Boundary Objects Michael Glassman: [The] big issue here that I am trying to grapple with…boundary objects… relates to the metaphor of the table…. [I]n the museum should the place be set up as affordances, perceived affordances, or constraints? It seems the museum in the study has potential affordances for the users. The cultural historical moment (unable to think of any other word) of the museum sets the context, meaning those walking through the museum are going to be restricted by the historical and cultural boundaries leading up to the art work, along with the expectations and needs of the individuals moving through the museum, but they will come across objects/artifacts that they think meets the needs of their particular journeys. …Or should museums should be designed for what Don Norman refers to as perceived affordances?...The focus goes from cultural history setting a general context…to actually setting the trajectory of the act….The object offers an opportunity to make communicative gestures…. Or should museums be designed as constraints. In the Metropolitan Museum of Art… the rooms are set up very, very carefully, so that in many ways the objects…to constrain your thinking, so that you are responding to a certain period or school of art, understanding how it all fits together. The table metaphor fits here as well I think. Does the table constrain our actions, limiting to certain types of behavior (use only certain types of forks for certain types of food). Henry Shonerd: …I see a parallel between your work on boundary objects, where individual persons collaborate to create spaces, AND boundary objects “negotiated” by groups of people who live in real spaces. I am thinking, among other things, of indigeneity, a big topic here in New Mexico, with so many Native Americans. Assymetries of power. Bullying. Testing and curriculum become instruments of war by other means…. Andy Blunden: [W]ould it be correct to describe the government institutions and political system are "boundary objects"? RS: [P]otentially…depending on how the concept is applied. Star describes three criteria: 1) interpretive flexibility 2) material/organizational structure and 3) scale/ granularity in which the concept is useful. …boundary objects are typically most useful at the organizational level - so I would say that one would have to justify the utility of applying the concept to a particular institution, as opposed to, say, an object within an institution. AB: …It seems to me that what BOs do is introduce some social theory into domains of activity (scientific and work collaborations for example) where the participants naively think they are collaborating on neutral ground. So it is not just granularity, but also the ideological context…. RS: …I think it depends on the aspect of activity one is attempting to explore as opposed to the definite identification of what may or may not be a boundary object…. HS: [What can be a boundary object?] AB: …[A]nything. But the point is objects which play some role in mediating the relation between subjects, probably a symbolic role, but possibly an instrumental role, too, and one subject challenges that role and turns the object into its opposite, and changes the terms of collaboration. …[The] core point is that the ideological construction placed upon an object is subject to contestation, and if successful, the re-marking of an artefact is a tremendously powerful spur to subjectivity. Yrjo raises the question: is the"boundary object" a mediating artefact or the object of work (/Arbeitsgegenstand/)? I think the answer is that in these cases it is a mediating artefact, tool or symbols according to context. In principle it is not the Object in the Engestromian sense, though it might happen to be. AJG: the difference that [Engeström & cols.] point out between boundary object on the one hand, and object and instrumentality as different aspects of activity theory on the other. …[Rolf & I] noticed that the museum space…was a means, an instrument for achieving a final design product. At the same time, the museum space begun to become the object of the designers' activity. …what seemed to be a common object for all them was the museum as place. Thus, most representations of it begun to be made in terms of narratives about being there. That was the orientation that seemed to stick them together. Thus, the museum space was both object and instrument. We wondered whether we should do connections to notions of object of activity and tools, but we felt that that road would take us away from the focus on body and experience. We ended up drawing from Binder et al (2011), who differentiate between object of design, the design thing that work delivers, and the object's constituents (or means of presentation before the design thing is finished). …One advantage was that boundary objects focus on the materiality, which, as already mentioned, is not about materials in themselves, but about consequences in action. … But I still want to learn what we may get out of making the distinction between object and tool, as Engeström and colleagues do (so I should perhaps read more carefully their study rather than be here thinking aloud). Boundary Object // Methodology: definition of ‘object’ and discussions about Activity Theory LSP: I am not sure what you mean in this sentence: "But I still want to learn what we may get out of making the distinction between object and tool, as Engeström and colleagues do (so I should perhaps read more carefully their study rather than be here thinking aloud)." In classic Activity Theory there is a very well defined distinction between the object of activity and the means/mediating instruments for shaping/changing that object. Actually, one of the "formulas" or models is Subject (in the sense of Classical German philosophy)--Means--Object (of that activity). ...