A Reply to Stephen Hawking’s, The Grand Design Introduction Stephen Hawking has become an icon of a living genius. Undoubtedly heroic in his productive life in spite of a debilitating illness, Hawking has, among other things, popularized aspects of modern physics and astronomy. Most recently, he expressed his opinions on the possibility of a grand, unified theory of everything. His book, The Grand Design, written with Leonard Mlodinow, proposes a theory of cosmic origins that has no need of a transcendent God. My purpose in writing is not to criticize the scientific data Hawking uses to support his broader theory. My concerns are several-fold. First, after reading his book, I’m convinced that Hawking does not realize the extent to which his book is an exercise in philosophical speculation rather than pure science. Second, I do not think Hawking appreciates the philosophical reasons supporting the existence of God. These reasons, I will argue, give belief in God a greater standing than the atheistic position espoused by Hawking. Similarly, it should be made evident that Hawking’s tendency to embrace materialistic assumptions influences his interpretation of the scientific data. Third, Hawking rejects human freedom. I will argue that his rejection of freedom also implies a rejection of truth. All of these criticisms point to features of his book that seriously undermine its value. Is Philosophy Dead? In the second paragraph of his book,i Hawking declares, “philosophy is dead.” Since philosophy has failed to keep up with the discoveries of science, scientists “have become the bearers of the torch of discovery in our quest for knowledge.”ii The great questions concerning human knowledge, reality, origins, and creation, admittedly of concern to most people at least sometimes, now fall to the scientist. Hawking then proceeds to tell, in abbreviated form, the philosophical history that preceded the rise of modern science. One might wish to point out the errors of fact and simplistic summations that are found in the first few chapters of the book. For instance, he incorrectly identifies Epicurus as an opponent of atomism when in fact Epicurus used atomism to support his rejection of life after death.iii He fails to do justice to Aristotle’s reasons for rejecting atomism asserting “he could not accept that human beings were composed of soulless, inanimate objects.”iv In fact, his reasons were many but his most pressing reasons were his various problems with the notion of a “void” that were so essential to atomism. Quibbling about the misrepresentation of historical backgrounds is unnecessary here, however, since it only detracts from the more blaring problem in Hawking’s analysis. In particular, The Grand Design is, almost in its entirety, a work of philosophy. Rather than supporting his claim that philosophy is dead, his book is an effort to provide a theoretical framework for answering ultimate questions based on inferences derived from certain physical theories about the A Reply to Stephen Hawking (McNeil) world. In a move reminiscent of Rene Descartes’ “evil genius” proposal, Hawking rejects scientific realism based on the fact that more than one scientific explanation can explain the observable phenomena. He then proposes “model-dependent realism,” an approach that admits the possibility of a plurality of successful explanatory frameworks but considers questions about the “reality” of the frameworks or models “pointless.”v In other words, he declares the philosophical problem of theoretical knowledge unsolvable and asserts it is not an important question anyway since he is happy to work with a model that embraces inescapable relativism. If the model is “convenient,” that is good enough. What is most interesting at this point is that Hawking is engaged in a series of epistemological choices. Based on the fact that our scientific models are often adapted, modified, or, in more extreme cases, discarded in favor of a different model that explains the data more effectively, he concludes that we are, in principle, incapable of knowing the objective nature of reality. This kind of choice about what sort of knowledge human beings may have is quite similar to what one would find in any introductory philosophy textbook. The fact is that science itself is incapable of answering the question about what humans may know about the world. To the contrary, science rises only from the intuitive certainty that we are truly experiencing “reality.” Hawking is aware, to what degree I am unsure, of the many serious questions that may be raised regarding his position. Since he has chosen a position that makes the argument between realists and anti-realists “pointless,” we might infer from this that Hawking is not at all enthusiastic about a protracted philosophical discussion on the point. He finds a relativistic stance on these questions most appealing. My point here, though, is that this foundational decision is not one that may be proven through a purely scientific argument. In fact, this decision is really one that will shape and determine how he interprets the scientific data; a