PKU2 CAUSATION 3 Modern Science Claims to Producing Knowledge Excerpted from pp 830-32 on CD-ROM, in Western Civilization with Chinese Comparisons, (WCwCC), 3rd ed, Shanghai: Fudan University Press, 2010 The cultural authority of science is based largely on its claims to producing knowledge that is factual, objective, and universal in application. And for centuries, scientific knowledge has been increasingly successful in reliably predicting the behavior of the physical universe. Most practicing scientists today emphasize the modesty of their goals: trying to understand “how things work.” But the larger framework of the Western tradition, carried over after the end of the Middle Ages to our own time, aimed higher, at truth: knowledge that would be beyond challenge because it was authoritative, hence certain. As long as the (Roman Catholic) Church maintained its medieval control over Western beliefs, truth was understood as theological in origin, as based on faith. Once modern science began to displace the confidence in the authority of Christianity, however, many Westerners looked to science as if it offered a comparable level of certainty. Over time, then, though scientists gradually ceased thinking in terms of truth, laymen attributed to science the same high cultural authority that had accompanied truth in earlier times. The history of science as an institution of knowledge production calls many of the high claims for its authority into question. The 19th century was probably the historical high point of Western confidence that science could explain everything that happens and, in the long run, solve all human problems. Since then, for a variety of reasons, this authority has come to seem questionable. To understand how and why, we need to examine briefly the procedures and presumptions of modern empirical science. Updating Aristotle on Causation Under modernity, the scientific method as a means to objective truth developed elaborate protocols (rules of procedure) in search of objectivity. Laboratories provided the possibility of controlling experimental circumstances in order that all factors except one (or a very small number) could be held constant or made irrelevant so that the single changing element in the experiment could be defined as the cause of whatever changes took place. In the process of this development, Aristotle’s four causes were collapsed down into one, what he called the “efficient cause” [link: Aristotle on causation]. The reason for the change boils down to the difference between a philosophical goal – to describe what we know as completely as possible – and a pragmatic goal – to understand natural processes in order to control them (and, especially under capitalism, to profit from them). Modern scientists seek to control experimental conditions so thoroughly that they focus on only one changing factor. In that case it can be construed as the sole (“efficient”) cause of the observed effect. In any experimental scientific procedure, the results must be repeatable by other researchers. That is obligatory in order to verify that no unrecognized factors produced the observed results. Otherwise some conditions that seemed to be sufficient may turn out not to be so, in which case no scientific connection has been established but the correlation is merely a coincidence, an accidental association. Necessary and Sufficient Causes If one can identify reliably the efficient cause (x) that always produces a desirable event as outcome (y), then one can hope to reproduce that effect whenever one feels the need. In modern terms, that means to identify the conditions that are both necessary and sufficient to produce the desired outcome. In fact, the possible links between any two events can be analyzed logically by way of if/then sentences expressed in terms of necessary and sufficient relationships. Here is a logical breakdown of the possible combinations that apply involving x and y: 1 “If x is neither necessary nor sufficient to y, then there is no causal connection between x and y.” This is a case without scientific interest because there is no reliable association between the two events; if they occur together it must be by accident. No further investigation is called for. Most of the events in the world fall into this broad category of unrelatedness. 2 “Even if x is sufficient for y, it may not always be necessary for y.” “A table’s being square is a sufficient, but not a necessary condition, for its having four sides.” Some four-sided shapes are not square, such as trapezoids. 3 “If x is necessary to y but not sufficient, then x will not all by itself result in y; BUT if x is not present, then y cannot take place.” “A table’s having four sides is a necessary, but not a sufficient, condition for its being square.” For something to be square, a number of conditions are necessary: a. the object has (exactly) four sides; b. each of the object’s sides is straight; c. the object is a closed figure (geometrically: all sides link up); d. the object lies in a plane; e. each of the object’s sides is equal in length to each of the others; f. each of the object’s interior angles is equal to the others (they are each right angles, i.e., 90-degrees). The foregoing is a complete set of necessary conditions; i.e., the set taken as a whole comprises the conditions sufficient for x’s being square. One might say that each of the items on this list is individually necessary but not sufficient for x’s being defined as a square. 4 “If x is both necessary and sufficient for y, then x will always entail y.” “If all the conditions listed under 3 are met, the table is square.” In other words, these conditions, taken all together, are jointly sufficient and necessary for the desired result. This is the case that science cares about because only this relation between x and y will hold predictably and verifiably. A Test Case: Boiling an egg in Lhasa Let us test this analysis against a concrete instance. Suppose that a researcher in Beijing has run an experiment that show that water boils at 100 degrees Centigrade, and this observation is reported as universally valid. On the basis of this “fact,” someone in Lhasa allots three minutes to the process of soft-boiling an egg, only to find that the egg is inadequately cooked because more time is needed to reach the same degree of cooked-ness. How did this happen? The researcher in Beijing did not identify one necessary but invisible condition for the observation to be valid everywhere, namely, that atmospheric pressure at or near sea level must be maintained for the cooking to take place at that temperature. Historically speaking, atmospheric pressure as a factor in boiling temperatures was formally quantified in the 18 th century. From then on, anyone working scientifically on such matters knew to take those conditions into account. But with any new investigation, there may be any number of invisible preconditions that must be identified before anyone can make a satisfactory list of necessary conditions which taken together are collectively sufficient to specify scientifically the outcome one desires to produce. It is exhausting and, most probably, impossible to make explicit all the necessary conditions pertaining to a completely precise observation. One negative result suffices to show that the double need [link: necessary and sufficient] for specificity of conditions has not been met. The success of the physical sciences has depended on identifying a very small number of variable conditions on which the results of an experiment depend. Such controlled circumstances are easier to achieve in a laboratory than in the world at large. Implications: physical sciences can follow these rules because they can stop the world in a laboratory in order to test their theories. Social sciences do not have that luxury so their claim to “science” is limited by their inability to experiment without having an impact on the events they wish to study.