Off #1 - T Failure to specify beyond “legalize” makes the plan void for vagueness-it wrecks negative ground and makes policy analysis impossible Kleiman and Saiger 90 -lecturer public policy Harvard, consultant drug policy Rand- 18 Hofstra L. Rev. 527. A SYMPOSIUM ON DRUG DECRIMINALIZATION: DRUG LEGALIZATION: THE IMPORTANCE OF ASKING THE RIGHT QUESTION. Defining Legalization Legalization, like prohibition, does not name a unique strategy. Perhaps the most prominent inadequacy of current legalization arguments is their failure to specify what is meant by "legalization ." Current drug policy provides an illustration of this diversity. Heroin and marijuana are completely prohibited, 74 and cocaine can only be used in rigidly specified medical contexts, not including any where the drug's psychoactive properties are exercised. 75 On the other hand, a wide range of pain-killers, sleepinducers, stimulants, tranquilizers and sedatives can be obtained with a doctor's prescription. 76 Alcohol is available for recreational use, but is subject to an array of controls including excise taxation, 77 limits on drinking ages, 78 limits on TV and radio advertising, 79 and retail licensing. 80 Nicotine is subject to age minimums, warning label requirements, 81 taxation, 82 and bans on smoking in some public places. 83 [*541] Drug legalization can therefore be thought of as moving drugs along a spectrum of regulated statuses in the direction of increased availability. However, while legalization advocates do not deny that some sort of controls will be required, their proposals rarely address the question of how far on the spectrum a given drug should be moved, or how to accomplish such a movement. Instead, such details are dismissed as easily determined, or postponed as a problem requiring future thought. 84 But the consequences of legalization depend almost entirely on the details of the remaining regulatory regime . The price and conditions of the availability of a newly legal drug will be more powerful in shaping its consumption than the fact that the drug is "legal." Rules about advertising, place and time of sale, and availability to minors help determine whether important aspects of the drug problem get better or worse. The amount of regulatory apparatus required and the way in which it is organized and enforced will determine how much budget reduction can be realized from dismantling current enforcement efforts. 85 Moreover, currently illicit drugs, because they are so varied pharmacologically, would not all pose the same range of the problems if they were to be made legally available for non-medical use. They would therefore require different control regimes. These regimes might need to be as diverse as the drugs themselves. Vote neg – Ground – forces the negative to read generic disadvantages and prevents debates over the details of the plans legalization – PIC’s and disadvantage based off regulations are key in the lit Topic education – prevents having a debate over the heart of the literature – it’s not if you legalize organ sales, but how you do it – key to clash Off #2 – CP The United States should decriminalize nearly all organ sales in the United States. Legalization expands the black market – legitimacy and awareness Mendoza 2010 (Roger, PhD and Specialist in welfare economics, “Kidney black markets and legal transplants: Are they opposite sides of the same coin?”. Health Policy. 94 (2010). pp. 262-3) [nagel] One key implication we can gain from the foregoing analysis of the legal and regulatory framework is that consensus does exist within government and among Filipinos concerning the need to eradicate kidney trafficking. Yet, at the same time, there is considerable conflict within government agencies and hospitals, and lack of sufficient public involvement, because various authorities benefit from ensuring that kidney trafficking persists, as our surveyed vendors indicate. For these reasons, the black market is not effectively regulated by law-enforcement agencies. The measures that we reviewed have done little to achieve their policy objectives [48]. They have even paradoxically blurred the distinction between legal and illicit transplantation and, in effect, conferred some semblance of legitimacy to black market trading for the following reasons: 4.1. Lack of public awareness Policy implementation will be ineffective if existing rules and prohibitions are not common public knowledge. Our survey of kidney vendors indicates that 75.3–83.3 per cent either did not know it was illegal to sell their kidneys, or were unaware of the existence of such measures, which are written in English and strict legalese (Table 11). In contrast, kidney trading assumes a public and open character. Without a grassroots-based strategy, deliberate efforts at public education about health risks/hazards and health promotion, trade participants will likely find it economically inefficient to distinguish between what is legal and prohibited in kidney donation/transplantation. Safeguards produce an underclass of rejected donors who supply the black market Scheper-Hughes 2005 (Nancy, Professor at UC-Berkeley, “THE LAST COMMODITY: Post-Human Ethics and the Global Traffic in ‘‘Fresh’’ Organs”. Global Assemblages: Technology, Politics, and Ethics as Anthropological Problems. Ed. Aihwa Ong and Stephen Collier. Blackwell Publishing. Malden, MA. pp. 152-3) [nagel] Bangon Lupa is a garbage-strewn slum built on stilt shacks over a polluted and feces-infested stretch of the Pasig River that runs through the shantytown on its way to Manila Bay. In Bangon Lupa, ‘‘coming of age’’ now means that one is legally old enough to sell a kidney. But, as with other coming of age rituals, many young men lie about their age and boast of having sold a kidney when they were as young as 16 years old: ‘‘No one at the hospital asks us for any documents’’ they assured me. The kidney donors lied about other things as well – their names, addresses, and medical histories, including their daily exposure to the general plagues of the third world – TB, AIDS, dengue, and hepatitis, not to mention chronic skin infections and malnutrition. In this barangay of largely unemployed stevedores, I encountered an unanticipated ‘‘waiting list,’’ comprised of angry and ‘‘disrespected’’ kidney sellers who had been ‘‘neglected’’ and ‘‘overlooked’’ by the medical doctors at Manila’s most prestigious private hospital, St. Luke’s Episcopal Medical Center. When word spread that I was looking to speak to kidney sellers, several scowling and angry young men approached me to complain: ‘‘We are strong and virile men, and yet none of us has been called up to sell.’’ Perhaps they had been rejected, the men surmised, because of their age (too young or too old), their blood (difficult to match), or their general medical condition. But whatever the reason, they had been judged as less valuable kidney vendors than some of their lucky neighbors, who now owned new VCRs, karaoke machines, and expensive tricycles. ‘‘What’s wrong with me?,’’ a 42-year-old man asked, thinking I must be an American kidney hunter. ‘‘I registered six months ago, and no one from St. Luke’s has called me . . . But I am healthy. I can lift heavy weights. And my urine is clean.’’ Moreover, he was willing, he said, to sell below the going rate of $1,300 for a fresh kidney. When one donor is rejected, another, younger and more healthy looking, family member is often substituted. And kidney selling becomes an economic niche in some families that specialize in it. Indeed, one large extended family Bangong Lupa supplied St. Luke’s Hospital with a reliable source of kidneys, borrowing strength from across the generations as first father, then son, and then daughter-in-law each stepped forward to contribute to the family income. Legalization increases black market – empirics Turner 2009 (Leigh, Associate Professor in the Center for Bioethics, School of Public Health, and College of Pharmacy at the University of Minnesota, “Commercial Organ Transplantation in the Philippines”. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics. 18:2. April 2009. pp. 192-196. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0963180109090318) [nagel] Due to changes in legislation and regulatory enforcement, it is now much more difficult for foreign patients to purchase kidneys in China and several other jurisdictions where commercial sales of organs occurred. Pakistan and India now have legislation prohibiting buying and selling human organs. Though legislative reforms have driven commerce in organs underground , commercial transplants still occur in both countries . 7 In 2006, China curtailed the number of foreign patients purchasing organ transplants at Chinese medical facilities. 8 In contrast, commercial organ transplantation persists in the Philippines. Off – K The aff explicitly sanctions the neoliberal commodification of the body – they reify medical apartheid and social injustice Scheper-Hughes 2002 (Nancy, Prof at UC-Berkeley, “The Ends of the Body: Commodity Fetishism and the Global Traffic in Organs”. SAIS Review. 22:1. (Winter-Spring 2002), pp. 61-2) [nagel] Amidst the neoliberal readjustments of the new global economy, there has been a rapid growth of “medical tourism” for transplant surgery and other advanced biomedical and surgical procedures. A grotesque niche market for sold organs, tissues, and other body parts has exacerbated older divisions between North and South, haves and have-nots, organ donors and organ recipients. Indeed, a kind of medical apartheid has also emerged that has separated the world into two populations—organ givers and organ receivers. Over the past 30 years, organ transplantation—especially kidney transplantation—has become a common procedure in hospitals and clinics throughout the world. The spread of transplant technologies has created a global scarcity of viable organs. At the same time the spirit of a triumphant global and “democratic” capitalism has released a voracious appetite for “fresh” bodies from which organs can be procured. The confluence in the flows of immigrant workers and itinerant kidney sellers who fall prey to sophisticated but unscrupulous transnational organ brokers is a subtext in the recent history of globalization. Today’s organ procurement transactions are a blend of altruism and commerce; of science and superstition; of gifting, barter, and theft; and of voluntarism and coercion. International Organ Markets, Bioethics, and Social Justice The problem with markets is that they reduce everything — including human beings, their labor, and their reproductive capacity — to the status of commodities that can be bought, sold, traded, and stolen. Nowhere is this more dramatically illustrated than in the market for human organs and tissues. The concepts of the integrity of the body and human dignity have given way to ideas of the divisible body and detachable organs as commodities. The new field of bioethics has largely capitulated to the dominant market ethos. 1 Conventional medical ethics obscures the ancient perception of virtue in suffering and dying, while bioethics creates the semblance of ethical choice (e.g., the right to buy a kidney) in an intrinsically unethical context. The transformation of a person into a “life” that must be prolonged or saved at any cost has made life into the ultimate commodity fetish. This idea erases any possibility of a global social ethic. In the rational choice language of contemporary bioethics the conflict between non-malfeasance (“do no harm”) and beneficence (the moral duty to perform good acts) is increasingly resolved in favor of the libertarian and consumer-oriented principle that those able to broker or buy a human organ should not be prevented from doing so. In a market context, paying for a kidney “donation” is viewed as a potential “win-win” situation that can benefit both parties. 