2. The definition of knowledge: What is propositional knowledge? Introduction For this section of the course, you will need to know: 1. The difference between acquaintance knowledge, ability knowledge and propositional knowledge. 2. The tripartite view of knowledge. 2.1 Issues with the tripartite view of knowledge: the conditions are not individually necessary. 2.2 Issues with the tripartite view of knowledge: cases of lucky true beliefs (Gettier and Fake-Barn Cases) show that the justification condition should be strengthened, added to or replaced. 2.2.1 Responses to cases of lucky true beliefs: - Infallibilism: the justification condition should be strengthened, and there should be a requirement for an impossibility of doubt (Descartes). - A ‘no false lemmas’ condition should be added. - Reliabilism: the justification condition should be replaced with ‘produced by a reliable process’. - Virtue Epistemology: the justification condition should be replaced with ‘acquired as a result of a person exercising their intellectual virtues’. 1. The difference between acquaintance knowledge, ability knowledge and propositional knowledge. Acquaintance knowledge (knowing ‘of’) includes knowing a person, place, or thing because we have met the person/visited the place/experienced the thing. For example: I know Sally because I have met her. - I know London because I visited there. - I know the sound of Beethoven’s 5th symphony because I have heard it. - I know the taste of coffee because I have tried it. Importantly, acquaintance knowledge need not involve any capacity to express this knowledge in language. For example, I may know what Beethoven’s 5th symphony sounds like without being able to describe it or without knowing any facts about it. Ability knowledge (knowing ‘how’ or practical knowledge) involves knowing how to do something. For example: - I know how to ride a bike. - I know how to make a cup of tea. Like acquaintance knowledge, a person may have practical knowledge of how to do something without the capacity to express this knowledge in language. For example, I may know how to ride a bike without being able to express the details of what this knowledge entails (the details of how to ride a bike). Propositional knowledge (knowing ‘that’) is knowing that something is the case. For example: - I know that the earth orbits the sun. - I know that I had breakfast this morning. - I know that I am studying AS philosophy. Unlike the other two types of knowledge, this type of knowledge can (at least in principle) be expressed in language; I can make statements about what the world is like. For example, when I make the statement, ‘I know that the earth orbits the sun’ I am claiming that this is a true fact about the world. 2. The tripartite view of knowledge. The distinction between true beliefs and knowledge is first discussed in Plato’s dialogue, the Meno. The character Socrates argues that: “True beliefs are a fine thing and do all sorts of good so long as they stay in their place; but they will not stay long. They run away from a man’s mind, so they are not worth much until you tether them by working out the reason… Once they are tied down, they become knowledge, and are stable. That is why knowledge is something more valuable than right belief. What distinguishes one from the other is the tether” Plato, Meno. Thus, for Plato, knowledge is more certain than belief because it is ‘tethered’ by reasons or evidence. In Plato’s Theaetetus he claims that ‘true belief accompanied by a rational account is knowledge’, or in other words, knowledge is a true belief that is supported by strong reasons or evidence. So, the traditional view of knowledge is that it is a justified, true belief: to know a proposition these three conditions must be met: - The person must believe the proposition; It must be true; and - The person must have justification for believing in it. The tripartite view of knowledge: S knows that p if and only if: 1. S believes that p 2. p is true 3. S has adequate or sufficient evidence for p, or is justified in believing that p. e.g. Sally knows that the earth orbits the sun if and only if: 1. Sally believes that the earth orbits the sun (the ‘psychological’ or ‘internal’ criterion). 2. It is true that the earth orbits the sun (the ‘external’ criterion). 3. Sally is justified in believing that the earth orbits the sun because she read it in a reliable science journal. These three conditions for knowledge are considered to be individually necessary for knowledge (each condition must be satisfied for there to be knowledge) and jointly sufficient (if all three conditions are satisfied then there definitely is knowledge). 