Paper 2 The Role of Reason in Exercising Christian Faith Matthew B. Scraper PH 501X1 Philosophy of Religion Dr. Kevin Kinghorn Introduction The question that we are asked to engage for the purpose of this assignment is to assess what role, if any, reason should play in regard to a person’s decision to exercise Christian faith. In an attempt to engage this question, I will first seek to propose a working definition of three key terms, those being “belief,” “faith,” and “reason.” It is my belief that engaging an adequate working definition of these terms as they relate to the subject of Christian philosophy will offer an appropriate answer to one manner in which reason can and must play a role in the individual’s decision to exercise Christian faith. Defining Belief and Faith In order to engage this question fully, it is first necessary to enter into a working definition that offers an appropriate distinction between “belief” and “faith.” I would submit, as I will seek to further define, that within the context of Christianity, in which we seek to engage these two terms, belief must precede faith. I will therefore first seek to build an adequate definition of belief so that the distinction between belief and faith will become clear. Concerning the nature of belief, William Hasker indicates that a belief is something for which there is “good reason” to hold to be true.1 It is therefore reasonable to consider that a belief itself is something that is held to be true by an individual or group of individuals, based reasons that adequately support the notion that what is believed is very likely to be true. It must be considered at this point that such reasons may or may not be based on the individual’s personal experience with the truth that is supported adequately enough to be held as truth. Rather, it may be more appropriate to consider that a belief, as 1 William Hasker, Metaphysics: Constructing a World View, (Downers Grove: IVP Academic, 1983), 17-19. such, may be held to be true based on what is known, (or rather perhaps commonly accepted to be true). While it must be considered that much of what is accepted as true based on adequate reasons for doing so is likewise based on human experience with what is accepted to be true, it is also possible to hold something as true that is as of yet not directly experienced by anyone, but is supported by logical consistency that is reasonable, in that the premise that serves as the foundation for the logic used to support the belief is itself commonly held to be true. What, then, is the distinction between belief and faith? It must be considered that this distinction is being considered (for the purposes of this assignment) within the context of Christianity, in which there is sufficient evidence scripturally to shed light on what faith is to be held as within a Christian context. For such evidence perhaps one of the most important scriptural references comes from the book of James, where the writer states that “…someone will say, ‘You have faith and I have works.’ Show me your faith apart from works, and I by my works will show you my faith.”2 Shortly thereafter is the assertion that only a “senseless” person would assume that faith can exist apart from “works.”3 While such scriptural references cannot perhaps provide an adequate definition of faith as they are certainly Christian-specific, they do offer an understanding of what faith is to be considered as within a Christian context, namely that, as indicated, faith must combine belief with action. As the writer of James indicates, faith without action cannot be considered to be faith. Therefore, it should be noted that action is a critical component of faith for a Christian, but action alone is insufficient for faith to be considered faith. What is 2 3 James 2:18, NRSV. James 2:20, NRSV. it that must be acted out in order for the action to be considered to be faith, and not simply action in and of itself? Based on such scriptural references, it would be appropriate to assert that for the Christian, the difference between faith and action is that faith is the belief of the Christian that is acted upon. Therefore faith is more than belief alone, but belief itself is a critical component of faith, which requires action based on that belief in order to be considered faith. Faith is therefore highly experiential in nature, and is based on a set of beliefs regarding the nature and reality of God (in this Christian context) that are held to be true by the individual Christian or group of Christians. It would be wise, at this point, to also consider the nature of what is believed to be true by the Christian, in as much as the nature of that belief is ultimately linked to the action that is based on it. It must also be acknowledged that arguing the existence or reality of God, or the experience of the reality of God is not within the scope of this assignment and will therefore not be attempted here. However, it must be noted that the primary belief that is to be acted upon by the Christian in order for the combination of belief and action to be considered to be faith is a belief that is relative to the reality of God, and the experience (or likelihood of the possibility of an experience) of the reality of God by the believer, to the extent that the experience of the reality of God, or the belief in the reality of God and subsequent possibility of real experience related to it by the Christian results in action (faith) that is consistent with the belief about the reality of God related to the life of the individual believer or Christian community. The Role of Reason If reason is to play a role in the exercise of Christian faith (and I would assert that it must), then as is suggested by Michael Peterson and others, the question that must be answered is one of “validation (or invalidation).”4 It is further suggested by Peterson and others that (in accordance with the notion of critical rationalism) the appropriate method for validation (or invalidation) is to “look at reasons for and against accepting the belief.”5 These authors note that,“ …at best, such reasons will fall short of conclusive, universally convincing proof, but that does not mean that they have no value at all. It has been pointed out by George Mavrodes that in many cases the success of reasons and arguments for a belief is “person-relative”-that is to say, there are arguments which are convincing for one person…and yet those same arguments may fail completely for another, equally intelligent person.6 If proper reason can result in arguments that are “person-relative,” it is essential to further explore a necessary means of engaging reason relative to belief in God that takes into account that which reason itself is relative to. As stated within the working definition for a belief, the reasons that are commonly held to be true which form the foundation for a belief (which is then acted on as faith) are either based on human experience with what is accepted to be true because of that experience, or are supported by logical consistency that is reasonable, in that the premise that serves as the foundation for the logic used to support the belief is itself commonly held to be true. It is therefore important to note that as human 4 Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Reason & Religious Belief: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion, (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009), 54. 5 Peterson, Hasker, Reichenbach, and Basinger, 63. 6 Peterson, Hasker, Reichenbach, and Basinger, 63. knowledge about what is generally accepted to be true changes (whether that knowledge is based on either human experience or on logical consistency that is reasonable) then the belief that is supported by what is held to be true can likewise change. Simply put, the logical reasoning used to validate or invalidate belief systems is relative to what is commonly accepted to be true. If what is commonly accepted to be true changes (in any way) then the logical reasoning that is used to validate or invalidate belief systems must likewise change, less it become illogical. As human knowledge changes, it must therefore be considered that human knowledge is incomplete and that should something come to be known that was previously unknown the logic such knowledge supports must likewise change. Therefore in order for reason to be used as a means for validating or invalidating systems of belief, it can only be properly used if it is likewise considered that such logical reason is based on limited knowledge. Therefore for something (such as a belief in the reality or the experience of the reality of God) to be adequately addressed by reason, it must be accounted for that even if sufficient proof for such a belief may not conclusively reasonably exist, there forever remains the possibility that because human knowledge is limited, that which is seemingly illogical but claimed (by the believer) through experience cannot be reasonably conclusively proven to be illogical or unreasonable simply because the reason that is based on limited human knowledge has the potential to be altered should that which is currently unknown come to be known. While such reason cannot certainly be considered to be conclusive convincing proof of the validity of such a belief system or the experience of it, it must certainly be considered that such a belief system (and subsequently the faith that results from the action that is based on the experience of it) cannot be rendered to be reasonably or conclusively invalid simply because the knowledge that forms the foundation for the reason that is employed to provide validation or invalidation is itself limited and subject to being altered should that which is presently unknown come to be known. Bibliography Hasker, William. Metaphysics: Constructing a World View. Downers Grove: IVP Academic, 1983. Peterson, Michael, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger. Reason & Religious Belief: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion. New York: Oxford University Press, 2009.