2 Individual decision making has become the final arbiter of medical bioethical values. Social justice hardly figures into these discussions because bioethical standards have been finely calibrated to mesh with the needs and desires of consumer-oriented globalization. Their focus on subjective flashpoints of violence creates a stop-gap in thought which distracts us from attempts to solve the root cause of all violence - Capital Zizek, ’08 (Slavoj, senior researcher at the Institute of Sociology, University of Ljubljana, Slovenia and a professor at the European Graduate School, Violence, p. 1-4) If there is a unifying thesis that runs through the bric-a-brac of reflections on violence that follow, it is that a similar paradox holds true for violence. At the forefront of our minds, the obvious signals of violence are acts of crime and terror, civil unrest, international conflict . But we should learn to step back , to disentangle ourselves from the fascinating lure of this directly visible “subjective” violence, violence performed by a clearly identifiable agent. We need to perceive the contours of the background which generates such outbursts. A step back enables us to identify a violence that sustains our very efforts to fight violence and to promote tolerance. This is the starting point, perhaps even the axiom, of the present book: subjective violence is just the most visible portion of a triumvirate that also includes two objective kinds of violence. First, there is a “symbolic” violence embodied in language and its forms, what Heidegger would call “our house of being.” As we shall see later, this violence is not only at work in the obvious—and extensively studied—cases of incitement and of the relations of social domination reproduced in our habitual speech forms: there is a more fundamental form of violence still that pertains to language as such, to its imposition of a certain universe of Second, there is what I call “systemic” violence, or the often catastrophic consequences of the smooth functioning of our economic and political systems . The catch is that subjective and objective meaning. violence cannot be perceived from the same standpoint : subjective violence is experienced as such against the background of a non-violent zero level. It is seen as a perturbation of the “normal,” peaceful state of things. However, objective violence is precisely the violence inherent to this “normal” state of things. Objective violence is invisible since it sustains the very zero-level standard against which we perceive something as subjectively violent. Systemic violence is thus something like the notorious “dark matter” of physics, the counterpart to an all-too- visible subjective violence. It may be invisible, but it has to be taken into account if one is to make sense of what otherwise seem to be “irrational” explosions of subjective violence. When the media bombard us with those “humanitarian crises” which seem constantly to pop up all over the world, one should always bear in mind that a particular crisis only explodes into media visibility as the result of a complex struggle. Properly humanitarian considerations as a rule play a less important role here than cultural, ideologico-political, and economic considerations. The cover story of Time magazine on 5 June 2006, for example, was “The Deadliest War in the World.” This offered detailed documentation on how around 4 million people died in the Democratic Republic of Congo as the result of political violence over the last decade. None of the usual humanitarian uproar followed, just a couple of readers’ letters—as if some kind of filtering mechanism blocked this news from achieving its full impact in our symbolic space. To put it cynically, Time picked the wrong victim in the struggle for hegemony in suffering. It should have stuck to the list of usual suspects: Muslim women and their plight, or the families of 9/11 victims and how they have coped with their losses. The Congo today has effectively re-emerged as a Conradean “heart of darkness.” No one dares to confront it head on. The death of a West Bank Palestinian child, not to mention an Israeli or an American, is mediatically worth thousands of times more than the death of a nameless Congolese. Do we need further proof that the humanitarian sense of urgency is mediated, indeed overdetermined, by clear political considerations? And what are these considerations? To answer this, we need to step back and take a look from a different position. When the U.S. media reproached the public in foreign countries for not displaying enough sympathy for the victims of the 9/11 attacks, one was tempted to answer them in the words Robespierre addressed to those who complained about the innocent victims of revolutionary terror: “Stop shaking the tyrant’s bloody robe in my face, or I will believe that you wish to put Rome in chains.”1 There are reasons for looking at the problem of violence awry. My underlying premise is that there is something inherently mystifying in a direct confrontation with it: the overpowering horror of violent acts and empathy with the victims inexorably function as a lure which prevents us from thinking . A dispassionate conceptual development of the typology of violence Instead of confronting violence directly, the present book casts six sideways glances. must by definition ignore its traumatic impact. Yet there is a sense in which a cold analysis of violence somehow reproduces and participates in its horror. A distinction needs to be made, as well, between (factual) truth and truthfulness: what renders a report of a raped woman (or any other narrative of a trauma) truthful is its very factual unreliability, its confusion, its inconsistency. If the victim were able to report on her painful and humiliating experience in a clear manner, with all the data arranged in a consistent order, this very quality would make us suspicious of its truth. The problem here is part of the solution: the very factual deficiencies of the traumatised subject’s report on her experience bear witness to the truthfulness of her report, since they signal that the reported content “contaminated” the manner of reporting it. The same holds, of course, for the so-called unreliability of the verbal reports of Holocaust survivors: the witness able to offer a clear narrative of his camp experience would disqualify himself by virtue of that clarity.2 The only appropriate approach to my subject thus seems to be one which permits variations on violence kept at a distance out of respect towards its victims. Must analyze the root social causes of organ sales – lack risks serial policy failure Epstein 2011 (Miran, Prof at Queen Mary University of London, “If I were a rich man could I sell a pancreas? A study in the locus of oppression”. J Med Ethics 2011; 37: 109-112. doi:10.1136/jme.2010.039636) [nagel] The assumption I have just discussed gives rise to a complex counterintuitive conclusion: the opponents and the proponents of organ vending are both right and wrong at the same time. The opponents are right in saying that it essentially involves oppression, but they are wrong in confining their search for it to the sphere of exchange alone. This sphere – the kingdom of transactions, the realm of buyer-vendor relations – may involve oppressive elements. Perhaps it involves such elements more often than not. That having been said, it does not necessarily involve them. But whereas the sphere of exchange is not essentially oppressive, its social context is! Conversely, the proponents of organ vending are right in saying that its sphere of exchange is not essentially oppressive. However, like their rivals, they are wrong in confining their search for any oppressive elements to that sphere alone. They ignore the possibility that perfectly fair commercial transactions can easily take place in a perfectly oppressive context. In the case of organ vending, this is presumably the rule. One might perhaps get the impression that each of the parties has made nothing but a simple error here. There is another way of looking at it, however. Their joint failure to spot the essentially oppressive context in which organ vending is taking place may not be accidental. Rather, it may be a necessarily distorted (and distorting) product of that very context, or in other words, an ideological façade that conceals and reaffirms the oppressive environment from which it has emerged . This possibility sheds new light on the reciprocal effect of each of the sides of the debate on the context of organ vending, which is at the same time their own constitutive context. The pro-vending camp reaffirms that context both by yielding to its essential oppressiveness as well as by concealing it. In contrast, the anti-vending camp happens to fight its oppressiveness, albeit indirectly and typically without even realizing that it does so, let alone intending to do so. Yet by ignoring its oppressiveness, it undermines its own enterprise. Indeed, any attempt to the halt the commoditisation of the body without explicitly tackling the conditions that give rise to its possibility cannot be taken too seriously. Cap’s unsustainable and causes extinction, but the alt solves This is not a meaningless question – the structures of capitalism are driving multiple large-scale processes that are increasingly out of the control of individuals living their lives. Global warming, multiple wars of accumulation, loss of land and income stratification: all of these are making life unlivable. Parr ’13 (Adrian, Assoc. Prof. of Philosophy and Environmental Studies @ U. of Cincinnati, THE WRATH OF CAPITAL: Neoliberalism and Climate Change Politics, pp. 145-147) A quick snapshot of the twenty-first century so far: an economic meltdown; a frantic sell-off of public land to the energy business as President George W Bush exited the White House; a prolonged, costly, and unjustified war in Iraq; the Greek economy in ruins; an escalation of global food prices; bee colonies in global extinction; 925 million hungry reported in 2010; as of 2005, the world's five hundred richest individuals with a combined income greater than that of the poorest 416 million people, the richest 10 percent accounting for 54 percent of global income; a planet on the verge of boiling point; melting ice caps; increases in extreme weather conditions; and the list goes on and on and on.2 Sounds like a ticking time bomb, doesn't it? Well it is. It is shameful to think that massive die-outs of future generations will put to pale comparison the 6 million murdered during the Holocaust; the millions killed in two world wars; the genocides in the former Yugoslavia, Rwanda, and Darfur; the 1 million left homeless and the 316,000 killed by the 2010 earthquake in Haiti. The time has come to wake up to the warning signs.3 The real issue climate change poses is that we do not enjoy the luxury of incremental change anymore. We are in the last decade where we can do something about the situation. Paul Gilding, the former head of Greenpeace International and a core faculty member of Cambridge University's Programme for Sustainability, explains that "two degrees of warming is an inadequate goal and a plan for failure;' adding that "returning to below one degree of warming . . . is the solution to the problem:'4 Once we move higher than 2°C of warming, which is what is projected to occur by 2050, positive feedback mechanisms will begin to kick in, and then we will be at the point of no return. We therefore need to start thinking very differently right now. We do not see the crisis for what it is; we only see it as an isolated symptom that we need to make a few minor changes to deal with. This was the message that Venezuela's president Hugo Chavez delivered at the COP15 United Nations Climate Summit in Copenhagen on December 16, 2009, when he declared: "Let's talk about the cause. We should not avoid responsibilities, we should not avoid the depth of this problem. And I'll bring it up again, the cause of this disastrous panorama is the metabolic, destructive system of the capital and its model: capitalism.”5 The structural conditions in which we operate are advanced capitalism. Given this fact, a few adjustments here and there to that system are not enough to solve the problems that climate change and environmental degradation pose.6 Adaptability, modifications, and displacement, as I have consistently shown throughout this book, constitute the very essence of capitalism. Capitalism adapts without doing away with the threat. Under capitalism, one deals with threat not by challenging it, but by buying favors from it, as in voluntary carbon-offset schemes. In the process, one gives up on one's autonomy and reverts to being a child. Voluntarily offsetting a bit of carbon here and there, eating vegan, or recycling our waste, although well intended, are not solutions to the problem, but a symptom of the free market's ineffectiveness. By casting a scathing look at the neoliberal options on display, I have tried to show how all these options are ineffective. We are not buying indulgences because we have a choice; choices abound, and yet they all lead us down one path and through the golden gates of capitalist heaven. For