3.1 Issues with the tripartite view of knowledge: the conditions are not individually necessary. The Belief condition - The philosophical consensus and traditional view is that belief is necessary for knowledge as it seems impossible for a person to know a proposition without believing that proposition. For example, it is incoherent to say ‘I know the earth orbits the sun but I don’t believe it does’. - Some philosophers, however, have argued that knowledge and belief are separable and others have even argued that they are mutually incompatible. - In Plato’s work The Republic (written later than the Meno) he adopts an incompatibilist view. In this work he argues that knowledge is infallible (beyond reasonable doubt) whereas belief is fallible (can be doubted) and therefore they are fundamentally different things. Knowledge entails a degree of certainty which belief does not. Thus, knowing goes beyond mere belief. - Additionally, people may not believe they know something until they answer a set of questions on it and get them right due to recalling previously-learnt information; thus they don’t believe they know the answer when they actually do. The Truth condition - This condition is fairly uncontroversial; it is impossible to know a proposition that is false. - While we may claim to know something that is false, it does not mean that we actually know it (for example people in the past claimed to know that the earth was flat but we would not call this knowledge). Our belief must correspond with the way the world is for us to have knowledge. The Justification Condition - This condition is required because it is possible to have a true belief that would not, at least intuitively, count as knowledge, e.g. lucky guesses. - For example (p.66 of Hayward, Jones and Cardinal) if a juror believes that a defendant is guilty purely because of the colour of their skin, and the defendant does turn out to be guilty, we would not intuitively say that the juror had knowledge because the juror did not have good justification for her belief (instead her belief was solely based on irrational prejudice). - However, the strength of the justification needed has been much debated. - Reliabilists claim that a reliable process that produces the true beliefs is what counts as knowledge (this will be discussed further on p….) 2.3 Issues with the tripartite view of knowledge: cases of lucky true beliefs (Gettier and Fake-Barn Cases) show that the justification condition should be strengthened, added to or replaced. Are the JTB conditions sufficient for knowledge? In his 1967 paper, ‘Is Justified, True Belief Knowledge?’ Edmund Gettier gave examples of justified true beliefs that we would not count as examples of knowledge. ‘Is Justified, True Belief Knowledge?’ – The example of Smith and Jones Suppose that Smith and Jones have applied for a certain job. And suppose that Smith has strong evidence for the following conjunctive proposition: (d) Jones is the man who will get the job, and Jones has ten coins in his pocket. Smith's evidence for (d) might be that the president of the company assured him that Jones would in the end be selected, and that he, Smith, had counted the coins in Jones's pocket ten minutes ago. Proposition (d) entails: (e) The man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket. Let us suppose that Smith sees the entailment from (d) to (e), and accepts (e) on the grounds of (d), for which he has strong evidence. In this case, Smith is clearly justified in believing that (e) is true. But imagine, further, that unknown to Smith, he himself, not Jones, will get the job. And, also, unknown to Smith, he himself has ten coins in his pocket. Proposition (e) is then true, though proposition (d), from which Smith inferred (e), is false. In our example, then, all of the following are true: (i) (e) is true, (ii) Smith believes that (e) is true, and (iii) Smith is justified in believing that (e) is true. But it is equally clear that Smith does not KNOW that (e) is true; for (e) is true in virtue of the number of coins in Smith's pocket, while Smith does not know how many coins are in Smith's pocket, and bases his belief in (e) on a count of the coins in Jones's pocket, whom he falsely believes to be the man who will get the job. Edmund Gettier – ‘Is Justified, True Belief Knowledge?’ As most people would claim that Smith did not have knowledge, Gettier’s example showed that there can be cases of justified, true beliefs which we would not count as knowledge because there is an element of luck involved, and therefore the JTB conditions are not sufficient for knowledge. Another famous example of a Gettier-Style problem was given by Carl Ginet: Henry is driving through the countryside and unbeknown to him he drives through Fake Barn County. This is an area filled with Fake Barn facades. Henry fails to notice all but one of the fake barns and he forms the belief, ‘there is a barn in that field’. However, Henry has chanced to look upon the only real barn in Fake Barn County. Thus, Henry’s belief that there is a barn in the field is true and he is justified in believing it because he