[H]ow is your approach related to classic Activity Theory?…I would like to clarify certain things for myself. For example: What are the limits and boundaries of Activity Theory? How much we can fuse Activity Theory and Postmodernist approaches? What do we gain when we infuse new methodological, epistemological, and ontological realities into Activity Theory? What do we lose? What is the threshold when it is not Activity Theory anymore? (I mean here Activity Theory as research methodology.) Do we need to call something Activity Theory if it is not? If we create a new approach starting with Activity Theory, do we need to call it Activity Theory? Activity Theory is a product of Modern thinking, Late Modernism. The discourse you use in your paper borrows strongly from Postmodern discourses and approaches. I am not sure that Modernist and Postmodernist discourses can be fused. We can borrow ideas across the range of discourses, but after we assimilate them for use in our project, they will "change hands" and will change their particular discourse affiliation and will become completely different components of a completely different discourse. Mostly because the epistemologies and ontologies are different; and the concepts are very different despite of the similarities in ideas and words used to name these ideas. Just a few questions that I hope will help me understand better what is going on in the realm of CHAT. AJG: …[W]e describe in the paper has to do with how the object of design emerged and developed for the team in and as they were dealing with, developing, and resorting to particular means or tools. But I guess we could say that in our analyses there is a lack of a historical account of the object that goes over and above the particular instances analyzed. Although we provide with some ethnographic contextualization of the team's developmental trajectories, all of our discussion is grounded on concrete events and their transactional unfolding. We did not resort to the distinction between object and means because it seemed to be the same thing in the there and then of the episodes analyzed, at least in what participants' orientations concerned. If they oriented towards anything beyond what was there in the meetings, it was in and through the meetings' means. How would then the distinction between means and object have added to our understanding of the events? (And this is not to doubt of the contribution from such a distinction, I really mean to ask this question for the purpose of growing and expanding; and as said before, part of the answer may be found in Engestrom et al. contribution). As to how we would position our contribution with regard to activity theory, I would reiterate what we said when introducing the paper for discussion: we begun with the purpose of working outside any particular framework and think, as we think Star did, broadly, drawing from several sources. These included cultural historical psychology, ethnomethodology, and discourse analysis. But also the ideas about Experience (in the Deweyan/Vygotskyan sense) that have been the topic in this discussion were in the background all the time, but we did not operationalize them in terms of any particular theory. This is not to say that we went for the "anything goes;" we tried our best to keep internal coherence between what we said about the data, and what the data was exhibiting for us. Perhaps Rolf would like to add to this…. AB: If I could try to do my thing and draw attention to some distinctions in this field ... we have at least three different versions of Activity Theory involved here plus Leigh Star's theory and in addition the theories that have spun off from Leigh Star's initial idea. Each is using the word "object" in a different way, all of them legitimate uses of the English word, but all indexing different concepts. So for the sake of this discussion I will invent some different terms. The German word Arbeitsgegenstand means the object of labour, the material which is to be worked upon, the blacksmith's iron. It is objective, in that if may be a nail to a man with a hammer and waste material for a man with a broom, but it is all the same Arbeitsgegenstand. Engestrom use the word "Object" in the middle of the left side of the triangle to mean Arbeitsgegenstand, and when it has been worked upon it becomes "Outcome." The hammer that the blacksmith uses is called "Instruments" or now "instrumentality," and the Rules, whether implicit or explicit, these are respectively the base and apex of the triangle. Engestrom says " The object carries in itself the purpose and motive of the activity." So this "purpose or motive" is not shown on the triangle, but I will call it the OBJECT. This is what Leontyev meant by "object" when he talks about "object-oriented activity." The OBJECT is a complex notion, because it is only *implicit* in the actions of the subject(s); it is not a material thing or process as such. Behaviourists would exclude it altogether. But this is what is motivating all the members of the design team when they sit down to collaborate with one another. Bone one of the team thinks the OBJECT is to drive the nail into the wood and another thinks the OBJECT is to sweep the Arbeitsgegenstand into the wastebin. These OBJECTs change in the course of collaboration and in the End an OBJECT Is *realised* which is the "truth" of the collaboration, to use Hegel's apt terminology here. Surely it is important to recognise that while everyone shares the same Arbeitsgegenstand, and ends up with Outcome as the same OBJECT, along the road they construe the object differently. This is what Vygotsky showed so clearly in Thinking and Speech. It is not the Arbeitsgegenstand or some problem carried within