these reasons, I have underscored everyone's implication in this structure – myself included. If anything, the book has been an act of outrage – outrage at the deceit and the double bind that the "choices" under capitalism present, for there is no choice when everything is expendable. There is nothing substantial about the future when all you can do is survive by facing the absence of your own future and by sharing strength, stamina, and courage with the people around you. All the rest is false hope. In many respects, writing this book has been an anxious exercise because I am fully aware that reducing the issues of environmental degradation and climate change to the domain of analysis can stave off the institution of useful solutions. But in my defense I would also like to propose that each and every one of us has certain skills that can contribute to making the solutions that we introduce in response to climate change and environmental degradation more effective and more realistic. In light of that view, I close with the following proposition, which I mean in the most optimistic sense possible: our politics must start from the point that after 2050 it may all be over. Challenging global capital is the ultimate ethical responsibility. The current order guarantees social exclusion on a global scale Zizek and Daly 2004 (Slavoj, professor of philosophy at the Institute for Sociology, Ljubljana, and Glyn, Senior Lecturer in Politics in the Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences at UniversityCollege, Northampton, Conversations with Zizek, page 14-16) For Zizek it is imperative that we cut through this Gordian knot of postmodern protocol and recognize thatour ethico-political responsibility is to confront the constitutive violence of today’s global capitalism and its obscene naturalization / anonymization of the millions who are subjugated by it throughout the world.Against the standardized positions of postmodern culture – with all its pieties concerning ‘multiculturalist’ etiquette –Zizek is arguing for a politics thatmight be called ‘radically incorrect’ in the sense that it break with these types of positions 7 andfocusesinsteadon the very organizing principles of today’s social reality:the principles of global liberal capitalism. This requires some care and subtlety. For far too long, Marxism has been bedeviled by an almost fetishistic economism that has tended towards political morbidity. With the likes of Hilferding and Gramsci, and more recently Laclau and Mouffee, crucial theoretical advances have been made that enable the transcendence of all forms of economism. In this new context, however, Zizek argues that the problem that now presents itself is almost that of the opposite fetish. That is to say, the prohibitive anxieties surrounding the taboo of economism can function as a way of not engaging with economic reality and as a way of implicitly accepting the latter as a basic horizon of existence. In an ironic Freudian-Lacanian twist, the fear of economism can end up reinforcing a de facto economic necessity in respect of contemporary capitalism (i.e. the initial prohibition conjures up the very thing it fears). This is not to endorse any kind of retrograde return to economism. Zizek’s point is rather that in rejecting economism we should not lose sight of the systemic power of capital in shaping the lives and destinies of humanity and our very sense of the possible. In particular we should not overlook Marx’s central insight thatin order to create a universal global system the forces of capitalism seek to conceal the politico-discursive violence of its construction through a kind of gentrification of that system.What is persistently denied by neo-liberals such as Rorty (1989) and Fukuyama (1992) is that the gentrification of global liberal capitalism is one whose ‘universalism’ fundamentally reproduces and depends upon a disavowed violence that excludes vast sectors of the world’s populations. In this way,neo-liberal ideology attempts to naturalize capitalism by presenting its outcomes of winning and losing as if they were simply a matter of chance and sound judgment in a neutral market place.Capitalism does indeed create a space for a certain diversity, at least for the central capitalist regions, but it is neither neutral nor ideal and its price in terms of social exclusion is exorbitant. That is to say,the human cost in terms of inherent global poverty and degraded ‘life-chances’ cannot be calculated within the existing economic rationale and,in consequence,social exclusion remains mystified and nameless(viz. the patronizing reference to the ‘developing world’). And Zizek’s point is thatthis mystification is magnified through capitalism’s profound capacity to ingest its own excesses and negativity: to redirect(or misdirect)social antagonisms and to absorb them within a culture of differential affirmation.Instead of Bolshevism, the tendency today is towards a kind of political boutiquism that is readily sustained by postmodern forms of consumerism and lifestyle.Against thisZizek argues for a new universalism whose primary ethical directive is to confront the fact that our forms of social existence are founded on exclusion on a global scale.While it is perfectly true that universalism can never become Universal (it will always require a hegemonic-particular embodiment in order to have any meaning),what is novel about Zizek’s universalism is that it would not attempt to conceal this fact or reduce the status of the abject Other to that of a ‘glitch’ in an otherwise sound matrix. Our alternative is to completely withdraw from the ideology of capital - this opens up the space for authentic politics Johnston ’04 (Adrian, interdisciplinary research fellow in psychoanalysis at Emory, The Cynic’s Fetish: Slavoj Zizek and the Dynamics of Belief, Psychoanalysis, Culture and Society) Perhaps the absence of a detailed political roadmap in Žižek’s recent writings isn’t a major shortcoming. Maybe, at least for the time being, the most important task is simply the negativity of the critical struggle, the effort to cure an intellectual constipation resulting from capitalist ideology and thereby to truly open up the space for imagining authentic alternatives to the prevailing state of the situation. Another definition of materialism offered by Žižek is that it amounts to accepting the internal inherence of what fantasmatically appears as an external deadlock or hindrance ( Žižek, 2001d, pp 22–23) (with fantasy itself being defined as the false externalization of something within the subject, namely, the illusory projection of an inner obstacle, Žižek, 2000a, p 16). From this perspective, seeing through ideological fantasies by learning how to think again outside the confines of current restrictions has, in and of itself, the potential to operate as a form of real revolutionary practice (rather than remaining merely an instance of negative/critical intellectual reflection). Why is this the case? Recalling the analysis of commodity fetishism, the social efficacy of money as the universal medium of exchange (and the entire political economy grounded upon it) ultimately relies upon nothing more than a kind of ‘‘magic,’’ that is, the belief in money’s social efficacy by those using it in the processes of exchange. Since the value of currency is, at bottom, reducible to the belief that it has the value attributed to it (and that everyone believes that everyone else believes this as well), derailing capitalism by destroying its essential financial substance is, in a certain respect, as easy as dissolving the mere belief in this substance’s powers. The ‘‘external’’ obstacle of the capitalist system exists exclusively on the condition that subjects, whether consciously or unconsciously, ‘‘internally’’ believe in it – capitalism’s life-blood, money, is simply a fetishistic crystallization of a belief in others’ belief in the socio-performative force emanating from this same material. And yet, this point of capitalism’s frail vulnerability is simultaneously the source of its enormous strength: its vampiric symbiosis with individual human desire, and the fact that the late-capitalist cynic’s fetishism enables the disavowal of his/her de facto belief in capitalism, makes it highly unlikely that people can simply be persuaded to stop believing and start thinking (especially since, as Žižek claims, many of these people are convinced that they already have ceased believing). Or, the more disquieting possibility to entertain is that some people today, even if one succeeds in exposing them to the underlying logic of their position, might respond in a manner resembling that of the Judas-like character Cypher in the film The Matrix (Cypher opts to embrace enslavement by illusion rather than cope with the discomfort of dwelling in the ‘‘desert of the real’’): faced with the choice between living the capitalist lie or wrestling with certain unpleasant truths, many individuals might very well deliberately decide to accept what they know full well to be a false pseudo-reality, a deceptively comforting fiction (‘‘Capitalist commodity fetishism or the truth? I choose fetishism’’). Our alt is more political than the plan – the plan is pseudo-activity that makes us feel like we’ve done something when nothing has changed. Use your ballot to vote neg and refuse to participate in politics-as-usual. Zizek, ’08(Slavoj, senior researcher at the Institute of Sociology, University of Ljubljana, Slovenia and a professor at the European Graduate School, Violence, p. 216-217) In psychoanalytic terms, the voters’ abstentionis something like the psychotic Verwerfung (foreclosure, rejection/repudiation) whichisamore radicalmove than repression (Verdrangung). According to Freud, the repressed is intellectually accepted by the subject, since it is named, and at the same time is negated because the subject refuses to recognise it, refuses to recognise him or herself in it. In contrast to this, foreclosure rejects the term from the symbolic tout court. To circumscribe the contours of this radical rejection one is tempted to evoke Badiou’s provocative thesis: “It is better to do nothing than to contribute to the invention of formal ways of rendering visible that which Empire already recognizes as existent.”6 Better to do nothing than to engage in localised acts the ultimate function of which is to make the system run more smoothly(acts such as providing space for the multitude of new subjectivities).The threat today is not passivity, but pseudo- activity, the urge to “be active,” to “participate,” to mask the nothingness of what goes on. People intervene all the time, “do something”; academics participate in meaningless debates, and so on. The truly difficult thing is to step back, to withdraw.Those in power often prefer even a “critical” participation, a dialogue, to silence—just to engage us in “dialogue,” to make sure our ominous passivity is broken.The voters’ abstention is thus a true political act: it forcefully confronts us with the vacuity of today’s democracies. If one means by violence a radical upheaval of the basic social relations,then,crazy and tasteless as it may sound, the problem with historical monsters who slaughtered millions was that they were not violent enough. Sometimes doing nothing is the most violent thing to do. ADV General Solvency F/L 1. Scarcity artificially constructed – special interest corruption Scheper-Hughes 2001 (Nancy, Prof at UC-Berkeley, “Commodity Fetishism in Organs Trafficking”. Body and Society. 2001. 