to it, in the present matter it would be so unfair as to amount to a denial of justice if the Court were to shy away from interrogating the constitutional considerations, even if only to establish whether there actually are alternative legal grounds available. In the area of protection of human rights, the courts have the primary responsibility and duty of giving force and effect to the basic human rights and fundamental freedoms enshrined in the Constitution. Under Section 18(1) of the Constitution, if a person feels that any of the protective clauses, that is, Sections 3 to 16 (inclusive) of the Constitution has been or is being or is likely to be contravened in relation to him, he should apply to the High Court for redress. Under subsection 2, clause (a) the High Court has original jurisdiction to hear and determine such an application. 70 Furthermore it is trite law that the constitutionality of legislation does not depend on whether the litigant has a satisfactory alternative remedy. The whole point of the procedure is to measure the validity of the impugned Melvin Mbao (1993) “Accountability in Government and realization of Human Rights in Botswana” 12 Third World Legal Studies 59, 64. 70 54 section of the Adoption Act under the Constitution, and the Court cannot therefore escape the constitutional issue. The court must delve into constitutional questions of necessity when weighing up the various interests in this matter. Especially in a case like this where the father and the child have had a relationship and the father has established an ongoing and definitive interest and involvement in the life and welfare of the child. There are the child's rights to family and to know and be raised by its biological parent that may trump the unclear rights of a parent, especially those of the unmarried biological father. There is a nuanced a delicate balancing act that the Court must engage in when the state seeks to aid in permanently severing the ties between a parent and a child, the Constitution is a strong manual in navigating such murky waters as human relationships. VI. CONCLUDING REMARKS The current Children’s Act with its enhanced acknowledgment of the parental role of unmarried biological fathers would seem to suggest that some biological fathers hold protected rights regarding the parent-child relationship. Especially as seen from the perspective of the child and their best interests which are to be considered paramount in all decisions concerning children. The ultimate test for each of the decisions that are taken concerning the minor child in this and in every matter will be her best interests. The Court 55 and every decision-making body tasked with her matter must weigh all choices against this standard. Furthermore, the standard is context-specific and the court will be influenced to a large extent by the social, political and economic conditions of Botswana. There is a danger that in using this standard any rights that Khwarae and other unmarried biological fathers may seek to rely upon will be defeated by the socio-economic benefits and stability that adoption might proffer a child. However, this danger is mitigated by the reinforced message in the Children’s Act that the parent is to be supported and assisted in their efforts to care for the wellbeing of their child – this includes granting them primacy in the queue for custodial relationship with their children. Protecting the substantive rights of women would meet the test of section 3 of the Constitution as advanced by Amissah JP in the Dow case and reinforced in the more recent decision by the Appeal Court in the Ramantele ruling for upholding the applicable derogation under section 15. In order to show that he has been made to suffer “inhuman or degrading punishment or other such treatment,” Khwarae would have to show that he was intentionally exposed to mental or physical suffering and that this intentional exposure was committed by or with the acquiescence of state authorities. Failing which, his prayer under section 7 ought to be unsuccessful. The current provisions of section 4(1)(d)(i) of the Adoption Act have serious consequences for the unmarried biological father alone. The Court must 56 clearly and unequivocally elaborate the meaning of consultation as provided for under the 2009 Children’s Act: does consultation entail the opportunity to withhold consent? If not then it does not qualify as a meaningful involvement in the decision-making process and instead becomes an empty provision that does nothing to alleviate the potential consequences for the unmarried father and his biological child. It is further suggested that consultation in some cases may even require that the father grants his consent to the adoption proceedings. The deciding factor will be the best interests of the child, and the prior established relationship or bond between the two would necessarily be relevant and ought to be factored in to the decision making process. The consultation requirement ought to be calibrated accordingly. That leaves the Court in the Khwarae decision with an opportunity to flesh out broad parameters of this requirement, including practicalities relating to the who, when and how of consultation. 57