Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 1 Speech Rights, Speech Wrongs © Onora O’Neill Rights to freedom of speech and to press freedom, and latterly to ‘freedom of expression’, have become so central to discussions of the rights and wrongs that bear on communication that they may seem to define and limit claims about speech rights—and speech wrongs. However, disputes about which types of speech, ranging from lying to hate speech, from intimidation to breaches of privacy, from causing offence to defamation, should permitted and which prohibited, cannot be resolved merely by appealing to a generic right to freedom of expression. They also require clarity about other rights, about the diversity of speech acts, and about the diversity of communication technologies. 1. Speech Rights in Transition I begin with some very short comments on reasons to think carefully and fundamentally about speech rights and speech wrongs today—the more so at a time at which the murderous attack on Charlie Hebdo Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 and others has challenged free speech in a most brutal and 2 fundamental way. First, it is worth noting that early modern arguments for aspects of freedom of expression never use that C20 phrase. The arguments of the Reformation and the Enlightenment are instructive, but focus only on specific aspects of freedom of expression. these arguments were Many of not about rights – let alone universal rights—but about duties, and in particular about duties to tolerate others’ speech even if it was false or wrong, that is even if others had no right to speak or publish in certain ways. Many are arguments for speech rights in specific areas, such as freedom of worship and arguments rights to free speech, press freedom (Federfreiheit). Some are directed only at speech that makes truth claims, and stress the importance of protecting and fostering the discovery and communication of truth, especially in religion or in science. These classical arguments are not irrelevant today, and they are often bought up in discussion of freedom of expression, but can offer at most selective justification for freedom of expression. A focus solely of rights to speak or to publish is now too narrow. The last century has seen the development of film, telephony, radio and television; the last 40 years the rise of the internet and mobile telephony; the last 20 years the wider penetration of these Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 communication technologies, and the rise of globalised marketing and social media. In the background there are ongoing revolutions in technologies, including technologies of encryption, and reconfigurations (mostly not relocations) of boundaries, whose reconfigured porosity allows some agencies to insulate themselves powerful agents and from the rule of law and so from the enforcement of others’ rights. This is where we have got to, and I do not think it is a coincidence that a remarkable proportion of the more intractable current disputes about policy and legislation are about ways in which speech rights should be protected and regulated by law. For example, there has been and there will be more legislation on surveillance and privacy; on copyright and open access; on transparency and encryption; on data protection and freedom of information; on open data and intellectual property; on online privacy and online anonymity; on defamation and trolling; on cyber fraud and identity fraud of countless ingenious varieties. It is tempting to wade into discussion of the technologies, but probably more useful to start by reconsidering the underlying arguments for specifying what may and may not be done with words. Which speech rights should people have? Where may speech rights be restricted, and for which reasons? 3 Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 4 2. Speech Acts and Speech Content As a first point, I think it is useful to note that speech rights protect and prohibit types of speech act, rather than types of speech content. In the past some restrictions focussed on speech content. In some cultures certain words were taboo; in our own, legislation on blasphemy and obscenity—now largely repealed or obsolete—aimed to regulate some sorts of speech content. But legislation operates primarily by requiring or prohibiting, sanctioning or rewarding certain types of action, and it is rarely feasible to do so by proscribing or regulating all uses of specific types of content. 1 Attempts of regulate speech content have often foundered because parody and euphemism, satire and pseudonyms, allow people to convey ostensibly prohibited content, while keeping within the law. 2 The Censor’s life is not a happy one. 3 Individuals and institutions enjoy determinate speech rights when permitted and prohibited types of speech act are clearly distinguished, and 1 interference with permitted speech, whether by prior restraint That does not stop people trying. Cf. the data protection approach to privacy protection which assumes that it is possible to separate personal from non personal content. 2 For examples consider Private Eye, or the C18 publishers who printed forbidden books outside France, and sold not only political but erotic literature under the useful euphemism ‘livres philosophiques’, Robert Darnton, The Great Cat Massacre and Other Episodes in French Cultural History 1984 3 Robert Darnton, Censors at Work; How States Shaped Literature, NY 2014. Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 or by retrospective sanction, is prohibited, and (if well 5 institutionalised) effectively prevented. In drawing this line, certain types of speech act will be classified as speech wrongs and be prohibited (think of speech acts that defraud, intimidate, incite violence, defame, or abuse, for starters) and others will be permitted and protected. for Freedom of expression has become the generic term rights that are to protect a wide range of speech acts, both individual and institutional. These rights may protect speech that is spoken, written, imaged or enacted; that is face to face or technologically mediated; that reaches or fails to reach varied audiences. 