Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought Jeffery Nicholas June 1, 2012 DRAFT (Please do not cite without author approval) ... the whole reason for the existence of civil authorities is the realization of the common good.... Peace on Earth, #54 In The Person and The Common Good, Jacques Maritain argues that the individual is prior to the communityi, or, at least, that the individual and the 1 Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 2 community are “correlative and equally fundamental.”ii He bases his argument on a passage from St. Thomas’ Summa. At ST I-II Q21 a.4 ad.3, Thomas writes that “man is not ordained to the body politic according to all that he is and has.” Pope Benedict XVI uses this same phrase from Thomas in Caritas in Veritate. I argued elsewhere, though, that Benedict did not mean, nor did Thomas, that the individual was prior to the community.iii In fact, Maritain misunderstood Thomas here. For Thomas, the human being is ordered to a higher end than the common good of political society. This higher end, God, however, comprises, not an individual, but a common good of the universe. Given that conclusion, several problems arise for Catholic social teaching and the philosophy of Catholic social justice. One can begin with the simple question, how do the rest of the papal social encyclicals define the common good? What is the relationship of the individual to the community given this notion of the common good? If I reject Maritain’s reading of Thomas Aquinas do I not undo his work to protect the autonomy of the individual and, at the same time, undermine much of Catholic social teaching? How does one avoid a hegemonizing politics if politics is centered around a conception of the common good. Finally, how can we realize a politics of the common good in the modern world? As I will show, the social encyclicals define the temporal common good of the political order. This definition mirrors that of Jacques Maritain and of John Finnis. Further, the papal documents consistently seek a balance between the Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 3 good of the individual with the good of the community. In Benedict’s words, Catholic social justice seeks a polis in which members can pursue their good consistent with the good of others. This pursuit entails first and foremost the protection of individual rights. This notion of the common good, however, proves inadequate. It proves inadequate because, first, it cannot identify what it is for human beings to flourish in society – which is necessary for reaching the common good, and, second, because it cannot in the end ground the rights that papal documents defend. I propose a fuller concept of the common good basing my understanding off of the work of Alasdair MacIntyre. I do so, however, recognizing that MacIntyre has his own critics: critics like Iris Marion Young who are wary of any substantive conception of the common good and promote, in opposition to the polis of MacIntyre or even Benedict XVI, a conception of citylife. I shall conclude my discussion by providing an example of the common good – practical reason – which is necessary for the kind of city life Young desires. Reason is a common good, not only in the sense of a social condition necessary for communal life, but also as a good that is only realizable as a social good choice-worthy in-itself. I originally developed these thoughts in an attempt to engage the feminist critique of MacIntyre. I presented a paper at the American Maritain Association in 2003 arguing for a conception of rights based on the natural law of Maritain. Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 4 Later, I developed a critical conception of natural law in opposition to the new natural law of Finnis at the 2008 ISME conference. I put these ideas aside because I knew I was missing something in the analysis. Only when I came to engage Benedict XVI’s Caritas in Veritate did I recognize that it was a clearer conception of the common good that was missing in these debates. In the meantime, Alasdair MacIntyre has turned his attention to Maritain. He has shared some of his thoughts with myself and others in an unpublished paper, “Common Goods, Modern States, Rights, and Maritain.” Not surprisingly, our thoughts run parallel in several cases, though, I think, in the end our approaches and conclusions prove sufficiently distinct to merit separate treatments. I thank him for giving me permission to refer to his paper here. The Common Good in the Papal Documents Pope Leo XIII, the progenitor of modern Catholic social teaching, has little to say about the common good, and what he does say can prove inimical to modern beliefs about equality and autonomy. Thus, in paragraph 34 of Rerum Novarum, he writes “But although all citizens, without exception, can and ought to contribute to that common good in which individuals share so advantageously to themselves, yet it should not be supposed that all can contribute in the like way and to the same extent.” In conjunction with this understanding that all share in the advantages of the common good, Leo contends that some hold pride Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 5 of place in the society because they devote themselves to the commonwealth. He immediately makes clearer his position in paragraph 35 when he writes that “We have said that the State must not absorb the individual or the family.” In general, Leo’s contribution to Catholic social justice consists in bringing that 2000 year-old tradition in dialogue with the “new things” of the modern world, most notably, classical liberalism and capitalism. Between Rerum Novarum and the next social encyclical, Quadragesimo Anno lay 40 years. In 1931’s Quadragesimo Anno, Pius XI says of the common good that “The public institutions themselves, of peoples, moreover, ought to make all human society conform to the needs of the common good; that is, to the norm of social justice” (#110). It took another 30 years till Mater et Magistra in which we receive a definition of the common good: “It is necessary that public authorities have a correct understanding of the common good. This embraces the sum total of those conditions of social living, whereby men are enabled more fully and more readily to achieve their own perfection” (MM, #65). John XXIII modifies the definition in paragraph #74: “The common good embraces the sum total of all those conditions of social life which enable individuals, families, and organizations to achieve complete and effective fulfillment” (MM, #74). This definition can be taken as the standard definition of the common good in Catholic social doctrine. It is restated in Gaudium et Spes #26, Pacem in Terris #58, Octogesima Adveniens #46, and finally in the Compendium of the Social Doctrine of the Church #164. Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought John XXIII, then, ties the common good as a set of social conditions to the development of the human person. In Mater et Magistra, John XXIII holds that those invested with care for the political must “must take account of all those social conditions which favor the full development of human personality” (#65). This notion of the full development of human personality, though not noted, refers back to Maritain’s understanding of the goal of natural law. In Pacem in Terris, he insists that “all members of the state are entitled to share” in this common. John XXIII elucidates what he means by saying that the political leaders must care for the common good: “On the contrary, it must do all in its power to promote the production of a sufficient supply of material goods, "the use of which is necessary for the practice of virtue" (MM #20). It has also the duty to protect the rights of all its people, and particularly of its weaker members, the workers, women and children. It can never be right for the State to shirk its obligation of working actively for the betterment of the condition of the workingman” (#20). Thus, with the first definition of the common good, the papal documents link that definition with the defense of the “rights of all its people.”iv John XXIII reiterates this understanding of the relationship between the common good and rights in Pacem in Terris at #s 56 and 63: “it is also demanded by the common good that civil authorities should make earnest efforts to bring about a situation in which individual citizens can easily exercise their rights and fulfill their duties as well.” 6 Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 7 For Catholic social thought, the common good does not comprise a sum of individual goods. “It remains ‘common’ because it is indivisible and because only together is it possible to attain it, increase it, and safeguard its effectiveness, with regard also to the future” (Compendium #164). This understanding of the common good, then, relies on an understanding of the human being as social. It also remains consistent with Thomas’ contention that God is a common good to all human beings – God is indivisible and we cannot attain God without cooperating with and cooperation from others. Pope Benedict XVI ties these ideas together more clearly. “To take a stand for the common good is on the one hand to be solicitous for, and on the other hand to avail oneself of, that complex of institutions that give structure to the life of society, juridically, civilly, politically, and culturally, making it the polis, or ‘city.’” This stand defines “the institutional path – we might also call it the political path” which will contribute “to the building of the universal City of God, which is the goal of the history of the human family” (CIV 35). The common good comprises a complex of institutions that structure the life of society. In taking a stand, Benedict claims that individuals will be taking an institutional path and identifies the institutional path as the political path. I will return to this understanding of the polis, of politics, and of institutions throughout the rest of this essay. First, however, I want to look at the common good from a more philosophical vantage point. Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 8 Philosophical Accounts of the Common Good Jacques Maritain Because of his importance to the general debate about the relationship between the individual and society and because of his influence on Catholic social thought in the 20th century, Jacques Maritain provides an interesting person with whom to begin a discussion of the philosophy of the common good. This discussion will allow me, further, to contrast the understanding of the common good in John Finnis and Alasdair MacIntyre. In the end, I shall argue that we must turn to MacIntyre’s Thomistic-Aristotelian understanding of the common good to better underwrite Catholic social justice. Maritain grounds his view of rights in Thomas Aquinas’ Natural Law Theory. What is central in this Natural Law Theory, for Maritain, is the notion of the person that lies behind it. While recognizing the individuality of the person, Maritain rightly claims that the person becomes such only within a community. Indeed, as an individual, rights do not pertain to “man;” they pertain to the person.v The human person is a human being; the human being is “more whole than a part and more independent than servile.”vi As such, the person possesses an incomparable worth. Nothing but God is more important than the individual person. Yet, the person is a social animal. It is social because it seeks to Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 9 communicate to others its nature and to reach out to others in givingness and love.vii The society, then, is a whole consisting of wholes -- for each person is a whole, but society itself is a whole – not fragmented parts.viii The ground for the conception of rights in Maritain rests on the notion of incommensurable worth of the person. Since society consists in these incommensurable wholes, the aim of society lies in the common good -- the good of each one. The common good of society is neither a mere collection of private goods, nor the good proper to a