Existence is a real

advertisement

"Existence is a real property of concrete individuals." Excerpted from Chapter Two of

Barry Miller's Philosophical Theology , forthcoming, by Elmar J. Kremer

Miller's entire philosophical theology is directed toward understanding the difference between creatures and God. As Miller sees it, the difference is based on the fact that every creature is distinct from its existence, whereas God is identical with his existence. Hence the entire project depends on the controversial metaphysical claim that existence is a real property of concrete individuals. . . . An individual is concrete if it “can either effect real change or be subject to real change” (

E , p. 40). . . .

I: Is existence a property of concrete individuals?

Miller divides the question of whether existence is a real property of concrete individuals into two, first asking whether existence is a property of such individuals, and only secondly whether it is a real property. His answer to the first question is a development of Geach’s distinction between two main senses of the predicate 'exists' and related expressions, which can be called the there is sense, and the actuality sense.

'Exist(s)' is used in the there is sense to indicate that a general term is non-empty, as in

'Black swans exist', which means the same as 'There is at least one black swan'; and in the latter sense to express a property of a concrete individual or concrete individuals, as in

'President Obama exists' and 'Elephants (as opposed to dinosaurs) exist'.

1

Miller was aware that most philosophers in the Western tradition going back to

Greek philosophy have denied that existence is a real property; the only period in which that view was widely held was the high middle ages. (The historical point is developed in

The Fullness of Existence , p. 10-17.) Nevertheless it receives strong initial support from pre-philosophical common sense. Miller's strategy is to begin with singular propositions that are or might be true and that on their face involve the use 'exists' as a predicate standing for a property of concrete individuals. In From Existence to God , Miller begins with just one example, 'Socrates no longer exists' (p. 66). In A Most Unlikely God, he adds ‘Socrates came to exist’ and ‘Socrates ceased to exist’ (p. 26). In The Fullness of

Existence , he adds 'Socrates exists', 'Socrates is no more', 'Socrates might never have existed', and two examples from the Bible: 'Joseph is not and Simeon is not' (Genesis

42:13) and 'Before Abraham was, I am' (John, 8:58) ( F , p. 23) 2 . He then considers and rejects various attempts that have been made to show that such examples should not be taken at face value and need to be "interpreted" in some way to remove the implication that existence is a property of concrete individuals. In E , he deals with arguments which focus on the apparent absurdity of negative existential statements like ‘Joseph does not exist’. . . [In

F , he considers objections focusing on positive existential statements, including the oft repeated Kantian objection that existence is not a property because when one says a thing exists one does not "make the least addition to the thing". (Critique of

Pure Reason, B628). I will turn to the Kantian argument in section III below. ]

1. Who is the Joseph that no longer exists?

1 See E , p. 68-69.

2 Henceforth From Existence to God will be referred to as " E ", A Most Unlikely God as " U ", and The

Fullness of Being as " F ".

2

Against the view that the above examples are to be taken at face value, one objection is that if 'Joseph exists' says something about Joseph, so also does 'Joseph does not exist'. But the negative proposition cannot be about Joseph because if it were true, there would be no Joseph for it to be about. So the affirmative proposition is similarly not about Joseph, and does not predicate existence of him. This oft-repeated argument, as

Miller points out, assumes that if a name refers to an individual at a given time, the individual must exist at that time. That assumption is false, for one can use a proper name to refer to an individual that existed in the past and no longer exists. Reference to individuals can, so to speak, cut across time to the past. To put the point in another way, the argument confuses the relation being a referent of a name with the relation being a bearer of a name.

If x is a bearer of a name y at time t, then x must exist at t, but x can be a referent of a name y at time t without existing at t. Supposing that Socrates existed but no longer exists, then ‘Socrates’ currently has no bearer, and yet may currently be used to refer to Socrates. Miller holds that every real (as opposed to fictional) proper name has or has had an existing bearer. But there is nothing paradoxical about the proposition that

Socrates (who existed in the past) does not (now) exist.

