MCLS6202 Enquiry and Issues in Society and Culture Lecture 9-10 Rule of Law and Socio-Political Participation: Enquiry into Issues of Hong Kong Today (II) The Concept of Civil Disobedience A. Civil Disobedience and its Relationship with the Rule of Law and Democratic Participation 1. Conceptions of civil disobedience: a. John Rawls’s conception: “I shall begin by defining civil disobedience as a public, nonviolent, conscientious yet political act contrary to law done with the aim of bringing about change in the lawn or policies of the government. By acting in this way one addresses the sense of justice of the majority of the community and declares that, in one’s considered opinion the principles of social cooperation among free and equal men are not being respect. …It allows for what some have called indirect as well as direct civil disobedience.” (Ralws, 1971, P. 365-366) b. Jurgen Habermas’s conception: In an interview made in 1986, Habermas said, “There are three things to be said about that (referring to civil disobedience). First: civil disobedience cannot be ground in an arbitrary private Weltanschauung. But only in principles, which are anchored in the constitution itself. Second: civil disobedience is distinguished from revolutionary praxis, or from a revolt, precisely by the fact that it explicitly renounces violence. The exclusively symbolic breaking of rules ― which furthermore is only a last resort, when all other possibilities have been exhausted ― is only particularly urgent appeal to the capacity and willingness for insight of the majority. Third: a position, such as that defended by Hobbes, Carl Schmitt, or …. In which the upholding of the law is made only the highest, but the exclusive ground of legitimation of a legal system, seems to me to be extremely problematic, After all, one would very much like to know under what conditions, and for what purpose, the legal peace should be upheld.” (Habermas, 1986, P. 225) c. Ronald Dworkin’s conception: “Civil disobedience…is very different from ordinary criminal activity motivated by selfishness or anger or cruelty or madness. It is also different…from the civil war that break out within a territory when one group challenges the legitimacy of the government or the dimensions of the political community. Civil disobedience involves those who do not challenge authority in so fundamental a way. They do not think of themselves…as seeking any basic rupture or constitutional reorganization. They accept the fundamental legitimacy of both government and community; they act to acquit rather than to challenge their duty as citizens.: (Dworkin, 1985, P105) d. Jean Cohen and Andrew Arato’s conception: “Civil disobedience involves illegal acts, usually on the part of collective actors, that are public, principle, 11 Tsang & Mak Inquiry & Issues in Society & Culture and symbolic in character, involve primarily nonviolent means of protest, and appeal to the capacity for reason and the sense of justice of the populace. The aim of civil disobedience is to persuade public opinion in civil and political society…that a particular law or policy is illegitimate and a change is warranted. Collective actors involved in civil disobedience invoke the utopian principles of constitutional democracies appealing to the ideas of fundamental rights or democratic legitimacy.” (Cohen & Arato, 1992; quoted in Habermas, 1996, P. 383) 2. Justificatory grounds for Civil Disobedience a. The institutional assumption of civil disobedience: As the preceding definitions suggest, advocates and organizers of civil disobedience start off their campaign under the working assumption that they are living “within a more or less just democratic state and that they “recognize and accept the legitimacy of the constitution” (Rawls, 1971, P. 362) And their focal point of defiance is only on particular law or policy, which they find so unacceptable or even wrong that they have to defy it directly or indirectly. As a result, the organizers and participants of a civil disobedience campaign owe the law-abiding majority of the community a burden of proof of their act of disobedience. b. Ronald Dworkin, a prominent scholar of jurisprudence in the US, has induced three basic justificatory grounds for civil disobedience. i. “Conscience or integrity-based” civil disobedience: He points to the Fugitive Slave Act of 1850 in the US. He indicates, “Someone who believes it would be deeply wrong to deny help to an escaped slave who knocks at his door, and even worse to turn him over to the authority, think the Fugitive Slave Act