sees it. However, the context – of Henry being in Fake Barn County – means that his justified, true belief seems to be luckily true. Therefore, this Gettier-style counter example suggests that the JTB conditions are not sufficient for knowledge. Thus, the JTB account of knowledge needs modification. (See p.69 of AQA AS Philosophy, Hayward, Jones and Cardinal, for more Gettier-style examples). i. Responses to cases of lucky true beliefs (a) Infallibilism: the justification condition should be strengthened, and there should be a requirement for an impossibility of doubt. Infallibilists claim that the justification must be so strong that it is impossible to doubt the truth of the proposition. So, the belief is infallible – it cannot be wrong. Therefore, we should only accept as knowledge those things which we cannot doubt. Examples of which might include: - I believe that 2+2=4. - I believe that I am currently in pain. - I believe that a thinking thing exists. Descartes adopted an Infallibilist approach in his Meditations. Descartes’ approach involved him doubting all of his beliefs until he could find a belief/set of beliefs which could not be rationally doubted. It was Descartes’ hope to find a bedrock of infallible beliefs from which he could build a system of certain beliefs. After using his ‘Three Waves of Doubt’ he found that the only infallible belief that remained was Cogito ergo sum, ‘I think therefore I am.’ It was impossible to doubt this belief as in the very act of doubting he would be thinking. ‘Some years ago I was struck by how many false things I had believed, and by how doubtful was the structure of beliefs that I has based on them. I realised that if I wanted to establish anything in the sciences that was stable and likely to last, I needed – just once in my life – to demolish everything completely and start again from the foundation.’ Descartes, Meditation 1, p.1 Evaluating Infallibilism Strengths of Infallibilism as a response to Gettier • • • Infallibilism is not open to Gettier cases because none of the cases would count as knowledge in the first place as they are open to some doubt. By restricting knowledge to only those things that cannot be doubted then there is no room for Gettier counter examples to thrive as these all rely on beliefs that are merely plausibly justified - which might be false, but turn out to be luckily true. It fits with our intuition that knowledge involves a level of certainty. Weaknesses of Infallibilism as a response to Gettier. • Infallibilism implies that we have very little knowledge – going against our intuition that we know a lot of things. • Unless Descartes can build his a system of knowledge only using infallible beliefs then Infallibilism leads to scepticism. • While some philosophers might argue that our common definition of knowledge needs such a radical revision, others would argue that to diverge too radically from common usage involves our leaving behind the very concept we set out to analyse. • Infallibilism seems to be prescribing what our concept of knowledge should be, rather than analysing/describing what it is. (b) No False Lemmas: A no false lemmas condition should be added, so K= J+T+B+ no false lemmas. A lemma is a subsidiary proposition used to justify another proposition. By adding a no false lemmas condition, knowledge becomes a justified, true belief that has not been formed from any false propositions/beliefs. So, in the Gettier example of Smith and Jones, Smith’s true belief that the person who gets the job will have ten coins in their pocket was based on the false belief that Jones would get the job. Therefore, as Smith’s belief was based on a false lemma it cannot be knowledge. Evaluating the no false lemmas theory. Strengths of the no false lemmas theory as a response to Gettier The no false lemmas theory copes well with the standard Gettier cases where a true belief is based on a false belief; for example the case of Smith and Jones. Weaknesses of the no false lemmas theory as a response to Gettier. It does not cope with other Gettier-style counter examples where there is no obvious false belief involved in the formation of the person’s true belief. For example, the Fake Barn Case of Henry driving through Fake Barn County does not seem to involve any false beliefs. A further example can be found on p.82 of Hayward, Jones and Cardinal: You look up at a clock that says it is 12 O’clock and form the belief that it is midday. However, this clock stopped yesterday at this time. But, coincidentally it is 12 O’clock. Therefore your belief that it is midday is true, justified and does not seem to rely on any false lemmas; however, we would not intuitively call it knowledge due to the belief only being luckily true. The no false lemmas theory improved... The theory can be added to by not accepting as knowledge any justified, true belief which has been based upon tacit or