7:31. pp. 31-62. DOI: 10.1177/1357034X0100700203) [nagel] The market in organs is driven by the simple calculus of ‘supply and demand’ and by the specter of waiting lists, organ scarcities and organ panics. But the very idea of organ or kidney ‘scarcity’ is what Ivan Illich (1992) would call an artificially created need, one that is invented by transplant technicians, doctors and their brokers, and dangled before the eyes of an ever expanding sick, aging, desperate and dying population. Newer and better technologies of organ retrieval and preservation and later generation immune suppression and anti-rejection drugs (see Cohen, this issue) promise an extension of life or an improvement in the quality of life through transplant surgery to an ever expanding pool of transplant candidates. In recent years, various transplant centers have begun to offer, on an experimental basis, transplants to populations of previously excluded patients – the elderly (over 65 years), the immunologically impaired, the difficult to match, HIV serropositive and hepatitis C patients. These are high-risk, poor-outcome patients who were previously denied a place on organs transplant waiting lists in most countries. Now, ‘guardedly optimistic’ reports on the outcomes of such experimental programs in Western Europe were uncritically discussed at the annual meetings of Eurotransplant, which I attended in the fall of 2000 in Leiden, the Netherlands. There was almost no reflection on the effect that such marginal programs might have in inflating the demands for already ‘scarce’ organs. Instead, an ethos of rugged market individualism prevailed in place of a discourse on social medical ethics. One hesitant pediatric surgeon raised a lonely voice from the convention hall. She rose to the microphone to ask the panelists the following question. Since the pool of available organs was finite, and given that donation rates were flat or even declining in some Eurotransplant countries, wouldn’t these experimental transplant programs further decrease the availability of organs for child and adolescent patients? The chair of the panel replied that the distribution of organs would continue to be monitored by Eurotransplant with attention to the constantly shifting priorities that are accorded to different classes of patients. ‘Yes, it is a bit like a balloon’, the chairman stated, ‘and demands and pressures from one group impact the expectations of other, previously privileged groups. But this is part of the democratic process through which organ allocations are made.’ Here ‘democracy’ has been redefined as the contestations among special interest pressure groups, which seems inappropriate in the medical context. 2. No shortage solvency – underlying fears Neri 2002 (Rebecca M., Associate of Devorsetz, Stinziano, Gilberti, Smith & Heintz, NY Attorney, The Digest, 10 Digest 67, p. 80-1) [nagel] The corruption lies not in the potential for market abuses, but rather in the existing social consciousness of the population. As mentioned above, the six [*81] most popular reasons people give for not donating organs are: "hastiness of organ retrieval and a feeling that declaration of death and immediate subsequent removal of organs interferes with the family's expression of grief; mutilation; fatalism and superstition; religion; age and ignorance." n67 If the greater social value of organs is to prevent their being interred without harvesting and to save lives, then the market must arrange itself around enabling people to weigh their cost or fear concerning donation. But how is a market to do this when, in fact, the incentive is merely valued in fiscal terms? How can a market theory, which relies on the wealth of its participants more so than the social justice of its actors effectively push social mores towards weighing the benefits of giving over the cost of facing ones personal fears? It simply cannot. Though any market incentive might push people towards realizing that money is preferable in exchange for needed organs, the market incentive simply fails to account for the underlying fears of the people concerning donation. The market cannot provide a structure in which ordinary people can rationally weigh costs and benefits of organ donation, because the market lacks sufficient grounding in the irrational fears concerning donation. A pure incentive program that replaces altruism with cash, or other necessities is inadequate as it falls short of effectively replacing existing social fears connected with donating organs after death. If there really is to be any increase in the organ supply, the answer lies in reshaping society not through a free market and property system, but rather, through structuring discussion around changing social values at their core. 3. Squo solves – 3D printing Griggs 4/3/2014 (Brandon, Senior Contributor to CNNTech Online, “The next frontier in 3-D printing: Human organs”. CNN Online. DA: 8/10/2014. http://www.cnn.com/2014/04/03/tech/innovation/3-dprinting-human-organs/) [nagel] Bioprinting works like this: Scientists harvest human cells from biopsies or stem cells, then allow them to multiply in a petri dish. The resulting mixture, a sort of biological ink, is fed into a 3-D printer, which is programmed to arrange different cell types, along with other materials, into a precise three-dimensional shape. Doctors hope that when placed in the body, these 3-D-printed cells will integrate with existing tissues. The process already is seeing some success. Last year a 2-year-old girl in Illinois, born without a trachea, received a windpipe built with her own stem cells. The U.S. government has funded a university-led "body on a chip" project that prints tissue samples that mimic the functions of the heart, liver, lungs and other organs. The samples are placed on a microchip and connected with a blood substitute to keep the cells alive, allowing doctors to test specific treatments and monitor their effectiveness. "This is an exciting new area of medicine. It has the potential for being a very important breakthrough," said Dr. Jorge Rakela, a gastroenterologist at the Mayo Clinic in Phoenix and a member of the American Liver Foundation's medical advisory committee. "Three-D printing allows you to be closer to what is happening in real life, where you have multiple layers of cells," he said. With current 2-D models, "if you grow more than one or two layers, the cells at the bottom suffocate from lack of oxygen." To accelerate the development of bioprinted organs, a Virginia foundation that supports regenerative medicine research announced in December it will award a $1 million prize for the first organization to print a fully functioning liver. One early contender for the prize is Organovo, a California start-up that has been a leader in bioprinting human body parts for commercial purposes. Using cells from donated tissue or stem cells, Organovo is developing what it hopes will be authentic models of human organs, primarily livers, for drug testing. 4. Effective regulation impossible Rothman and Rothman 2006 (S.M. and D.J., Profs at Columbia University, “The Hidden Cost of Organ Sale”. American Journal of Transplantation. 6:7. July. 1524-1528. DOI: 10.1111/j.16006143.2006.01325.x) [nagel] We disagree with the Ableist language used. Whatever the proposed system, regulation may not be readily accomplished. Once a market is lawful, halfway measures that allow for sellers but not for buyers might prove inoperative. Effectively regulated markets typically involve so-called ‘natural monopolies’ wherein entry points can be effectively policed. (Think of electric power, telephone service and railroads.) By contrast, in kidney sale, with almost everyone eligible to enter the market, oversight [regulation] will not be easily established or maintained. So too, as most students of regulated markets are quick to admit, change almost inevitably carries unintended consequences. Deregulate the market in energy trading and Enron scandals occur; deregulate the telephone market and the communications industry is transformed; deregulate the savings and loan business and corruption breaks out. Hence, the question must be asked: since practices may develop in ways that cannot be predicted or controlled, are we ready to live with a system that makes kidneys a commodity? 5. Legalization bad – 5 reasons -altruism decrease, increase poverty, consent coerced, legal safeguards fail, health decline Goyal et al 2002 (Madhav, and Ravindra L. Mehta, Lawrence J. Schneiderman, and Ashwini R. Sehgal, Department of Internal Medicine, Geisinger Health System, State College, Pa (Dr Goyal); Department of Nephrology, University of California, San Diego (Dr Mehta); Departments of Family and Preventive Medicine and Medicine, University of California, San Diego, School of Medicine (Dr Schneiderman); Division of Nephrology and Center for Health Care Research and Policy, MetroHealth Medical Center, and Departments of Medicine, Biomedical Ethics, and Epidemiology and Biostatistics, Case Western Reserve University, Cleveland, Ohio (Dr Sehgal). “Economic and Health Consequences of Selling a Kidney in India”. Journal of the American Medical Association. 2002; 288(13):1589-1593. doi:10.1001/jama.288.13.1589.) [nagel] We disagree with the gendered language used. Our quantitative findings, along with those of previous qualitative studies,9,16,31,32,34,35 undercut 5 key assumptions made by supporters of the sale of kidneys. First, although paying people to donate may have increased the supply of organs for transplantation, the financial incentive did not supplement underlying altruistic motivations. Only 5% of participants said wanting to help a sick person was a major factor in their decision to sell. Second, selling a kidney did not help poor donors overcome poverty. Family income actually declined by one third, and most participants were still in debt and living below the poverty line at the time of the survey. Third, regardless of these poor economic outcomes, sellers arguably have a right to make informed decisions about their own bodies. However, most participants would not recommend that others sell a kidney, which suggests that potential donors would be unlikely to sell a kidney if they were better informed of the likely outcomes. Fourth, safeguards such as eliminating middle [persons]men or having an authorization committee did not appear to be effective. Middlemen and clinics paid less than they promised, and the authorization committees did not ensure that donations were motivated by altruism alone. Fifth, nephrectomy was associated with a decline in health status. Previous qualitative reports suggest that a diminished ability to perform physical labor may explain the observed worsening of economic status.31- 35 Persistent pain and decline in health status have not been reported in previous long-term follow-up of volunteer donors in developed countries.47 Morality/Justice Turn Turn – the only true justice and moral stance is to reject organ sales Shalev 2003 (Carmel, Lawyer-Ethicist Gertner Institute, Tel Hashomer, Israel, “Organs, justice and human dignity”. Debate - Controversy: An ethical market in human organs Charles A Erin, John Harris J Med Ethics 2003; 29:3 137-138 doi:10.1136/jme.29.3.137) [nagel] Justice is at stake, because the moral question that the shortage of organs raises is one of fair distribution. Globally, it is clear that the need for organs for all persons suffering renal failure throughout the world will not be satisfied. The rich will benefit from a market in human organs and not the poor. There are many sick persons facing risk of death in the world. Most live in countries that do not have the professional capacity and technological infrastructure for either dialysis or transplantation. Only some are fortunate enough to have access to medical services that can save their lives, and the ability (or insurance) to pay for their costs. In countries that have public medical facilities with transplantation capability, the poor will wait on dialysis for organs from cadavers while rich people will buy transplantation services with living donors. The argument for human dignity is a moral intuition, which Margaret Radin articulated several years ago. To put it simply, there are certain things that money can’t buy and that are not for sale. Once upon a time medicine was a calling, but now it is becoming a business. Despite the vagueness of the idea of human dignity, it is an intuitive value that resists the notion of a contract for a pound of flesh. Freedom of contract is not an absolute. Many legal systems refuse to recognize the validity of contracts that are illegal, immoral or contrary to public policy. In 1991 the World Health Organization published guiding principles on organ transplantation. Guiding Principle 5 is crystal clear: “The human body and its parts cannot be the subject of commercial transactions. Accordingly, giving or receiving payment (including any other compensation or reward) for organs should be prohibited.” Nothing has changed since then except for the flourishing of an international black market of profit -seeking private practitioners and institutions pandering to “consumer demand”. Considerations of distributive justice and of human dignity are sufficient justification to restrict the liberty of individuals . It is true that all we need is an organ, but there are also moral limits on the means that we may employ for the end of saving our own lives. The value of saving life does not give a sick person a right to an organ from a living other