it alone which motivates action, but *the concept the subject makes of the Arbeitsgegenstand*! Then Leigh Star comes along and applies (as Lubomir astutely notices) postmodern ideology critique to the collaboration within an ostensibly neutral infrastructure - that is, in Engestrom's terms Rules and Instruments, which are naively supposed to be there just to aid collaboration. And Leigh Star shows that this is an illusion; the Rules and Instruments are in fact residues of past collaborations which carry within them the Outcomes, i.e., realised OBJECTs of past collaborations. It is these one-time OBJECTs, now-Instruments+Rules which are the Boundary Objects. But it seems that others have grasped the postmodern critique elements of this idea, that apparently ideologically neutral obJects (in the expanded sense of socially constructed entities, usually far more than OBJects - as things, or artefacts, including institutions fossilised "systems of activity") and recognised the shared OBJECT as a Boundary Object, reflecting the fact not everyone has the same concept of the OBJECT, as Vygotsky proved. But what Engestrom has done, by placing the Boundary Object in the place of Object on his triangle, joining two "systems of activity," for the purpose of looking not at cooperation but rather the conflict within the broader collaboration. The reconstrual of the Arbeitsgegenstand is deliberate and aimed to change the relation between Subject and obJECT (here referring to the Hegelian "Object" usually rendered as "the Other.") thereby introducing yet a different strand of postmodern critique into the equation, namely Foucault's Poststructuralism, to my mind, with great effect. OK, so we have Arbeitsgegenstand. OBJECT, Boundary Object, OBject, obJECT and obJect. And I might say, the situation is almost as bad in Russian and German. LP: …I will try to focus on one particular relation you have highlighted. If I am clear on your distinctions then: It is not the Arbeitsgegenstand ALONE [the object OF labour or the object upon which labour works] where the problem resides. The problem is NOT carried WITHIN the Arbeitsgegenstand as an abstraction. The OBJECT [purposes and motives] includes also the "concept" that the subject-person makes OF the arbeitsgegenstand [object OF labour]. So it is the concept's relation WITH the arbeitsgegenstand [object OF labour] that generates "subject's socially shared OBJECTs [purposes and motives]. Andy, I may have garbled your construal of the relations involved in these two meanings of "object", my question is why not just say "object of labour" [when we mean arbeitsgegenstand] AND say "purposes and motives” when we mean OBJECT. In the same way that Dewey wishes he had used a different term for "experience" it seems we need alternative terms for "object". I am also struggling to understand the historical movement implied in the alternative changing OBJECTs [purposes and motives] expressed in how a term is situated. The notion of "polyphonic" languages with shifting meanings and OBJECTS seems very complex and seems to require expansive understandings of multiple different "languagegames" [as Wittgenstein uses that concept. The labour process AND the conceptual process and multiple modern / postmodern understandings of "their" [using personal pronoun] relations. Very complex process. AJG: …[C]oncern[ing] the quote that the object "carries in itself the purpose and motive of the activity." What does "in itself" mean here? AB: Well, they're Yrjo's words so he will have to tell you, but I can tell you how I've construed them. Not until you asked, did I see that there is ambiguity in the phrase. I had always taken it that the purpose and motive is "in the nature" of the Arbeitsgegenstand. I think Yrjo gives an example somewhere of a person who is ill - it is obvious that the illness needs to be cured. So I read "in itself" literally. "in it" would be the same. But there is an alternative Hegelian reading, that in the Arbeitsgegenstand, the is an OBJECT which is only "in itself," that is, not yet realised, and that makes good sense. It slides over the point that Larry raised, that the OBJECT is not in the Arbeitsgegenstand alone but in the relation of the Arbeitsgegenstand to the Subject, but that is consistent with how Hegel uses the phrase "in itself." LSP: The object doesn't carry in itself the motive and the purpose of activity. Actually, depending on the motive and purpose of activity, the object can be approached in many different ways. It is true that the relationship between the object and the subject caries the purpose/goal/objective/motive of activity. This type of relationship might have several aspects and the teleological aspect is one of them. Actually, in AT, the teleological aspect is central one among all aspects of Subject-Object relationships. The teleological aspect in AT is envisaged at several levels with distinctive teleological phenomena: motivation, goal, etc…. LP: Here is a quote from the introduction of "The Cambridge Handbook of MerleauPonty on the topic of the subject. "Foucault's archaeological studies of the early 1970's, most notably "The Order of Things" and "The Archaeology of Knowledge", did perhaps more than any other work of the period to LEGITIMIZE conceiving of processes without subjects." This is an "antihumanist" program as Foucault saw the failure of phenomenology and the residual links between subjectivism and anthropology. The force of Foucault's argument was tying the philosophy of the subject to what he saw as an outmoded humanism. It may be what Andy is highlighting is a new humanism. AB: That is exactly right, Larry, I am advocating a humanism, in opposition to poststructuralism, structuralism Marxism, and strands of Activity Theory which give everything to the