3. Speech Rights as Human Rights The right to freedom of expression is the central speech right proclaimed both in the United Nations Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR, 1948) and in the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR, 1950), whose standards have (supposedly) been given more definitive form in subsequent international conventions and implemented in national legislation (enforced with varying enthusiasm and efficacy). Freedom of expression is now standardly cited as the default and overarching speech right, both for individuals and for the media, and is deeply entrenched in contemporary liberal cultures and legislation. 4 4 And has long been assimilated into First Amendment jurisprudence in the US. Thomas Emerson The System of Freedom of-expression, NY, Vintage 1970. Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 The Universal Declaration articulates the right to freedom of expression for individuals in the following words: Everyone has the right to freedom of opinion and-expression; the right includes freedom to hold opinions without interference and to seek, receive and impart information and ideas through any media regardless of frontiers (UDHR, 1948: Art 19)5 The same emphasis on the rights of individuals is central to Art 10 of the European Convention of Human Rights (ECHR), drafted some two years later than UDHR. The first clause runs: 10 (1) everyone has the right to freedom of expression … This right shall include freedom to hold opinions and to receive and impart information and ideas without interference by public authority and regardless of frontiers… (ECHR 1950)6 Following the standard format of the European Convention, Art 10 (2) also lists permissible types of restriction on this freedom: 10 (2) The exercise of these freedoms, since it carries with it duties and responsibilities, may be subject to such formalities, conditions, restrictions or penalties as are prescribed by law and are necessary in a democratic society, in the interests of national security, territorial integrity or public safety, for the prevention of disorder or crime, for the protection of health or morals, for the protection of the reputation or rights of others, for preventing the disclosure of information received in confidence, or for maintaining the authority and impartiality of the judiciary. 5 It is notable but not surprising that the media appear here not as right holders, but as supporting the rights of individuals. 6 Once again, media rights are seen as supporting individual rights. 6 Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 Freedom of expression is a qualified, not an absolute right. Clearly what matters is to understand which qualifications are necessary and proportionate, and how they can best be enshrined in law. And yet, as you all know, there are endless protagonists of freedom of expression who imagine that matters can be settled merely by invoking freedom of expression. I think this is where arguments have to begin rather than end. 4. Freedom of Expression and Self Expression Evidently the generic right to freedom of expression set out in UDHR and ECHR is not the same as the right to self-expression for which John Stuart Mill argued so memorably in Ch 1 of On Liberty, and which still plays a central part in English language debate. The two rights are often conflated. In well known passages Mill argued for strong individual rights of self-expression as essential in order to recognise ‘the permanent interests of man as a progressive being’, and to respect individuals’ ‘sovereignty over their own minds and bodies’. Respect for this ‘sovereignty’, he argued, requires that harmless self-expression not be restricted, even if (for example) unintelligible, untrue, or cavalier about evidence, or about the other disciplines of truth seeking. Rather 7 Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 ...the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of any of their number, is self-protection. 7 Mill describes acts of self-expression as (we might now say self-regarding self-affecting), and points out that they typically harm no others and should be restricted only where (exceptionally) they cause or risk harm to others (shouting ‘fire!’ in a crowded theatre; slander; libel). In all other cases, he concluded, individuals should enjoy …absolute freedom of opinion and sentiment on all subjects, practical or speculative, scientific, moral, or theological’, Whether this is a coherent position depends on the feasibility of assessing the harm likely to be created by types of speech act. The harm caused by token speech acts of a given type can varied, and claims about expected harm will be highly often defy calculation.8 This has not prevented the harm principle from entering popular culture, as a supposed criterion not merely for self expression but for freedom of expression. Mill’s claims about individual self expression may be convincing, and may still have huge cultural resonance. But they cannot be adapted to 7 8 Ibid. 13. Judges seek to assess the harm of particular acts, but even they may quail about assessing the likely harm of act types. Lee Boland also Scanlon 8 Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 justify press or media freedom, for two reasons. First 9 institutions have no selves, so do not engage in self-expression. Institutional speech is directed, successfully or unsuccessfully, to audiences: to think of it merely as self-expression would mislead. Secondly an assumption that media (or other institutional speech) is generally harmless would be naïf. It may be tempting for the media to insist on maximal speech rights while representing —or rather misrepresenting — their speech as trivial and harmless. But this does not fit the realities of media power, or more generally of institutional power, nor the steps typically taken to constrain other types of institutional communication. Claims that media speech rights should parallel individuals’ rights to self-expression do not convince. How then should the freedom of expression be configured? How should it be differentiated for individuals, for the media and for other institutional actors? 