at all costs. If saving lives is such an important value, we should be encouraging altruistic donations and an ethic of solidarity, care and compassion. Suffering Turn Kidney donation creates a life of suffering – medical, economic, social Scheper-Hughes 2005 (Nancy, Professor at UC-Berkeley, “THE LAST COMMODITY: Post-Human Ethics and the Global Traffic in ‘‘Fresh’’ Organs”. Global Assemblages: Technology, Politics, and Ethics as Anthropological Problems. Ed. Aihwa Ong and Stephen Collier. Blackwell Publishing. Malden, MA. pp. 162-3) [nagel] Transplant surgeons have disseminated an untested hypothesis of ‘‘risk-free’’ live donation in the absence of any published, longitudinal studies of the effects of nephrectomy among the urban poor living anywhere in the world. The few available studies of the effects of neprectomy on kidney sellers in India34 and Iran35 are unambiguous. Even under attempts (as in Iran) to regulate and control systems of ‘‘compensated gifting’’ by the Ministry of Health, the outcomes are devastating. Kidney sellers suffer from chronic pain, unemployment, social isolation and stigma, and severe psychological problems. The evidence of strongly negative sentiments – disappointment, anger, resentment, and even seething hatreds for the doctors and the recipients of their organs – reported by 100 paid kidney donors in Iran strongly suggests that kidney selling there represents a serious social pathology. Our research with 22 kidney sellers in Moldova and 20 sellers in the Philippines, which in several cases included diagnostic exams and sonograms, found that kidney sellers face many post-operative complications and medical problems, including hypertension and even subsequent kidney insufficiency, without access to medical care or necessary medications. On returning to their rural villages or urban shantytowns, kidney sellers often find themselves weakened, sick, and often unemployable, because they are unable to sustain the demands of heavy agricultural or construction work, the only labor available to men of their skills and backgrounds. Kidney sellers are most often alienated from their families and coworkers, excommunicated from their churches, and, if single, they are even excluded from marriage. The children of kidney sellers are ridiculed as ‘‘one-kidneys.’’ In my sample of 22 kidney sellers in Moldova, my assistants and I found that not one had seen a doctor or been treated at a medical clinic following their illicit operations in Istanbul and Georgia (Russia). I had to coax the young men to agree to a basic clinical examination and sonogram at the expense of Organs Watch. Some said they were ashamed to appear in a public clinic, as they had tried to keep the sale a secret; others said they were fearful of learning negative results from the tests. All said that if serious medical problems were discovered, they were unable to pay for follow-up treatments or necessary medications. Above all, they said, they feared being labeled as ‘‘weak’’ or ‘‘disabled’’ by employers and coworkers, as well as (for single men) by potential girlfriends and brides. ‘‘No young woman in the village will marry a man with the tell-tale scar of a kidney seller,’’ the father of a village kidney seller said sadly. ‘‘They believe that he will be unable to support a family.’’ Sergei, a married man from Chisenau, revealed that his mother was the only person who knew the reason for the large, saber-like scar on his abdomen. Sergei’s young wife believed that he had been injured in a construction accident while he was away in Turkey. 1NC Ethics Turn Legalizing organ sales creates a violent racial and economic system that collapses ethics into management Scheper-Hughes 2005 (Nancy, Professor at UC-Berkeley, “THE LAST COMMODITY: Post-Human Ethics and the Global Traffic in ‘‘Fresh’’ Organs”. Global Assemblages: Technology, Politics, and Ethics as Anthropological Problems. Ed. Aihwa Ong and Stephen Collier. Blackwell Publishing. Malden, MA. pp. 164) [nagel] In his 1970 classic, The Gift Relationship, Richard Titmuss anticipates many of the dilemmas now raised by the global human organs market. His assessment of the negative social effects of commercialized blood markets in the U.S.A. could also be applied to the global markets in human organs and tissues: The commercialism of blood and donor relationships represses the expression of altruism, erodes the sense of community, lowers scientific standards, limits both personal and professional freedoms, sanctions the making of profits in hospitals and clinical laboratories, legalizes hostility between doctor and patient, subjects critical areas of medicine to the laws of the marketplace, places immense social costs on those least able to bear them—the poor, the sick, and the inept—increases the danger of unethical behavior in various sectors of medical science and practice, and results in situations in which proportionately more and more blood is supplied by the poor, the unskilled and the unemployed, Blacks and other low income groups.36 The goal of this project is frankly adversarial in its attempt to bring social justice concerns to bear on global practices of organs procurement and transplant. This chapter has been an attempt to delineate some of the contradictions inherent in a market-driven solution to the problem of ‘‘scarcity’’ of human organs; as well as an attempt to recapture the original biosociality inherent in the once daring proposal to circulate human organs as a radical act of fraternity; and, finally, to bring a critical medical anthropological sensibility into the current debates on the commodification of the body. Yes Coercion/No Consent No empirics for free consent – all ev goes negative Scheper-Hughes 2007 (Nancy, Vera N. Schuyler Institute Fellow and Professor at Harvard University, “In Defense of the Body from the Queen of Hearts to the Knave of Hearts:”. J Med Ethics. 4/27/2007. DA: 7/31/2014. http://jme.bmj.com/content/33/4/201.full/reply#medethics_el_1538) [nagel] Taylor makes the leap from my discussions of tissues harvesting from the dead to living, voluntary sale of organs. As these cannot be subsumed under the same heading, I have supplied one. I have only one question: What is Taylor evidence for the blanket assertion that "voluntary trades in human organs that take place between consenting adults, untainted by force or fraud, make all parties to them better off". Where are the empirical studies to support his claim? It is, I fear, the philosopher's speculation that in the best of all possible worlds this would or could possibly be the case. To date, however, all empirical studies of living kidney donors indicate varying degrees of coercion, deception, feelings of exploitation, shame, and resentment following arranged kidney sales. In addition to my research are studies conducted by Lawrence Cohen, Sheila and David Rothman, Goyal, Schneiderman and Sehgal and Zargooshi. There are also as yet unpublished doctoral dissertations by medical anthropologists working in Iran, Turkey, Egypt, and the Philippines with similar findings. While selling a kidney means different things and has different medical, social, and psychological consequences, depending on many factors (including access to medical after care, attitudes toward the body, religious and cultural beliefs about gifting, sales, and reciprocity, living and work conditions, and so on) thus far the data show negative consequences. Most kidney sellers report lower wages and decreased income in the first years after the sale. Since the sale of one kidney per family is never enough, the temptation is strong in many areas where kidney selling has almost become routine (as in Manila) for families to pass along the role of kidney seller from father to his sons. Would regulation of black markets in organs solve matters? The only test case we have to draw on is Iran. Iran's government regulated system of kidney sales for transplant surgeries is highly contested within the Iranian medical profession. Internal medical critics of the system say that easy access to the bodies of poor people has prevented the development of a deceased donor system in Iran and has eroded living kidney donation among loving family members. They report that kidney sellers are often treated, like deceased donors, as anonymous suppliers of medical material. There is in Iran today no medical registry of paid donors and no medical accountability, mandatory reporting of mishaps, or seller follow up. Regulation in Iran has not ended the black market, it has simply made it an official policy. Living donors are still recruited by middlemen and payments are negotiated behind the scenes. More affluent transplant patients demand healthier, better-off donors, and are willing to pay an additional price for a 'higher quality' kidney. While regulation is generally preferable to an underground black market, it is contradictory for governments and Ministries of Health to weaken one previously healthy segment of the population in the interest of a sicker and wealthier section. Consent impossible – “autonomy” violates ethical practice and exploits the poor Scheper-Hughes 2005 (Nancy, Professor at UC-Berkeley, “THE LAST COMMODITY: Post-Human Ethics and the Global Traffic in ‘‘Fresh’’ Organs”. Global Assemblages: Technology, Politics, and Ethics as Anthropological Problems. Ed. Aihwa Ong and Stephen Collier. Blackwell Publishing. Malden, MA. pp. 161-2) [nagel] Bioethical arguments about the right to sell an organ or other body part are based on Euro-American notions of contract and individual ‘‘choice.’’ But the social and economic contexts make the ‘‘choice’’ to sell a kidney in an urban slum of Calcutta, or in a Brazilian favela or Philippine shantytown, anything but a “free” and “autonomous” one. Consent is problematic with “the executioner” – whether on death row or at the door of the slum resident – looking over one’s shoulder. Putting a market price on body parts – even a fair one – exploits the desperation of the poor, turning suffering into an opportunity. Asking the law to negotiate a fair price for a live human kidney goes against everything that contract theory stands for. When concepts such as individual agency and autonomy are invoked in defending the ‘‘right’’ to sell an organ, anthropologists might suggest that certain “living” things are not alienable or proper candidates for commodification. And the surgical removal of nonrenewable organs is an act in which medical practitioners, given their ethical standards, should not be asked to participate. The problems multiply when the buyers and sellers are unrelated, because the sellers are likely to be extremely poor and trapped in life-threatening environments where the everyday risks to their survival are legion, including exposure to urban violence, transportation- and work-related accidents, and infectious disease that can compromise their kidney of last resort. And when that spare part fails, kidney sellers often have no access to dialysis, let alone to organ transplant. While poor people in particular cannot “do without” their ‘‘extra’’ organs, even affluent people need that “extra” organ as they age, and when one healthier kidney can compensate for a failing or weaker kidney. No legal consent Adair and Wigmore 2011 (Anya and Stephen, Edinburgh Transplant Unit at the Royal Infirmary of Edinburgh, “Paid Organ Donation: The Case Against”. Ann R Coll Surg Engl. Apr 2011; 93(3): 191–192. doi: 10.1308/147870811X565061a) [nagel] Sadly for the majority of donors, selling a kidney does not result in the significant economic benefit of which they dreamed. Often it is associated with a decline in general health. Many fall back into debt, often compounded by the inability to work following donation due to ill health.8 Supporters of paid donation argue that a person should have the basic right to choose the fate of his or her organs. In the setting of paid donation, informed consent is often of dubious quality, with the risks of surgery often not being properly explained or understood. Furthermore, many individuals are pressured to donate by family members, with the outcome of any ‘balanced discussions’ about wishing to proceed with organ donation predetermined.8 In the UK, our society believes that we have a responsibility to protect individuals from harm. This principal applies even when harm may be self-inflicted. That is why we have motorcycle helmet and seatbelt laws. Why should this statebrokered paternalism be overturned to allow paid donation? Coercion inevitable – market dynamics and destruction of bioethics Caplan 2004 (Arthur, Prof at UPenn, “Transplantation at Any Price?”