fact established by reading the rest of his book. Rather than proving the death of philosophy, Hawking’s book is an attempt to answer philosophical questions and support a particular philosophical position by showing its consistency with the latest scientific discoveries. Calling this something other than science only betrays a failure to understand the difference between philosophy and science. If “science,” at least as it is understood now, has to do with what is empirically verifiable through a method of repeated observation and supported generalization about the behavior of the physical world, how could one possibly prove those things that cannot be subjected to that method? It begs the question to suggest that the method proves the truth of its undemonstrated assumptions by its successes. If one has no philosophical confidence that reality is more than merely a fantastic “dream,” the successes of science need be merely a projection of my wishes. Science proceeds based on the philosophical assumption (or, if thought-out, conviction) that there is a world beyond our minds that we can know. It assumes that our minds are somehow adapted to grasp the world and understand its workings. Further, it assumes the basic legitimacy of our powers of reason. This is a point of utmost significance. Physical “laws,” 2 A Reply to Stephen Hawking (McNeil) it seems to me, are primarily our inducted generalizations based on repeated experience. The accumulation of experience supports certain convictions we have about how the world will behave in the future. Of course, I cannot prove that the world will behave tomorrow as it does today. How is it possible to rule out, let’s say, that when the matter of this universe reaches twenty billion years of age it will produce radically different properties than are presently observed? To argue from the “laws of physics,” is to argue from past and present experience and is rooted in a deep trust in the accuracy of the laws of thought that are applied to the sensory world. The so-called “laws of physics” are not observable entities at all. They are inferences from observed behavior of things; inferences that are the result of logical thought. The confidence in the very structures of reason in the human mind is an assumption of science. Science can do nothing at all without this assumption. Science emerges from the confidence of the human mind in its own powers of understanding. Hawking’s declaration that philosophy is dead might have merit as a rebuke to philosophers that have abandoned the great questions to which philosophy classically devoted itself. Simply declaring philosophy “dead” and then proceeding to engage in philosophical reasoning and using science to support one’s philosophical tendencies is blaringly inconsistent, however. Of this inconsistency Hawking is guilty. Near the end of his book, Hawking raises several great questions, similar to those raised early in the work, and proceeds to offer his answers. “Why is there something rather than nothing? Why do we exist? Why this particular set of laws and not some other?”vi He then quickly discards the solution that “there is a God who chose to create the universe that way.” His reply is of utmost importance: “It is reasonable to ask who or what created the universe, but if the answer is God, then the question has merely been deflected to that of who created God.” What does Hawking propose? His conclusion is that gravity is the cause of the creation of the universe. “Because there is a law like gravity, the universe can and will create itself from nothing.”vii From the flow of his argument, it is clear that Hawking thinks that the supreme “given” in this universe is gravity. Since there is gravity, everything else follows. There is no reason to seek further understanding of what this claim might mean. A host of problems present themselves immediately. One might reasonably ask about the origins of the gravitational force itself. Questions might also be offered about whether or not gravity is sufficient, of itself, to explain the origin of all energy and matter. What is “gravity” in radical isolation from space and time? What does it mean to speak of matter coming into existence “from nothing”? Here we are confronted with philosophical questions again. The principal of causality affirms that nothing happens without a reason or cause. In other words, things don’t happen without reason. I do not suspect that Hawking thinks that matter came to be for no reason. He would speak of Who Created God? 3 A Reply to Stephen Hawking (McNeil) conditions in which matter can emerge. Indeed, he admits as much when he speaks of the law of gravity as a precondition for the emergence of matter. “Because there is a law like gravity, the universe can and will create itself from nothing” (emphasis added). The existence of the universe is then a result of certain laws that have a causal relationship to the emergence of energy. What proof is there of the principle of causality? Why must we acknowledge that there is a reason for any given effect? The most obvious reason is that otherwise nothing would