requires him to behave in an immoral way. His personal integrity, his conscience, forbids him to obey.” (Dworkin, 1985, P. 107) ii. “Justice-based” civil disobedience: Dworkin points to the civil rights movement and the anti-Vietnam-war movement in the US during the 1960s in the US. He suggests that those participating in these civil disobedient movements aim “to oppose and reverse a program they believe unjust, a program of oppression by the majority of a minority. Those in the civil rights movement who broke the law and many civilians who broke it protesting the war in Vietnam thought the majority was pursuing its own interests and goals unjustly because in disregard of the rights of others, the rights of the domestic minority in the case of civil rights movement and of another nation in the case of the war. This is “just-based” civil disobedience. (Dworkin, 1985, P. 107) iii. “Policy-based” civil disobedience: Dworkin points to the movement of occupying US military bases in West Germany during the Euro-missile deployment debate in the 1980s. He suggests that “people sometimes break the law not because they believe the program they oppose is immoral or unjust…but because they believe it very unwise, stupid, and dangerous for the majority as well as the minority. The recent protest against the deployment of American missiles in Europe, so far as they violate local law, were for the most part occasions of this third kind of civil disobedience , which I shall call ‘policy-based’. If we tried to reconstruct the beliefs and attitudes of …the people who occupied the military bases in Germany, we would find that…they thought that majority had made a tragically wrong choice from the common standpoint. …They aim, not to 22 Tsang & Mak Inquiry & Issues in Society & Culture force the majority to keep faith with principle of justice, but simply to come to its sense.” (Dworkin, 1985, P. 107) 3. The function of civil disobedience in democratic and rule-of-law state: Taking together John Rawls’, Jurgen Habermas’ and Ronald Dworkin’s formulations, they consensually point to the positive contribution of civil obedience to the formation of the political culture of the democratic and rule-of-law state (Rechtsstaat in Germen) a. John Rawls underlines, “Indeed, civil disobedience ( and conscientious refusal as well) is one of the stabilizing devices of a constitutional system, although by definition an illegal one. Along with such things as free and regular elections and an independent judiciary empowered to interpret the constitution (not necessary written), civil disobedience used with due restraint and sound judgment helps to maintain and strengthen just institutions. By resisting injustice within the limits of fidelity to law, it serves to inhibit departures from justice and to correct them when they occur. A general disposition to engage in justified civil disobedience introduces stability into a well-ordered society, or one that is nearly just.” (Rawls, 1971, P. 383) b. Jurgen Habermas characterized the civil disobedience (in the form of occupying the US military bases in Germany) against the Euro-missile deployment in Germany in early 1980 in the following ways: “The present movement gives us the first chance, even in Germany, to grasp civil disobedience as an element of a ripe political culture.” (Habermas, 1983; quoted in Specter, 2010, P. 156; my emphasis) “The practice gives the German public, for the first time, the chance to liberate itself from a paralyzing trauma and to look without fear on the previous taboo question of the formation of a radical democratic consciousness. The danger is that this chance ― which other countries with a longer democratic tradition …have integrated productively ― will be passed up.” (Habermas, 1985; quoted in Specter, 2010, P. 156; original emphasis) c. Jurgen Habermas has also put civil disobedience against the context of Rechtsstaat (the rule-of-law state) and suggests that “The paradox of the Rechsstaat is that it must embody positive law, but also stand for principles which transcend it, and by which positive law may be judged. The Rechsstaat, wanting to remain identical with itself, stands before a paradoxical task. It must protect …against injustice that may emerge in legal forms, although this mistrust cannot take an institutionally secured form. With this idea of a non-institutionalizable mistrust of itself, the Rechsstaat projects itself over the entirety of its positive law.” (Habermas, 1983; quoted in Specter, 2010, P. 156) Immediately following the quotation, Mathew Specter underlines that “Habermas claim that the paradox can be resolved by citizens of ‘matured’ political culture because they alone show the ‘sense of judgment’ necessary to decide how to act in relation to unjust laws, or majority decision, with which they agree. Civil disobedience was thereby figured as a necessary component of a successful Rechsstaat.” (Specter, 2010, P. 167; my emphasis) d. Ronald Dworkin in retrospective reflection on the civil disobedient movements of the US in the 1960s and 70s, he suggests that “we can say something now we could not have said three decades ago: that Americans accept that civil disobedience has a legitimate if informal place in the political culture of their 33 Tsang & Mak Inquiry & Issues in Society & Culture community. Few Americans now either deplore or regret the civil rights and antiwar movements of the 1960s. People in the center as well as on the left of politics give the most famous occasions of civil disobedience a good press, at least in retrospect. They concede that these acts did engage the collective moral sense of the community. Civil disobedience is no longer a frightening idea in the United States.” (Dworkin, 1985, P. 105) 4. To summarize, we may map out the connection between the rule of law, democratic political participation and civil disobedience in the following way 44 Tsang & Mak Inquiry & Issues in Society & Culture (III) The Concept of Patriotism A. Is Patriotism a Virtue or a Vice? A Value and Moral Enquiry 1. Meaning of patriotism: a. Alasdair MacIntyre’s definition: In his oft-cited article entitled “Is Patriotism a Virtue?” MacIntyre defines patriotism as “a kind of loyalty to a particular nation which only those possessing that particular nationality can exhibit. Only Frenchmen can be patriotic about France.” (MacIntyre, 2002, P. 44) Furthermore, MacIntyre characterizes that patriotism as a kind of attitude supportive towards one’s own nation and evaluative of its merits and achievements are extremely particularistic in nature. That is, “patriots does not value in the same way precisely similar merits and achievements when they are the merits and achievements of some nation other than his or hers. For he or she ── at least in the role of patriot ── values them not just as merits and achievements, but as the merits and achievements this particular nation.” (MacIntyre, 2002, P. 44) b. Leo Tolstoy’s definition of “extreme patriotism”: Tolstoy states that “The sentiment (of patriotioism), in its simplest definition, is merely the preference of one’s own country or nation above the country or nation of any one else.” (Tolsky, 1969, quoted in Nathanson, 1993, P. 4) He goes on to emphasized that patriotism may consist the following features. 55 Tsang & Mak Inquiry & Issues in Society & Culture “1. A belief in the superiorty of one’s country 2. A desire for dominance over other contries 3. An exclusive concern for one one’s own country 4. No constrints on the pursuit of one’s country’s goals 5. Automatic support of one’s country’s military policies.” (quoted in Nathanson, 1993, P. 29) It must be underlined that Tolstoy did not himself identify with such a extreme version patriotism. In fact, he formulates it for criticism and he goes on to state that “this sentiment is …very stupid and immoral.” c. Stephen Nathanson’s definition of “moderate patriotism”: He stipulates that patriotism need not have the features that Tolstoy attributes and thus that it need not be open to his criticisms. Moderate patriotism involves the following features: 1. Special affection for one’s country 2. A desire that one’s country prosper and flourish 3. Special but not exclusive concern for one’s own country 4. Support for morally constrained pursuit of national goals 5. Conditional support of one’s country’s policies.” (Nathanson, 1993, P. 34) 2. Criticism of patriotism from the deontological and liberal perspectives in value and morality enquiry a. According to the deontological perspective in morality enquiry, all evaluation and moral judgments are supposed to be judged according to some impersonal and impartial criteria or rules. However, for patriotism it “requires me to exhibit peculiar devotion to my nation and you to yours. It requires me to regard such contingent social facts as where I was born and what government ruled over that place at that time, who my parents were, who my great-great- grandfathers were, and so on, as deciding for me the question of what virtuous action is.” (MacIntyre, 2002, P. 45) Accordingly, the deontological “moral standpoint and the patriotic standpoint are systematically