. American Journal of Transplantation. 4:12. 1933-1934. December. DOI: 10.1111/j.1600-6143.2004.00686.x) [nagel] Matas focuses his ethical analysis of kidney markets on the claim that sellers will be exploited. He rejects this argument noting that the poor are capable of rationality when it comes to sales and the inequity he sees when only those who supply parts among all involved with transplants are asked to go without compensation. On ethical grounds, however, his argument is wanting. The issue is not the rational capacity of the seller, but the likely absence of real alternatives. It is hard to imagine that there will be numerous persons in wealthy Western nations eager to sell a kidney unless their compensation were significant. That has been the experience with markets in egg sales and paid surrogacy in the United States (9,10). Choice is imperiled by high compensation, not because the sellers are rendered irrational by the prospect of money, but for those in need of money certain offers, no matter how degrading, are irresistible (10–12). Those who are in need of money might rationally decide to sell their children, but the sale of babies is not permitted because this is seen as a gross exploitation of the poor if they have no options but to resort to child sales. It is precisely for this reason that severe restrictions are in place on what can be paid to subjects who ‘volunteer’ themselves or their children for medical experiments and toxicity testing (12). The possibility of making a lot of money relative to one's means also creates enormous pressure from third parties on the prospective seller to ‘choose’ to sell. Those in severe debt with no alternatives cannot truly be said to choose to become organ vendors if those to whom they are in debt force them into sales. Choices require options as well as the ability to reason about them. Matas has not, however, grasped the real ethical nettle with his focus on exploitation. The debate about whether exploitation is inevitable in markets in rich or poor countries misses the two most important reasons why allowing the sale of kidneys is unethical. Participation in sales, even in a tightly regulated market, violates the ethics of medicine. And markets will prove next to impossible to implement in North America and Europe on ethical grounds. Medicine has long held that the core ethical norm of the profession is the principle ‘Do no Harm’. Taking organs from living persons is in direct violation of this moral norm. The only way in which it seems morally defensible to remove an organ from someone is on the grounds that the donor chooses to undergo the harm solely to help another and that there is sufficient medical benefit to the recipient. The creation of a market puts medicine in the position of removing body parts from persons solely to abet their interest in securing compensation for themselves. Is this a role that medicine can ethically countenance? What would such a role do to public trust in physicians? The goal of medicine is the alleviation of illness, disability and suffering not finding ways to permit persons to make a profit for themselves by interventions that cause them permanent and significant harm. A key moral problem with markets in kidneys and other body parts is what it does to the ethics of the medical profession. In a market, even a regulated one, doctors use their skills to help people harm themselves for money and solely for money. 1NC Poverty No poverty solvency – compensation is too small Greasley 2012 (Kate, Prof of Law at Oxford University, “A legal market in organs: the problem of exploitation”. J Med Ethics. 2012; 0: 1–6. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2012-100770) [nagel] We disagree with the Ableist and gendered language used. When it comes to the usefulness of research into the kidney trade in countries such as India it is, of course, important to keep in mind a realistic picture of what a regulated UK system would look like. Yet to this end, it should be stressed that the problems of advantage taking which I have underscored in the Indian context are not primarily matters of reliable payment or arbitrary pricing (though for many this is, naturally, a related problem). The main issue is that there is no material improvement to the vendors’ conditions even where full payment is reliably made. Unless, then, what is envisioned in a regulated system involves truly transformative sums of compensation (which clearly it does not), there is no reason to think that this persistent feature would not be replicated. And it is a reasonable assumption to make that anyone desperate enough to sell [their] his kidney is not in a position to invest the proceeds in such a way as to make them, eventually, transformative. In other words, there is nothing in the notion of a well-regulated, fairly priced UK market which casts the common Indian story of the urgent sell to pay off debts which only continue to accrue in a parochial light. Donation locks in poverty and social isolation long term Delmonico et al 2008 (F.L. and D.A. Budiani-Saberi, Prof at Harvard Medical School and Prof at University of Pennsylvania, “Organ Trafficking and Transplant Tourism: A Commentary on the Global Realities”. American Journal of Transplantation. 8:5. pp. 925-929. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/j.1600-6143.2008.02200.x/full) [nagel] CLD = commercial living donors Egypt is one of the few countries that prohibits organ donation from deceased donors. In the absence of an entity to govern allocation or standards for transplants, the market has become the distribution mechanism. Egypt is also one of the countries in which COFS has conducted extensive field research and long-term outreach service programs for victims of the organ trade. In-depth longitudinal interviews conducted by Budiani reveal that 78% of the CLDs (n = 50) reported a deterioration in their health condition. This is likely a result of factors such as insufficient donor medical screening for a donation, pre-existing compromised health conditions of CLD groups and that the majority of employed CLDs reported working in labor-intensive jobs. A kidney sale does not solve the most frequently given reason for being a CLD, 81% spent the money within 5 months of the nephrectomy, mostly to pay off financial debts rather than investing in quality of life enhancements. CLDs are not eager to reveal their identity; 91% expressed social isolation about their donation and 85% were unwilling to be known publicly as an organ vendor. Ninety-four percent regretted their donation (13). The studies in Pakistan and Egypt are consistent with findings in India (14), Iran (15) and the Philippines (16) that revealed deterioration in the health condition of the CLDs. A long-term financial disadvantage is evident following nephrectomy from a compromised ability to generate a prior income level. The common experience also entails a social rejection and regret about their commercial donation. These reports are consistent with the COFS experience in the CLD interviews; a cash payment does not solve the destitution of the vendor. We control uniqueness – legalization net increases poverty and exploitation Greasley 2012 (Kate, Prof of Law at Oxford University, “A legal market in organs: the problem of exploitation”. J Med Ethics. 2012; 0: 1–6. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2012-100770) [nagel] In addition to this, the single purchaser system would do nothing to combat another logical corollary of a free market in organs, this being an added incentive on behalf of the wealthier community to maintain the supply of organs by keeping the conventional source of sellers from improving on their socioeconomic status. Indeed, it was a further finding of Cohen’s study in Chennai that the relatives of a patient who needed a kidney would now ask themselves why they should assume the risks of donating when they could simply go out and buy one. As Rothman puts it, ‘a market in organs stimulates a market in organs’. Health Turn Donation causes massive health decrease (also in TT DA) Goyal et al 2002 (Madhav, and Ravindra L. Mehta, Lawrence J. Schneiderman, and Ashwini R. Sehgal, Department of Internal Medicine, Geisinger Health System, State College, Pa (Dr Goyal); Department of Nephrology, University of California, San Diego (Dr Mehta); Departments of Family and Preventive Medicine and Medicine, University of California, San Diego, School of Medicine (Dr Schneiderman); Division of Nephrology and Center for Health Care Research and Policy, MetroHealth Medical Center, and Departments of Medicine, Biomedical Ethics, and Epidemiology and Biostatistics, Case Western Reserve University, Cleveland, Ohio (Dr Sehgal). “Economic and Health Consequences of Selling a Kidney in India”. Journal of the American Medical Association. 2002; 288(13):1589-1593. doi:10.1001/jama.288.13.1589.) [nagel] Participants rated their health status before and after nephrectomy by using a 5-point Likert scale ranging from excellent to poor (Table 3). Forty participants (13%) reported no decline in their health after nephrectomy, 117 (38%) reported a 1- to 2-point decline, and 147 (48%) reported a 3- to 4-point decline. Of all participants, 50% complained of persistent pain at the nephrectomy site and 33% complained of long-term back pain. Advice for Others Participants were asked what advice they would give someone else with the same reasons they had for selling. Of 264 participants who answered this question, 79% would not recommend selling a kidney, while 21% would. 1NC Exploitation DA Organ selling causes targeted exploitation of the poor Park 2012 (Alice, Senior Contributor to Time and CNN, “Should people be allowed to sell their organs?”. CNN Online. DA: 7/30/2014. http://www.cnn.com/2012/07/03/health/allowed-sell-organstime/) [nagel] Of course, certain body parts are already up for sale. Aside from sperm and plasma, donors can also be paid for their eggs and hair. But by expanding that list, the court's ruling reopens the long-standing ethical debate over the commercialization of human tissues. For now, legally "sellable" human body parts aren't ones that could be used to cure fatal diseases, which prevents a market frenzy. But if the bonemarrow case starts changing that -- and experts say it could -- it might jump-start a dangerous trend in which lowerincome groups were disproportionately targeted or incentivized to give up their marrow and people with rarer blood types demanded more money for their valuable cells. Our ethical responsibility precedes everything – failure to resist exploitation for organs makes life disposable Scheper Hughes 2000 (Nancy, Prof at UC-Berkeley, “The Global Traffic In Human Organs”. Current Anthropology. 41:2. April 2000. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/300123) [nagel] We disagree with the Ableist language used. I will argue that transplant surgery as it is practiced today in many global contexts is a blend of altruism and commerce, of science and magic, of gifting, barter, and theft, of choice and coercion. Transplant surgery has reconceptualized social relations between self and other, between individual and society, and among the “three bodies”—the existential lived body‐self, the social, representational body, and the body political (see Scheper‐Hughes and Lock 1987). Finally, it has redefined real/unreal, seen/unseen, life/death, body/corpse/cadaver, person/nonperson, and rumor/fiction/fact. Throughout these radical transformations, the voice of anthropology has been relatively muted, and the high‐stakes debates have been waged among surgeons, bioethicists, international lawyers, and economists. From time to time anthropologists have intervened to translate or correct the prevailing medical and bioethical discourses on transplant practice as these conflict with alternative understandings of the body and of death. Margaret Lock's (1995, 1996) animated discussions, debates, and difficult collaborations with the moral philosopher Janet Radcliffe Richards (see Richards et al. 1998) and Veena Das's (n.d.) responses to the latter and to Abdullah Daar (Das 1996) are exemplary in this regard. But perhaps what is needed from anthropology is something more akin to Donna Haraway's (1985) radical manifesto for the cyborg bodies and cyborg selves that we have already become. The emergence of strange markets, excess capital, “surplus bodies,” and spare body parts has generated a global body trade which promises select individuals of reasonable economic means living almost anywhere in the world—from the Amazon Basin3 to the deserts of Oman—a miraculous extension of what Giorgio Agamben (1998) refers to as bios—brute or naked life, the elementary form of species life.4 In the face of this late‐modern dilemma— this particular “end of the body”—the task of anthropology is relatively straightforward: to activate our discipline's radical epistemological promise and our commitment to the primacy of the ethical (Scheper‐ Hughes 1994). What follows is an ethnographic and reflexive essay on the transformations of the body and the state under conditions of neoliberal economic globalism. Impact is the erosion of all morality Leyton 2000 (Elliot, Professor of Anthropology, Memorial University of Newfoundland, St John’s “Comments” from “The Global Traffic In Human Organs” by Nancy Scheper-Hughes. Current Anthropology. 