hidden false assumptions (not just false explicit beliefs/premises as in the Smith and Jones example). So, in the clock example above, the person who forms the belief that it is midday makes the tacit assumption that the clock is working. As this assumption is false, the person does not have knowledge to begin with and so the Gettier problem no longer exists. However, this improvement still does not seem to be able to solve Fake Barn Cases. In the case of Henry seeing a real barn in Fake Barn County there do not seem to be any false lemmas or tacit false assumptions in his formation of this belief. The Philosopher who formulated the theory that knowledge should not involve tacit false assumptions , William Lycan, has responded to this by arguing that there are no false assumptions in Fake Barn Cases but that these do not count as Gettier-style counter examples as the people do actually have knowledge. So Henry does have knowledge that there is a barn in the field, despite the lucky context in which he forms this belief. (c) Reliabilism: the justification condition should be replaced with ‘produced by a reliable process’ (K= R+T+B). Knowledge is a true belief that is produced by a reliable process. Reliabilism claims that you know that P if: - P is true; - You believe that p; - Your belief is caused by a reliable process. A reliable process is one that produces a high percentage of true beliefs. For example, take these two cases: - You read on www.conspiracies4ever.com that the Prime Minister is a reptile. - You read in a broadsheet newspaper that foxes are mostly nocturnal. You would say that you could probably know that foxes are mostly nocturnal because this information is from a broadsheet newspaper – a reliable type of newspaper which prints a high percentage of truths. However, you would not say that you know the Prime Minister is a reptile because www.conspiracies4ever.com is an unreliable website that does not publish many true beliefs. Reliabilism is not saying that knowledge is a justified, true belief that has been formed by a reliable process, it is saying that knowledge is a true belief that has been formed by a reliable process; thus replacing the justification condition. Examples of reliable processes (processes that produce a high percentage of true beliefs) include: seeing things close up; simple arithmetic; using trustworthy sources. Examples of unreliable processes (processes that do not produce a high percentage of true beliefs) include: wishful thinking; beliefs formed through hallucinations/dreaming; glimpsing things from a distance; complex mental arithmetic; remembering things from a long time ago. Evaluating Reliabilism 1) Which is better: a reliable process or justification? Reliable Process A reliable process is easier to define than good justification. It can be difficult to define what is good justification and the definition can often be circular, e.g. for a belief to be sufficiently justified to count as knowledge it needs to have knowledgeworthy justification. Reliabilism offers a clear account of justification. The theory allows animals to have knowledge (they have evolved to develop reliable processes of vision, memory, etc) and grants knowledge to any reliable process for example a man who is able to very successfully predict the future but does not know how. Justification Justification and ‘formed by a reliable process’ are different things as justifications are internal to the believer, (the believer can explain why they are justified in holding the belief) whereas being involved in a reliable process does not have to involve a conscious thought process. Reliabilism allows animals to have knowledge, which they don’t. Justifications involve reasons for beliefs whereas reliable processes involve causes (see example of John on p.89 of Hayward, Jones and Cardinal). 2) How well does Reliabilism respond to Gettier and Fake Barn Cases? Strengths of Reliabilism as a response to Gettier Reliabilism deals fairly well with standard Gettier cases – any belief that is true due to luck is probably not going to have been formed through a reliable process. Reliabilism can respond to the claim that reliable processes seem to be in place in Fake Barn Cases by saying that the individuals do indeed have knowledge. So, despite the lucky context in which Henry forms the belief that there is a barn in the field, he does have knowledge because his perceptual process was reliable. Reliabilists can also respond by saying that the reliability of a process changes according to the context. For example, the context of being in Fake Barn County means that simply looking at what looks like a barns is not a reliable process to form the belief ‘there is a barn in that field’. Weaknesses of Reliabilism as a response to Gettier. There is flexibility in how we describe processes. For instance, in the clock example we could define the process