5. Interpreting Rights, Implementing Rights How else might we seek to justify a determinate configuration of freedom of expression? I suggest we might start from two obvious features of the human rights set out in the Declaration (and the 1966 Covenants). Human rights are intended to set standards for everyone. Second human rights are not to be considered one-right-ata-time: each right holder is to enjoy all rights. We might say Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 that human rights are intended to be doubly universal: all rights for all human beings. However, these two formal requirements do not appear to show why we should accept the standard list of human rights. However, many are prepared to accept the canonical lists. I suggest that this is not because they are confident that these are the right lists, let alone demonstrably the right lists, but rather because the rights listed are highly indeterminate, so that some interpretation of virtually all of them would be included in any plausible list of universal rights. The magic that secures such widespread agreement to human rights is largely that the lists set out in UDHR allow people to bracket much that is contentious or about which they disagree. So it is not after all very surprising that so many who think that human rights standards require deeper justification are nevertheless quite accepting of the UDHR list. It does not follow that there is wide agreement about which of many possible interpretations of the rights listed is to be preferred. There are persistent disputes about the adequacy or inadequacy of interpretations of freedom of expression and rights to privacy, indeed of rights to life and rights to security, which illustrate the point.9 The UDHR list of rights poses rather than resolves difficult questions of justification, in declaring many 9 Cf. earlier disputes about the right to work (a free labour market or the right to be assigned a job?—a major dispute between market and centrally planned societies before 1990) and current disputes about the right to marry (opposite sex partners only, or same or opposite sex partners?). 10 Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 qualified rights that have to be adjusted to one another. questions can only be for addressed by Those selecting and arguing more specific interpretations of each indeterminate right. 6 Human Rights are for Everyone. Any coherent interpretation of the UDHR rights has to satisfy at least three formal constraints. It must find consistent interpretations of the various rights held by each person; consistent interpretations of each person and others’ like rights; and interpretations of the rights of each person that are consistent with the action needed to secure respect for those rights. An immediate corollary of requiring that any interpretation of rights for all be consistent in these three respects is that few rights can be seen as unconditional. At most a few important liberty rights might be interpreted as absolute. The right not be tortured and the right not to be enslaved are often said to be absolute, meaning that no other consideration, and no other right, provides an acceptable reason for restricting them. But most human rights constrained in numerous the rights of each person are to ways if have to be be compatible with one another, compatible with others enjoying the 11 Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 same rights, and compatible realise those rights. with the action needed to respect or 10 The task of interpreting human rights, other than the few that may be absolute, is sometimes described as a matter of balancing one right against others. This metaphor misleads. Its proper use is in characterising judicial decision-making about particular cases, where balancing considerations is a matter of taking the multiple facts of the case into account. In considering the justification of interpretation human rights we are not dealing with particular cases, but with principles, and since there is no particular case, there are no facts of the case to be balanced. There is no metric for rights, analogous to the metrics used for physical balances. What is actually required is in the first place an interpretation of each right that adjusts it to others held by the same individual, takes account of the fact that each right is to be enjoyed by all, and does not obstruct or prevent the action that respect for each right of all others requires— i.e. allows for the performance of the counterpart duties needed to make a reality of rights. 10 It is common to speak of some non-absolute rights as limited and others as qualified. Some human rights may be limited by statue, as the right to liberty is limited by legislation that specifies when a prison sentence or detention for reasons of mental health is permitted. Other human rights may be qualified for wider reasons than those set out in statute, such as the need to protect the rights of others or wider society. 12 Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 Difficult questions must be decided. For example, what line should be drawn between rights to freedom of expression and rights to privacy? When can protection of rights to liberty and security justify restrictions of freedom of expression? How should freedom of expression be adjusted to protect rights to a fair trial? Under what circumstances does retention of or access to others’ communications breach rights to privacy? Under which circumstances does it not? There are nevertheless some cases in which matters are not particularly difficult, and one of those has been prominent recently. We have heard it said that there is no right to speak in ways that offend. Our legislation, I think correctly, does not restrict speech merely because it offends some others. Offence is a subjective matter, and what offends A may not offend B. There is therefore no way of securing robust forms of freedom of expression that is compatible with recognising a right not to be offended. Speech acts that incite hatred, or that intimidate, or that defraud, or that abuse, can be regulated without putting freedom of expression at the mercy of others. But there can be no right not to be offended. While we may often choose to speak in ways that will not offend, for good reasons (kindness, or good manners) or for bad reasons (currying favour, condescension), those reasons do not and cannot include a supposed right not to be offended. 