41:2. April 2000. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/300123) [nagel] But this erosion of all morality follows most naturally from the assumptions and expectations associated with the utterly unleashed industrial world order. If human beings are both philosophically and economically reduced to mere commodities, then it follows as night follows day that their parts—their eyes, livers, lungs, hearts, kidneys, and so on—also be offered for sale in the trading houses. And, once commodified, their living tissue provides the basis for a new world market that offers the wealthy and the well‐connected an indefinite extension of life, limited only by the abilities of current medical technology—the end of the body indeed, and the double end of death, too, for not only can the rich now live forever (at least in theory) but the diagnosis of death must be pushed farther and farther back into active life if we are to be provided with the juiciest and most vital organs. Black Market Demand for organs drives international black market – government and military ties empirics Scheper-Hughes 2005 (Nancy, Professor at UC-Berkeley, “THE LAST COMMODITY: Post-Human Ethics and the Global Traffic in ‘‘Fresh’’ Organs”. Global Assemblages: Technology, Politics, and Ethics as Anthropological Problems. Ed. Aihwa Ong and Stephen Collier. Blackwell Publishing. Malden, MA. pp. 158-9) [nagel] Israel, for complicated reasons having to do with moral, political, and institutional obstacles to the procurement and distribution of cadaver organs, is a major player in the global market for ‘‘fresh’’ (living donor) organs. The search by Israeli surgeons and patients for living donor organs began in the West Bank and Gaza, and then moved to Turkey, India, and Iraq, and, later to Moldova, Romania, and Russia. When these options closed down, the Israeli market for kidneys moved to Brazil30 and South Africa. Thus, today, one half of all Israelis who have a transplanted kidney purchased that kidney abroad. Caught between a highly educated and medically conscious public and a very low rate of organ donation, the Israeli Ministry of Health has expedited the expansion of transplant tourism by allowing Israeli patients to use their national insurance to pay for transplants conducted elsewhere, even if illegally. The cost of the transplant ‘‘package’’ increased from $120,000 in 1998 to $200,000 in 2001. The cost includes the air travel, bribes to airport and customs officials, ‘‘double operation’’ (kidney extraction and kidney transplant), the rental of operating and recovery rooms, and hotel accommodation for accompanying family members. The donor fee of between $3,000 and $20,000 (depending on the status of the donor) is also included. Well known Israeli businessmen and their associates have formed ‘‘corporations’’ (including the firms of Kobi ( Jacob) Dyan and Ilan Perry) with ties to illicit medical centers and rogue transplant units (public and private) in Turkey, Russia, Moldova, Estonia, Georgia, Romania, South Africa and the U.S.A. The specific sites of the illicit surgeries are normally kept secret from transplant patients until the day of travel, and the locations are continually rotated to maintain a low profile. The surgeries are performed at the dead of night in rented operating rooms. In one scenario, Israeli patients and doctors (a surgeon and a nephrologist) fly to a small town in Turkey, where the kidney sellers sometimes include young Iraqi soldiers or guest workers. In another scenario, the Israeli and Turkish doctors travel in tandem to a third site in eastern Europe, where the organ sellers are unemployed locals or guest workers from elsewhere. In a third scenario, living kidney donors are recruited from the slums and favelas of Recife, Northeast Brazil (by brokers who include a military police officer) and sent by plane to Durban and Johannesburg in South Africa, where they are met by South African brokers, who will match these unfortunates up with Israeli patients arriving from Tel Aviv. In this instance, South African surgeons operate alone, without the presence of Israeli surgeon accomplices. The collaboration of the Israeli government and Ministry of Health in this multimillion dollar business , which is making Israel something of a pariah in the international transplant world, requires some explanation. Between 2001 and 2003, medical insurance programs under Israel’s national health care system (Kupot Holim) funded 319 foreign kidney transplants with living unrelated donors who were paid. According to government tax investigators looking into the illegal trade, each Israeli transplant tourist was paid prior to, or reimbursed following, kidney transplant abroad $120,000 plus an additional $25,000 for pre- and post-op testing, treatment and care of the living donor and the patient. In the absence of a strong culture of organ donation and under the pressure of angry transplant candidates, each person transplanted abroad is one less demanding and angry client with which to contend. More troubling, however, is the support and involvement of the Ministry of Defense in the illicit transplant tourism. Israeli patients who traveled on the transplant junkets to Turkey and eastern Europe recorded the presence of military officers accompanying their flights. Incompetence, corruption, and line-blurring Mendoza 2010 (Roger, PhD and Specialist in welfare economics, “Kidney black markets and legal transplants: Are they opposite sides of the same coin?”. Health Policy. 94 (2010). pp. 263) [nagel] Inefficient monitoring due to resource constraints and lack of coordination remains a challenge for government agencies [40], especially in developing countries like the Philippines. Credibility issues appear to be part of this ineffectiveness. To illustrate, not long after the 2008 Revised National Policy was enacted, a Department of Health’s undisclosed exemption of 8 Israelis from the foreigners’ ban “because of humanitarian considerations” provoked public indignation [49]. Inefficient compliance monitoring renders the kidney commerce tolerable at minimum, emboldens its participants and subverts policy intent. 4.3. Duplicate participants and functions The dividing line between the underground and legal transplant systems becomes razor-thin when several participants (matching agencies, foundations, hospitals, doctors and law-enforcers) in one system consciously or unconsciously perform the same roles and functions in the other with relative ease. “Non-directed” kidney donations to governmentapproved foundations, for one, help unscrupulous brokers and criminal syndicates to circumvent the prohibition against unrelated donations. The Philippine Society of Nephrology also discovered that recipients pay huge sums for new kidneys, but most of them go to brokers, including some licensed doctors and medical facilities, who locate many poor donors for the “non-directed” program [10,50]. Corruption within government offices, hospitals, and law-enforcement agencies also need to be addressed. Effective law enforcement helps connect legislation to the regulation of economic behavior. Gratuities, deep markets, lack of broker penalties Mendoza 2010 (Roger, PhD and Specialist in welfare economics, “Kidney black markets and legal transplants: Are they opposite sides of the same coin?”. Health Policy. 94 (2010). pp. 263) [nagel] LNRD = Live Non-Related Donor While regulatory measures may prohibit kidney selling, self-contradictory provisions and policy loopholes create reverse incentives (to trade illicitly). Both National Policy and Revised National Policy allow “gratuities,” which could stimulate kidney selling. A foreigners’ cap or ban, as the Secretary of Health acknowledged, may not suppress organized kidney crimes and could have the opposite effect, as syndicates are forced to go deeper in their covert operations [10]. Crafting legislation or public policy cannot be restricted to textual provision but need to address opportunities (demonstration effects) that may arise to subvert its own intent. 4.5. Relative insulation of commodity brokerage A prevailing issue concerns the legal burden disproportionately placed on poor and vulnerable donors in their role as kidney vendors. Conversely, brokers who stand to profit the most are relatively shielded from a law enforcement standpoint in the absence of broker-specific penalties. Without brokers, it is doubtful if most LNRDs will find kidney buyers, as our survey has indicated. Without incentives (e.g., cash rewards) to report these brokers and their vast patron–client network, and swift government action, the underground kidney trade will continue to flourish, entrench market injustices based on ability-to-pay and dent reform efforts. Grey areas, low broker costs, inflexible enforcement Mendoza 2010 (Roger, PhD and Specialist in welfare economics, “Kidney black markets and legal transplants: Are they opposite sides of the same coin?”. Health Policy. 94 (2010). pp. 263) [nagel] Unlike most developed countries, the Philippines permits kidney donations to emotionally related as well as unspecified recipients out of consideration for socio-cultural values (e.g., extended family, altruism). How to distinguish genuine emotional ties from those that are brokered overnight (e.g., short-term marriages to obtain a Filipino spouse’s kidney have reportedly increased since the foreign recipients total ban took effect [51,52]), or how to address genuine but paid kidney donations to related recipients, underline grey areas in legal compliance that may require a case-by-case approach. They arise in many developing countries where reward-based, patron–client ties can be cemented within a short period of time and are crucial to individual goal achievement. 