English Modals 1 analysis of modals [ep] [deon] [pot] must must will will shall shall [ff] [ ev] should should would would may can [cw] [ev] may can [cw] [ev] might might could could could [ff] [ev] this is an analysis of what the different modals can be used to spell out, not the features that they are associated with – see later on this This analysis ignores certain differences between some modals epistemic might/could he might be being followed he could be being followed it is often assumed that there is a difference of certainty between these, but I don’t believe it epistemic will/shall (would/should) he will win I shall win tradition has it that shall is used for first person and will for all the rest it is difficult to know what the status of this distinction is it has a prescriptive feel to it most people use will and tend to avoid shall there are cases where shall can be used (even formally) in non-1st person contexts he shall be king of all England epistemic must/will must is conclusive, will is predictive = minor features the butler must have done it the butler will have done it Deontic must/shall must places the obligation on the subject shall places the obligation on the speaker you must go to the ball you shall go to the ball Deontic may/can (might/could) this seems to be a formal/informal distinction – again, it is difficult to know how to treat this grammatically you may leave you can leave 2 two questions 1. how can we use these modals to express these range of meanings? 2. how can we account for the fact that while there is a lot of crossover in terms of the type of modality that modals express, there is not crossover at all in the degree or evidentiality that they express? 3 a late insertion approach helps to answer the first question if we assumed a lexical approach one would have to accept that there are at least two (three in one case) lexical entries for each modal if we assume we start with lexical items and these introduce the features of meaning, we could not assume that must is marked for both epistemic and Deontic type, otherwise both would be introduced every time must was used so there must be one must marked as epistemic and another marked as Deontic a late insertion approach allows us to have just one entry for each modal which spells out varying underlying features because it is the best fit in each case 4 the question is, what features are the modals associated with? if we assume a Superset condition approach, each modal will be associated with all of the features it is used to spell out must [ep] [deon] [ff] [ev] shall [ep] [deon] [ff] [ev] will [ep] [pot] [ff] [ev] should [ep] [deon] [ff] [ev] would [ep] [pot] [ff] [ev] may [ep] [deon] [cw] [ev] can [deon] [pot] [cw] [ev] might [ep] [deon] [cw] [ev] could [ep] [deon] [pot] [cw] [ev] this would work, but isn’t very informative in particular it cannot answer the second question why can modals be associated with various type features but are always associated with the same degree and evidentiality features? A Subset condition approach would not even be possible e.g. will would have to be associated with [pot] [ff] [ev] to account for why it is the only modal which can spell this combination of features out But if this is so, by the Subset condition, it should not be able to spell out [ep] [ff] [ev] as it is associated with an incompatible feature suppose it isn’t associated with [pot] therefore but only [ff] [ev] but then so would must and shall in order to account for why they are able to spell out [ep] [ff] [ev] then we would have no account for why will can spell out [pot] and must and shall cannot and why will cannot spell out [deon] and must and shall can again, under this assumption (even if it could be made to work) there would be no answer to question 2 5 the solution is to have the modals associated with certain features that they don’t always spell out (basically taking a Superset condition approach) but allow the modals to be used to spell out features that they are not associated with (taking a Subset approach) this apparent contradiction can be made sense of under the assumption that, in accordance with the Superset condition, underlying features are generally spelled out but some features are earmarked for not being spelled out if necessary the assumption is that the type feature does not need to be spelled out if there is no vocabulary item compatible with it 6 Under this analysis, the following vocabulary entries are proposed: may can [ep], [cw], [ev] [pot], [cw], [ev] might [cw], [ev] could [pot], [cw], will shall [pot], [ff], [ev] [deon], [ff], [ev] would [pot], [ff], [ev] should [deon], [ff], must [deon], [ff], [ev] [ev] [ev] to see how this works, consider some examples given that may is associated with [ep] [cw] [ev], it will be the best selection for spelling these features out. Hence not other modal can. but there is no modal specified for [deon] [cw] [ev], so what will be selected? The choice is between shall, should, must (specified for [deon]), may, might, can, could (specified for [cw]) may, can, will, shall, and must (specified for [ev]). of these, may, can, shall and must are associated with two out of the three features, whereas the others are associated with only one. Therefore we can discard the others and concentrate on these four Assuming that if it is not possible to match a vocabulary item with the type feature it doesn’t have to, but there must be a match for degree and evidentiality features, we see that while may and can have the right degree and evidentiality features shall and must are mismatched for [cw]. Therefore both may and can will be selected as possible spell outs for this set of features We can represent this in terms of an OT system match degree match evid match type [deon] [cw] [ev] may [ep], [cw], [ev] * *! might [cw], [ ev] can * [pot], [cw], [ ev] *! could [pot], [cw], [ev] will [pot], [ff], [ev] *! would [pot], [ff], [ev] *! shall [deon], [ff], [ev] *! should [deon], [ff], [ev] *! must [deon], [ff], [ev] *!