whole... It is the good human life of the multitude, of a multitude of persons, the good life of totalities at once carnal and spiritual.... The common good of society is their communion in the good life; it is therefore common to the whole and to the parts...ix The political task of this common good is to procure the common good of the multitude, in such a manner that each concrete person, not only in a privileged class, but throughout the whole mass, may truly reach that measure of independence which is proper to civilized life and which is insured alike by the economic guarantees of work and property, political Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 10 rights, civil virtues, and the cultivation of the mind.x Significantly, Maritain focuses on the demands for the concrete person. This person, while perhaps a member of this or that class, is unique as a concrete person and cannot be reduced to class membership or to humanity at all. So each concrete person must share in the common good in a concrete and unique way. Persons are concrete, not abstract, in their familial, social, and historical situation. The good, moreover, of each concrete individual is assured by, among other things, rights. The human person possesses rights because of the very fact that it is a person, a whole, master of itself and of its acts, and which consequently is not merely a means to an end, but an end, an end which must be treated as such. The dignity of the human person? This expression means nothing if it does not signify that by virtue of natural law, the human person has the right to be respected, is the subject of rights, possesses rights.xi The person is a whole, but only a whole because it is in society. The dignity of the person means that, as a whole in a community, that whole has rights – particularly rights to be respected. Each person has a right to the “minimal conditions” for a truly human life.xii These minimal conditions include Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 11 not only “a collection of public commodities and services” like “roads, ports, and schools,” but also “sound fiscal condition of the state and its military power, the ody of just laws, good customs, and wise institutions,” the “heritage of its great historical remembrances” Above these items, the common good also includes “the whole sum itself of these, a sum which is quite different from a imple collection of juxtaposed units” (PCG 51). As an example, Maritain mentions that, for Aritotle, “6” is not the same thing as “3 + 3.” These rights derive from Natural Law. Natural law, in its simplest statement, is the belief that, through reason, human beings can discover on the basis of their very human nature an order or disposition to the necessary ends of the human being -- that is, to become more human.xiii Natural law, then, is geared toward the fulfillment of the human being and it recognizes that said fulfillment rests, in part, on the rights of the human person -- not as distinct from society but a whole within and because of society. John Finnis In contrast to Maritain, John Finnis avoids discussion of human nature. Rather, he begins where Maritain ends: a set of individual goods as a foundation for his natural law theory. His theory “defines the good in such a way that the common good is nothing other and nothing more than one aspect of the set of fundamental human goods.”xiv Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 12 In Natural Law and Natural Rights Finnis avoids giving an account of human nature. He asserts that, in Thomas, first principles of natural law are “not inferred from metaphysical propositions about human nature, or about the nature of good and evil, or about the ‘function of the human being.’” xv This position opposes that of Maritain, and, I would say, of any true reading of Thomas. Notice, however, that Finnis arrives at a definition of the common good that mirrors that of Maritain. Finnis defines the notion of common good as “a set of conditions which enables members of a community to attain for themselves reasonable objectives, or to realize reasonably for themselves the value(s) for the sake of which they have reason to collaborate with each other (positively and/or negatively) in a community.”xvi This definitions comprises an abstract account of the common good as a set of conditions that help people realize their objectives or the values which might make them collaborate. If Maritain states that the common good is the communion in the good life, we can see a difference only of degree from Finnis; “collaborate with each other in a community.” Further, it is difficult to tell at this abstract level whether Maritain and Finnis disagree about whether the sum of the goods is greater than their parts. More importantly for my discussion, nothing really distinguishes the discussion of the common good in Maritain or Finnis from the discussion of the common good in the papal encyclicals. All three insist on a set of conditions that allow individuals to achieve their perfection. Finnis might be given credit, in Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 13 fact, for spelling out this perfection as “attaining for themselves reasonable objectives.” Catholic social doctrine might add to this that the primary reasonable objective is union with God. As pronouncements on the common good of political society, however, the distinctions fade to nothingness. I want to suggest that reading the notion of the common good in this minimalist way leads to problems. In fact, it cannot support the “polis” which Benedict calls for in Caritas in Veritate. MacIntyre’s Critique of Maritain and Finnis From MacIntyre’s Thomistic-Aristotelian perspective, two problems present themselves with the Maritain-Finnis reading of the common good in natural law. First, both attempt to define the worth of the individual prior to the common good and, second, the account of the common good remains too abstract. MacIntyre focuses on the way in which modernity rejects natural law. Disagreement over fundamental values