4.7. Minimal transaction costs in brokerage trading Low transaction costs to kidney buyers and sellers owe to the ease of information exchange (e.g., extended family ties, word of mouth), speed of (brokered) transplant arrangements, broker price-fixing, nephrectomy in top-quality private and state-run hospitals, and direct involvement by politicians and law-enforcers. Despite government pronouncements to the contrary, they help make the Philippines a favored destination for medical/ transplant tourism [53]. Compliance monitoring is insufficient and costly without the benefit of effective law enforcement. That, in turn, demands creative policing and prosecution (e.g., with adequate and objective media coverage) to cope with everchanging trade environments (e.g., online and sham marriages) and rules (e.g., contracting by scouts). Governments intentionally overlook criminal organ harvesting – this practice corrupts the medical profession and allows atrocities to be praised as heroic acts of altruism Scheper-Hughes 2003 (Nancy, Prof at UC-Berkeley, “Rotten trade: millennial capitalism, human values and global justice in organs trafficking” trans. by ProQuest from Spanish, Journal of Human Rights. June, Vol 2:2) [nagel] Anyway, how is a national government able to put price to a healthy part of the body of a human being without the democratic essential commitment and the ethical principles that guarantee the equivalent value of all the human lives? Some system national regulator would have to participate in the global black markets, wece the value of the human organs with arrangement to the consumer's prejudices, until the point that at the moment in the market of kidneys an Indian kidney is sold for only 1.000 dollars, a Philippine kidney 1.300, a kidney moldavo or Romanian reaches those 2.700, while a Turkish salesperson can be won 10.000 and an urban Peruvian can perceive until 30.000. The circulation of kidneys already transcends the national frontiers and the international markets can coexist and to compete aggressively with any national regulated system. Putting a market price - even equal - to the parts of the body, you exploits the poor person's desperation, translating their suffering in an opportunity. Also, the surgical transplanting of non-renewable organs is an act in the one that the medical technicians, because of its ethical referents, they should not be invited to participate. The surgeons whose fundamental responsibility is to propitiate care, they should not plead for the paid car-mutilation, even with an eye toward saving lives. The bio-ethical arguments on the right to sell an organ or another part of the body are based on euro-American notions on the contract and the individual "election." This believes the appearance of an ethical election - for example, the right to buy a kidney – is in context intrinsically not ethical. The social and economic contexts make that the "election" of selling a kidney in a suburb of Calcutta or in a Brazilian favela or in the Philippine shanties it is all less "free" and "autonomous" one. The idea of the consent is the ideology of "the executioner" - either in the hall of the death or to the door of the shanty - that looks above the shoulder to the salesperson that doesn't have another option that to sell an organ. I insist: to even being this equal - it exploits put a market price to the parts of the body the desperation of the poor ones and he/she makes of their suffering an opportunity. To interpellate to the law to negotiate a fair price for the kidney of an alive human goes against all that the theory of the contract sustains. When concepts like those of individual agency and autonomy are invoked to defend the right to sell an organ, the anthropologists should suggest that certain "alive" things are not alienable neither convenient candidates for mercantilism. And the surgical transplanting of non renewable organs is an act in the one that the doctors, because of their ethical approaches, they should not be invited to participate. Organized Crime Organ sales expands the black market – funds organized crime Scheper-Hughes 1998 (Nancy, Prof at UC-Berkeley, “The New Cannibalism”. New Internationalist. .300 (Apr. 1998): p14-17) [nagel] We disagree with the Ableist language used. But nowhere more openly and flagrantly than in India has the `shortage' encouraged a sale of kidneys. There a veritable organs bazaar is operated out of private clinics, especially in Bombay and Madras. Until a new law last year prohibited the sale of living donor organs, patients from the Gulf States - Kuwait, Saudi Arabia, Oman and the United Arab Emirates - travelled to India to purchase a kidney. Now that market has been driven underground. Recent reports by human-rights activists, journalists and medical anthropologists indicate that the international kidney trade has declined but left in its wake an even larger underground market controlled and organized by cash-rich crime gangs expanding out from the heroin trade into the organs trade. In some cases they have the backing of local political leaders. Organ `donors' are recruited by `agents' to sell a spare organ in order to cancel crippling debts, to pay for a necessary operation, or to cover large family expenses. And where there is an illegal market there are likely to be other criminal practices as well. Professor Veena Das of the University of New Delhi has come across stories, from reliable sources, of `organ theft'. She told the story of a young woman with stomach pains who went to a small clinic where she was told by the doctor: `It looks like you have a bladder stone and we had better remove it.' But in fact the doctor used it as a pretext to operate and remove a kidney which he had contracted to deliver to an intermediary for an undisclosed third party. Fetish Organ sales construct a fetishized desire around “freshness” that creates an increasing underground demand Scheper-Hughes 2002 (Nancy, Prof at UC-Berkeley, “The Ends of the Body: Commodity Fetishism and the Global Traffic in Organs”. SAIS Review. 22:1. (Winter-Spring 2002), pp. 72) [nagel] The idea of the organ as fetish conjures up the magical energy that is invested in the “fresh” organ purchased from a living donor. Averham, a 71 year old kidney buyer who flew from Jerusalem to Georgia in Eastern Europe where he purchased a kidney from a young peasant, explained to me why he would never tolerate a cadaveric kidney: “That kidney is practically dead. It was probably pinned down under the wheels of a car for several hours and then it was put on ice for another several hours. Then you expect it to go right back to work for me? It’s really disgusting to think about putting that dead man’s organ inside you. So I chose a better way. I was able to see my donor [in a small town in Eastern Europe]. He was young, strong, healthy. Just what I was hoping for.” As Averham’s preferences show, cadaver organs are no longer the primary organs of desire. In the last decade, there has been a dramatic shift worldwide toward the procurement and use of organs from living donors who can give one kidney, half a liver, or the lobe of one lung. The move to living organ donation is seen as the only solution to the chronic scarcity of organs for transplant and a means to increase the viability and longevity of transplanted organs. In the United Sates live donor kidney transplants account for 50 percent of all transplants, and live donor liver transplants for 10 percent. 12 Similarly, in Israel, an experimental program of live, unrelated kidney donation was established to screen and select purely “altruistic” donors. But the head of the screening committee stated that: “Of the 40-some applications we reviewed and approved, it is possible that two were truly altruistic. All the others were paid. ” Scarcity The rhetoric of organ scarcity artificially constructs a fake need to drive medical racism and exploitation – this ethical utilitarianism creates garbage populations for destruction Scheper-Hughes 2002 (Nancy, Prof at UC-Berkeley, “The Ends of the Body: Commodity Fetishism and the Global Traffic in Organs”. SAIS Review. 22:1. (Winter-Spring 2002), pp. 67-8) [nagel] Sadly, however, the discourse on scarcity conceals the actual existence of excess and wasted organs that end up in hospital dumpsters on a daily basis throughout those parts of the world where the necessary infrastructure to use them is lacking. Indeed, the ill will and competitiveness of some hospital workers and medical professionals also contributes to the production of organ “wastage.” For example, transplant coordinators in public hospitals in many developing countries are often told to dispose of usable organs rather than allow the competition to “get their hands on them.” The very idea of organ “scarcity” is what Ivan Illich would call an artificially created need, invented by transplant technicians and dangled before the eyes of an ever-expanding sick, aging, and dying population. The resulting artificially created organs scarcity is “misrecognized” as a natural medical phenomenon. 4 In this environment of “survivalist” utilitarian pragmatics, the ethics of transplantation is modeled after classical “lifeboat” ethics. 5 With ethical presumptions of scarcity, there appears to be clear choices to be made, namely who gets into the lifeboat (“getting on the waiting list”); who will be shoved off the boat when it gets overcrowded (getting triaged while on the waiting list); and who will, in the end, be “eaten” so that others may live (race and class disparities in organs procurement and distribution practices). A new kind of organ trade has emerged out of the global economy: transplant tourism. Along with it, a group of self-defined transplant outlaws — doctors, patients, brokers, and kidney sellers — has emerged. They short-circuit national waiting lists and make a mockery of national and international codes of ethics prohibiting the sale of organs, from either living or dead donors. The key actors are a new class of entrepreneurial organs brokers, who take advantage of questionable organs scarcity panics and the desperation of both the organs buyers and the organs sellers. The sellers are recruited from populations that are suffering from economic transitions. These include displaced rural populations, guest workers, refugees, and young soldiers. Eurocentrism Organ sales promote a privileged and Western ideology that maintains poverty and violence – regulation inevitably fails and expands corrupt market practices Scheper-Hughes 2002 (Nancy, Prof at UC-Berkeley, “The Ends of the Body: Commodity Fetishism and the Global Traffic in Organs”. SAIS Review. 22:1. (Winter-Spring 2002), pp. 77-79) [nagel] In the developing world, poor people cannot really “do without” their “extra” organs. Transplant surgeons have disseminated an untested hypothesis of “risk-free” live donation in the absence of any published, longitudinal studies of the effects of organ removal on the poor. Organs Watch has found that living kidney donors from shantytowns, inner cities, or prisons face extraordinary threats to their health and personal security through violence, accidents, and infectious disease that can all too readily compromise their remaining kidney. As the use of live kidney donors has moved from the industrialized West, where it takes place among kin and under highly privileged circumstances, to areas of high risk in the developing world, transplant surgeons have become complicit in the needless suffering of a hidden population. In all these transactions, the body, as we know it, is radically transformed. The integration of the body and its parts as naturally given is exchanged for a divisible body in which individual organs and tissues can be detached, isolated, and sold. This juncture points to the demise of classical humanism and holism and to the rise of what Lawrence Cohen refers to as “an ethics of parts”— part histories, part truths, and now, it seems, divisible bodies in which detached organs emerge as market commodities, as fetishized objects of desire and consumption. Bioethical arguments about the right to sell an organ or other body part are based on Western notions of contract and individual “choice.” But the social and economic contexts that make the “choice” to sell a kidney in an urban slum of Calcutta, a Brazilian favela, or a Filippine shantytown is anything but a “free” and “autonomous” one. The idea of consent is problematic when one has no other option but to sell an organ. Putting a market price on body parts — even a fair one — exploits the desperation of the poor, turning their suffering into an opportunity. Asking the law to negotiate a fair price for a live human kidney goes against everything that contract theory stands for. When concepts like individual agency and autonomy are invoked in defending the “right” to sell an organ, anthropologists might suggest that certain “living” things are not alienable or proper candidates for commodification. And the surgical removal of non-renewable organs is an act in which medical practitioners, given their ethical standards, should not be asked to participate. The argument for regulation is out of touch with the social and medical realities operating in many parts of the world but especially in developing nations. The medical institutions created to “ monitor ” organs harvesting and distribution are often dysfunctional, corrupt, or compromised by the power of organs markets and the impunity of the organs brokers and of outlaw surgeons willing to violate the first premise of classical medical bioethics: above all, do no harm. Amidst the tension between organ-givers and organ-recipients, between doctors and patients, between North and South, between individuals and the state, between the illegal and the “merely” unethical, clarity is needed about whose values and whose notions of the body and embodiment are being represented. In fact, the values of bodily integrity and dignity are more widespread in the poorer parts of the world than they are in the more affluent and more secular parts. The values of bodily integrity and dignity lie behind “First Peoples” demands for the repatriation and reburial of human remains warehoused in museum archives. They lie behind the demands of the wretchedly poor for dignified death and burial. 20 And they certainly lie behind rumors of organ theft and popular resistance to presumed consent laws.