13 Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 7 Constraints and Justifications In solving problems it sometimes fewer constraints, since this 14 helps to have more rather than narrows down the range of possibilities. We are all familiar with equations that can be solved once one knows enough constraints, and with crossword puzzles, where solving each clue easier to complete constrains possibilities and the puzzle. makes it Justifications of specific interpretations of human rights can, I suggest, make headway by focusing on the necessary constraints on interpreting rights that can be rights for all. The power of consistency constraints is easily missed if one tries to think about rights or their interpretation one-right-at-a-time. Even the first of these consistency requirements—that the several rights of a given individual be mutually consistent – cannot be resolved by thinking about an individual’s rights one-by-one. If we consider rights one-at-a-time it would be tempting to imagine that the best interpretation of each right must be a maximal interpretation. However, this would overlook what is needed for individuals to enjoy other rights, and for others to enjoy like rights. If A had a maximal right to liberty, she could not also have a right to security, since some measures required to protect her security would restrict her liberty. If A had a maximal right to freedom of expression, B could not enjoy any right to privacy. And so on. Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 The second consistency requirement sets even more powerful constraints on any adequate interpretation of rights. Human rights are rights for everyone—for all human beings, not merely for some privileged ones. So no interpretation of rights can endorse supposed rights could be held only by some, but not by all: if rights are universal, it must be possible for others to hold like rights. There cannot, for example, be universal rights to positional goods: there can be no universal right to win, to be the richest, or the best, or to enjoy upward social mobility. (None of us lives in the magical world of Lake Woebegon, where all the children are above average). If rights are universal we must reject as spurious any interpretation of a right under which it could not be held by all. Nor can any adequate interpretation of rights endorse supposed rights whose successful exercise would prevent others from enjoying like rights: there can therefore be no rights to coerce, to destroy, or to control others, since they would all evidently undermine others’ like rights. Nor can anybody’s freedom of movement be interpreted as an unrestricted right to occupy any chosen location on the surface of the earth—since this would be incompatible with others enjoying a like right. Here the fact that rights are not to be considered one-right-at-atime filters out many possibilities: A’s right to privacy must be construed in ways that are compatible with B’s right to a fair trial; C’s right to liberty must be construed in ways that are consistent with D’s 15 Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 right to security; E’s right to food must be construed in ways that are consistent with F’s rights to grow and sell food, and so on and on. A third powerful consistency constraint on any adequate interpretation of rights arises from the fact that rights cannot be respected or realised unless some others — individuals or institutions, depending on the case— are required to discharge the counterpart duties that can realise the right. However it they are required to act and forbear in ways that realise the right in question, it must remain possible for them to do so. No way of adjusting rights to one another can guide action unless it also leaves room for the action and forbearance required if rights are to be respected or realised. So any adequate interpretation of human rights (for a given society at a given time ) has to take a clear view about whose action is required to respect those rights, and cannot prescribe requirements that obstruct respect for and realisation of rights. In thinking about these questions we have to ask not only which rights can consistently be held by all, but also which counterpart duties on others (themselves right holders) are compatible with everyone’s rights. It is not enough merely to accept or assume that everyone has each listed right: rights shorn of counterpart duties are no more than rhetoric and gesture, and the fundamental task of justifying rights is to find an interpretation under which each person can coherently have all of a range of rights, and these rights are not mere rhetoric because 16 Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 they can be matched to and secured by a pattern of duties that would respect and realise those rights. Following through the ways in which these constraints interact is analogous to solving a simultaneous equation. The complexity of these interlocking consistency requirements means that any coherent interpretation of a plurality of rights has to meet specific criteria. The full set of rights must be given an interpretation under which any given individual can have the range of rights; under which all individuals can have that same range of rights; and under which the duties that must be met in order to respect and realise those rights can be met. tall order. It may not This is quite a show that there is a single optimal interpretation of human rights, but it is likely to provide a robust way of identifying inadequate interpretations that should be rejected. An interpretation of rights that meets all three consistency tests will not demonstrate that there is one and only one justifiable configuration of human rights, but will offer a robust justification that rules out many possibilities, and allows only for limited variation. If we approach rights to freedom of expression with this in mind, it will I believe be feasible to identify many of the ways in which they 17 Kent Freedom of Expression Feb 2015 must and must not be qualified. No interpretation will be acceptable unless it allows that all are to enjoy rights to freedom of expression. No interpretation will be acceptable unless it allows for respect and realisation of all other rights of all parties. And no interpretation will be acceptable unless it leaves room for the action needed to respect and realised all rights of all individuals. Legislation that aims to secure respect for human rights is therefore inevitably complex. What is required in underdetermined by the basic documents. What is required cannot be worked out if one considers matters one-right-at-atime. What is required cannot be worked out without ensuring that action that must be taken if rights are to be respected is actually feasible. 18