Object. LSP: Merleau-Ponty works in a completely different paradigm than AT and what he says should be interpreted in the context of that paradigm. AT should be interpreted in the context of Historical Materialism. Otherwise, it is not AT. It might be a study of activity, but in a different paradigm…. In historical materialism, activity and process are two different things. Activity is a process, but it is more than a process. It is planned and goal-directed, while the process is naturally flowing. In the natural world (Nature) there are processes, but they are not activities. The primacy of the subject is typical for historical materialism…. The study of activity and AT are two different things. AT is a particular way of studying activity in the framework of historical materialism. Any attempt to fuse phenomenology or hermeneutics in AT might create a product that is not AT. …AT is not the most productive way to engage in experiential and descriptive study of activity as an everyday phenomenon. AT presupposes a top-down approach to the study of activity, imposing a set of methodological principles and theoretical framework. There are situations when this approach is very productive. However, if we emphasize the human experience aspect and the importance to unveil new aspects and their subsequent descriptions, I would not use AT. MC: …I recall Lubomir writing that AT was centered on the subject. And now Andy is gesturing to Strands of AT theory that give everything to the object. Question-- isn't this a version of Rubenshtein/Leontiev schools' conflict? Or LSV "vs" AN L on the problem of the environment? Or? What is at stake here theoretically and practically? …I almost want to ask -- what forms of joint mediated activity do not involve boundary objects?... AB: …What it comes down to is the insistence of ANL in interpreting contradictions between the "subjective sense" and the "objective meaning" of an activity in terms of the social vs. the individual. This reduces subjectivity to a matter of the capriciousness of the individual mind or the underdevelopment of the child mind. This is hardly objectionable in the domain of child development, but in the domain of social theory it is a Neanderthal position. Social life is made up of a multiplicity of standpoints among which none have the right to claim unproblematic "objective truth" for themselves. This is the basis on which I describe ANL as giving too much to the Object….I see Engestrom's approach as a kind of social behaviourist approach in which change occurs only thanks to "contradictions" at different levels in the "system." My aim in proposing to see the "system" as a "project" at one or another phase in its life cycle aims to restore the purposiveness of human action to Activity Theory…. …The problem with your question about Boundary Objects…I can now see 3 different meanings of the term. Manfred Holodynski: …As far as I interpret ANL he presented a very elegant solution of the relation between sense and meaning: For ANL, subjective sense is not a part or subset of objective meaning (as you seem to insinuate him), but a psychological quality that emerges when a person uses societal signs and their objective meanings in order to regulate his or her socially embedded activity. What happens is a transformation of societal meanings into the personal sense of those involved. The personal sense that an individual assigns to interactions, facts, and experiences through the use of signs can be conceptualized not as a subset of societal meanings but as a particular sphere of mind that is constituted by two psychological factors in particular (a) the relation to the motives of the person, and (b) the relation to the situated and sensorially mediated experiences of the individual within the process of internalization. a) People do not appropriate the use of signs and their meanings during social interactions in an impartial way. They interpret and use them in the light of their actually elicited motives along with the motives they assign to the interaction partner. The societal meaning of the used signs does not have to match the individually assigned personal sense. For example, an outsider may well interpret a public fit of rage by a low-ranking bank employee toward his superior as an inexcusable violation of social etiquette. However, for the menial employee, it may well be a reassertion of self-esteem in response to a humiliating directive. b) The personal sense of sign-use is also determined by the situatedness and sensory mediation of the previous encounters in which the use of signs is (or was) embedded. Societal meanings are coded primarily not by propositional phrases (e.g., “a dog is a mammal” or “wide-open eyes signal fear”) but through their ties to sensorially mediated and situated perceptions—as complex as these interrelations may be…. Thus, conventionalized signs and the meanings assigned to them are subject to an interpersonal process of interpretation and coordination that more or less successfully supports the embodiment and expression of personal sense. People do not have a private “speech” at their disposal that they can construct and use on their own (Wittgenstein). Therefore, they depend on the appropriation and use of conventionalized signs when they want to communicate successfully and satisfy their motives in social interactions. By an act of reflection, the person can try to realize and to become aware of his personal relation and sense of the situation and the used signs, but also this reflection has to fall back on societal signs in order to express this personal relations. So, this is the overall tension between objective meaning of an event or an object and its personal sense for a specific person. AB: …I am a social theorist, that is I am interested in