be the cause of something. This is equal to affirming that reality is nonsensical. If an effect is produced without a reason or cause, then we cannot rule out any effect. Acceptance of nothing as the final “explanation” of a given effect would, if consistently accepted, signal the end to all rational thought, including all science. Science is, by its very nature, the search for causes. Hawking’s book is an attempt to provide an explanation of the world that we observe. To conclude by saying that the universe came from “nothing,” if taken at face value, would mean that the universe is ultimately reducible to an absurd, nonsensical foundation. Of course, it is not quite so simple. Hawking does not reduce the universe to nothing at all. There is the principle of gravity that is able to spontaneously generate a universe through its positive and negative interactions. Although the matter of the universe did not exist before the initial gravitational fluctuations, the forces themselves existed and are their causal basis. It appears that Hawking has reduced our choices regarding the origins of the universe to two. We either accept the law of gravity as the ultimate explanation for the origins of everything, or we accept the notion of an independent, transcendent cause: God. The second of these is unacceptable, he reasons, because we are merely “deflecting” the issue of creation. At some point, he reasons, we have to admit something is the final explanation of this world. He chooses the law of gravity, others choose God. God is an unnecessary and unhelpful hypothesis, however, since we still have to ask the unsolvable question: Who created God? This line of reasoning is particularly common among atheists who use their scientific background as a platform upon which to air their philosophical commitments. It arises from a fundamental failure to grasp the traditional arguments for God’s existence and their necessary implications. This is especially true regarding the cosmological argument. Let me explain. Every happening must have a cause. The alternative, of course, is that a happening can occur with no cause at all. This is equal to claiming that absolutely nothing can produce something. Offering “nothing” as an explanation is intellectually unsatisfying precisely because nothing lacks explanatory power: it is nothing. Offering nothing as a reason for a particular effect is a non-answer. If the universe is rational and knowable, it follows that we may reasonably search for causes if we observe a happening. If the atheist wishes to reject this he will either (a) undermine science altogether since it is arises from the conviction that reality is 4 A Reply to Stephen Hawking (McNeil) rational or (b) define “nothing” in such a way that it is actually something. If the cause of a given effect is itself an effect of yet another cause, we must search for yet another cause. In other words, if we find that the reason(s) for a given effect are themselves in need of an explanation, we must search for another cause. This search cannot go to infinity, however. If the number of causal preconditions for a given effect or happening are truly infinite in number the effect would never have occurred. Imagine you have to walk past an infinite series of trees before you arrive at your house. What time will you arrive? Never, of course, since one cannot reach the end of an infinity. Since the number of causal preconditions for any given effect cannot be infinite in number, one must acknowledge an end to the causal series. Current Big Bang theory recognizes an “end” insofar as it postulates an origin of the universe. Hawking does not deny such an origin. What he does deny is that anything is needed beyond the physical laws (especially gravity) that are found in this universe. If one argues to God’s existence, he will reason that something beyond the space-time world is needed to account for this universe as a “happening.” Since the series of dependent causes and effects that brought us to this moment of time are finite, we must recognize that something must ground the entire series. That ground must be self-explanatory since otherwise it would merely be another piece of the series of dependent causes. It must escape the categories of change, dependence and matter (as a changing aspect of the space-time world) altogether. We will call this reality “God.” If one follows this reasoning, it makes no sense to ask, “What caused God?” God is discovered precisely as that which needs no cause. A God that needs a cause is no God at all. The real question should be: Is there any reason to think there is a reality that needs no cause? As long as we are confronted with things about which we can reasonably ask, “Why is it?” we are not in the presence of the final explanation of this universe. Hawking admits that “it is reasonable to ask who or what created the universe” (emphasis added). He then proceeds, however, to propose that one of the inferred “laws” of this universe is a transcendent cause of the universe. This conclusion seems to be dictated by a conscious decision to search for an explanation