characterizes advanced modernity. For MacIntyre, this characteristic of advanced modernity deprives natural law of two of its central features. “What the natural law was held to provide was a shared and public standard,” appeal to which could justify positive law, and that natural law “appeals to the judgment of plain persons and not to those of professional specialists.”xvii In advanced modernity, one can neither appeal to Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 14 shared and public standards nor to one’s own judgment when it comes to law. Such a failure in modernity undermines the subversive power of natural law in opposing oppressive and dominating systems. If natural law is to be saved, then, according to MacIntyre, it must do two things. First, it must explain why natural law can no longer secure widespread assent and second identify the grounds for assent to the precepts of natural law which plain persons meet.xviii MacIntyre notes, then, that Finnis has attempted to explain why natural law no longer secures widespread assent. He fails, however, to provide an adequate notion of the common good. Finnis appeals to individual goods as a foundation for his natural law theory rather than to a conception of human nature. In gutting the notion of common good of any appeal to human nature, Finnis undermines the ability of natural law to explain why it might be rejected under certain conditions. The Aristotelian-Thomist system has within it, according to MacIntyre, a theory of moral and legal error. MacIntyre returns us to Maritain’s discussion of natural law to find out how to explain the failure of natural law in advanced modernity. Maritain’s Thomist account of natural law includes two key features. First, the precepts of natural law comprise those which a plain person obeys when functioning normally. That is, plain persons already obey the precepts of natural law because just those precepts lead to human development, or as stated above, the expansion of human personality. Secondly, the Aristotelian-Thomistic Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought account of natural law views people as essentially social. 15 We develop our human personality “through being bound to others through a variety of familial, social, and political relationships expressed in joint activity aimed at achieving our common good.”xix Thus, “the common good is that toward which we are inclined when we are functioning normally and developing as we should be.”xx That is, the common good consists in the human inclination to develop to be more and more fully human. If the theory of natural law fails to provide an account of human nature, however, the common good cannot be achieved. Again, the subversive power of natural law flounders. For MacIntyre, “Maritain errs in supposing that we can give any account, let alone a Thomistic account, of the nature and worth of human individuals prior to and independently of a characterization of their relationships to common goods.”xxi Maritain has reason for this error of course. He misunderstands Thomas’ position concerning how the human person is ordered to society. Where Thomas asserted that human beings are ordered to a good beyond political society, Maritain understood him to mean that individual human beings are metaphysically prior to society. Finnis’ New Natural Law Theory is characteristic of theories in advanced modernity that fail from their own shortcomings. The failure of advanced modernity lies in a misunderstanding of human nature. Just so long as that misunderstanding reigns, so long does a theory of natural law become impossible to defend. Thus, advanced modernity 16 Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought impairs, not only the subversive aspect of natural law as social criticism, but, for Macintyre, the recognition plain persons have of the natural law within them. Maritain’s discussion of the common good, further, remains at an abstract level. The definitions of the common good in the papal encyclicals also remain at an abstract level. MacIntyre rightly asks, how can plain persons “translate those generalities into concrete and particular terms?” (Common Goods, pg. 10). Such persons must, first and foremost, identify a set of agreements on the “rank ordering of goods.” This ordering of goods must further include an agreement on right methods for pursing and ordering those goods. These agreements further entail a common understanding of law and justice “for it is only through relationships governed by the precepts of natural law and informed by justice that common goods can be achieved” (Common Goods pg. 11). Consider MacIntyre’s description of oppression: “What is always oppressive is any form of social relationship that denies to those who participate in it the possibility of the kind of learning from each other about the nature of their common good that can issue in socially transformative action.”xxii MacIntyre links natural law to the common good. For MacIntyre, we understand the common good, first, as a concept that applies across a variety of associations and practices (PPCG 239, cnf. Common Goods, pg 5). Families, for instance, have one kind of common good, and workplaces have another, and political societies have a third. From an Aristotelian perspective, of course, politics constitutes the highest science 17 Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought because politics orders the common goods of all the other associations in the polis. From a Catholic social justice perspective, theology takes the place of the highest science because God is the common good of all people and politics organizes the common good of human beings on earth. The common good of many of these associations, for MacIntyre, including that of the political association proves prior to the good of the individual. Why? These goods are “in key part constituted by cooperative activity and shared understanding of their significance” (240). Engaging in the associations and practices, individuals raise two questions: first, what place should the