changing societal arrangements (to put it very politely), and I am one of few social theorists, properly so-called, who base themselves on Vygotsky's theories, and use Activity Theory as well. My position is a contradictory one because Vygotsky and Leontyev were psychologists (like you) and not social theorists. …Social theorists have ideas about psychology, but generally not scientific ones, and vice versa. In my opinion, Vygotsky's ideas provide an excellent foundation for social theory because he introduced into human development and every interaction between two individuals a culturally produced sign. But he only went so far. He showed how people acted and developed within their social situation, but he did not tackle the problem of how that situation arose. Leontyev, by his discovery of the Activity as a macro-unit of activity, made an epoch-making development which opened CHAT to become a fully developed social-and-psychological theory. But what he said himself on questions of social theory was of very poor quality…. Now, to your point. If I am not mistaken "objective meaning" is not a psychological category at all for Leontyev. Yes? And personal sense is, as you eloquently explain, a fundamental Psychological category. So if what I said were to be interpreted to say that personal sense is a subset of objective meaning, that would be quite wrong. While I accept (as I must) a categorical difference between material objects/processes and their reflection in my mind, I do not at all understand societal processes as nonpsychological processes. I try to conceive of them together in one unit, and I think I am on my own there…. There remains of course the distinction between the individual (Einzeln) and the universal (Allgemein), mediated by the particular (Besonder). A human individual is something radically different from a number of individuals….I am interested in how the Activities go. In small part to avoid having arguments with followers of Leontyev I call activities "projects." …if there is any confusion with projects as defined by Existentialists, I call them "collaborative projects." (i.e., people usually join them, not create them). …all those things which gives our lives meaning while we build the world we and our children must live in, what Fedor Vasilyuk called an отношение . A project is not a collection of people, it is an aggregate of actions (like an Activity) and the "logic" of projects is something different from Psychology, but it is inclusive of Psychology as well. A project is a kind of psychological phenomenon, but it is also much more than psychology, because, as you remind us, people regulate their own behaviour using signs created in the world beyond their ken. Projects are the material substance of Concepts, and I rely on Vygotsky for a Psychology of concepts. OK? LSP: Hi Mike and Andy, Sorry, it takes time to respond…. In Historical Materialism, the subject is an active social agent. The subject exists objectively. This is not a paradox in that paradigm. On the other hand, although materialists talk about the objective existence of the world, they conceptualize people as active social agents, while the object of activity is subservient to the social agent/subject of activity. In addition, there is a dialectic between the objective existence of human beings and their subjective (in the sense of personal, individual) perception of the world. The subject is in the center of everything. When we talk about "subject", we do not mean subjectivity in the US sense. The Histmat is an objectivist paradigm that professes the objective existence of humans but at the same time acknowledges the perceptions and agency of the individual. It is a bit different to translate/transfer these concepts. In Historical Materialism the subject is not subjective in the Anglo sense, not biased, not partial, but exists objectively according to the laws of social reality. Of course, in a different usage of the term "subjective," the subject can display subjectivity in the Anglo sense, like developing political bias and prejudice in his/her perceptions and actions regarding the social world. So, the subject exists objectively and always in control of the object. The dialectic of the subjective and objective regarding a social individual also means that each individual has his/her own specific consciousness, but its content is affected strongly by objective social laws that the subject cannot disregard, even if he/she wishes so. By "social laws" we mean social regularities, and actually the Histmat people say -- objectively existing social regularities. This means that the subjects or individuals can not affect or change these objective social regularities. Again, there is no paradox when the Histmat people believe that the objective laws of social reality cannot be changed, but at the same time subjects have the power to change their lives and the organization of society. Yes, subjects/social agents can make changed, but within the limits of social regularities and using these objective social processes to their advantage, creating synergy. In Histmat, they talk about subjective meaning (like in the Anglo discourses) and objective meaning (socially agreed and accepted in everyday life conventions)…. In principle, it is very difficult to translate/convert Histmat ideas into Anglo discourses. Most of the stuff will be lost in translation. Even German words like Tatigkeit and Activitat are used very differently than in German language where they are synonyms. Marx has used these words to denote two very different concepts: Tatigkeit is activity, whole Aktivitat is used for all kinds of chemical and biological process, denoting some kind of movement and development of the situation or the cell, or whatever. The Histmat people religiously