of this universe without admitting the existence of anything beyond it. It is a theory arising from a methodological, philosophical commitment to materialism. To this writer, at least, it seems far more reasonable and compelling to embrace a supreme, transcendent mind as the source of this universe. Our ability to transcend matter in thought, our deep conviction that reality is rational and knowable, and our ability to discover truth are evidence that reality must be understood by appeal to more than mere matter. Furthermore, accepting belief in a transcendent God who willed the creation of the world provides a basis for cosmic meaning. If the ultimate origin of this world is a blind force like gravity, there is no basis for cosmic or human “meaning” or value. In fact, if one is committed to materialistic explanations of this world, his tendency will be to 5 A Reply to Stephen Hawking (McNeil) reduce the more spiritual or immaterial aspects of human experience to merely material effects. Mind and freedom are casualties since they must be treated as illusions arising from the complex operations of a purely material system. Indeed, Hawking draws this conclusion for us in his remarks on human freedom. centered in the brain while the truly moral act that includes freedom involves transcendence above purely material causality. We might add that it appears there is at least some empirical evidence for “neuroplasticity,” the notion that the brain and its activities can be changed over time by deliberate acts of will.ix Additionally, the intuitive experience of “overruling” impulses of the body in view of an intellectually envisioned “end” or goal is powerful evidence in support of a real distinction between the brain and the mind. Contrary to Hawking’s description and suggestions, moral freedom is not simply physical desire.x Further, Hawking makes a conscious choice to reject the interior, intuitive experience of freedom in favor of “the molecular basis of biology” that shows “biological processes are governed by the laws of physics and chemistry and therefore are as determined as the orbits of the planets.” This is a rather astonishing admission. Something of which I am immediately aware (i.e., freedom) is rejected as an illusion in view of something I observe through my senses (biological processes). To my mind this move discredits the validity of his theory. Later Hawking will assert that a “good model” is one that “agrees with and explains all existing observations.”xi Why doesn’t the direct experience of freedom through interior conscious awareness constitute “observational” evidence? If the reply is that only empirically verifiable observational evidence will be accepted it is only too easy to reply that all empirical verification must find its way into the conscious awareness of the person and therefore our conscious life is the ultimate context or precondition for a discussion about No Free Will? Hawking denies “free will”: “It is hard to imagine how free will can operate if our behavior is determined by physical law, so it seems that we are no more than biological machines and that free will is just an illusion.”viii Because desire to move parts of the body can be simulated by electrically stimulating the relevant parts of the brain, it follows, he argues, that our actions and desires are nothing more than effects of physical causes. However, the physical causes of any given desire or action are so complicated that we can make use of the “effective theory” that humans are free. In other words, we are not really free but we can act like we are because of how complicated the physical causes are that determine our actions. In reply, Hawking does not seem to understand what is meant by freedom of the will. Freedom has specifically to do with intellectual understanding and moral direction. One can admit a physical basis for much of human activity without denying moral freedom. For instance, a person may have the desire to do one thing but know they should not yield to those desires. The desire might be rooted in a physical response 6 A Reply to Stephen Hawking (McNeil) models, theories, God, freedom, or whatever else one might wish to discuss. Explaining away the conscious life or experience of freedom as simply a determined or necessary effect of a purely physical process creates a crisis of truth. Let’s consider an example. Hawking thinks there is no God and that gravity is the absolute principle that explains the entire universe of our experience. I, on the other hand, think there is a God and that the universe cannot explain itself. Despite the illusion of freedom and conscious decision-making involved in our assertions, both of us are really merely saying and thinking what the physical causes within our biology are requiring that we say and think. If the physical causes are the ultimate reason why we say, do, and think, the category of “truth,” as anything more than an illusion of consciousness, evaporates. It doesn’t make sense to say that one set of physical causes is “true” while another set is “false.” These are merely subjective effects somehow