goods of this practice/association have in my life, and, second, what place should these goods have in our common life? In asking these questions, so MacIntyre argues, the individuals in community must recognize that the achievement of their own good occurs only in achieving the shared goods of the practices in the community and of the community as a whole (240-1). The common good, then, proves prior just because I cannot articulate my good without reference to it. This discussion of the common good constitutes the practice of politics. Politics involves the ordering of the practices within a community. Thus, members of the community must come to some agreement about what that ordering is. Coming to the agreement is as much a part of the common good as is the ordering that the members of the community arrive at. At the level of politics, persons determine the right allocation of resources within the community to support the pursuit of the common good of the community. “So to Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 18 have a care for the common good of family and household or of political society is to have a care for both a just ordering of those institutions, in which each individual receives her or his due, and for the justice of transactions between individuals and between individuals and institutions” (Pg2). This fact entails that politics of the common good is always politics of the local community (Common Goods pg. 10). Education is essential in this politics of the common good. People ignorant of the history of the practices and community will be excluded by that very ignorance from debates in the common good. For MacIntyre, such education includes a knowledge of history, geography, social structure, and political economy. Thus, MacIntyre claims that “our primary shared and common good is found in that activity of communal learning through which we together become able to order goods both in our individual lives and in the political society” (PPCG 243). Problems of the Common Good and Polis In contrast to Maritain and Finnis, MacIntyre comes to the conclusion that we need a politics of the common good pursued within a polis. Yet, his discussion of the common good and of the polis presents two problems. On the one hand, MacIntyre’s understanding of the polis and the common good seems to contrast with that of, for instance, Benedict XVI as quoted above. On the Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 19 other, MacIntyre’s defense of a polis and of the common good seems to leave him open to a charge that both Maritain and Finnis seem to escape viz., that the common good can be hegemonizing. Iris Marion Young is perhaps the most articulate critic of the idea of community in MacIntyre’s politics.xxiii She agrees with the critique of classical liberalism for its atomistic conception of the human person (Young, 228). However, Young argues that MacIntyre’s politics cannot defeat two challenges. First, she holds that the idea of community within a politics of the common good hegemonizes. Second, Young points to the lack of a theory within MacIntyre’s politics that addresses power relations between communities. I believe that Kelvin Knight has sufficiently put to rest the idea that MacIntyre’s politics cannot address power relations between communities. However, more can be said to defend MacIntyre’s notion of community. Young challenges MacIntyre for his ideal of community. This ideal, she thinks, tends to hegemonize and overlook differences. “She believes that small face-to-face communities may entail too much social pressure to conform to a single standard, and the idea of a global community may require too much abstraction and the loss of individual and unique strengths.”xxiv Other feminists, including Seyla Benhabib and Nicola Lacey and ElizabethFraser, have also voiced to this criticism.xxv For Young, the debate between liberalism and communitarianism often ended up in false dichotomies. Community appears opposite individualism, the Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 20 separated self opposite the shared self, and the private opposite the public. Both liberalism and communitarianism rest on a logic of identity which tries to deny difference. “Liberal individualism denies difference by positing a self as a solid, self-sufficient unity, not defined by anything or anyone other than itself …. Proponents of community, on the other hand, deny difference by positing fusion rather than separation as the social ideal.”xxvi For Young, this search for community among communitarianism can lead to a false common good. Making public life political – open to the participation of all persons – does not require “the creation of a unified public realm in which citizens leave behind their particular group affiliations, histories, and needs to discuss a mythical ‘common good.’” Rather, “the perception of anything like a common good can only be an outcome of public interaction that expresses rather than submerges particularities.”xxvii Rejecting the logic of identity that submerges difference, Young is led to reject both communitarianism and liberalism and to defend what she calls city life. Young defines city life as “a form of social relations which I define as the being together of strangers. In the city, persons and groups interact within spaces and institutions they all experience themselves as belonging to, but without those interactions dissolving into unity or commonness.” xxviii The emphasis on city-life as opposed to community rests on Young’s belief that community tends to squelch difference and that city-life affirms difference. Here, of course, we have an immediate question from the presentation of natural Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought law. 21 To what extent does the affirmation of difference expand our human personality? It’s hard to imagine any limits here because human beings tend to learn from others and grow in self-awareness by studying the practices and cultures of other people. But to what extent can a city maintain engagement