follow and keep this differentiation. It is a big mistake to substitute Tatigkeit (deyatelnost in Russian) for Aktivitat (aktivnost in Russian). Actually, the definition of deyatelnost is that it is goal-directed aktivnost. AB: …[I]t is not a problem of unfamiliarity with diamat…. It is partly a problem of the departmentalisation of knowledge and activity, and partly a problem of getting one's head around genuinely interdisciplinary concepts. Unlike Manfred, you have ventured beyond the bounds of Psychology, so you give me the opportunity to illustrate my point. Let us suppose that there are three characters whom I will call the Psychologist, the Sociologist and the Social Theorist for the sake of convenience. You play the role of *the Psychologist*. Everything in your explanation is about the individual (a.k.a. subject) on one side, and society with its unchangeable laws, on the other. Objective meaning, is *socially agreed*! By whom? Pretty well any Psychologist will be inclined to see things this way…. They are a very small agent in the world, but enough of an agent to change what matters to them. It is the subject, an individual, on one side, and society with its unchanging, "agreed," "objective" meanings on the other. *The Sociologist* on the other hand, does his or her survey and tells us that men and women think differently, as do retired people and workers, and blue collar workers have different opinions from white collar workers and so on. And these different groups of people interact. The Sociologist agrees that "objective laws of social reality cannot be changed" but he/she knows that every proposition you want to make about the social reality is contested, and there is no "socially agreed" meaning for anything. …[I]f things change it is because of the changing relations between these groups, and these changes are beyond the power of any individual to do anything about them. …It is a matter of formulating the laws governing the interaction between these groups. For *the Social Theorist*, the individual is an agent in the world beyond their immediate sphere of life only insofar as they can participate in some project…it is here, taking actions as part of a collaborative project, that the regularities of social life are made and broken. These projects are motivated by concepts of themselves which are manifested by their actions in the world as a whole, embedded in artefacts and signs and active in the consciousness of individual participants…. These projects are not the Sociologists' social groups, but activities made up not of individuals but of actions. Projects are not sociological entities. They are the actions of individuals and are just as much part of Psychology as Social Theory, but the actions of individuals as such are mere capriciousness, grains of dust in the wind, except insofar as they are coordinated by concepts, that is, are carried out in collaboration with others. The world is made up not of old and young, male and female, Muslim and Christian, but feminism, business, farming, sport, socialism, etc., activities, the unit of which is a project. Mike asked what is at stake here? What is at stake if we insist that there is an objective world, whose laws cannot be changed, and words/signs have objective meanings which are "socially agreed"? Where, if you don't accept the "socially agreed" meaning, you need to see a Psychologist to find out why. And who is it that is the arbiter of the "socially agreed" meaning of everything? Surely it speaks for itself. LP: …I find myself wondering about the characteristics of "action" which are NOT individual. Actions "manifest" projects which are "realized" by concepts OF the projects. In other words, projects manifest "by" concepts "upon" these projects. …[A]s I try to grasp this understanding I reflect on Dewey's "having an experience" in relation to "having knowledges. Your way of unifying experiences and knowledges though shared actions (undergone and manifested) as historically effected activities coming to be through developing concepts…. AB: When I say: "activities made up not of individuals but of actions," I should have said "activities made up not of persons but of actions." It is always persons who act. I referred to concepts being "manifested", not projects. Projects are aggregates of actions, and both projects and actions are manifested in physical movements of things and people. It is not projects which are realised by concepts, but concepts which are realised by projects. And this is the only part of Activity Theory as I see it which is really difficult to get your head around. MH: …Ok, if one is going to analyze what the essence of an "objective meaning" e.g. of the word "dog" is (and all the more of abstract terms such as feminism, social justice), then one will find oneself in a confusing struggle of different meanings that are also changing with time. So, the objective meaning of a word or concept is fuzzy and of many voices. Nevertheless, people are sometimes (:-) ) able to communicate their personal sense by using words and concepts. This is not a hopeless endeavor although it sometimes and for some people fails miserably. Your construction of a theory of collaborative projects is indeed a noteworthy proposal to deal with the societal emergence and change of the objective meanings of concepts that maintain the link between the social and psychological plane. AB: Thanks Manfred. I think we are on the same page. This "confusing struggle of different meanings" is of course nothing other than activity. That is how signs and situations acquire psychological meanings, and children learn not only by observing but by participating in those activities. David Kellogg: I think that the theory of language described here is really on a par with the Social