resulting from physical causes that, if Hawking is right, completely explain our mental states. The conclusion, then, is there is no such thing as objective truth about anything. Hawking wrote his book because his biology demanded that he do so. The illusion that he did so freely and that he consciously chose his position because it corresponds to reality is worthless (except, perhaps, as an “effective theory” masking the true reality). Unless the human mind and will transcend matter in some truly meaningful sense, the pursuit of truth is nonsensical. If biological determinism is true, neither of us is “right.” This is so fundamentally opposed to our universal, interior conviction that we not only are able to make judgments about objective truths but also that we are able to act freely in acts of selfdetermination. This is especially evident when we think about truths that have a logical force that compels or forces the mind to assent. The geometry student that “sees” in the mind’s eye that the interior angles of a Euclidean triangle must be 180 degrees sees this conclusion through the light of reason that imposes itself on the human mind. It is this ability to see by the light of reason that enables us to understand the nature of the world around us, develop theories about it, know the reality of our own minds and, at its height, become aware of the reality of the God who transcends all matter and is the ultimate source of reason and truth. The Pythagoreans, Stoics, Plato, Plotinus, Augustine, and a host of others were captivated by the all-pervasive presence of reason governing the material world. The very predictability and regularity of nature that lends itself to mathematical analysis directs our minds to a supreme mind that is the ultimate source the “laws of nature.” As mathematical truth properly belongs in a mind in order to be seen as “true,” so it is the material world’s ordered activity is evidence of a supreme mind as its ultimate ground and source. Just as Hawking leaves out the interior experience of freedom and consciousness and reduces all of reality to material processes, so he seeks to reduce all order and rationality in the universe to purely material causality. The consequence, as noted, is that if there is no mind that transcends matter, there is no truth. Hawking cannot lay 7 A Reply to Stephen Hawking (McNeil) claim to having arrived at truth, then, but only to doing what his biology required that he do. energy of this universe will one day undergo a final development. Mortality will be elevated to immortality. The process of death and decay will be shed in favor of a renewed creation featuring the triumph of life over death. Since this transformation of nature has yet to occur, it is inaccessible to science. If God has performed a miracle revealing that ultimate divine intention it could only be accessed by historical memory. The existence of Christianity through the centuries is the historical effect of the historical claim that Christ rose from the dead. If Christianity is right on this point, as I believe it is, the typical regularity of nature provides a sufficient grounds for science (as well as other disciplines) while miracle highlights the inherent limits of science and the power of God over the creation as well as the conviction that the worldprocess has a meaning grounded in the will of a personal God who has acted in history. Conclusion Although I lack the background to make a judgment on Stephen Hawking’s scientific achievements, I am relatively certain that his achievements will merit him a place in books on the history of science. In my judgment, however, his efforts at integrating his scientific insights with his commitment to materialism and, apparently, atheism, are not compelling. One final thought. Since he rejects the need for God in his understanding of the universe, Hawking also rejects the notion of miracle. In this article I have suggested that the “laws of physics” are not independently existing entities but are, instead, descriptions of the regular behavior of this world. The ultimate cause of the structure and behavior of this world is beyond the methods of science. If the regularity of nature is ultimately a scientific way of describing divine providence, one cannot a priori exclude the possibility of miracle. It may be that the regular providence of God only places an accent mark on miracles as unique moments in history by which God directs attention to realities and truths that transcend the revelatory power of nature. A Christian, for instance, believes that in Christ God revealed his heart of love in a way that the created world was incapable of expressing. It is not, for instance, that the resurrection of Jesus is a “violation” of nature as much as it is a manifestation of the eschatological will of God revealed early. The Christian believes that the Mark A. McNeil 9-26-2010 i Stephen Hawking and Leonard Mlodinow, The Grand Design (Bantam Books: NY), 2010. ii 5. iii 22. iv Ibid. v 46 vi 171. vii 180. viii 32. ix Schwartz, Mind and Brain. 8 A Reply to Stephen Hawking (McNeil) x xi Hawking, 31-2. 51. 9