with strangers while allowing each the pursuit of the common good and their own good? For city dwellers “being together entails some common problems and common interests, but they do not create a community of shared final ends, of mutual identification and reciprocity.”xxix In contrast to Young’s city, MacIntyre offers a polis. A polis does “require a high degree of shared culture by those who participate in it, [but] it is not itself constituted by that shared culture and is very different from those political societies whose essential bonds are the bonds of a shared cultural tradition.”xxx While embracing the notion of a shared culture, MacIntyre rejects the Volk of Herder and Heidegger whose bonds are “pre-rational and non-rational.” Rather, MacIntyre’s polis has three characteristics.xxxi First, the members of the polis recognize that adherence to standards of natural law becomes necessary if they are to learn from each other. Second, it must be relatively small-scale. It is an interesting question whether the sizes of MacIntyre’s polis and Young’s city overlap, and this may determine the degree to which they in fact overlap or diverge in their respective understandings of community and justice. Finally, the deliberative and other social relationships of the polis demand a general equality that the “free market” of advanced modernity violates. For MacIntyre, Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 22 “[g]enuinely free markets are always local and small-scale markets in whose exchanges producers can choose to participate or not.”xxxii MacIntyre and Young disagree on the shared political cultural of their ideal political units. For MacIntyre, however, the high degree of shared culture must satisfy the ends of society. In his polis, “individuals are always able to put into question through communal deliberation what has hitherto by custom and tradition been taken for granted both about their own good and the good of the community. A polis is always, potentially or actually, a society of rational enquiry, of self-scrutiny.”xxxiii As a society of rational enquiry, there will always be, not only room for, but encouragement of disagreement and engagement with others in rational debate about the good. MacIntyre’s polis may seem at first glance to be the kind of community that could have no room for individuals or groups who do not share the prevailing view of human goods. But this is a mistake, and not only because nothing I have said precludes the existence within such a political society of individuals and groups who hold and are recognized to hold radically dissenting views on fundamental issues. What will be important to such a society, if it holds any kind of view of the human good and the common good that I have outlined, will be to ask what can be learned from such dissenters.xxxiv 23 Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought MacIntyre’s polis requires diverse groups, even if such a polis requires a high degree of shared culture. Here we might look to examples I’ve discussed before.xxxv The example of the Roman Catholic Church will constitute the more familiar one. The Roman Catholic Church is known for emphasizing its catholic – that is, universal – nature. It tolerates disagreements over many issues, though it still maintains a high degree of shared culture. That shared culture is captured most evidently in the Bible and the teachings of the Church. It also evidences a wide variety of disagreement. The Catholic Church serves as home to Franciscans, Dominicans, Benedictines, and Augustinians who disagree over many issues. One of the strongest disagreements concerns the depravity of human beings, the role of grace, and predestination, all of which Augustinians tend more closely to Protestants than toward Thomists. Second, the Catholic Church welcomes and encourages a wide variety of specifically cultural practices within the framework of the shared culture of Catholicism. I see this on an everyday level working at a Catholic seminary in the western United States. The Vietnamese hold a Tet celebration and the Mexicans sponsor an Our Lady of Guadalupe celebration, to which they invite all members of the community. MacIntyre writes A communitarian politics is at home within the contemporary institutional framework imposed by the state and Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 24 the market and, just because it is thus at home, its conception of the common good is limited by that framework …. But the communitarian conception of the common good is not at all that of a kind of community of political learning and enquiry participation in which it is necessary for individuals to discover what their individual and common goods are.xxxvi MacIntyre is not a communitarian because they have the wrong conception of the common good. They, in fact, have values which sometimes coexist happily with liberal values, and only at the extremes of political theory do communitarians reject the framework of modern liberalism which governs human life. Moreover, their community is not one of political learning and enquiry. Once again, we find parallels between MacIntyre and Young this time in their rejection of communitarianism. A Substantive Account of the Common Good MacIntyre argues, then, against Maritain and Finnis, that the good of individual human beings cannot be given without reference to the common good as a common good of all and that the conception of the common good within Maritain and Finnis is too abstract. By drawing a parallel between the conception of the common good within Catholic social doctrine, I have suggested Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought that this conception might fall to the same criticism. 