Theory that Andy described--that is, Neanderthal. But even the Neanderthals, at least according to N.Y. Marr, and Volosinov, and Vygotsky knew that sense is actually primary, not signification. Signification emerges, in the life of the child and for all we know in the life of primitive societies as well, as a generalization of sense, rather than sense emerging as a psychological category from the activation of signification. That is why Voloshinov says that if there were a language that consisted of a single word (e.g. childly language) it would have sense and not signification. Whenever someone tries to justify the Leontievian idea that sense is a psychological category that emerges from the activation of signification in social contexts, and that it is underwritten by perception, they always use examples like "dog". But a much more appropriate example would be "this", since this is very often the child's first word in English. Since the sense of "this" changes with almost every single use, it's quite impossible to see how it might emerge from a correspondence to perceptual categories. "This", "that", "those", "there", and "then" (as well as their interrogative forms, "which", "what", "whose", "where" and "when") may or may not correspond to perceptions; they certainly don't correspond to any perceptual categories. What kind of perception or experience corresponds to "If you are thirsty, there's some beer in the fridge"? Does it correspond to the experience that every time I am thirsty beer appears in the fridge by magic? LP: David [and Andy] and others interested in this topic. I am trying to get clear on the question of the "starting" point/place. David wrote: “sense is actually primary, not signification. Signification emerges, in the life of the child and for all we know in the life of primitive societies as well, as a generalization of sense, rather than sense emerging as a psychological category from the activation of signification.” THIS sense before THAT generalization. David, you are making a claim that Andy starts from a place of generalization. ALL signification is generalization. Your claim is THAT THIS occurs after "sense". SO the question becomes the relation of sense AND signification. [this and that]. Categories such AS the psychological category do or do not emerge FROM activating signification. Is this relation the question? Apologies if I misunderstand DK: Larry, Manfred: My claim goes with Andy's--he wants to organize a little colloquium where the sociologist and the psychologist are each put right by the social theories. I am inviting linguists too--I think that linguists actually provide the practical means by which the social becomes psychological and vice versa. Andy wanted to point out how grossly inadequate Leontiev's social theory was. I would like to add that his theory of language is (as a consequence, actually) grossly inadequate as well. Much of Thinking and Speech is devoted to showing that learning the names of objects is not the same thing as learning language; the power of language does not lie in its ability to signify objects or even percepts but rather in its ability to realize meanings (Vygotsky says "signifying" as opposed to "nominative" or "indicative" function). Meanings aren't things that you see; in fact, if we have to relate them to things we see at all, we might start by saying that the meanings are precisely the things you don't see. MH: …may be you misunderstood my claim…a person has to use signs with their objective meaning in order to express his sense and to realize and satisfy his motives. So, sense doesn't emerge from signification - that is what I tried to say - and I also understand Leontyev in this way. Also, the first words of children are related to a perception. Also first words such as "this" are related to a common situation or object that child and caregiver share and the meaning of this may be "look at this and share it with me" as a kind of joint attention between child and caregiver. Of course, the word "this" or "da" is related to different objects in different situations, but in socially shared situations where the referent of "this" is clear to both. …The argument that speech can go far beyond perceptions, ok, this is obvious, but this is not the starting point of speech development. So, what is your point? DK: I think that Leontiev and Vygotsky disagreed, and they disagreed fundamentally. For Leontiev, language use is essentially ancillary; that is, it is there to help along material processes (perception in the child and labor in the adult) which would function without language. A rose is a rose by any other name, and in fact a rose is a rose without any name at all. For Vygotsky language use is not ancillary at all. This is because the specifically human functions--the things that make language into language and the things that make human beings into truly human beings--are actually produced by language itself (verbal thinking, social thinking, culture, higher psychological processes, whatever we wish to call them). A name is a name without a rose. Child language isn't brought into being through perception; animals do perception pretty well, and they never develop language. It would be much truer to say that it is brought into being through gesture, or that it arises alongside gesture. This is certainly true ontogenetically, and it is probably just as true sociogenetically (although there isn't really any way to know this). Meaning, in the sense of "intending" is primary not perception. A name is not a name until the child intends to name the rose. LP: This "confusing struggle of different meanings" is of course nothing other than activity. That is how signs and situations acquire psychological meanings. …I will share Vygotsky's own words on what a concept