2. If existence is a property, is non-existence also one?

A second objection begins with the observation that if 'Joseph exists' attributes the property of existence to Joseph, then 'Joseph does not exist' attributes the property of nonexistence to him. But an individual that does not exist cannot be the subject of a property.

So 'Joseph does not exists' does not attribute a property of non-existence to Joseph, and similarly ‘Joseph exists’ does not attribute a property of existence to Joseph. D. G.

Londey puts the point in a colorful way, speaking of the absurdity of sheep farmers inspecting their flocks "with the aim of sorting the existing sheep from the non-existent ones."

3

Miller begins his reply with a distinction between external and internal negation, that is, between 'Joseph (does-not-exist)' and 'It is not the case that (Joseph exists)'.

‘Joseph does not exist’, can be interpreted as a case of external negation, in which the negative predicate ‘does not exist’ fails to occur and which does not assert anything of

Joseph, though it does include a clause in which ‘exists’ ( not ‘does not exist’) is predicated of him. Thus the objection is disarmed.

Now the distinction between external and internal negation plays no part in ordinary predicate logic. Nevertheless, Miller contends, it is significant in other contexts.

For example, there is a difference between saying that an action is not moral (meaning that it is immoral) and saying that it is not the case that an action is moral (meaning that it is amoral). Again, if one wanted to deny that pure water is green while being careful not to imply that it is some other color, one might say, "It is not the case that pure water is green" rather than "Pure water is not green." The difference between 'Joseph (does-notexist)' and 'It is not the case that (Joseph exists)' is similarly significant. . . .

II: Is existence a real property of concrete individuals?

3 Quoted by Miller (in E , p. 64) from D. G. Londey, “Existence,” Philosophia Arhusiensis 1(1970), p. 3.

3

It might seem evident that if existence is a property of concrete individuals, then it is a real property of them—that its presence or absence makes a real difference to the individuals that have it. But Miller tries to back up that position in two quite different ways. In E he tries the approach of citing an equivalent property that is more evidently real than existence itself. [The property he cites is the capacity to be referred to.]. . .That attempt is less than a resounding success, for it is no more obvious that the capacity to be referred to is a real property than it is that existence itself is a real property. Miller might have been better advised to cite the property of effecting and undergoing real change. As a concrete individual, Socrates is an individual that “can either effect a real change or be subject to a real change or both” (p. 1 above). But it was true of him as an existing concrete individual that he not only could, but constantly did effect and undergo real change. Indeed, it is true of all concrete individuals of anyone’s acquaintance that they are constantly effecting and undergoing real change, something they cease doing just as soon as they cease existing. Since the difference between undergoing and effecting real change on the one hand, and not undergoing or effecting real change on the other, is a real difference in a thing, the equivalent difference between existing and not existing is an equally real difference. . . .

III: [There remains Kant's objection that existence "adds nothing" to an individual.]

The Kantian objection is sometimes expressed by saying that it is uninformative to be told that some individual exists. Let me use a passage from Brian

Davies (who happens to disagree with Miller about whether existence is a real property) to build a counter-example: Endorsing the Kantian objection, Davies says,

"While there are predicates which do give us information about Brian Davies

(predicates truly ascribing properties to him) '____ exists' is not one of them. If 'Brian

Davies snores' is true, someone who comes to know this learns something about Brian

Davies. 'Brian Davies snores' says something about Brian Davies. This is not the case, however, with 'Brian Davies exists'.” 4 But if one concentrates on the present tense of

'Brian Davies exists', then it becomes clear that the proposition does give information about Davies: Davies still exists. The proposition also provides a basis for classifying

Davies with, e.g., Alvin Plantinga, and setting him apart from Barry Miller (who ceased existing on August 16, 2006). Therefore, 'Brian Davies exists', taken as a present-tense, first-level predication about Brian Davies, is informative. It does not give information about what Davies is, but it does give that information that he is actual. In other words, an individual's existence does not add to what the individual is; it does not add to what might be called the quidditative content of the individual. But it does make a real difference to the individual: It makes the individual actual. So an individual's existence is a real property of the individual.]

4 Brian Davies, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion , third edition, Oxford U. P., 2003, p. 107.

Download