25 Given my previous argument about Caritas in Veritate, however, I should make one caveat. In that argument, I noted that Benedict does not make the same conclusion about the priority of the individual to the common good that Maritain made. I focused on Benedict’s use of a citation from Thomas’ Commentary of the Sentences to make that argument. If my argument there is true, however, then it gives me pause for how to consider the issue at hand: do the papal documents in fact presume the priority of the individual over the common good, as Maritain does? The theological anthropology that lies behind these encyclicals is known as personalist and received full development from John Paul II. Whether personalism is individualist in the modern sense deserves a treatment of its own. If it relies heavily on Maritain’s understanding of personalism, then it may in fact be. If, however, it relies on the personalism of Immanuel Mounier, then it might have a richer understanding of the human person as social being. I suspect, however, that when John Paul II declared each individual person a common good,xxxvii his personalism slides into an individualism at contrast with the Thomistic-Aristotelian tradition. More telling, however, is the reliance on a minimalist conception of the common good and its connection to the idea of rights in the papal encyclicals. The notion of rights is mean to protect the individual from the totalizing nature of society. The popes include that conception as a stop-gap to the socialism of the former Soviet Union, with which John Paul II was all too familiar. Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 26 I would suggest, however, that the common good cannot be reduced to a set of social conditions that provide for the flourishing of the human person. Rather, the common good is a good that can be had only as common – that is, it is the nature of the good of the common good that it can only be good as something shared. As an example to close my argument, I shall propose that practical reason itself is a common good. Reason names a set of social practices. Theses practices include the asking of and giving of reasons, the evaluation of those reasons, and the evaluation of the good. It is social, as I have argued elsewhere,xxxviii because the standards of reason are constituted by and constitutive of the conception of the good within a tradition or practice. Consider, for instance, the practice of midwifery. Midwives approach birth much differently than medical practitioners do. A midwife will spend, for instance, an hour or more at a home visit with the expectant parents. She will commit herself to “being with” the mother through the birth process, not just to catch the baby. Her after visits look at the way the mother and child are getting along and how the family is adjusting to the presence of the new baby. The aim of the midwife is to empower the mother to trust in her body and in the natural process of birth. This aim entails that the midwife use technology and medicine when appropriate, but that generally she allows the birth to occur as nature intended. The midwife acts as she does based on the practical reason of her practice. This practical reason entails standards of reason like “trust in the body,” “limit Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 27 the use of technology,” and “the birth does not exist in a vacuum.” The issue of technology is important for discussion of midwifery and birth in the United States. Over the last 120 years, birth has moved out of the house and into the hospital, has become increasingly medicalized, and has meant the death of midwifery. Doctors fought for their right to oversee birth. In doing so, they characterized pregnancy and birth as pathology and insisted that more medicine and more technology could ease the birth process and make it safer for women and children. Midwives, in contrast, act on a standard of reason that limits the use and role of technology because they see birth as natural. Moreover, their conception of the good of the birth extends beyond the physical health of the mother and infant to the whole health of the mother, infant, and family. It is reasonable for midwives to resist the use of technology in a way that it would not be reasonable for medical practitioners. Practical reason on my account is social essentially. We cannot understand reason as something individuals have because individuals cannot give accounts to themselves without reference to the standards of reason identified as such but a group of fellow practitioners or other members of their tradition. A theory of human nature supports this. Mary Midgley argues, for instance, that reason developed specifically as social for those highly social animals like human beings and could not have developed for animals like alligators. Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 28 As such, reason constitutes a common good. It is not something that I can have alone. Nor is it something that comprises a composite of all the reasonings that we do within a community. In this sense, Maritain’s reference to the idea that 6 is greater than 3 + 3 misses the point. Numbers exist, if you will, as individual entities, but reasons do not. Reasons exist only as something common. While we cannot achieve our flourishing individually without reason, it is not simply one more condition that makes flourishing possible. Rather, practical reason comes into existence as social – as common and good only because it is common. Nor does my account of reason entail that all of our reasons reduce to unity in some kind of Kantian categorical imperative as Young would have us fear about the common good. Reasons and the standards of reasons come into existence as a common good, but we each participate in those standards of reasons in a variety of irreducible ways. When, for instance, conservative Catholics and liberal Catholics – whatever those terms might mean – debate the justice of a war or the distribution of contraceptives, if they are reasonable, they do so with a shared set of standards of reason. Thomas Aquinas exemplifies this picture of reason in the way that he masterly articulates reasons against his position and then incorporates and understanding of why those reasons make sense under his answer. Thomas’ approach only works, however, if he is engaged in a social good that is good because social. Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 29 Given this richer understanding of the common good, I think some things can be said about Catholic social teaching. I began with a set of questions: how do the papal social encyclicals define the common good? What is the relationship of the individual to the community given this notion of the common good? If I reject Maritain’s reading of Thomas Aquinas do I not undo his work to protect the autonomy of the individual and, at the same time, undermine much of Catholic social teaching? How does one avoid a hegemonizing politics if politics is centered around a conception of the common good. I gave a reading of the common good within the papal documents as minimalist and conducive to a defense of human rights. I suggested that this reading aligns with the understanding of the common good in Maritain and Finnis. I think suggested that Maritain’s and Finnis’ accounts fall short of a notion of the common good because they attempt to define the worth of the individual prior to the common good and because their conceptions of the common good remain abstract. An abstract conception of the common good prevents any formulation of a substantive and subversive critique of modern society. This critique is the heart of modern Catholic social thought – a critique of both capitalist and communist modes of social and market organization. Thus a richer conception of the common good is necessary for Catholic social thought. Practical reason as a common good provides one aspect of this richer conception. It is a common good because it is good only as something common or shared. If society aims at a common good, then society must work together to Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 30 bring that good to fruition not as your or mine or ours together but as common to us. The common good establishes just relations in society because, without those just relations, the common good cannot come into existence. Similarly, these just relations entail that the individual is a being worthy in herself. Without the participation of each individual in the community, the common good remains deficient if it exists at all. Within the practice of midwifery, it is the good of the whole human family that makes the birth good. The mother cannot achieve her good of giving birth without the support of her extended family and, sometimes, friends. If any individual in that network remains uncommitted or absent from the work of the common good, then the good achieved will not be the highest good possible. My account of the common good, then, both protects the individual and makes a politics of the common good possible without reducing to a hegemonizing state. Individuals achieve their individual goods in pursuit of the common good with others. Catholic social teaching, then, must make clearer its statements on the common good, on the protection of individuals in society, and of its use of rights language. It must further, as I concluded before, become a supporter of the politics of the local community. A politics of the common good is possible only at the local community for discussion of the common good – which is, of course, the essential element of the common good of political society – must occur between concrete individuals in concrete ways. Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought 31 NOTES i Pg. 71. ii MacIntyre, unpublished essay, 2011, p. 14. iii Nicholas 2010, “Local Communities and Globalization in Caritas in Veritate.” iv See Thompson, 59. v The Rights of Man, 2-3. vi 4-5. vii 6. viii 7. ix 8-9. x 44. xi Rights of Man, 65. xii Cnf, the “Common Good and Catholic Social Teaching,” letter of the Conference of Catholic Bishops of England and Wales. xiii 61. xiv MacIntyre, ‘Theories of Natural Law in the Culture of Advanced Modernity’, p. 105. xv Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights, p. 33. xvi Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights, p. 155. xvii MacIntyre, Alasdair (2000) “Theories of Natural Law in the Culture of Advanced Modernity,” in Common Truths: New Perspectives on Natural Law, ed. Edward B. McLean, Wilmington, DE: ISI Books, 91-115, 103-4. xviii Ibid., 104. xix MacIntyre, ‘Theories of Natural Law in the Culture of Advanced Modernity’, p. 108. xx MacIntyre, ‘Theories of Natural Law in the Culture of Advanced Modernity’, p. 109. xxi MacIntyre 2011, p. 14, unpublished manuscript Nicholas, Common Good and Politics in Catholic Social Thought xxii 32 Alasdair MacIntyre, “Politics Philosophy, and the Common Good,” in Kelvin Knight (ed) The MacIntyre Reader, (Notre Dame, In: Notre Dame Press,1998), pp. 235-254, 251. Young, Iris Marion. Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton: Princton University Press, xxiii 1990. McKenna, Erin. The Task of Utopia: A Pragmatist and Feminist Perspective. Lanham, Md: xxiv Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 2001, 132. xxv Cnf. Benhabib’s The Claims of Culture: Equality and Diversity in the Global Era. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002, and Elizabeth Frazer and Nicola Lacey. The Politics of Community: A Feminist Critique of the Liberal-Communitarian Debate. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1993. xxvi Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference, pp. 228-9. xxvii Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference, p. 119. xxviii Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference, p. 237. xxix Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference, p. 238. xxx MacIntyre, ‘Politics Philosophy, and the Common Good’, p. 241. xxxi MacIntyre, ‘Politics Philosophy, and the Common Good’, pp. 247-9. xxxii MacIntyre, ‘Politics Philosophy, and the Common Good’, p. 249. xxxiii MacIntyre, ‘Politics Philosophy, and the Common Good’, p. 241. xxxiv MacIntyre, ‘Politics Philosophy, and the Common Good’, p. 251. xxxv Self Reference Here. xxxvi MacIntyre, ‘Politics Philosophy, and the Common Good’, p. 246. xxxvii Cnf Waldstein 575-576. xxxviii Reason, Tradition, and the Good, forthcoming UNDP 2012.