as either a person looking at a clock or a person looking at a broken clock – the former would be a reliable process whereas the latter would not be. We might also add that a newer clock is more reliable than an older one. Therefore, it is not clear how, and in what detail, a process should be described and thus it becomes more difficult to define what counts as a reliable process. In Fake Barn Cases it is not always obvious that the process is unreliable. For example, in Henry forming the belief that there is a barn in the field, he uses the process of seeing at a close distance; a process we would usually class as reliable. However, this raises the issue of how specific/general we define the context. (d) Virtue Epistemology : the justification condition should be replaced with ‘acquired as a result of a person exercising their intellectual virtues’ (K=V+T+B). Virtue epistemology moves away from focussing on the process to focussing on the agent (the person). Virtue epistemology claims that you know that P if: - P is true - You believe that P - Your true belief is a result of you exercising your intellectual virtues. An intellectual virtue is a tendency or disposition to use the reliable process and so more frequently gain true beliefs. For example, to trust truths in reliable broadsheet newspapers over www.conspiracies4eva.com. An intellectual vice is the tendency to use unreliable processes. For example, to trust www.conspiracies4eva.com over reliable, broadsheet newspapers. We tend to trust what people say if we know they use reliable processes to acquire their beliefs and tend to distrust what people say if we know they often use unreliable processes to acquire their beliefs. While Reliabilsm would claim that a person has knowledge because their true belief is formed through a reliable process, virtue epistemology would claim that a person has knowledge because their true belief was formed as the result of their intellectual virtues operating in a suitable way. A problem with virtue epistemology: The theory is prone to standard Gettier counter examples. For example, in the clock example, the person believes that the time is midday (which it is) and their belief is formed through looking at a clock (a reliable process). Therefore, they have a true belief which has been acquired through the application of an intellectual virtue. However, the clock had stopped yesterday at midday, so the person’s belief is only accidentally true so we would not count it as knowledge. Ernest Sosa’s developed account of Virtue Epistemology: Sosa used the analogy of an archer shooting an arrow to give a more nuanced account of Virtue Epistemology. A shot is adroit if it is skilful (might not always hit the target if external factors like a gust of wind are involved). A shot is accurate if it hits the target (could come about through skill or luck). The shot is apt if it was accurate and the accuracy was due to the shot being adroit. Sosa applies this analogy to knowledge, claiming that: - A belief is accurate if it is true. - A belief is adroit if it is formed by an intellectual virtue. - A belief is apt if it is true because of the intellectual virtue. So, knowledge is apt belief. Evaluating Virtue Epistemology Strengths of Virtue Epistemology as a response to Gettier In general, Virtue Epistemology, copes well with Gettier cases. Any belief that is luckily true is not going to be an apt belief – lucky beliefs are not true because of an intellectual virtue. For example, Smith’s true belief that the man who would get the job would have ten coins in his pocket was not true because of an intellectual virtue, therefore it cannot be counted as knowledge. Therefore, as Smith does not have knowledge this example is not a problem in the first place. One response to the problems posed by Fake Barn Cases is to say that these are cases of knowledge, so Henry does know that there is a barn in the field despite the element of luck. Another response is to say that the context in the Fake Barn Cases means that the exercising of an intellectual virtue is not adroit – the context changes the level of skill needed to have an apt belief. Sosa argues that in Fake Barn Cases, the believer lacks an understanding of their context and so they are not able to judge how apt, or not, their belief is. Because of this, he claims that in these cases the believer has animal knowledge but not reflective knowledge. Weaknesses of Virtue Epistemology as a response to Gettier. Virtue Epistemology deals less well with Fake Barn Cases. For example, Henry does seem to have an apt belief: - his belief is true (accurate) – there is a barn in the field; - his belief is adroit as it was formed by an intellectual virtue (trusting one’s senses under normal conditions), and - his belief is apt because it is true due to him using his intellectual virtues. However, many would not count this as knowledge.