incompatible.” (MacIntyre, 2002, P. 45) b. Furthermore, according to the liberal perspective in moral enquiry, the criteria and rules, which moral judgments should follow, should not only be impartial and impersonal but should also i. be “neutral between rival and competing interests;” ii. be “neutral between rival and competing sets of beliefs about what the best way for human beings to live is;” iii. take individual human being as the basic unit in moral evaluations and “each individual is to count for one and nobody for more than one;” and iv. apply to all moral agents universally “independent of all particularity.” (MacIntyre, 2002, P. 47) Accordingly, it is obvious that patriotic standpoint of morality, which base its judgment on the particularistic interest and form of life and belief of one own nation, will not be incompatible with that of the liberal but will simply be treated a vice. 3. In search of morally justifiable or virtuous ground for patriotism a. MacIntyre indicates first of all that “For patriotism and all other such particular loyalty can be restricted in their scope so that their exercise is always within the confine imposed by morality. Patriotism need be regards as nothing more than a perfectly proper devotion to one’s own nation which must never be allowed to 66 Tsang & Mak Inquiry & Issues in Society & Culture violate the constraints set by the impersonal moral standpoint.” (MacIntyre, 2002, P. 46) b. As a communitarian, MacIntyre is quick to stress that there “is never morality as such, but always the highly specific morality of some highly specific social order.” (P. 48) And “it is an essential characteristic of the morality which each of us acquires that is learned from, in and through the way of life of some particular community.” (P. 48) MacIntyre further specifies that the distinct rules of morality derived from the way of life of a particular community are therefore (P. 48) i. specific “practices” and responses to the natural and social situations in which a community found and formed itself; ii. specific “narratives” through which a community and its way of life evolve and develop through its own history iii. specific “tradition” and social arrangements and orders which have been institutionalized in the way of life of a community c. Built on this communitarian version of moral rules, MacIntyre further rejoins the liberal’s version of free-footing (impartial and neutral) moral agents by specifying that i. the moral goods pursued by moral agents are always embedded in “the enjoyment of one particular kind of social life, lived out through a particular set of social relationships.” (P. 49) Therefore, “rules of certain kind are justified by being productive of and constituted of goods of a certain kind …only if …these particular sets of rule incarnated in the practices of …these particular communities are productive or constitutive of ….these particular goods enjoyed at certain particular times and places by certain specifiable individuals.” (P. 49) ii. a moral duty and agency performed by a moral agent “is characteristically and generally a hard task for human being.” MacIntyre underlines that “I can only be a moral agent because we are moral agents, that I need those around me to reinforce my moral strengths and assist in remedying my moral weakness. It is general only within a community that individuals become capable of morality.” (P. 49) d. Taken together, MacIntyre asserts that patriotism can be accepted as a virtue on conditions that i. “If first of all it is the case that I can only apprehend the rules of morality in the version in which they are incarnated in some specific community; ii. “if secondly it is the case that the justification of morality must be in terms of particular goods enjoyed within the life of particular communities; iii. “if thirdly it is the case that I am characteristically brought into being and maintained as a moral agent only through the particular kinds of moral sustenance afforded by my community, then it is clear that deprived of this community, I am unlikely to flourish as a moral agent.” (P. 50) 4. Dialectics between liberalism and communitarianism in the controversy over patriotism a. Confronted with the two rival and incompatible moralities, namely morality of liberalism and that of patriotism, MacIntyre suggests that “one way to begin is to be learned from Aristotle, …we shall do well to proceed dialectically.” (P. 50) b. One the one hand, from the viewpoint of the morality of liberalism, patriotism is “a permanent source of moral danger.” (P. 54) It