is: "A real concept is an IMAGE of an objective thing in all its complexity. Only when we recognize the thing in all its connections and relations, only when this diversity is synthesized in a word in an INTEGRAL IMAGE through a multitude of determinations, do we develop a concept. According to the teaching of dialectical logic, a concept INCLUDES not only the general but also the individual and particular. In contrast to contemplation, to direct knowledge of an object, a concept is filled with definitions of the object; it is the RESULT of rational processing of our existence AND it is mediated knowledge of the object. To think of some object with the help of a concept MEANS TO INCLUDE the GIVEN object in a complex SYSTEM of mediating connection and relations DISCLOSED in determinations of the concept" [Vygotsky, The Collected Works, Volume 5, Child Psychology, page 53] I felt my struggle I am going through may be relevant to others. In particular "when we recognize the thing in all its connections and relations .... THROUGH a multitude of DETERMINATIONS". THIS [thing] is synthesized "in a word" IN AN INTEGRAL IMAGE". AB: …I am not the only one who insists that a concept is a unity of individual, universal and particular! The thing is, Larry, if we think of the concept of "game", how does the child come to use "game" in a way that adults will understand and in turn be able to react when adults use it? This is of course a protracted process but it is through actions. In Thinking and Speech, Vygotsky explains concept formation only in terms of actions, not any kind of hypothetical mental images or dictionaries or mental filing systems or whatever. It is all actions which are in one way or another organised around some artefact, and in particular a word. …But it is in the whole bundle of actions around the word “game” that a child or an adult learns to use the word correctly, to utter the word meaningfully and coordinate their own actions with respect to the word. The words on their own are nothing. They acquire meaning only through their use in collaborative activity in which the learner participates in some way. The problem is, of course, that not everyone in the world uses the word in a uniform, consistent way. David Kellogg: I think that the word Vygotsky uses here is not so much "image" as "imagination" or perhaps "construal". Or rather, it is "image" but it isn't image in the sense of a photographic image but more in the sense of a Russian icon. That's why you can have an image of a game, and it's also why it is really only half true to say that the concept is built through actions. Painting isn't reducible to actions, and in a very important sense the ideal image of the painting exists long before any action at all is taken. LP: This answer to my struggle shifts or slants everything. If we cannot "reduce" or "abstract" actions from "having an experience" then to be explicit and clear we must also include some other factor that is "beyond" reducing having "an" experience to just actions. This other factor is "construal" or "imaginal" phenomena. Having an experience is an INTEGRAL EXPERIENCE including both the imaginal and actions. David the other relation is the unity of "construing" and "disclosing"/"undergoing" an experience (as a unity or integral phenomena.) The relation(s) of the imaginal to action and the slant from which we approach THIS unity (that cannot be reduced or abstracted) from having an experience. How we understand THIS integral phenomena that is extending "beyond" actions but must necessarily INCLUDE actions. Ritva Engeström: Although the discussion has taken some other theoretical threads, I like to thank still Alfredo and Rolf for the meaningful and refined article on a boundary object. I agree very much to the solution in the article to start the analysis by differentiating ”the object of design” from ”the object or ’thing’ that is handed over at the end of the design process”; the former addressing situated processes in which ”the designers’ relation with their object of design” is observable and available for analyses. In terms of object-oriented AT (as I see it), I would designate these different kinds of object as related to the first order activity (”develop technology-enhanced solutions for the design and redesign of museum exhibitions”) and the second order activity that does interactive, epistemic, performative, reflective etc. function and is materialized in collaborative emergent processes while working jointly on the object of the first order activity. A good reason to emphasize this distinction is that today’s complexity is not only a feature of the systems in society, but it is also concerned with the way in which we generate and organize our thinking about those systems and their phenomena. Thus, the article reminds us about co-evolution processes of knowledge production (inter- and multidisciplinary collaboration) and society. The above distinction holds methodologically the objects (activities) as unity but allows a variety of logic of empirical methods depending on the interest of the study (such as the importance of the living body). The research focus on the second order activity highlights also the importance of a dialogical approach which guides us to study object in subjectrelation (e.g. Bakhtin, Marková). The objects are, then, reflexively constituted, being outside and inside at the same time. The next question would be how to incorporate values to the object’s constituents, always present in sciences, and particularly in developmental or intervention research. The examination of the concept of imagination by Stoetzler and Yuval-Davis may include some interesting discussion (”Standpoint theory, situated knowledge and the situated imagination”, Feminist Theory 2002, vol. 3(3).