is because the morality of patriotism will always argue for exemption from general of morality principles in 77 Tsang & Mak Inquiry & Issues in Society & Culture the interest or even common goods for one’s own nation. MacIntyre agrees that such accusation from the liberals “cannot in fact be successfully rebutted” by the patriots. (P. 54) Therefore, MacIntyre suggests that morality of patriotism must be extremely careful in examining their arguments and justification for exemption from moral principles for the sake of national goods. MacIntyre specifically underlines that “whatever is exempted from the patriot’s criticism the status quo of power and government and the policy pursued by those exercising power and government never need be so exempted. What then is exempted? The answer is: the nation conceived as a project, a project somehow or other brought to birth in the past and carried on so that a morally distinctive community was brought into being which embodied a claim to political autonomy in its various organized and institutionalized expressions.” However, such patriotic claim for the overall project of the nation can pose moral danger “to the best interest of mankind” as the case of the project of the Nazi Germany. (P. 52) Hence, the exemption is by no means absolute and must be critically examined dialectically and continuously. c. On the other hand, MacIntyre underlines once again that “liberal morality of impartiality and impersonality turns out also to be a morally dangerous phenomenon in an interesting corresponding way. For suppose the bonds od patriotism to be dissolved: would liberal morality liberality be able to provide anything adequately substantial in its place?” (P. 54) “A central contention of the morality of patriotism is that I will obliterate and lose a central dimension of the moral life if I do not understand the enacted narrative of my own individual life as embedded in the history of my country. For if do not so understand it I will not understand what I owe to other or what others owe to me.” (P. 55) As a result, each individuals will probably come together simply for the pursue of naked self-interest and competition for maximization of one’s own profit like the institution of the capitalist market or simply for pleasure seeking and instant gratification to mass media and mass consumption markets. In the end, the morality of liberalism will be relegated into morality of emotionism as MacIntyre criticizes at the beginning of After Virtue. (2007) 88 Tsang & Mak Inquiry & Issues in Society & Culture Addition References 戴耀廷 (2010) 。香港的憲政之路。香港 : 中華書局(香港)有限公司。 Bendix, Reinhard (1977) Nation-Building and Citizenship. Berkeley: University of California Press. Cohen,, Jean and Andrew Arato (1992) Civil Society and Political Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Dworkin, Donald (1985) “Political Judges and the Rule of Law.” Pp. 9-32. In R. Dworkin. A Matter of Principle. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Dworkin, Ronal (1985) “ Civil disobedience and nuclear Protest.” Pp. 104-116. In R. Dworkin. A Matter of Principle. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Faure, David (2003) Colonialism and Hong Kong. Hong Kong: Centre of Asia Stuides, HKU. 99 Tsang & Mak Inquiry & Issues in Society & Culture Giddens, Anthony (1982) “Class Division, Class Conflict and Citizenship Rights.” In A. Giddens. Profiles and Critiques in Social Theory. London: Macmillan. Habermas, Jurgen (1986) Autonomy and Solidarity: Interviews with Jurgen Habermas, Revised Edition. Edited by P. Dews. London: Verso. Habermas, Jurgen (1996) Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. MacIntyre, Alasdair (2002) “Is Patriotism a Virture.” PP. 43-58. In I. Primoratz (Ed.) Patriotism. New York: Humanity Books. Macpherson, C.B. (1997) The life and Times of Liberal Democracy. Oxfard: Oxford University Press. Mann, Michael ((1987) “Ruling Class Strategies and Citizenship.” Sociology, 21 (3), Pp. 339-354. Marshall, T.H. (1992) “Citizenship and Social Class.” Pp. 3-51. T.H. Marshall and T.B. Botoomore. Citizenship and Social Class. Lonon: Pluto Press. Nathanson, Stephen (1993) Patriotism, Morality, and Peace. Lanham: Rowan & Littlefield. Rawles, John (1971) A Theory of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Specter, Andrew G. (2010) Habermas: An Intellectual Biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Tamanaha, Brain Z. (2004) On the Rule of Law: History, Politics, Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1010 Tsang & Mak Inquiry & Issues in Society & Culture